About this ebook
The self-contained treatment features numerous problems, complete proofs, a detailed bibliography, and indexes. It presumes some knowledge of abstract algebra, providing necessary background and references where appropriate. This inexpensive edition of a hard-to-find systematic survey will fill a gap in many individual and institutional libraries.
Related to Partially Ordered Algebraic Systems
Titles in the series (100)
Applied Functional Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsInfinite Series Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mathematics for the Nonmathematician Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Fourier Series and Orthogonal Polynomials Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFirst-Order Partial Differential Equations, Vol. 1 Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Analytic Inequalities Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Laplace Transforms and Their Applications to Differential Equations Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Dynamic Probabilistic Systems, Volume II: Semi-Markov and Decision Processes Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOptimization Theory for Large Systems Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Introduction to the Theory of Abstract Algebras Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCalculus Refresher Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5An Introduction to the Theory of Canonical Matrices Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Catalog of Special Plane Curves Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5A History of Mathematical Notations Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Counterexamples in Topology Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Statistical Inference Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Gamble If You Must: Inequalities for Stochastic Processes Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDifferential Forms Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Methods of Applied Mathematics Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Advanced Calculus: Second Edition Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5History of the Theory of Numbers, Volume II: Diophantine Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsExtremal Graph Theory Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Calculus: An Intuitive and Physical Approach (Second Edition) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5An Introduction to Information Theory: Symbols, Signals and Noise Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Theory of Approximation Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFirst-Order Partial Differential Equations, Vol. 2 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Adventurer's Guide to Number Theory Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Topology for Analysis Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Chebyshev and Fourier Spectral Methods: Second Revised Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Differential Forms with Applications to the Physical Sciences Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Related ebooks
Infinite Abelian Groups Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAlgebra Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Infinite Crossed Products Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsRepresentation Theory of Finite Groups Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Groups, Rings, Modules Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsElementary Algebraic Geometry: Second Edition Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPermutation Groups Rating: 1 out of 5 stars1/5Modern Algebra Essentials Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTheory of Lie Groups Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBasic Algebra I: Second Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Group Theory I Essentials Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOperators and Representation Theory: Canonical Models for Algebras of Operators Arising in Quantum Mechanics Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5A First Course in Functional Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsUniform Distribution of Sequences Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Linear Algebra Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Rudiments of Algebraic Geometry Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Introduction to Algebraic Structures Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5Introduction to Topology and Geometry Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAlgebraic Theory of Numbers: Translated from the French by Allan J. Silberger Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFoundations of Modern Analysis Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Introduction to Algebraic Geometry Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Applications of Model Theory to Functional Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsRegular Algebra and Finite Machines Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Function Theory on Planar Domains: A Second Course in Complex Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTopological Transformation Groups Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Topological Methods in Galois Representation Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGeometric Algebra Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Abstract Lie Algebras Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Mathematics For You
What If? 10th Anniversary Edition: Serious Scientific Answers to Absurd Hypothetical Questions Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Math Magic: How To Master Everyday Math Problems Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5A Beginner's Guide to Constructing the Universe: The Mathematical Archetypes of Nature, Art, and Science Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus Made Easy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Fluent in 3 Months: How Anyone at Any Age Can Learn to Speak Any Language from Anywhere in the World Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Mental Math Secrets - How To Be a Human Calculator Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5My Best Mathematical and Logic Puzzles Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Standard Deviations: Flawed Assumptions, Tortured Data, and Other Ways to Lie with Statistics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Secrets of Mental Math: The Mathemagician's Guide to Lightning Calculation and Amazing Math Tricks Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Quantum Physics for Beginners Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Logicomix: An epic search for truth Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Little Book of Mathematical Principles, Theories & Things Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Precalculus: A Self-Teaching Guide Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Basic Math & Pre-Algebra For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Seeing Further: The Story of Science and the Royal Society Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Mind For Numbers: How to Excel at Math and Science (Even If You Flunked Algebra) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Pre-Calculus For Dummies Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Golden Ratio: The Divine Beauty of Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Algebra I Workbook For Dummies Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Everything Guide to Algebra: A Step-by-Step Guide to the Basics of Algebra - in Plain English! Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Introductory Discrete Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Introducing Game Theory: A Graphic Guide Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus Essentials For Dummies Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Calculus For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Game Theory: A Simple Introduction Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mental Math: Tricks To Become A Human Calculator Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5Mathematics, Magic and Mystery Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Algebra - The Very Basics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Reviews for Partially Ordered Algebraic Systems
0 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
Partially Ordered Algebraic Systems - Laszlo Fuchs
CHAPTER I
INTRODUCTION
1. Partially ordered sets
It will be convenient to collect here the fundamental concepts and terminology we shall need.
If a binary relation is defined on a set A with the properties
then A is called a partially ordered set (abbreviated: p. o. set) and is called a partial order on A. The dual of A is the p. o. set A′ with the same elements and with the partial order ′ defined as follows: a ′ b (in A′) if, and only if, b a (in A).¹
As usual, one may write b a for a b, and a < b (or b > a) to mean that a b and a ≠ b. If neither a b nor b a, then a and b are called incomparable, in sign: a | | b.
It may happen that a relation satisfies only P1 and P3; in this case we say is a preorder.² A preorder induces an equivalence relation ~ on A, namely, a ~ b if, and only if, simultaneously a b and b a. The set of classes a*, c*, … of this equivalence can be partially ordered in the natural way : a* c* if for some (and hence for all) a in a* and for some (and so for all) c in c* we have a c. The set A* of the classes a*, c*, ... is a p. o. set.
A partial order on A induces in the natural way a partial order on any non-void subset B of A) namely, for a, b ∈ B one puts a b in B if, and only if, a b in the original partial order of A. This induced partial order of B will be denoted by the same symbol .
A (closed) interval³ [a, b] of A (where a b) consists of all c ∈ A satisfying a c b; a and b are called the endpoints of [a, b], The subsets Ia = [x ∈ A | x a], defined for each a ∈ A, and their duals Ja = [x ∈ A | x a] are also considered as (closed) intervals. A subset of A is called convex if it contains the whole interval [a, b] whenever it contains the endpoints a, b. If we replace by < we obtain the definition of open intervals (a, b), . . ..
Let A and A′ be p. o. sets. A mapping a → a′ from A into A′ is called isotone if it is single-valued and order-preserving in the sense that a b implies a′ b′. A mapping which is one-to-one and isotone in both directions is said to be an isomorphism (or order-isomorphism) of A onto A′; A and A′ are then called isomorphic (order-isomorphic). If a one-to-one mapping between A and A′ reverses order (i. e. a b if, and only if, a′ b′), then it is a dual isomorphism.
Assume that two partial orders, 1 and 2, are defined on the same set A. Then 2 is an extension of 1 if, for all a, b ∈ A, a 1 b implies a 2 b.
A has the trivial order if, for all a, b ∈ A, a b implies a = b (i. e. a < b never holds). The order relation is called a full (or linear or simple or total) order on A and A a fully ordered (etc.) set (f. o. set) or a chain, if, in addition to P1 — 3, also
P4. for all a, b ∈ A, either a < b or a = b or a > b
holds. The subsets of a f. o. set are again f. o. sets under the induced partial order.
For a subset B of a p. o. set A, an upper (lower) bound of B in A is an element u ∈ A (v ∈ A) such that b u (b v) for every b ∈ B. B is called bounded (in A) if A contains both upper and lower bounds of B. The set of all upper (lower) bounds of B will be denoted by U(B) (L(B)). If B consists of the elements x, y, … , then we shall often write U(B) = = U(x, y, . . .) and L(B) = L(x, y, . . .). If B is the void set, then U(B) = L(B) = A, while if B has no upper bound in A, then U(B) = Ø.
Note that B ⊆ C implies U(B) ⊇ U(C) and L(B) ⊇ L(C). Furthermore
thus
A p. o. set A satisfying
P5. for any a, b ∈ A, the set U(a, b) is not void,
and the dual law
P6. for any a, b ∈ A, the set L(a, b) is not void,
is called u- and l-directed, respectively. Obviously, P5 implies that U(B) is never void if B is a finite subset of A. A is said to be directed (or to have the Moore-Smith-property) if it satisfies both P5 and P6.
A p. o. set A is a ∨-semilattice or a ∧-semilattice according as
P7. to all a, b ∈ A there exists a c ∈ A such that U (a, b) = U(c),
or
P8. to all a, b ∈ A there exists a d ∈ A such that L(a, b) = L(d) is satisfied. Then the elements
are uniquely determined elements of A (if they exist) and are called the join (or union or least upper bound) and the meet (or intersection or greatest lower bound)⁴ of a and b.
If P7 and P8 are both satisfied, then A is called a lattice.⁵ A lattice may alternatively be defined as an algebraic system in which two operations, ∨ and ∧, are defined such that
L1. a ∨ a = a and a ∧ a = a,
L2. a ∨ b = b ∨ a and a ∧ b = b ∧ a,
L3. (a ∨ b) ∨ c = a ∨ (b ∨ c) and (a ∧ b) ∧ c = a ∧ (b ∧ c),
L4. (a ∨ b) ∧ a = a and (a ∧ b) ∨ a = a
for all a, b, c ∈ A. In fact, the join a ∨ b and the meet a ∧ b of a, b satisfy Ll — 4, and if in some set A the operations ∨ and ∧ possess properties Ll — 4, then putting a b if, and only if, a ∨ b = b (or equivalently, a ∧ b = a), A becomes a p. o. set in which P7 — 8 hold.
A f. o. set W is said to be well-ordered if every non-void subset V of W contains a smallest element, i. e. a u such that u v for every v ∈ V. The Axiom of Choice will be assumed for all sets. Then by a theorem of ZERMELO, every set can be well-ordered. An equivalent statement is ZORN’S lemma: if every subset of a p. o. set A which is a chain (in the induced partial order) has an upper bound in A, then A contains a maximal element, say x, in the sense that if y ∈ A and x y, then y = x.
2. Partial order in algebraic systems
As usual, by an algebraic system (or algebraic structure) we understand a set A in which operations fα are defined satisfying certain rules.⁶ Thus each fα is a single-valued function from a product set A × … ×A (say, with n = n(α) components) into A. The notions of isomorphism, homomorphism, etc. of two algebraic systems with the same operations will be understood in the ordinary sense.
A function g(x) from a p. o. set A into a p. o. set A′ is called isotone if x y in A implies g(x) g(y) in A′ and antitone if x y in A implies g(x) g(y) in A′. A function g(x1, … , xn) of more than one variable can be isotone in some of its variables, antitone in others and both in yet others,⁷ and it can, of course, be none of these things in further variables.
The following formulation of monotony is sufficiently general and suitable for all cases to be considered here.
We shall say that an operation f of an algebraic system A satisfies a monotony law with the monotony domain⁸ C if
1. f(x1, … , xn) ∈ C whenever x1, … , xn ∈ C,
2. for each i (i = 1, … , n), f is either isotone or antitone or both in the variable xi ∈ C.
According as which of these three alternatives occurs, f will be called of type ↑ , ↓ or ↕ in the variable xi. We shall say that f(x1, … , xn) is of type (γ1, … , yn) in the domain C if γi (= ↑, ↓ or ↕) denotes the type of f in xi. If no γi equals ↕ , then f is non-degenerate in C.
By a partially ordered algebraic system we shall mean a set A satisfying
(i) A is an algebraic system,
(ii) A is a p. o. set,
(iii) every operation f α of A fulfils a monotony law.
Our main interest lies in groups, rings and semigroups, therefore we shall now derive some consequences of the definition for binary operations.
a) An associative operation f(x, y) for which g(x, y, z) = = f(f(x, y), z) (considered as a ternary operation) is non-degenerate must be of type ( ↑ , ↑ ) in any monotony domain C. For assume, on the contrary, that f(x, y) is of type ↓ in x. Then g(x, y, z) is of type ↑ in x, while f(x, f(y, z)) is obviously of type ↓ in x. The same argument applies for y.
b) Every operation f(x, y) with a neutral element e (i. e. f(e, x) = f(x, e) = x for all x ∈ A) is of type ( ↑ , ↑ ) in any monotony domain C containing e. In fact, x1 < x2 implies f(e, x1) < < f(e, x2) and f(x1, e) < f(x2, e).
c) If f(x, y) is of type ( ↑ , ↑ ) and g(x) is a right-inverse operation in the sense that f(x, g(x)) is a fixed element e of A for every x ∈ A, then g(x) is of type ↓ in any C.
Hence we see that in a loop, group, semigroup (with some uninteresting exceptions), and (not necessarily associative) ring with unit element, the multiplication and addition are of type ( ↑ , ↑ ) in every monotony domain; while inversion is of type ↓ and subtraction is of type ( ↑ , ↓ ). Thus in the cases mentioned the definition of partial order to be given here is the onl, reasonable one in view of our general definition of partially ordered algebraic systems. However, in quasigroups—and a fortiori in groupoids—the operation may be of type ( ↑ , ↓ ) or of type (↓ , ↓), as shown by the example of integers if the operation ∘ is defined by x ∘ y = x — y and x ∘ y = — x — y, respectively.
¹ We shall often speak of the dual of an assertion; thereby we mean that the signs and are to be interchanged throughout.
² It is also called quasiorder; cf. BIRKHOFF [3].
³ Generalized intervals have been considered by BURGESS [1].
⁴ We shall use the customary abbreviations l.u.b. and g.l.b.
⁵ We shall need several results of lattice theory; the reader is referred to BIRKHOFF [3] for them.
⁶ We may content ourselves with this naive definition of algebraic systems, since for our purposes we do not need a more precise one.
⁷ If A is u- directed or l-directed, then this third alternative means that the function is independent of the variables now considered.
⁸ A monotony domain is always a non-void subset of A.
FIRST PART
PARTIALLY ORDERED GROUPS
CHAPTER II
PRELIMINARIES ON PARTIALLY ORDERED GROUPS
1. Definitions
A partially ordered group (p. o. group) is a set G such that
Gl. G is a group under multiplication,¹
G2. G is a p. o. set under a relation ,
G3. the monotony law² holds with the whole of G as monotony domain:
Since a group contains a neutral element³ e and the cancellation laws hold, either one of the following conditions is equivalent to G3:
(1) a b implies cad cbd for all c, d ∈ G.
(2) a < b implies ca < cb and ac < bc for all c ∈ G (that is to say, x → cx and x → xc are, for any c ∈ G, one-to-one and isotone mappings).
(3) a < b implies cad < cbd for all c, d ∈ G.
On using the transitivity of , it follows readily that further equivalent conditions are the laws:
(4) a b and a′ b′ imply aa′ bb′.
(5) a b and a′ < b′ imply aa′ < bb′ and a′a < b′b
Let us note the following immediate consequences of the definition:
(6) a b implies a–1 b–1 [a < b implies a–1 > b–1]
(7) For all a, b ∈ G the sets U(a) and U(b) are, regarded as p. o. sets, isomorphic, say, under x → ba–1 x.
(8) For all a ∈ G, the sets U(a) and L(a) are, again as p. o. sets, dually isomorphic, say, under x → ax–1 a.
(9) If G is a p. o. group, then it remains so if the partial order is replaced by its dual.
The following generalizations of the concept of p. o. groups deserve mention.
MATSUSHITA [1] and ZAǏCEVA [2] considered the case when only the half of the monotony law G3 is assumed. Cf. also CONRAD [10] and COHN [1].
A somewhat more general notion than p. o. group has been studied by BRITTON and SHEPPERD [1] under the name almost ordered groups
.
If condition G2 is weakened to the requirement that G is a pre-ordered set, then G3 implies that
and that
Hence one obtains at once that the equivalence class containing e is a normal subgroup N of G and the other classes are just the cosets of N. The p. o. set of the equivalence classes is nothing else than the factor group G/N which is now a p. o. group.
If a, b ∈ G have an upper (lower) bound c ∈ G, then their inverses, a–1 and b–1, have a lower (upper) bound. Hence a p. o. group which is u-directed (l-directed) is necessarily l-directed (u-directed), and thus directed. If this is the case, we call G a directed group.
Moreover, if we assume merely that in the p. o. group G, for some fixed a0∈ G and for every b ∈ G, an upper (lower) bound of a0 and b exists, then G is directed. In fact, if a1 and b1 are arbitrary and c is an upper (lower) bound for a0 and , then c is an upper (lower) bound for a1 and b1.
Proposition 1. (CLIFFORD [1].) If a p. o. group G contains an element a e such that U(a) generates G, then G is directed.
Conversely, if G is a directed group, then for every a ∈ G each element b of G may be written in the form⁴
It suffices to verify the first part for a = e, since U(e) = = a–1 U(a) is contained in the subgroup generated by U(a). Assuming {U(e)} = G, any b ∈ G has the form b = x1 … xr with xi or . Since the product of two elements of U (e) and the conjugates of every element of U(e) also belong to U(e), b may be written as b = yz–1 with y, z ∈ U(e). Then y e and y b, that is, e and each b have an upper bound, and so G is directed. Conversely, if G is a directed group, then e, b ∈ G have an upper bound c ∈ G. Let y = ca and z = = (b–1 c)a. Then y, z ∈ U(a) and b = yz–1 has the indicated form. Q.E.D.
If a, b ∈ G have a 1. u. b. a ∨ b in G, then the inverses a–1 and b–1 have a g. 1. b. a–1 ∧ b–1 in G. In fact, (a ∨ b)–1 a–1 and b–1, because a ∨ b a, b, and if x a–1, b–1, then x-1 a, b, whence x-1 a ∨ b, x (a ∨ b)–1 and (a ∨ b)–1 is the g. 1. b. of a–1 and b–1. Hence a p. o. group G which is a ∨-semilattice (∧-semilattice) is at the same time a ∧-semi-lattice (∨-semilattice) and thus a lattice where
A p. o. group which is a lattice under its partial order will be called a lattice-ordered group (I. o. group⁵).
If the order of G is full, we say G is a fully ordered group (f. o. group).
We list some elementary and useful rules on the sets⁶ U(. . . , aa, . . .) and L(. . . , aa, . . .):
(i)
(ii) xU (. . . , a a , . . .) y = U (. . . , xa a y . . .),
(iii) the multiplication ⁷ of the U(. . . , aa, . . .) is associative,
(iv)
,
(v) L ( a, b ) = a U ( a, b ) – ¹ b ,
(vi) U (. . . , a a , . . .) U (. .., b β ,...) ⊆ U (. . . , a a b β , . . .),
(vii) U ( x ) U (. . . , a a , . . .) = U (. . . , xa a , . . .),
and the dual laws for all aa, bβ, x, y ∈ G. The proofs are obvious and may be left to the reader.
If the p. o. group is at the same time an operator group with an operator domain Ω, then it is assumed that the operators ω ∈ Ω preserve order, i. e.
A p. o. group G is said to be Archimedean if
that is, if {e} is the only subgroup having an upper bound in G.⁸
A p. o. group is called completely integrally closed if
Any completely integrally closed p. o. group is Archimedean. For, if an < b (n = 0, ±1, ±2, . . .), then an < b and (a–1)" < < b (n = 1, 2, . . .) whence a e and a–1 e by complete integral closure; thus a = e. The converse implication does not hold in general (see EVERETT and ULAM [1]), but it does in 1. o. groups (see Chapter V, 1).
2. The positive cone
In a p. o. group G, an element a is called positive (integral) if a e, strictly positive (strictly integral) if a > e, and negative if a e. If the group operation is written as addition and 0 denotes the neutral element, then positivity has the usual meaning a 0.
The set P = P(G) = G+ of positive (integral) elements of G, i. e. P = U(e), is said to be the positive cone (or the integral part) of G. This concept is a natural tool for studying partial orders. Its precise significance will become fully apparent from Chapter III.
A partial order is already uniquely determined by the corresponding positive cone P, for
In view of this, instead of "the partial order with the positive cone P, we may say briefly
the partial order P".
It is readily seen that the reflexivity of is equivalent to e ∈ P, its antisymmetry to the fact that P ∩ P–1 contains no element ≠ e, transitivity to the inclusion PP ⊆ P, while the monotony law is equivalent to the fact that ba–¹ ∈ P implies (cbd) (cad)–¹ = c(ba–1)c–1 ∈ P, i. e. to cPc–1 ⊆ P. We may use (1) to define from P if P is given.
Theorem 2. A subset P of a group G is the positive cone of some partial order of G if, and only if, it satisfies the following three conditions:
a. P ∩ P–1 = e,
β. PP ⊆ P,
y. xPx–1 ⊆ P for all x ∈ G.⁹
In other words, P is a normal subsemigroup of G containing e, but no other element along with its inverse.
This result may be completed by
Proposition 3.¹⁰ (a) G is a directed group if, and only if, P generates G;
(b) G is a l. o. group if, and only if, P generates G and P is a lattice under the induced order ;
(c) G is a f. o. group if, and only if,
Statement (a) is contained in Proposition 1, while (c) follows at once from the fact that G is f. o. exactly if, for each a ∈ G, either a e or a–1 e. The only if part of (b) is obtained from (a) and from the obvious sublattice property of P. Finally, its
if" part may be shown by verifying that (ac–1 ∧ bc–1)c is a g. 1. b. for a, b ∈ G where c is a lower bound for a, b (note that ac–1, bc–1 and ac–1 ∧ bc–1 ∈ P).
Observe that the partial order on G is trivial if, and only if, P consists of e alone.
BRUCK [1] observes that in a f. o. loop G the sets P and N = = [x ∈ G | x e] have the following characterizing properties: P ∩ N = = e, P U N = G; PP ⊆ P; NN ⊆ N;P (and hence N) is normal in G.
We turn to an intrinsic characterization of the positive cones. In Theorem 2, P was assumed to be embedded in a group G. We get rid of this assumption in the next
Theorem 4. (BIRKHOFF [1].)¹¹ An arbitrary semigroup P is the positive cone of some p. o. group G if, and only if,
(i) the cancellation laws hold in P ;
(ii) P contains a neutral element e ;
(iii) ab = e ( a, b ∈ P ) implies a = b = e ;
(iv) Pa = aP for all a ∈ P .
We may restrict ourselves to the proof of sufficiency. We embed a semigroup P with properties (i)—(iv) in a group G as follows. If given a, x ∈ P, by (iv) and (i) there exists exactly one xa ∈ P such that xa = axa. The correspondence x → xa (with a fixed a) is