Other Terms
Other Terms
Other Terms
The complexities which arise in trying to understand the notion of linguistic
reference don't end with names and indexicals. Here, we will consider two further
sorts of terms that are often thought of as referential natural kind terms and
singular definite descriptions as well as whether the notion of reference can be
productively extended even to a range of terms to which it does not intuitively apply.
But according to Putnam (1975), it would be a mistake to suppose that natural kind
terms refer via descriptive content inside the head of the competent speaker. I can
refer to such things as furze (gorse) and filberts (hazelnuts) even if the descriptive
content I associate with the expression in question is not uniquely satisfied by such
things indeed, even if the content in question is satisfied by (say) walnuts or
cashews. (This is basically the problem of ignorance and error.) Putnam made the
same basic point via a number of thought-experiments. Thus, I refer to elm trees
when I use the term elm; and I refer to beech trees when I use the term beech.
But the descriptive content I associate with these terms may well be the same
something like deciduous tree of some sort. Thus, it cannot be what is inside my
head that determines that to which I refer. Consider the famous Twin Earth
thought-experiment. Oscar and Twin Oscar refer to different kinds of substances
(H2O, XYZ) when they use the term water despite the fact that their narrow or
internal psychological states are identical, that (more specifically) the descriptive
content they associate with the term (clear, odorless, colorless liquid, that falls from
the sky and accumulates in lakes, rivers, and oceans) is the same. The moral is: the
reference of a natural kind term cannot be determined solely by what's in the head.
So, if meanings are reference-determiners, they are not in the head. (And if they are
in the head, they are not reference-determiners.)
This brings us to the Putnam/Kripke causal view of reference for natural kind terms.
It is similar to Kripke's account of nominal reference; indeed, it is more or less an
extension of that account. Reference is initially fixed at a dubbing, either by
perception or description of samples of some particular natural kind. The reference
is then to whatever has an internal structure identical to that of the samples. In the
case of water, this would be having the chemical structure H 2O. Speakers at a
dubbing are able to lend their reference to others via communicative exchanges, and
these others can then lend reference to still others. Speakers who are ignorant as to
the properties of the kind in question can nevertheless use the natural kind term to
refer to the members of the kind because underlying their uses are causal chains
stretching back to a reference-fixing.
Putnam thought that his causal account of natural kind terms could be extended
to artifactual kind terms as well. These are terms that refer to kinds of man-made
objects: pencils, clocks, telephones, and so forth. Putnam motivates his causal
account of artifactual kind terms by appealing to intuitive considerations that is,
to thought experiments. Suppose we were to discover that pencils are not artifacts,
but organisms. We would still call them pencils, and would be correct in doing so.
This shows that the reference of such expressions cannot be fixed via some
description of the form artifact the function of which is to
Perhaps. But that only shows (at most) that the description in question cannot be of
the particular form in question. Perhaps the relevant description is one of the
form: that which has such-and-such a function. There need be no mention of the
notion of an artifact per se. In fact, a descriptivist view, according to which the
reference of such terms is fixed by a function-specifying description, is intuitively
plausible. Why? Presumably, because artifacts are not individuated by anything
hidden, but rather by something transparent, i.e. their function. If function is
indeed transparent, it should not be implausible to suppose that reference is
determined by a description that specifies the function in question. Does that mean
that one must know the reference-fixing description in order to refer to the kind in
question? No. What it means is only that non-experts effectively defer to experts
who do know (and don't just theorize about) the relevant reference-fixing
descriptions. The question remains whether or not one can properly conceive of an
organism as having a function extrinsic to its own being (as in Putnam's livingpencils example). But again, one can easily modify the relevant description to
something like: that which purportedly has such-and-such a function. This would
allow for mistaken attributions of artifactuality.
(or stated or said) by means of this utterance. On Russell's view, the statement is
false as it involves the false claim that there exists a unique king of France. The
meaning of the description, on Strawson's view, is given by a rule: one to the effect
that it is to be used in cases where there is a (contextually) unique king of France to
whom one is referring by means of the term.
Keith Donnellan (1966) thought that definite descriptions were pragmatically
ambiguous in that they had two different uses, and that these two uses were relevant
to what is said, to the statement made. One of these uses, the so-called attributive
use, was captured by Russell's theory but not Strawson's; the other use, the
referential use, was captured by Strawson's theory but not by Russell's. Or so
Donnellan claimed. To see the motivations for positing this sort of ambiguity,
consider the following case. Smith is found brutally murdered and it is claimed (on
account of the heinousness of the crime) that:
20. The murderer of Smith is insane.
Suppose that the speaker has no idea who the murderer is. Then, the description is
used attributively to say something about whoever (uniquely) murdered Smith
and Russell's analysis applies. That is, the statement is true just in case there is a
unique murderer of Smith and whoever murdered Smith is insane. But now suppose
that Jones is accused of Smith's murder and that the speaker believes that Jones is
guilty. In attempting to say something about Jones, the speaker comes out with an
utterance of (20). In this case, the description is used referentially, to pick Jones out
so as to say something about him. According to Donnellan, the statement is thus true
just in case Jones is insane even if he is innocent and the actual murderer
(Robinson) is quite sane. Russell's theory, according to Donnellan, cannot
accommodate the referential use, and so is incomplete at best.
Kripke's (1977) responds to Donnellan's argument by accusing Donnellan of
mistaking pragmatic facts for semantic facts. More specifically, Kripke accuses
Donnellan of confusing speaker reference for expression reference. Kripke claimed
that the referential use of definite descriptions was both genuine and interesting, but
was not properly semantic. Thus it was not relevant to Russell's theory. According to
Kripke, the truth value of:
21. The man in the corner drinking champagne is happy tonight.
depends only on whether the man in the corner drinking champagne is happy. This
is so even if the speaker intends to refer to someone else, a man in the corner who
only appears to be drinking champagne but who is in fact drinking sparkling water.
In such a case, the speaker may say something true (or false) about the individual to
whom he intends to refer. Nevertheless, the truth-value of the sentence itself will not
depend upon the properties of the speaker's referent, but on those of the semantic
referent: on those of the description's denotation, should there be one. Thus,
according to Kripke, Russell's theory of descriptions, though perhaps not without its
problems, is not undermined by the referential use of descriptions. Although many
have accepted at least the basics of Kripke's rejoinder to Donnellan, the debate over
the referential use over whether it in fact undermines Russell's theory of
descriptions continues unabated.[19]
undeniably be the case that the man universally known as Jack is so-called because
a woman dubbed some other baby with that name. (1982, p. 301)
The causal theorist faces a dilemma here. First, she might propose that (contra what
seems to be the natural way of describing these cases) in each case a new name has
actually been introduced, i.e. Madagascar-2 and Jack-2. This would entail that
not every reference-fixing use of a name turns out to be intentional; sometimes new
names are introduced, and their reference somehow fixed, unintentionally.
Alternatively, the causal theorist can modify her view so as to allow for events
subsequent to the initial dubbing to affect what a given name refers to. Devitt (1981)
develops a version of the latter strategy by contending that a name is typically
grounded in its bearer in numerous perceptual confrontations after the initial
dubbing. As part of what grounds reference, these perceptual confrontations are
thus semantically significant and capable of effecting reference change over time.
The basic idea is that, given a sufficient number of such groundings over a sufficient
period of time, reference change may occur. Thus, Madagascar was able to shift
reference from the mainland to the island once perceptually-based groundings in the
island became established. The island was effectively dubbed Madagascar by
means of such groundings. (Note that this entails that Marco Polo was unlikely to be
the first to use the name Madagascar to refer to the island, since, although he might
have been apt to apply that name to the island, an insufficient number of groundings
would have obtained at the point when he was himself using the name.) And the man
known by all as Jack is not so-called because, years earlier, someone dubbed
another individual that name. He is so-called because numerous uses of Jack are
grounded in him.
Although the causal theory (as revised by Devitt) provides a plausible account of
nominal reference, its advocates still need to supplement their theory of reference
with a theory of meaning a theory that accounts for the fact that proper names
appear to have some sort of meaning or cognitive content. [9] On its own, the causal
theory of reference does not provide any answers to the questions of cognitive
significance that so bothered description theorists like Frege and Russell.