Explore 1.5M+ audiobooks & ebooks free for days

Only $12.99 CAD/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Introducing Logic: A Graphic Guide
Introducing Logic: A Graphic Guide
Introducing Logic: A Graphic Guide
Ebook387 pages2 hoursGraphic Guides

Introducing Logic: A Graphic Guide

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Logic is the backbone of Western civilization, holding together its systems of philosophy, science and law. Yet despite logic's widely acknowledged importance, it remains an unbroken seal for many, due to its heavy use of jargon and mathematical symbolism.This book follows the historical development of logic, explains the symbols and methods involved and explores the philosophical issues surrounding the topic in an easy-to-follow and friendly manner. It will take you through the influence of logic on scientific method and the various sciences from physics to psychology, and will show you why computers and digital technology are just another case of logic in action.
LanguageEnglish
PublisherIcon Books
Release dateJun 5, 2014
ISBN9781848317611
Introducing Logic: A Graphic Guide

Related to Introducing Logic

Titles in the series (82)

View More

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Reviews for Introducing Logic

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Introducing Logic - Bill Mayblin

    What is Logic?

    Nothing is more natural to conversation than argument. We try to convince the person we are arguing with that we are right, that our conclusion follows from something that they will accept. It would be no good if we could not tell when one thing followed from another. What is often passed off in conversation as an argument does not fit the bill.

    ALL PROPERTY IS THEFT.

    SO ALL THEFT IS PROPERTY.

    THEREFORE THESE PEARLS ARE MINE.

    This is clearly rubbish because there is nothing to link the truth of the conclusion to the truth of the supporting claims. What we need is to ensure that the truth of the supporting claims is preserved by the argument. Logic is quite simply the study of truth-preserving arguments.

    Studying Sentences

    The Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–322 BC) first gave us the idea of a tool (organon) to argue convincingly. This study included grammar, rhetoric and a theory of interpretation, as well as logic. The first thing Aristotle does is discuss sentences.

    SENTENCES COME IN THREE TYPES …

    IN EACH OF THESE TYPES WE ARE SAYING THAT SOMETHING OR SOME THINGS ARE OF A CERTAIN KIND.

    1. Singular: Socrates is a man.

    2. Universal: Every man is mortal.

    3. Particular: Some men are mortal.

    The objects we talk about (e.g., nouns like Socrates and tables; abstract nouns like walking; and pronouns like someone and everyone) Aristotle calls the subject of the sentence.

    What we say about the subject of the sentence (e.g., verbs like is eating and has fallen; adjectives like is difficult; and nouns like man in things like Socrates is a man) Aristotle called the predicate.

    The Square off Oppositions

    Aristotle noticed that the truth of some subject-predicate sentences has an effect on the truth of other subject-predicate sentences.

    THE FOLLOWING SENTENCES STAND IN DEFINITE RELATIONS TO EACH OTHER. I CALL THIS MY SQUARE OF OPPOSITIONS.

    Sentences 1 and 2 cannot both be true.

    The diagonal statements 1 and 4 are known contradictories. As long as there are men, one of them has to be true but never both – the truth of one guarantees that the other is false.

    The same is true for the diagonal statements 2 and 3.

    Sentences 1 and 3 can both be true. If 1 is true then 3 must be true, but 3 being true does not mean that 1 must be true.

    Similarly with 2 and 4. The same relation holds between All men are mortal and Socrates is mortal.

    The Syllogism

    Using the square of oppositions, Aristotle noticed a mysterious fact. Take a sentence like Socrates is a man. If an argument of three statements is built where the subject of the first statement is the predicate of the second (call these the premises) and the third statement is composed of the remaining terms (call this the conclusion), then the truth of the conclusion is guaranteed by the truth of the premises.

    THIS SCHEMA I CALL A SYLLOGISM. WE CAN USE IT TO SEE WHY ONE ARGUMENT IS TRUE AND ANOTHER FALSE.

    Aristotle forgot conditional statements that have more than one predicate, e.g.,

    If Socrates is a man, then Socrates is mortal.

    We now have two reasons why the argument Arsenal are in London, therefore Arsenal will win the cup is false. The first comes from what is actually said. There is no way that the facts that I support Arsenal and that Arsenal are in London are enough to guarantee that Arsenal will win the cup. But there is also the formal reason that the predicate of the first premise is not the subject of the second.

    YES, BUT THIS IS VALID …

    1. If I support Arsenal, then they will win the cup.

    2. I do support Arsenal, so ...

    3. Arsenal will win the cup.

    IT IS STILL FALSE BECAUSE VALIDITY ONLY GRARANTEES THE TRUTH OF THE CONCLUSION IF THE PREMISES ARE TRUE. IN YOUR EXAMPLE THE PREMISES ARE FALSE SO THE CONCLUSION REMAINS FALSE.

    SO WHAT GOOD DOES THIS FORMALIZATION DO US?

    YOU’LL SEE.

    Connective Logic

    About a hundred years later, Chrysippus of Soli (c.280–c.206 BC) changed the focus of logic from single subject-predicate statements to complex statements such as: "Socrates is a man and Zeno is a man. This was a major achievement. It was said, If the gods used logic, it would be the logic of Chrysippus". As we shall see, the same is true of us humans, but it took us a couple of millennia to catch on.

    WITH WORDS LIKE AND, OR AND IF…THEN…, DIFFERENT STATEMENTS CAN BE JOINED TOGETHER AND THE TRUTH OF THE WHOLE WILL DEPEND EXCLUSIVELY ON THE TRUTH OF THE PARTS.

    Each of these connectives has a unique way of combining the truth of the parts into the truth of the whole.

    For example the or connective and only the or connective can be used in the following way.

    Either Muhammad will go to the mountain or the mountain will go to Muhammad. Muhammad did not go to the mountain, therefore the mountain went to Muhammad.

    USING MY DEFINITIONS FOR CONNECTIVES, I CAN SHOW HOW TO DERIVE VARIOUS STATEMENTS WHOSE TRUTH IS ALWAYS GUARANTEED BY THE TRUTH OF THE INITIAL STATEMENT.

    Chrysippus had no real impact on the history of logic for at least the next 1,500 years, not least because his writings were lost and his ideas known only by second-hand reports, but also because Aristotle became the darling of the Catholic Church.

    Leibniz’s Law

    For the next 2,000 years, logicians came up with an ever increasing number of syllogisms, some including more than two premises. The logician was a kind of alchemist playing around with concepts to get valid arguments. Eventually, a method in this madness was provided by Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716).

    Leibniz came up with the idea of treating statements like equations in algebra. Equations use the equality sign = to say that two sides must have the same numerical value,

    Leibniz introduced the equality sign in logic to show that "a is identical with b".

    TWO THINGS ARE IDENTICAL IF EVERYTHING THAT CAN BE SAID OF THE ONE CAN BE SAID OF THE OTHER.

    IF YOU CAN SAY EXACTLY THE SAME OF TWO THINGS, THEN THEY ARE IDENTICAL.

    This has been known ever since as Leibniz’s Law. He analysed it into two inseparable claims, "a is b and b is a, which he took to mean that all a’s are b’s and all b’s are a’s",

    e.g., All bachelors are unmarried men and all unmarried men are bachelors.

    Clearly if a is identical with b, then we can replace the symbol "a in any statement with the symbol b, whilst preserving the truth value of the statement. For example: Socrates is an unmarried man, an unmarried man is the same as a bachelor, so Socrates is a bachelor."

    This is important because it allows us to assess the truth value of a potentially infinite number of sentences using a manageable number of steps. Leibniz had four.

    1. "a = a"

    e.g., Socrates is Socrates.

    2. If "a is b and b is c then a is c"

    e.g., All men are mortal, Socrates is a man, therefore Socrates is mortal.

    Saying "a is b is the same as saying that all a’s are b".

    SO THIS HAS

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1