British Journal For The History of Philosophy Volume 22 Issue 4 2014 (Doi 10.1080 - 2F09608788.2014.962477) Boehm, Omri - Freedom and The Cogito
British Journal For The History of Philosophy Volume 22 Issue 4 2014 (Doi 10.1080 - 2F09608788.2014.962477) Boehm, Omri - Freedom and The Cogito
A RTICLE
Kierkegaard makes here two main claims. First, that Descartes views the will
as a higher faculty than the intellect. This is apt: the will in Descartess view
is free and active, whereas the intellect is passive; the will is unrestricted,
whereas the intellect is nite; and it is in virtue of the will, not the intellect,
1
Special thanks are due to Michael Della Rocca, Ulrika Carlsson, Elliot Paul, Anat Schecht-
man and Ariane Schneck.
2
Kierkegaard, Papers and Journals, 173.
2014 BSHP
FREEDOM AND THE COGITO 705
that we bear the image and likeness of God. These advantages of the will
3
vis--vis the intellect well known from the fourth Meditation indeed
make it a more promising candidate for establishing the certainty announced
in the second. The will is better suited than the intellect for answering chal-
lenges potentially imposed on the mind by an omnipotent God or a supremely
powerful evil deceiver, for example. Kierkegaards second claim is that
despite these advantages of the will, Descartes considers the intellect as the
faculty doing the work in the Cogito. And, on this point, much of the scho-
larly literature would seem to agree. Unceasing attention has been given over
the years to the study of the Cogito, but little thought has been dedicated to the
role of the will, and to the wills freedom, in establishing Descartess Archi-
medean self-assertion. And conversely: while Descartess conception of the
will and its freedom is nowadays the object of much (and yet growing) inter-
est, relatively little attention has been given to the Cogito as a relevant case in
point one that could illuminate Descartess account of the will.4
One reason for this tendency may have to do with Descartess choice of
words. Emphasis on think in I am thinking therefore I am and its sister
formulations may create the impression that he views the intellect as the cer-
tainty-generating faculty the meditator does not assert Im willing there-
fore I am, Im desiring, I exist or anything of the sort. Moreover, later in
the text the meditator concludes, sum res cogitans (AT 7:27; CSMII:18).
Thought, this alone is inseparable from me, he asserts. Only thought, it
may appear insofar as the Cogito is concerned, thought qua intellectual
representation of ideas has survived the programme of doubt.5
Yet, in an important passage composed late in his career Descartes writes
that the virtuous person knows that nothing truly belongs to him but his
freedom (AT 11:446f; CSMI:384). This statement is telling, I shall argue,
among other reasons because it may illuminate the fundamental role that
freedom has to play in establishing the Cogito. If nothing truly belongs to
us but freedom, it may be that Descartes, ultimately, is committed to the
view that we know ourselves by knowing our freedom. As we will see,
that the meditators will is free is the rst certainty asserted in the Cartesian
philosophy. The meditators assertion sum follows from insofar as only
freedom truly belongs to us, it consists in the assertion of freedom.
The paper is divided into two parts. In the rst, before directly tackling the
Cogito, I offer a sketch of the relation, in Descartess thought, between ethics
and theoretical philosophy. I argue that Descartes is what we may call an
intrinsic-Stoical thinker rather than an instrumental-Baconian thinker.6
3
AT 7:57; CSMII:40. All references are taken from Descartes, Oeuvres de Descartes (AT 112).
Unless otherwise noted, translations are from Descartes, The Philosophical Writings of Des-
cartes (CSMI/II), and Descartes, The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (CSMKIII).
4
I interact with some important exceptions below.
5
Cf. Cottingham, Cartesian Reections, 99f.
6
Signicant contributions have been made recently to reading Descartes in this vein, including
works by Davies, Descartes; Alanen, Descartes Concept of Mind; Brown, Descartes and the
706 OMRI BOEHM
That is, he holds that the value of theoretical thinking consists in the happi-
ness afforded by contemplation itself, not by its technological fruits not (as
sometimes is assumed) by the mastery of nature.7 On Descartess account,
exercising virtue, which he identies as the highest good, is a necessary and
sufcient condition of happiness absolute containment of mind, complete
tranquillity. Virtue is the foundation of human happiness because it perfects
our highest faculty, the will; and because it is the only good that depends
exclusively on us other goods depend on natures contingent favour
(AT 4:264; CSMK:257). The self-contained tranquillity afforded by virtue
consists in the experience of gnrosit: ones knowledge, mentioned
above, that nothing truly belongs to him but his freedom, combined with
a feeling of a rm and constant resolution to use it [his freedom] well
(AT 11:445f; CSMI:384). Now, Descartes also holds that no conduct is
exclusively within our control but the conduct of our thinking and this
too only to the extent that our thoughts depend on us alone (that they are
not imposed on our mind, say, by an evil deceiver). Therefore, ensuring
the freedom of thought is for Descartes the primary ground of tranquillity
of mind. Theoretical contemplation, done virtuously, is in itself the principal
ground of human happiness. The project carried out in the Meditations
deserves to be studied in this light. Here, I consider the case of the Cogito.
Perhaps the pressing question surrounding the Cogito concerns the
grounding relation between the programme of doubt, specically its
radical stage, and the certainty asserted by the meditator. Existing literature
often fails to address this question accounts of the Cogito tend to render the
rst Meditations programme of doubt unnecessary to the certainty asserted
in the second.8 One way to explain this grounding relation, we will see, is to
do better justice to the role Descartes assigns to freedom. In a well-known
letter to Mesland, he writes that one can hold back from a clearly perceived
truth if he considers it a good thing to demonstrate the freedom of the will
Passionate Mind; Jones, The Good Life in the Scientic Revolution; Shapiro, Turn My Will in
Completely the Opposite Direction, 2139, as well as her Descartes Ethics, 44563;
Naaman-Zauderer, Descartes Deontological Turn.
7
The term Stoic is to be understood broadly. Descartess position has clear similarities to
Stoicism, but also profound differences. Descartes denies the Stoics eudaimonistic denition
of happiness as the highest good. He identies virtue as the highest good, and insists that
despite the fact that it is necessary and sufcient for happiness, it is not identical with it. More-
over, Descartes refuses the Stoics hostility to the passions. He names their hostility barbaric,
and considers gnrosit, a passion, as the key to all the virtues. See Cassirer, Descartes:
LehrePersnlichkeitWirkung, 10412 and Rutherford, On the Happy Life, 17797.
8
Margaret Wilsons nave account, for example, explains the certainty of sum as derived from
the certainty of cogito leaving the will irrelevant (see Wilson, Descartes, 5070; the term
nave is Wilsons). Other strategies, in which the meditators existence is assumed as a
formal condition of the thought I am deceived about x, or of I doubt that x (cf. Frankfurt,
Demons, Dreamers and Madmen, 136) underplay doubt as a programme. One important
exception is Broughtons Descartess Method of Doubt, 10843; another contribution here,
as of yet unpublished, is Paul, The Meditators Cogito.
FREEDOM AND THE COGITO 707
by so doing (AT 4:173f.; CSMK:244f.). Indeed this is just what the medi-
tator does at the nal stage of doubt, when confronting the thought of the evil
deceiver. Here lies the grounding relation between doubt and the Cogitos
self-afrmation: by resolving to doubt everything he has a good reason to
doubt, and managing to achieve such doubt, the meditator comes to experi-
ence gnrosit he becomes aware that his will is free and that nothing
truly belongs to him but this freedom. On the basis of such experience
the self-knowledge afforded by determining that he is free the meditator
comes to assert, sum.9
9
Marion reads gnrosit as the last formulation of the Cogito the ethical counterpart of the
theoretical Cogito (Marion, Gnrosit et phnomnologie, 517). I will claim that it is not
an ethical counterpart but the ground of theoretical certainty itself.
10
Spinoza, Ethics, pt. 4 prop. 26.
11
Wilson, Spinozas Theory of Knowledge, 90.
708 OMRI BOEHM
always try to master [vaincre] myself rather than fortune, and to change my
desires rather than the order of the world; and in general, to accustom
myself to believe that there can be nothing entirely in our power but our
thoughts.
(AT 6:25f.; CSMI:123)
There is a tension between this maxim and the mastery manifesto quoted
above. Consider Descartess words master myself rather than fortune,
change my desire rather than the order of the world: they dismiss what
had been promised in the ideal of mastery; deny that mastery of nature is
something worth striving for. There are, then, in Descartes two competing
ethical strands:
(a) Mastery of nature as the value of theoretical inquiry. I will refer to this
strand of thought as the instrumental ethos.
(b) Mastery of the will rather than the nature (the order of the world) as
the key for ethics. I will refer to this strand of thought as a Stoic ethos,
and will later defend the terminology intrinsic.
that it is the only good, among those we can possess, which depends
entirely on us hence, it is the only good that does not depend on
natures contingent favour (AT 4:276; CSMK:261); and second, on the
fact that virtue consists in perfecting our greatest faculty, the will, whose
proper use renders us in a certain way like God by making us masters of our-
selves (AT 6:446; CSMI:384). Free will is in itself the noblest thing we can
have, Descartes says, since it makes us in a way equal to God and seems to
exempt us from being his subjects; and so its correct use is the greatest of all
the goods we possess (AT 5:85; CSMK 326).
The mark of the state of mind of a virtuous person is the experience of
gnrosit ones knowledge, rst, that nothing truly belongs to him but
[the] freedom to dispose his volitions that he ought to be praised or
blamed for no other reason than his using this freedom well or badly; and
second, that there is within him a rm and constant resolution to use it [his
freedom] well that is, never to lack the will to undertake and carry out what-
ever he judges to be best (AT 11:446f; CSMI:384). Gnrosit is according to
Descartes a species of the passion esteem [estime], an inclination that the
soul has to represent to itself the value of the thing that is esteemed (AT
11:443f.; CSMI:383); and esteem he understands as a type of the feeling
of wonder [admiration], a sudden surprise of the soul which brings it to
consider with attention the objects that seem to it unusual and extraordinary
(AT 11:380; CSMI:353). Gnrosit, then, is the feeling of awe we experience
when surprisedly confronted with the value of ourselves. We experience gn-
rosit when (in fact, if) we come to discover that nothing truly belongs to
us but our freedom, which is unrestricted and in some sense godlike; when
we feel we have resolved to use it as well as we can.13
Clearly, Descartes is not orbiting an instrumental, Baconian ethos. Den-
ing the highest good in terms of virtue and gnrosit, in terms of mastering
the will rather than nature, he reiterates the Stoic ethos preluded in the
morales third maxim. While theres nothing surprising or contentious
about this observation the position Descartes takes in his ethical writings
is clear it is surprising when his Baconian, modern approach is taken
into view. Cottingham suggests that this stoical tendency in Descartess
ethical (and thus later) writings shows a genuine development even a
change of mind occurring after the death of his child, Francine. Reection
on the extent to which human life must remain hostage to the unavoidability
of pain and loss, Cottingham writes, led Descartes to retreat into a broadly
Stoical kind of resignation, and identify the domain of the ethical with the
only sphere wholly and entirely within our control.14 This goes in the
13
Cf. Cassirer, Descartes: LehrePersnlichkeitWirkung, 93102; Shapiro, Cartesian
Generosity, 24975. For an extremely important accounts of the sense in which our will is
godlike, see Naaman-Zauderer, Descartess Ontological Turn, 1448 and Ragland Alterna-
tive Possibilities in Descartess Fourth Meditation, 379400.
14
Cottingham, Philosophy and the Good Life, 102.
710 OMRI BOEHM
right direction insofar as it does not mitigate the discrepancy between Des-
cartess Stoic ethos and his instrumental approach, but two points call for
attention. First, what sphere or domain is said here to be entirely within
our control? Is it indeed entirely within our control? Second, Descartess
retreat to Stoical resignation is not the result of a late change of mind.
As we have seen, the Stoic ethos has been competing with the instrumental
ethos in Descartes all along in fact, as Cottingham himself observes earlier
in the same essay, the treatment of virtue and gnrosit in the ethical writ-
ings only echoes the position Descartes had taken in the third maxim of the
morale.
But then, how does the Stoic ethos illuminate Descartess theoretical phil-
osophy? To the extent that the project of pure enquiry the project of
achieving truth and certainty gains value by enabling the mastery of
nature, it ultimately loses its signicance. For according to Cartesian
ethics the highest good, and human happiness, are achieved by mastering
the will rather than nature. How, then, is the value of theoretical thinking
understood in light of the Stoic ethos?
The Discourse provides a beginning of an answer. Immediately following
the third maxim of the morale, Descartes puts forward another, concluding
maxim: [T]o devote the whole of life to the cultivation of reason, and pro-
gress, as far as I will be able to, in the knowledge of the truth, according to
the method that I had given myself (AT 6:27f.; CSMI:124). Whether this
should count as a fourth maxim is controversial Descartes introduces the
morale saying he will mention just three or four maxims, and he formulates
this maxim in a rather personal tone but theres no need to enter a debate
about it here. Signicant for our purposes is that the maxim he here formu-
lates can be deduced from the one preceding it. The pledge to dedicate my
life to the cultivation of reason and to knowing the truth follows from the
morales third maxim to limit my will to what depends on me, master
the will rather than nature if an intermediate premise is assumed,
namely that mastery of the will, and limiting my desire to what depends
on me, is rst and foremost possible in the cultivation of reason and the
pursuit of truth. Descartes makes this assumption, in the transition from
the third maxim to the one following it, and he explicitly connects it to an
ancient, intrinsic ethos. In the realization that nothing lies entirely in our
power but our thoughts, he writes, lies the secret of those philosophers
who in earlier times were able to escape from the dominion of fortune
and, despite suffering and poverty, rival the gods in happiness, Descartes
writes:
Through constant reection upon the limits prescribed for them by nature,
they became perfectly convinced that nothing was in their power but their
thoughts, and this alone was sufcient to prevent them from being attracted
to other things. This mastery over their thoughts was so absolute that they
had reason to count themselves richer, more powerful, freer and happier
FREEDOM AND THE COGITO 711
than other men who, because they lack this philosophy, never achieve such
mastery however favoured by nature and fortune they may be.
(AT 6:27; CSMI:124)
No wonder, then, that the morale concludes with a maxim prescribing the
cultivation of reason. The pursuit of the truth expressed in this maxim is
indeed Descartess personal choice but, on his premises, all those who seek hap-
piness should choose the same. From this perspective, theoretical contemplation
is valued for its own sake not for its consequences.15 In line with this intrinsic
ethos, Descartes writes in the Rules that theoretical contemplation is practically
the only happiness in this life that is complete and untroubled by pain (AT
10:361; CSMI:10). The Discourse repeats this almost to the word: Since begin-
ning to use this method [devoting life to truth], Descartes writes, I have felt
such extreme contentment that I did not think one could enjoy any sweeter
or purer one in this life (AT 6:27; CSMI: 124). It is sometimes overlooked
that the Meditations shows no less of an intrinsic tendency. Having proved
Gods existence in the third Meditation, the meditator says, echoing the
words of the Rules and the Discourse,
I would like to pause here and spend more time in the contemplation of God;
to reect on his attributes, and to gaze with wonder and adoration on the
beauty of his immense light, so far as the eye of my darkened intellect can
bear it. For just as we believe through faith that the supreme happiness of
the next life consists solely in the contemplation of the divine majesty, so
experience tells us that this same contemplation, albeit much less perfect,
enables us to know the greatest joy of which we are capable in this life.
(AT 7:52; CSMII:36)
15
This, I take it, is the source of Naaman-Zauderers ingenious interpretation of this philos-
ophy as a deontology.
712 OMRI BOEHM
and even if it is not in my power to know any truth, I shall at least do what is in my
power, that is, resolutely guard against assenting to any falsehoods, so that [atque
ita; Cest pourquoi] the deceiver, however powerful and cunning he may be, will
be unable to impose [imponere; imposer] on me in the slightest degree.
(AT 7:23; CSMII:15)16
Motivating the programme of doubt then is not only and not merely the
problem of deception as an epistemological worry. At stake is the freedom
of the will the meditator aspires to ensure that his assent to ideas indeed
is entirely within his control, as required by Descartess intrinsic ethics.
As we will see, fullling this aspiration is the ground of the Cogito.
16
See de Araujos discussion in Scepticism, Freedom and Autonomy, 89f.
FREEDOM AND THE COGITO 713
II
in a manner that everybody can easily grasp, the argument by which I claim to
prove that there is nothing at all more evident and certain than the existence of
God and of the human soul. But I did not dare to try to do so, since I would
have had to explain at length the strongest arguments of the sceptics to show
that there is no material thing of whose existence one can be certain I would
have shown that a man who thus doubts everything material cannot for all that
have any doubt about his own existence.
(AT 1:353; CSMK:55)
One peculiarity about Descartess statement is the order in which things are
presented. He speaks of nothing being more certain than the existence of
God and of the human soul perhaps this is just a slip of the tongue, but
one would expect him to mention the human soul rst. We will consider
below the sense in which this is not just a slip; but for the moment the obser-
vation can be put aside.
Descartess words in the letter make two things clear. First, the
Cogitos certainty does not merely survive doubt if confronted with it.
The Cogito is not established in spite of doubt but, somehow, by it.
Otherwise, the argument presented in the Discourse would not suffer
from the great defect that it does. Indeed, this is just whats innovative
about Descartess manoeuvre: other philosophers had tried to answer
scepticism before him; Descartes promises to turn scepticism on its
head, introduce the deceiver, to use doubt in establishing Archimedean
certainty.17 The eventual result of this doubt, Descartes writes in the
Synopsis of the Meditations, is to make it impossible for us to have
any further doubts about what we subsequently discover to be true
(AT 7:12; CSMII:9; my emphases). In fact, doubt is so signicant as
the ground of certainty that at least on one occasion Descartes refers to
doubt, not to the Cogito, as the Archimedean origin itself. In The
Search for Truth he has Eudoxus, a Cartesian philosopher, instruct Poly-
ander, the innocent pupil of common sense:
just give me your attention and I will conduct you further than you think.
For from this universal doubt, as from a xed and immovable point, I
propose to derive the knowledge of God, of yourself, and of everything
in the universe.
(AT 10:514f.; CSMII 409)
17
Cf. Broughton, Descartess Method of Doubt, esp. 97174.
714 OMRI BOEHM
Second, Descartess words to Silhon imply that not just any form of doubt is
sufcient. To achieve certainty, it is necessary to achieve full doubt. This is
the step Descartes did not dare to try in the Discourse: he provided the
argument against the veracity of the senses, as well as the dream argument,
but not the evil deceiver hypothesis. In short, the Cogitos certainty is
grounded in the programme of doubt, of which the last radical phase, doubt-
ing such transparent truths as contained in arithmetic, geometry and other
subjects of this kind, is an indispensible component. To the extent that the
challenge of understanding the Cogito consists in understanding how Des-
cartes puts scepticism on its head, the challenge consists in understanding
this grounding relation.18
The prevalent literature on the Cogito tends to overlook this challenge
available accounts often render the programme of doubt unnecessary, if not
atly irrelevant, to the certainty asserted in the second Meditation. Janet
Broughtons account has contributed signicantly to our understanding of
doubts relation to certainty, but it cannot explain Descartess insistence that
without going through doubts last radical phase, the Cogito suffers from a
great defect; and it licenses merely a conditional conclusion of the Cogito
not I exist but if I use a consideration to doubt, I exist.19 Fruitful as
they may be,20 conditional reconstructions of the Cogito do not do much
justice to Descartess bolder, Archimedean aspirations. (It is not clear, for
example, to what extent hypothetical Cartesianism provides an answer to a
sceptic.) The task of explaining the Cogito seems to consist in showing
how, by achieving radical doubt, the meditator achieves an assertoric sum.
3. In fact, Descartes says something that may illuminate this grounding
relation. In a well-known passage from his 1645 letter to Mesland a text
thats normally mentioned in connection with Descartess theory of
freedom, not the Cogito Descartes writes:
18
One plausible approach is to assume that given the Cogitos sheer basicness, it is not
grounded at all: doubt at most removes the misconceptions that dim the Cogitos self-evi-
dence. (Arguably, Descartes ontological argument proceeds similarly.) I argue in the fol-
lowing that doubt grounds the Cogito in a more fundamental way: by removing
misconceptions, it reveals to us our freedom. It is this truth that is then self-evident.
19
Broughton, Descartess Method of Doubt, 11420.
20
See also Frankfurts reductio.
FREEDOM AND THE COGITO 715
21
Cassirer, LehrePersnlichkeitWirkung, 92 (translation mine).
22
Ibid.
23
For an excellent discussion of Descartess proof of freedom through doubt see Shapiros
Turn My Will in Completely the Opposite Direction. As Shapiro observes, radical doubt
provides the context in which the meditator arrives at the certainty he seeks (27).
24
Compare Shapiros discussion in Turn My Will in Completely the Opposite Direction (27).
In a footnote, Shapiro points out that if the meditator is actually negating the transparent
ideas in question in the rst Meditation, she isof mixed minds about whether this move
exemplies the sort of case described in the 1645 letter to Mesland. Given that the meditator
is impelled to afrm the cogito, shouldnt he too afrm spontaneously what the Fifth Medita-
tion will mark as eternal truths?
If, however, as I argue below, the cogito is achieved through freedom, which is itself
achieved by doubting the transparent ideas of the rst Meditation, there is no problem equat-
ing the rst Meditations procedure with described in the 1645 letter to Mesland.
716 OMRI BOEHM
there is no need for me to be inclined both ways; on the contrary, the more I
incline in one direction either because I clearly understand that reasons of
truth and goodness point that way, or because of a divinely produced disposi-
tion of my inmost thoughts the freer is my choice.
(AT 7:57;CSMII:39f.)
That there is freedom in our will, and that we have power in many cases to give or
withhold our assent at will, is so evident that it must be counted among the rst
and most common notions that are innate in us. This was obvious earlier on when,
in our attempt to doubt everything, we went so far as to make the supposition of
some supremely powerful author of our being who was attempting to deceive us
25
Shapiro observes here:Descartes takes Gassendi to have done exactly what the meditator
purports to do at the end of the First Meditation: deny self-evident propositions. Through
just this sort of denial we come to have the kind of experience of our own freedom. (Turn
My Will in Completely the Other Direction, 35)
26
I would not enter here the extensive literature on the (in)compatibilism debate. For compre-
hensive discussions, see Kenny, Descartes on the Will, 131; Chappell, Descartes Compa-
tibilism, 17790. Ragland, Was Descartes a Libertarian?, 5790 as well as his Descartes on
the Principle of Alternative Possibilities, 37794.
FREEDOM AND THE COGITO 717
in every possible way. For in spite of this supposition, the freedom which we
experienced within us was nonetheless so great as to enable us to abstain from
believing whatever was not quite certain or fully examined. And what we saw
to be beyond doubt during the period of that supposition is as self-evident and
as transparently clear as anything can be.
(AT 8A:19f.; CSMI:205f.; emphases added)
The claim that the transition from doubt to freedom was obvious earlier on
is a reference to 6. Appearing after 15, which elaborate the method of
doubt and culminate with the hypothesis of the evil deceiver, and before
7, which asserts the meditators existence, 6 asserts: we have free
will, enabling us to withhold our assent in doubtful matters and hence
avoid error (AT 8A:6; CSMI 194). That we are free, then, is, according
to the Principles the rst certainty asserted in the Cartesian philosophy a
certainty that we experience in the midst of doubt. Using the lower grade
of freedom doubt the meditator achieved a state of the higher grade of
freedom assent to an idea namely, he cannot but afrm freedom itself.
Thus, despite the fact that the higher degree of freedom is a state of determi-
nation rather than choice, the meditator himself is the ground of this deter-
mination. If he had not used his will appropriately, he would not have
achieved it.
4. Descartes is not explicit about this, but the absolutely clear experience
of freedom achieved through doubt may be taken for the mode by which the
meditator becomes aware and certain of his own existence.27 To see this, it is
important rst to consider Descartess use of the term experience in this
context he consistently employs that term (experimenter; experior) and
no other to characterize the mode in which we are conscious of our
freedom.28 This term does not stand for sense, imagine or any of the
other technical terms on Descartess standard list of conscious mental
states; it stands rather for what Descartes denes as a passion, in the sense
that term is used in the Passions of the Soul. (The fact that Descartes
speaks interchangeably of experiencing and feeling freedom, e.g. in the cor-
respondence with Elisabeth, is strong evidence of this.)29 Thus, when
27
For a different approach, see Christodous recent confrontation with Kants criticism of the
Cogito (Self, Freedom, and Reason, 3975.) While I agree with Christodous claim that
drawing on freedom may effectively answer Kants objections to the Cogito, I believe this
answer has to draw on Kants analysis of respect as a pure feeling of freedom by
analogy to Descartes feeling of gnrosit. I interact with the Kantian position (and Christo-
dous reconstruction) in (Omitted.)
28
Other than the passage quoted above from the Principles (the freedom which we experi-
enced ), see Descartess words in the fourth Meditation: It is only the will, or freedom
of choice, which I experience within me to be so great (AT VII:57); as well as in the Prin-
ciples: we nonetheless experience within us the kind of freedom (AT VIIIA:6;CSMI:
194) and the correspondence with Elisabeth: the independence which we experience and
feel in ourselves (AT IV:332;CSMK:277).
29
Cf. also Shapiro, Turn My Will in Completely the Opposite Direction, 30.
718 OMRI BOEHM
30
It is important to recall that on Descartess denition passions are, strictly speaking, caused
by the body. One might therefore think that a passion (like gnrosit) is ill suited to ground
anything from the disembodied moment of radical doubt. However, gnrosit is in fact the
only passion that is not generated by a perception of the body; it is caused rather by a percep-
tion of the wills freedom, which is not bodily. Moreover, while in our day a disembodied
passion may sound like an oxymoron, this notion had signicant technical relevance in the
Middle Ages. Both Thomas and Ockham employ notions of passions of the will. Especially
the latter is clear about the existence of non-bodily emotions, caused by the rational soul. (For
a comprehensive discussion, see Perler, Can We Control Our Emotions?).
31
Cf. Schiffer, Descartes on his Essence, 2143; and Williams, Descartes, 10210.
32
The language Descartes uses in the sixth Meditation is in fact closer to the language used in
the denition of gnrosit, replacing the second Meditations haec sola a me divelli nequit
(Elle seule ne peut tre dtache de moi) by nihil plane aliud ad naturam meam pertinere (il
appartienne ncessairement aucune autre chose sinon que). The denition of gnrosit
uses rien qui vritablement lui appartienne que
FREEDOM AND THE COGITO 719
freedom I come to know what essentially I am. Using strong terms such as
know (connat) and truly (vritablement), the denition of gnrosit
denes not merely what gnrosit is but what we are. In this light, the
knowledge that we are free achieved through radical doubt knowledge
that is transparent and clear as anything can be just is knowledge of our-
selves. By making us aware as generous subjects, radical doubt demonstrates
that we exist. In this sense, radical doubt can be viewed as the ground of the
Cogito.33
This analysis brings out an intriguing tension between the Passions
account of what we are and Descartess doctrine, as asserted in the Medita-
tions and in numerous additional texts, that we are essentially thinking
beings. If only freedom truly belongs to us, it is not the case that only
thoughts (as ideas) are inseparable. Indeed, the two accounts are not atly
contradictory, for even though many types of thoughts (having ideas,
sensing and imagining) are not free acts of will, some types of thought
(judging) are. Since the will is a type of thought, in other words, you con-
ceive yourself as a thinking being qua thinking yourselves as a willing
being34 (to that extent, theres no tension between the two accounts).
However, since not all thoughts are free, there is a tension: one is not essen-
tially free in virtue of being essentially (intellectually interpreted) thinking. I
will not speculate here about whether, or how, Descartess position changed
in his later writings, but it is worthy of notice that thoughts simpliciter do not
seem, strictly speaking, completely inseparable from us as the Meditations
suggests. While all ideas, including those implemented by an omnipotent
God or a supremely powerful evil deceiver, are our thoughts (metaphysically
depending on our mind), they are separable from us in the sense that they do
not depend on us exclusively; they are conditioned by a cause outside us.
There is, however, one type of thoughts that are inseparable from us in
any sense of that term, namely judgement. If a deceiver manipulates my jud-
gement, it is not free and in this sense it is not a judgement at all. But if my
judgement is free and this is something that radical doubt, as suggested,
establishes it is inseparable from me in every possible sense. Because Des-
cartes is in search of the one thing absolutely inseparable from us (the sixth
Meditation uses nihil plane), it would not be inappropriate for him ultimately
to conclude, as he does when dening gnrosit, that this is freedom and
hence judgement alone. One author who has recognized this tendency in
33
More specically, the meditator is entitled to experiencing himself as a generous subject
because he is aware not just of his freedom, but of the resolution to use this freedom well:
the undertaking of a programme of doubt in the rst place, the use of good reasons in gener-
ating doubt and the stubborn insistence to persist in doubt are expressions of this resolve. To
be sure, the meditator is not strictly speaking entitled to metaphysical knowledge of the struc-
ture of the will or the meaning of freedom. But the awareness he here achieves is the bit of
cognition that will be cashed out in terms of such knowledge later in the Meditations.
34
Cf. Principles I. 53 (AT 8a:25).
720 OMRI BOEHM
[The nal ethical philosophy of Descartes] completes, more clearly than the
earlier writings do, the turn from Intellectualism to Voluntarism which is
appropriate to the Cartesian system. The centre of gravity of the I lies, as
the ethical writings emphasize, not in thought but in will: for this is the
only thing that is ours and inseparable from us.35
Deborah Brown, analysing the Cartesian subject from the embodied biologi-
cal position of the sixth Meditation and the Passions rather than the epis-
temological perspective of the second Meditation, goes in a similar
direction, observing that whereas the meditator knows herself as a res cogi-
tans the moral sage recognizes herself as res volans:
The Passions carries the reader to the conclusion that what is known indubi-
tably in the moral domain is the essential freedom of ones own will This is
the crowning achievement of the treatise, just as the discovery of the intellec-
tual nature of the soul is a pivotal moment in the Meditations.36
As we have seen, there is a current in Descartes suggesting that also the dis-
embodied thinking subject considered from the theoretical epistemological
perspective is essentially a willing subject. Freedom, not only in the moral
but also in the theoretical domain, is the rst indubitable discovery, ground-
ing the philosophers assertion of his existence. The res cogitans is a res
cogitans not qua an intellectual thing but qua res volans.
5. Importantly, the same current does work in the Meditations as well.
There, too, radical doubt leads the meditator to experience freedom and
in experiencing freedom the meditator experiences himself. This becomes
clear once Descartess account of innity, freedom and self-knowledge, as
elaborated in the third and fourth Meditations, is brought to bear on the
second Meditation. In the following third Meditation passage, the meditator
says,
The fact that God created me is a very strong basis for believing that I am
somehow made in his image and likeness, and that I perceive this likeness,
which includes the idea of God, by the same faculty which enables me to per-
ceive myself [a me percipior per eandem facultatem, per quam ego ipse a me
percipior].
(AT 7:51f; CSMII:35)
The claim that we come to posses the idea of the innite by perceiving it is
reiterated, and the way in which we perceive that idea before perceiving our-
selves is illuminated somewhat further. We perceive our likeness to God, the
innite, by the same faculty with which we perceive ourselves. Of course,
one may still want to know in what this perception of ourselves and of the
innite consists; what is it that we perceive when perceiving the innite
and ourselves. And, insofar as the common interpretation of Descartes
goes e.g. when attributing to him the view that our mind is immediately
known, or transparent to us, through representation of ideas one might
expect that the faculty enabling us to know ourselves is the intellect. But
in fact already on the account offered in the Meditations, the faculty we
37
Schechtman, Descartess Argument for the Existence of the Idea of an Innite Being, 487
517.
722 OMRI BOEHM
experience when perceiving ourselves is not the intellect but the will; and
what we experience in this moment is freedom:
Descartes denes here freedom as the feeling that is, a passion that we
are not determined by any external force. He is referring to the experience of
freedom gnrosit. Just this experience of self-esteem is achieved by the
meditator, discovering his own worth, in the transition from doubt to cer-
tainty: let him deceive me as much as he can, the meditator announces
of the supremely powerful deceiver; he will never bring it about that I am
nothing so long as I think that I am something (AT 7:25; CSMII:17).
To bring the Meditations, the Principles and the Passions together, there is
a sense in which we perceive the innite, God, before perceiving ourselves.
Moreover, we perceive both the innite and ourselves by the same faculty.
This faculty is the will, not the intellect; and the content of that perception
is freedom, consisting in the experience of gnrosit. That experience
grounds our knowledge that nothing truly belongs to us but our freedom;
and that we are not determined by any external force, be it of an omnipotent
God or a supremely powerful evil deceiver. This transparently clear experi-
ence of freedom of ourselves does not merely survive the programme of
doubt; it is generated by it. For insofar as nothing truly belongs to us but
freedom, the meditators assertion I am, I exist consists in the assertion of
freedom.
BIBLIOGRAPHY