0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes) 438 views268 pagesWerner Heisenberg Physics and Beyond Encounters and Conversations
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
PHYSICS AND
BEYOND
PHYSICS AND BEYOND
WERNER HEISENBERG
HARPER
& ROWPHYSICS AND BEYOND
Encounters and ConversationsIl
Iv
VI
Vil
VIIL
IX
XIL
XII
XIV
XV
XVI
XVIL
WORLD PERSPECTIVES
Volumes already published
APPROACHES To Gop Jacques Maritain
ACCENT ON Form Lancelot Law Whyte
Score or Tota ARcHITECTURE Walter Gropius
Recovery oF Farr Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan
Wor tp INpIvIsIBLE Konrad Adenauer
Society AND KNOWLEDGE V. Gordon Childe
‘Tur TRANSFORMATIONS OF MaN Lewis Mumford
MAN AND MATERIALISM Fred Hoyle
‘Tue Art oF Lovinc Erich Fromm
Dynamics oF Farr Paul Tillich
MArrer, Mino AND MAN Edmund W. Sinnott
MysticisM: CHRISTIAN AND Buppitist
Daisetz Teitaro Suzuki
Man's Western Quest Denis de Rougemont
AMERICAN HUMANISM Howard Mumford Jones
‘Tue MeetiNc or Love aNp KNOWLEDGE
Martin C. D'Arcy, S.J.
Richt Lanps AND Poor Gunnar Myrdal
HinbutsM: ITs MEANING FoR THE LIBERATION
OF THE SPIRIT Swami Nikhilananda
Can Propte LEARN To LEARN? Brock Chisholm
Prysics ND PHILosoPHy Werner Heisenberg
Arr ano REALITY Joyce Cary
SicMuND Freup’s Mission Erich Fromm
Mirace or Heacta René Dubos
Issues oF FREEDOM Herbert J. Muller
HUMANISM Moses Hadas
Lire: Its DIMENSIONS AND Its Bounps
Robert M. MaclverXXVI
XXVII
XXVIII
XXIX
XXX
XXXI
XXXIL
XXXII
XXXIV
XXXV
XXXVI
XXXVII
XXXVI
XXXIX
XL
XLI
XLIL
Ciattece or Psycuicat Researcu Gardner Murphy
ALrrep NorTH WHITEHEAD: His REFLECTIONS
ON MAN AND NATURE Ruth Nanda Anshen
TE AcE or NATIONALISM Hans Kohn
Voices of MAN Mario Pei
New Patus in Brotocy Adolf Portmann
Myru ano Reauity Mircea Eliade
History as ArT AND As SciENcE _H. Stuart Hughes
REALIsM IN Our TIME Georg Lukacs
‘Tue MEAnine or THE TWENTIETH CENTURY
Kenneth E, Boulding
On Economic KNowLencE Adolph Lowe
Catan Reporn Wilfrid Mellers
‘TuroucH THE VANisHING Pont
Marshall McLuhan and Harley Parker
‘Tue Revotution or Hore Erich Fromm
EMercENcy Exit Ignazio Silone
Manxis AND THE ExIstentiatists Raymond Aron
PrystcaL CONTROL OF THE MIND.
José M. R. Delgado, M.D.
Priysics AND BEYOND Werner HeisenbergBOARD OF EDITORS
of
WORLD PERSPECTIVES
Lorp KENNETH CLARK
RicHarp CourANT
‘WERNER HEISENBERG
Ivan ILLicH
Konrap Lorenz
JosepH NEEDHAM
LI. Ras
SARVEPALLI RADHAKRISHNAN
Karu Rauner, S.J.
ALEXANDER SACHS
C.N. YANGWORLD PERSPECTIVES Volume Forty-two
Planned and Edited by RUTH NANDA ANSHEN
PHYSICS AND
BEYOND
ENCOUNTERS AND CONVERSATIONS
WERNER HEISENBERG
Translated from the German by Arnold J. Pomerans
#.
1817
HARPER & ROW, PUBLISHERS
NEW YORK, EVANSTON, AND LONDONPHYSICS AND BEYOND: ENCOUNTERS AND CONVERSATIONS. Copyright © 1971
by Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc. All rights reserved. Printed in the United
States of America, No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any
manner whatsoever without written permission except in the case of brief
quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. For information address
Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc., 49 East ggrd Street, New York, N.Y. 10016.
Published simultaneously in Canada by Fitzhenry & Whiteside Limited,
Toronto.
FIRST EDITION
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOG CARD NUMBER: 78-95963%
oO Rw
Cowra
Contents
Wortp Perspectives—What This Series Means ix
—Ruth Nanda Anshen
Preface xvii
First Encounter with the Atomic Concept (1919-1920) 1
‘The Decision to Study Physics (1920) 15
“Understanding” in Modern Physics (1920-1922) 27
Lessons in Politics and History (1922-1924) 43
Quantum Mechanics and a Talk with Einstein
(1925-1926) 58
Fresh Fields (1926-1927) 70
Science and Religion (1927) 82
Atomic Physics and Pragmatism (1929) 93
The Relationship between Biology, Physics and
Chemistry (1930-1932) 103
Quantum Mechanics and Kantian Philosophy
(1930-1934) 117
Discussions about Language (1933) 125
Revolution and University Life (1933) 141
Atomic Power and Elementary Particles (1935-1937) 155CONTENTS
Individual Behavior in the Face of Political
Disaster (1937-1941)
Toward a New Beginning (1941-1945)
‘The Responsibility of the Scientist (1945-1950)
Positivism, Metaphysics and Religion (1952)
Scientific and Political Disputes (1956-1957)
The Unified Field Theory (1957-1958)
Elementary Particles and Platonic Philosophy
(1961-1965)
165
1g2
205
218
230
237WORLD PERSPECTIVES
What This Series Means
It is the thesis of World Perspectives that man is in the process of
developing a new consciousness which, in spite of his apparent
spiritual and moral captivity, can eventually lift the human race
above and beyond the fear, ignorance, and isolation which beset
it today. It is to this nascent consciousness, to this concept of man
born out of a universe perceived through a fresh vision of reality,
that World Perspectives is dedicated.
Man has entered a new era of evolutionary history, one in
which rapid change is a dominant consequence. He is contending
with a fundamental change, since he has intervened in the evolu-
tionary process. He must now better appreciate this fact and then
develop the wisdom to direct the process toward his fulfillment
rather than toward his destruction. As he learns to apply his
understanding of the physical world for practical purposes, he is,
in reality, extending his innate capacity and augmenting his
ability and his need to communicate as well as his ability to
think and to create. And as a result, he is substituting a goal-
directed evolutionary process in his struggle against environ-
mental hardship for the slow, but effective, biological evolution
which produced modern man through mutation and natural
selection, By intelligent intervention in the evolutionary process
man has greatly accelerated and greatly expanded the range of
his possibilities. But he has not changed the basic fact that it
remains a trial and error process, with the danger of taking paths
that lead to sterility of mind and heart, moral apathy and
intellectual inertia; and even producing social dinosaurs unfit to
live in an evolving world.
Only those spiritual and intellectual leaders of our epoch who
have a paternity in this extension of man’s horizons are invited
to participate in this Series: those who are aware of the truth thatx ‘WORLD PERSPECTIVES
beyond the divisiveness among men there exists a primordial
unitive power since we are all bound together by a common
humanity more fundamental than any unity of dogma; those
who recognize that the centrifugal force which has scattered and
atomized mankind must be replaced by an integrating structure
and process capable of bestowing meaning and purpose on
existence; those who realize that science itself, when not in-
hibited by the limitations of its own methodology, when chas-
tened and humbled, commits man to an indeterminate range of
yet undreamed consequences that may flow from it.
Virtually all of our disciplines have relied on conceptions
which are now incompatible with the Cartesian axiom, and with
the static world view we once derived from it. For underlying the
new ideas, including those of modern physics, is a unifying order,
but it is not causality; it is purpose, and not the purpose of the
universe and of man, but the purpose in the universe and in
man. In other words, we seem to inhabit a world of dynamic
process and structure. Therefore we need a calculus of potential
ity rather than one of probability, a dialectic of polarity, one in
which unity and diversity are redefined as simultaneous and
necessary poles of the same essence.
Our situation is new. No civilization has previously had to
face the challenge of scientific specialization, and our response
must be new. Thus this Series is committed to ensure that the
spiritual and moral needs of man as a human being and the
scientific and intellectual resources at his command for life may
be brought into a productive, meaningful and creative harmony.
In a certain sense we may say that man now has regained his
former geocentric position in the universe. For a picture of the
Earth has been made available from distant space, from the
lunar desert, and the sheer isolation of the Earth has become
plain. This is as new and as powerful an idea in history as any
that has ever been born in man’s consciousness. We are all
becoming seriously concerned with our natural environment.
And this concern is not only the result of the warnings given by
biologists, ecologists and conservationists. Rather it is the result
of a deepening awareness that something new has happened, that
the planet Earth is a unique and precious place. Indeed, it may
not be a mere coincidence that this awareness should have beenWORLD PERSPECTIVES xi
born at the exact moment when man took his first step into outer
space.
This Series endeavors to point to a reality of which scientific
theory has revealed only one aspect. It is the commitment to this
reality that lends universal intent to a scientist's most original
and solitary thought. By acknowledging this frankly we shall
restore science to the great family of human aspirations by which
men hope to fulfill themselves in the world community as
thinking and sentient beings. For our problem is to discover a
principle of differentiation and yet relationship lucid enough to
justify and to purify scientific, philosophic and all other knowl-
edge, both discursive and intuitive, by accepting their interde-
pendence. This is the crisis in consciousness made articulate
through the crisis in science. This is the new awakening.
Each volume presents the thought and belief of its author and
points to the way in which religion, philosophy, art, science,
economics, politics and history may constitute that form of
human activity which takes the fullest and most precise account
of variousness, possibility, complexity and difficulty. Thus World
Perspectives endeavors to define that ecumenical power of the
mind and heart which enables man through his mysterious great-
ness to re-create his life.
This Series is committed to a re-examination of all those sides
of human endeavor which the specialist was taught to believe he
could safely leave aside. It attempts to show the structural kin-
ship between subject and object; the indwelling of the one in the
other. It interprets present and past events impinging on human
life in our growing World Age and envisages what man may yet
attain when summoned by an unbending inner necessity to the
quest of what is most exalted in him. Its purpose is to offer new
vistas in terms of world and human development while refusing
to betray the intimate correlation between universality and
individuality, dynamics and form, freedom and destiny. Each
author deals with the increasing realization that spirit and
nature are not separate and apart; that intuition and reason
must regain their importance as the means of perceiving and
fusing inner being with outer reality.
World Perspectives endeavors to show that the conception of
wholeness, unity, organism is a higher and more concrete concep-xii ‘WORLD PERSPECTIVES
tion than that of matter and energy. Thus an enlarged meaning
of life, of biology, not as it is revealed in the test tube of the
laboratory but as it is experienced within the organism of life
itself, is attempted in this Series. For the principle of life consists
in the tension which connects spirit with the realm of matter,
symbiotically joined. The element of life is dominant in the very
texture of nature, thus rendering life, biology, a transempirical
science. The laws of life have their origin beyond their mere
physical manifestations and compel us to consider their spiritual
source. In fact, the widening of the conceptual framework has
not only served to restore order within the respective branches of
knowledge, but has also disclosed analogies in man’s position
regarding the analysis and synthesis of experience in apparently
separated domains of knowledge, suggesting the possibility of an
ever more embracing objective description of the meaning of
life.
Knowledge, it is shown in these books, no longer consists in a
manipulation of man and nature as opposite forces, nor in the
reduction of data to mere statistical order, but is a means of
liberating mankind from the destructive power of fear, pointing
the way toward the goal of the rehabilitation of the human will
and the rebirth of faith and confidence in the human person.
The works published also endeavor to reveal that the cry for
patterns, systems and authorities is growing less insistent as the
desire grows stronger in both East and West for the recovery of a
dignity, integrity and self-realization which are the inalienable
rights of man who may now guide change by means of conscious
purpose in the light of rational experience.
The volumes in this Series endeavor to demonstrate that only
in a society in which awareness of the problems of science exists
can its discoveries start great waves of change in human culture,
and in such a manner that these discoveries may deepen and not
erode the sense of universal human community. The differences
in the disciplines, their epistemological exclusiveness, the variety
of historical experiences, the differences of traditions, of cultures,
of languages, of the arts, should be protected and preserved. But
the interrelationship and unity of the whole should at the same
time be accepted.
The authors of World Perspectives are of course aware that theWORLD PERSPECTIVES xiii
ultimate answers to the hopes and fears which pervade modern
society rest on the moral fibre of man, and on the wisdom and
responsibility of those who promote the course of its develop-
ment. But moral decisions cannot dispense with an insight into
the interplay of the objective elements which offer and limit the
choices made. Therefore an understanding of what the issues are,
though not a sufficient condition, is a necessary prerequisite for
directing action toward constructive solutions.
Other vital questions explored relate to problems of interna-
tional understanding as well as to problems dealing with preju-
dice and the resultant tensions and antagonisms. The growing
perception and responsibility of our World Age point to the new
reality that the individual person and the collective person
supplement and integrate each other; that the thrall of totali-
tarianism of both left and right has been shaken in the universal
desire to recapture the authority of truth and human totality.
Mankind can finally place its trust not in a proletarian authori-
tarianism, not in a secularized humanism, both of which have
betrayed the spiritual property right of history, but in a sacra-
mental brotherhood and in the unity of knowledge. This new
consciousness has created a widening of human horizons beyond
every parochialism, and a revolution in human thought com-
parable to the basic assumption, among the ancient Greeks, of
the sovereignty of reason; corresponding to the great effulgence
of the moral conscience articulated by the Hebrew prophets;
analogous to the fundamental assertions of Christianity; or to the
beginning of the new scientific era, the era of the science of
dynamics, the experimental foundations of which were laid by
Galileo in the Renaissance.
An important effort of this Series is to re-examine the contra-
dictory meanings and applications which are given today to such
terms as democracy, freedom, justice, love, peace, brotherhood
and God. The purpose of such inquiries is to clear the way for
the foundation of a genuine world history not in terms of nation
or race or culture but in terms of man in relation to God, to
himself, his fellow man and the universe, that reach beyond
immediate self-interest. For the meaning of the World Age con-
sists in respecting man’s hopes and dreams which lead to a deeper
understanding of the basic values of all peoples.xiv ‘WORLD PERSPECTIVES
World Perspectives is planned to gain insight into the mean-
ing of man, who not only is determined by history but who also
determines history. History is to be understood as concerned not
only with the life of man on this planet but as including also
such cosmic influences as interpenetrate our human world. This
generation is discovering that history does not conform to the
social optimism of modern civilization and that the organization
of human communities and the establishment of freedom and
peace are not only intellectual achievements but spiritual and
moral achievements as well, demanding a cherishing of the
wholeness of human personality, the “unmediated wholeness of
feeling and thought,” and constituting a never-ending challenge
to man, emerging from the abyss of meaninglessness and suffer-
ing, to be renewed and replenished in the totality of his life.
Justice itself, which has been “in a state of pilgrimage and
crucifixion” and now is being slowly liberated from the grip of
social and political demonologies in the East as well as in the
West, begins to question its own premises. The modern revolu-
tionary movements which have challenged the sacred institutions
of society by protesting social injustice in the name of social
justice are here examined and re-evaluated.
In the light of this, we have no choice but to admit that the un-
freedom against which freedom is measured must be retained with
it, namely, that the aspect of truth out of which the night view
appears to emerge, the darkness of our time, is as little abandon-
able as is man’s subjective advance. Thus the two sources of
man's consciousness are inseparable, not as dead but as living
and complementary, an aspect of that “principle of complemen-
tarity” through which Niels Bohr has sought to unite the quan-
tum and the wave, both of which constitute the very fabric of
life’s radiant energy.
There is in mankind today a counterforce to the sterility and
danger of a quantitative, anonymous mass culture; a new, if
sometimes imperceptible, spiritual sense of convergence toward
human and world unity on the basis of the sacredness of each
human person and respect for the plurality of cultures. There is
a growing awareness that equality may not be evaluated in mere
numerical terms but is proportionate and analogical in its real-
ity. For when equality is equated with interchangeability, indi-
viduality is negated and the human person extinguished.WORLD PERSPECTIVES xv
We stand at the brink of an age of a world in which human
life presses forward to actualize new forms. The false separation
of man and nature, of time and space, of freedom and security, is
acknowledged, and we are faced with a new vision of man in his
organic unity and of history offering a richness and diversity of
quality and majesty of scope hitherto unprecedented. In relat-
ing the accumulated wisdom of man’s spirit to the new reality of
the World Age, in articulating its thought and belief, World
Perspectives seeks to encourage a renaissance of hope in society
and of pride in man’s decision as to what his destiny will be.
World Perspectives is committed to the recognition that all
great changes are preceded by a vigorous intellectual re-evalua-
tion and reorganization. Our authors are aware that the sin of
hubris may be avoided by showing that the creative process itself
is not a free activity if by free we mean arbitrary, or unrelated to
cosmic law. For the creative process in the human mind, the
developmental process in organic nature and the basic laws of
the inorganic realm may be but varied expressions of a universal
formative process. Thus World Perspectives hopes to show that
although the present apocalyptic period is one of exceptional
tensions, there is also at work an exceptional movement toward a
compensating unity which refuses to violate the ultimate moral
power at work in the universe, that very power upon which all
human effort must at last depend. In this way we may come to
understand that there exists an inherent independence of spir-
itual and mental growth which, though conditioned by circum-
stances, is never determined by circumstances. In this way the
great plethora of human knowledge may be correlated with an
insight into the nature of human nature by being attuned to the
wide and deep range of human thought and human experience.
Incoherence is the result of the present disintegrative processes
in education. Thus the need for World Perspectives expresses
itself in the recognition that natural and man-made ecological
systems require as much study as isolated particles and elemen-
tary reactions. For there is a basic correlation of elements in
nature as in man which cannot be separated, which compose each
other and alter each other mutually. Thus we hope to widen
appropriately our conceptual framework of reference. For our
epistemological problem consists in our finding the proper bal-
ance between our lack of an all-embracing principle relevant toxvi WORLD PERSPECTIVES
our way of evaluating life and in our power to express ourselves
in a logically consistent manner.
Our Judaeo-Christian and Greco-Roman heritage, our Hellenic
tradition, has compelled us to think in exclusive categories. But
our experience challenges us to recognize a totality richer and far
more complex than the average observer could have suspected—
a totality which compels him to think in ways which the logic
of dichotomies denies. We are summoned to revise fundamentally
our ordinary ways of conceiving experience, and thus, by ex-
panding our vision and by accepting those forms of thought
which also include nonexclusive categories, the mind is then
able to grasp what it was incapable of grasping or accepting
before.
In spite of the infinite obligation of men and in spite of their
finite power, in spite of the intransigence of nationalisms, and in
spite of the homelessness of moral passions rendered ineffectual
by the scientific outlook, beneath the apparent turmoil and
upheaval of the present, and out of the transformations of this
dynamic period with the unfolding of a world-consciousness, the
purpose of World Perspectives is to help quicken the “unshaken
heart of well-rounded truth” and interpret the significant ele-
ments of the World Age now taking shape out of the core of that
undimmed continuity of the creative process which restores man
to mankind while deepening and enhancing his communion with
the universe.
RutH NANDA ANSHENPreface
Now, in what concerns these orations . . . 1
have found it impossible to remember their
exact wording. Hence I have made each orator
speak as, in my opinion, he would have done in
the circumstances, but keeping as close as I
could to the train of thought that guided his
actual speech.
—Txucyoiwes
Science is made by men, a self-evident fact that is far too often
forgotten, If it is recalled here, it is in the hope of reducing the
gap between the two cultures, between art and science. The
present book deals with the developments of atomic physics dur-
ing the past fifty years, as the author has experienced them.
Science rests on experiments; its results are attained through
talks among those who work in it and who consult one another
about their interpretation of these experiments. Such talks form
the main content of this book. Through them the author hopes
to demonstrate that science is rooted in conversations. Needless
to say, conversations cannot be reconstructed literally after sev-
eral decades. Nor is the book intended as a collection of memoirs.
Instead, the author has freely condensed and sacrificed certain
details; all he wishes to reconstruct is the broader picture. In
these conversations atomic physics does not invariably play the
most important role—far from it. Human, philosophical or po-
litical problems will crop up time and again, and the author
hopes to show that science is quite inseparable from these more
general questions.xviii PHYSICS AND BEYOND
Many of the dramatis personae are referred to by first name,
partly because they are not known to the general public, and
partly because the author’s relationship to them is best conveyed
in that way. Moreover, this should help to avoid the impression
that the author is presenting a verbatim report, true in every
detail. For that reason there has been no attempt to draw a more
precise picture of these personalities; they can, as it were, be
recognized only from their manner of speech. Careful attention,
however, has been paid to the precise atmosphere in which the
conversations took place. For in it the creative process of science
is made manifest; it helps to explain how the cooperation of
different people may culminate in scientific results of the utmost
importance. The author will be most happy, if, in this way, he
can convey even to those remote from atomic physics some idea of
the mental processes that have gone into the genesis and develop-
ment of that science, and this despite the fact that he has been
obliged to introduce some highly abstract and complex mathe-
matical relations.
And finally, by recalling these conversations, the author has
tried to pursue an even wider objective. Modern atomic physics
has thrown fresh light on basic philosophical, ethical and politi-
cal problems. Perhaps it is not too much to hope that this book
may help to draw the largest possible circle of people into this
vital discussion.1
First Encounter with the
Atomic Concept (1919-1920)
It must have been in the spring of 1920. The end of the First
World War had thrown Germany's youth into a great turmoil.
The reins of power had fallen from the hands of a deeply disillu-
sioned older generation, and the younger one drew together in
an attempt to blaze new paths, or at least to discover a new star
by which they could guide their steps in the prevailing darkness.
And so, one bright spring morning, some ten to twenty of us,
most of them younger than myself, set out on a ramble which, if I
remember correctly, took us through the hills above the western
shore of Lake Starnberg. Through gaps in the dense emerald
screen of beech we caught occasional glimpses of the lake be-
neath, and of tall mountains in the far distance. It was here that
Ihad my first conversation about that world of atoms which was
to play so important a part in my subsequent life. To explain
why a group of young nature lovers, enraptured by the glorious
spring landscape, should have engaged in such conversations in
the first place, I ought perhaps to point out that the cocoon in
which home and school protect the young in more peaceful
periods had burst open in the confusion of the times, and that,
by way of a substitute, we had discovered a new sense of freedom
and did not think twice about offering views on even such sub-
jects as called for much more basic information than any of us
possessed.
Just a few steps in front of me walked a fair, tall boy whose
parents had once asked me to help him with his homework. A2 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
year earlier, at the age of fifteen, this boy had been dragging up
ammunition for his father, who was manning a machine gun
behind the Wittelsbach Fountain. Those were the days of the
Soviet Republic in Munich. Others, including myself, had been
working as farm laborers in the Bavarian Highlands. And so a
rough life was not entirely alien to us; and we were not afraid to
form opinions on the most abstruse topics.
Our talk probably turned to atoms because I was preparing for
my matriculation in the summer, and hence liked to discuss
scientific subjects with my friend Kurt, who shared my interests
and hoped to become an engineer. Kurt came from a Protestant
officer's family; he was a good sportsman and an excellent com-
rade. The year before, when Munich had been surrounded by
government troops and our families had long since eaten their
last piece of bread, he, my brother and I had gone on a foraging
expedition to Garching, right through the front lines, and had
returned with a rucksack full of bread, butter and bacon. Such
shared experiences make for trust and happy understanding. I
now told Kurt that I had come across an illustration in my
physics book that made no sense to me at all. It was meant to
depict the basic chemical process of two uniform substances
combining into a third uniform substance, i.e., into a chemical
compound, The processes involved, so the book contended, were
best explained by the assumption that the smallest particles, or
atoms, of either element, combined into small groups of atoms,
called molecules. A carbon dioxide molecule, for instance, was
said to consist of an atom of carbon and two atoms of oxygen, It
was this process which our book tried to illustrate. And in order
to explain why it was that precisely one atom of carbon and two
atoms of oxygen formed a carbon dioxide molecule, the artist
had furnished the atoms with hooks and eyes, by which they
could hang together. I found this approach wholly unacceptable.
To my mind, hooks and eyes were quite arbitrary structures
whose shape could be altered at will to adapt them to different
technical tasks, whereas atoms and their combination into mole-
cules were supposed to be governed by strict natural laws. This, I
felt, left no room for such human inventions as hooks and eyes.
“If you do not hold with hooks and eyes—and I think them
fairly suspect myself—you should nevertheless try to get at the
particular experiences which persuaded the artist to use this typeFIRST ENCOUNTER WITH THE ATOMIC CONCEPT 3
of representation,” Kurt contended. “For modern science starts
from experience and not from philosophical speculation. Experi-
ence is all we have to go by, provided only we have gathered it
with due care. As far as I know, chemists have shown that the
elementary particles of a chemical compound are always repre-
sented in a fixed ratio by weight. That is remarkable in itself.
For even if one believes in the existence of atoms, i.e., the char-
acteristic particles of every chemical element, forces of the kind
we normally encounter in nature would hardly suffice to explain
why a carbon atom invariably and exclusively attracts two oxy-
gen atoms and binds them to itself. Even if we grant the
existence of some kind of attractive force between the two types
of atom, how can we explain why a carbon atom should never
combine with three instead of the usual two oxygen atoms?”
“Perhaps the carbon and oxygen atoms have such shapes that
the combination of three is impossible for spatial reasons alone.”
“If you assume that, and it seems a plausible enough idea, then
you are back with much the same things as the hooks and eyes of
your textbook. Perhaps the artist wanted to express just that, for
he, too, had no idea what atoms really look like. He simply drew
hooks and eyes in order to drive home the point that there are
forms which lend themselves to the union of two but never of
three oxygen atoms with one of carbon.”
“Very well, the hooks and eyes have no real meaning. But you
claim that the natural laws responsible for the existence of atoms
also endow them with just the form that will ensure the right
kind of combination. Unfortunately, neither of us is familiar
with that form, nor, for that matter, was the illustrator of the
textbook. The only thing we can say is that it is thanks to this
form that one carbon atom combines with two rather than three
oxygen atoms. The chemists, as the book tells us, have invented
the concept of ‘valence’ for this very purpose. But it remains to
be seen whether ‘valence’ is just a word or a truly useful concept.”
“It is probably more than just a word; for in the case of the
carbon atom the four valence bonds it is said to have—pairs of
which are assumed to join up with the two bonds of each oxygen
atom—must somehow be related to its tetrahedral form. There is
little doubt, therefore, that the valence concept is based on em-
pirical fact, much more so than we can grasp at the moment.”
At this point, Robert joined our conversation; he had been4 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
walking silently beside us, but had obviously been listening.
Robert had a thin but strong face, framed by dark hair, and at
first sight looked rather withdrawn. He rarely joined in the sort
of flighty conversations we were wont to have on our walks, but
at night, whenever readings were held in the tent, or at meal-
times when we liked to listen to poetry, we would invariably turn
to him, for none of us knew more about German poetry, or,
indeed, about the philosophers, than he did. Whenever he
recited a poem, he would do so without the least kind of pathos,
without any strain, and yet the message of the poet would filter
through to even the most sober among us. The quiet way in
which he formulated his thoughts, his great composure, forced
everyone to listen, and what he said struck us as eminently worth
listening to. He had obviously been dissatisfied with our con-
versation about atoms.
“You science worshipers,” he said, “speak ever so glibly about
experience, and all of you believe that it leads straight to the
truth. But if you really think about it, if you really consider what
happens during an ‘experience,’ you will surely have to revise
your opinion. Whatever we say is based on thoughts; only our
thoughts are directly known to us. But thoughts are not things.
We cannot grasp things directly, we must first transform them
into ideas, and then shape these into concepts. What reaches us
from the outside is a fairly incoherent mixture of odd sense
impressions, and these are by no means directly related to the
forms or qualities we perceive a posteriori. If, for instance, we
look at a square drawn on a piece of paper, neither our retina
nor the nerve cells in our brain register anything like a square.
To arrive at that, we must first arrange our sense impressions by
an unconscious process that helps to transform them into a co-
herent, ‘meaningful’ picture. Only through this transformation,
through this fitting together of individual impressions into a
‘comprehensible’ whole, can we claim to have perceived any-
thing. Hence we ought to inquire more closely into the origin of
the pictures on which our ideas are based, determine how they
can be grasped by concepts, and how they are related to things.
Only then can we make authoritative judgments about the
meaning of experience. For ideas are obviously prior to experi-
ence; indeed, they are the prerequisite of all experience!”FIRST ENCOUNTER WITH THE ATOMIC CONCEPT 5
“But surely the very ideas you are so anxious to distinguish
from the objects of perception must spring from experience in
their turn? Perhaps not as directly as one might naively believe,
but indirectly, for instance by means of frequent repetitions of
similar groups of sense impressions or by linking the evidence of
the different senses?”
“That seems far from certain, and not even particularly con-
vincing. I have recently been reading Malebranche, and I was
struck by a reference to this very problem. Malebranche examines
three possible ways in which ideas can originate. One you have
just mentioned yourself: as they impinge on our senses, objects
produce concepts directly in our mind. Now this is a possibility
Malebranche rejects, on the grounds that sense impressions differ
qualitatively both from things and also from ideas. The second
possibility is that the human mind has ideas from the outset, or
at least has the power to form these ideas by itself. In that case,
sense impressions merely remind us of ideas already present or
else impel the mind to form them. There is a third possibility—
and this is the one that Malebranche plumps for: that the human
mind participates in divine reason. It is linked to God, and it is
from God that it derives its conceptual power, the images or
ideas with which it can arrange the wealth of sense impressions
and articulate them conceptually.”
“You philosophers are always quick to introduce theology,”
Kurt objected. “As soon as things get difficult, you produce the
great unknown to get you out of your rut. I, for one, refuse to be
put off in this way. Since you yourself have posed the question,
just tell me how precisely the human mind gets hold of ideas, in
this world, not in the next. For the mind and ideas both exist in
this world, do they not? If you refuse to admit that ideas origi-
nate in experience, then it is up to you to explain how else they
come to be part of the human mind. Are you really suggesting
that ideas, or at least the ability to form ideas—through which
even a child experiences the world—are inborn? If you do, you
must believe that our ideas spring from the experiences of earlier
generations. Well, as far as I am concerned, it matters little
whether present experiences or those of past generations are
responsible.”
“No,” Robert replied, “that was not at all what I meant. On6 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
the one hand, it is extremely doubtful whether learning, which is
the result of experience, can be handed down by hereditary
processes. On the other hand, Malebranche’s view can be ex-
pressed without theological overtones, and so be brought into
closer line with modern science. I shall try to do so. Malebranche
might easily have said that the same tendencies that provide for
visible order in the world, for the existence of chemical elements
and their properties, for the formation of crystals, for the crea-
tion of life and everything else, may also have been at work in
the creation of man’s mind. It is these tendencies which cause
ideas to correspond to things and which ensure the articulation
of concepts. They are responsible for all those real structures that
only become split into an objective factor—the thing—and a
subjective factor—the idea—when we contemplate them from
our human standpoint, when we fix them in our thoughts.
Malebranche'’s thesis has this in common with your conviction
that all ideas are based on experience: it grants that the ability
to form ideas may well have originated in the course of evolu-
tion, in the wake of contacts between living organisms and the
external world. However, Malebranche went on to stress that
these links cannot be explained away by a chain of causally
determined, individual processes. In other words, he argues that
here—as in the genesis of crystals or living creatures—we come
up against higher morphological structures that elude all at-
tempts to contain them in the conceptual couple: cause and
effect. The question whether experience is antecedent to ideas or
vice versa is probably no more relevant than the old question
about the hen and the egg.
“For the rest, I have no wish to interfere in your conversation.
I only wanted to warn you against talking too glibly about
experience when dealing with atoms, for it might well turn out
that your atoms—which, after all, elude direct observation—are
not just things but parts of more fundamental structures which
cannot be meaningfully divided into idea and object. I agree, of
course, that the hooks and eyes in your textbook must not be
taken too literally, or for that matter any of those pictures of
atoms that abound in popular writings. Such pictures, which
claim to facilitate our understanding, only serve to obscure the
real problem, But I think that when you speak about ‘atomicFIRST ENCOUNTER WITH THE ATOMIC CONCEPT 7
forms,’ as you did just now, you have to be extremely careful.
Only if you give the word ‘form’ a very wide connotation, use it
in more than a purely spatial sense, only if you employ it as
loosely as, for instance, I myself have just spoken of ‘structure,’
can I follow you at least part of the way.”
I was suddenly reminded of a fascinating book I had read with
keen interest a year earlier, though parts of it had completely
eluded me. That book was Plato's Timaeus. It, too, contains a
philosophical discussion of the smallest particles of matter. Rob-
ert's words had just given me my first, vague inkling that it was
indeed possible to come to grips with these strange mental con-
structs. Not that these constructs, which I had previously found
quite absurd, had suddenly become plausible—it was just that I
had glimpsed a path that might lead to them.
To explain why I was so strongly reminded of the Timaeus at
just that moment, I must briefly recall the circumstances under
which I had read the book, In the spring of 1919, Munich was in
a state of utter confusion. On the streets people were shooting at
one another, and no one could tell precisely who the contestants
were. Political power fluctuated between persons and institutions
few of us could have named. Pillage and robbery (I was burgled
myself) caused the term “Soviet Republic” to become a synonym
of lawlessness, and when, at Jong last, a new Bavarian govern-
ment was formed outside Munich, and sent its troops into the
city, we were all of us hoping for a speedy return to more orderly
conditions. The father of the boy whom I had been coaching
took command of a company of volunteers, anxious to play their
part in the recapture of the city. He asked his son’s friends, all of
whom were familiar with the locality, to act as guides to the
advancing troops. And so we were assigned to Cavalry Rifle
Command No. 11, with headquarters in the Theological Train-
ing College opposite the university. Here I did my military
service, or rather here all of us led a fairly wild and adventurous
life. There were no lessons, as so often before, and many of us
were anxious to use this freedom to take a fresh look at the
world. Most of the boys with whom I later went hiking around
Lake Starnberg were somehow or other engaged in the fighting.
Our adventures were over after a few weeks; then the shooting
died down and military service became increasingly monotonous.8 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
Quite often it happened that, after spending the whole night on
guard in the telephone exchange, I was free for a day, and in
order to catch up with my neglected school work I would retire
to the roof of the Training College with a Greek school edition
of Plato's Dialogues. There, lying in the wide gutter, and
warmed by the rays of the early morning sun, I could pursue my
studies in peace, and from time to time watch the quickening life
in the Ludwigstrasse below.
One such morning, when the light of the sun was already
flooding across the university buildings and the fountain, I came
to the Timaeus, or rather to those passages in which Plato dis-
cusses the smallest particles of matter. Perhaps that section cap-
tured my imagination only because it was so hard to translate
into German, or because it dealt with mathematical matters,
which had always interested me. In any case, I worked my way
laboriously through the text, even though what I read seemed
completely nonsensical. The smallest particles of matter were
said to be right-angled triangles which, after combining in pairs
into isosceles triangles or squares, joined together into the regu-
lar bodies of solid geometry: cubes, tetrahedrons, octahedrons
and icosahedrons. These four bodies were said to be the building
blocks of the four elements, earth, fire, air and water. I could not
make out whether these regular bodies were associated with the
elements merely as symbols—for instance, the cube with the ele-
ment earth so as to represent the solidity and balance of that
element—or whether the smallest parts of the earth were actually
supposed to be cube-shaped. In either case, the whole thing
seemed to be wild speculation, pardonable perhaps on the
ground that the Greeks lacked the necessary empirical knowl-
edge. Nevertheless, it saddened me to find a philosopher of
Plato’s critical acumen succumbing to such fancies, I looked for a
principle that might help me to find some justification for Plato's
speculation, but, try though I might, I could discover none. Even
so, I was enthralled by the idea that the smallest particles of
matter must reduce to some mathematical form. After all, any
attempt to unravel the dense skein of natural phenomena is
dependent upon the discovery of mathematical forms, but why
Plato should have chosen the regular bodies of solid geometry, of
all things, remained a complete mystery to me. They seemed toFIRST ENCOUNTER WITH THE ATOMIC CONCEPT 9
have no explanatory value at all. If I nevertheless continued
reading the Dialogues, it was simply to brush up on my Greek.
Yet I remained perturbed. The most important result of it all,
perhaps, was the conviction that, in order to interpret the
material world we need to know something about its smallest
parts. Moreover, I knew from textbooks and popular writing that
modern science was also inquiring into atoms. Perhaps, later in
my studies, I myself might enter this strange world. But the time
‘was not yet.
Meanwhile, my uneasiness continued, though perhaps it was
only part of the general disquiet that had seized all German
youth. I kept wondering why a great philosopher like Plato
should have thought he could recognize order in natural phe-
nomena when we ourselves could not. What precisely was the
meaning of that term? Are order and our understanding of it
purely time-bound? We had all of us grown up in a world that
had seemed well ordered enough, and our parents had taught us
the bourgeois virtues underpinning that order. The Greeks and
the Romans had known that, at times, it may become necessary
to sacrifice one’s life for the sake of maintaining an orderly way
of life, and the death of many of our own friends and relatives
had shown us that such was the way of the world even now. That
was only to be expected. But there were many who now claimed
that the war had been a crime, a crime, moreover, committed by
the very men who had been responsible for maintaining the old
European order, who had tried to defend it come what may. The
old structure of Europe had been shattered by our defeat. That,
too, was nothing special. Wherever there are wars there must also
be losers. But did that mean that all the old structures had to be
discarded? Was it not far better to build a new and more solid
order on the old? Or were those right who, in the streets of
Munich, had sacrificed their lives to prevent a restoration of the
old ways and who proclaimed a new order, not just for a single
nation, but for all mankind, even though the majority of man-
kind might have no wish to build such an order? Our heads
were full of such questions, and our elders were unable to pro-
vide the answers.
After my reading of the Timaeus and before our walk on the
hills around Lake Starnberg I had another experience which was10 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
to affect my later thoughts profoundly, and which I shall report
before returning to our discussion of the atomic problem, A few
months after they had captured Munich, the government troops
pulled out again, and we returned to school. One afternoon, I
was buttonholed by an unknown boy on Leopoldstrasse: “Have
you heard about the Youth Assembly in Prunn Castle next
week?” he asked. “All of us intend to be there, and we want you
to come as well. The more the merrier. We want to find out for
ourselves what sort of future we should build!” His voice had the
kind of edge I had not heard before. And so I decided to go to
Prunn Castle, and asked Kurt to join me.
It took the train, which was running somewhat sporadically,
several hours to bring us to the Lower Altmiihl Valley. In early
geological times it must have been the floor of the Danube; here
the river Altmith] has twisted and bored its way through the
Jura Mountains, and the picturesque valley is crowned with old
castles reminiscent of the Rhenish scene. We had to cover the last
few miles to the castle on foot, and could see large crowds making
for the heights from all sides.
Prunn Castle stands sheer on a rock at the edge of the valley.
The courtyard, with its central well, was teeming with people.
Most of them were schoolboys, but there was a sprinkling of older
boys who had suffered all the horrors of war at the front and had
returned to a completely changed world. There were many
speeches that day, full of the kind of pathos that would ring
quite false today. We argued passionately about whether the fate
of our own nation mattered more than that of all mankind;
whether the death of those who had fallen for their country had
become meaningless through defeat; whether youth had the right
to fashion life according to its own values; whether inner truth
was more important than all the old forms that had been shaping
human life for centuries.
I myself was much too unsure to join in the debates, but I
listened and once again thought a great deal about the meaning
f “order.” From the remarks of the speakers it was clear that
different orders, however sincerely upheld, could clash, and that
the result was the very opposite of order. This, I felt, was only
possible because all these types of order were partial, mere frag-
ments that had split off from the central order; they might notFIRST ENCOUNTER WITH THE ATOMIC CONCEPT ql
have lost their creative force, but they were no longer directed
toward a unifying center. Its absence was brought home to me
with increasingly painful intensity the longer I listened. I was
suffering almost physically, but I was quite unable to discover a
way toward the center through the thicket of conflicting opin-
ions. Thus the hours ticked by, while more speeches were de-
livered and more disputes were born. The shadows in the
courtyard grew longer, and finally the hot day gave way to slate-
gray dusk and a moonlit night. The talk was still going on when,
quite suddenly, a young violinist appeared on a balcony above
the courtyard, There was a hush as, high above us, he struck up
the first great D minor chords of Bach's Chaconne. All at once,
and with utter certainty, I had found my link with the center.
The moonlit Altmihl Valley below would have been reason
enough for a romantic transfiguration; but that was not it. The
clear phrases of the Chaconne touched me like a cool wind,
breaking through the mist and revealing the towering structures
beyond. There had always been a path to the central order in the
language of music, in philosophy and in religion, today no less
than in Plato’s day and in Bach’s. That I now knew from my
own experience.
We spent the rest of the night around campfires and in our
tents on a meadow above the castle, giving full rein to our
romantic and poetic sentiments. The young musician, himself a
student, sat near our group and played minuets by Mozart and
Beethoven interspersed with old folk songs; I tried to accompany
him on my guitar. Otherwise, he proved a very gay young fellow
and was reluctant to discuss his solemn rendering of the Cha-
conne. When pressed, he came back at us with “Do you know the
key of the trumpets of Jericho?” “No.” “D minor [d-moll] also,
of course.” “Why?” “Because they d-moll-ished the walls!” He
escaped our wrath only by taking to his heels.
That night had slipped into the twilight of memories by the
time I went hiking across the hills round Lake Starnberg, and
talked about atoms. Robert’s references to Malebranche had
convinced me that our experience of atoms can only be indirect:
atoms are not things. This was probably what Plato had tried to
say in his Timaeus, and, seen in this light, his speculations about
regular bodies were beginning to make more sense to me. When12 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
modern scientists speak about the form of atoms, they must be
using the word “form” in its widest sense, i.e, they must be
referring to the atom’s structure in time and space, to the
symmetrical properties of its forces, to its ability to form com-
pounds with other atoms. In all probability, such structures will
forever elude our powers of graphic description, if only because
they are not an obvious part of the objective world of things. But
perhaps they are nonetheless open to mathematical treatment.
At once I wanted to learn more about the philosophical aspects
of the atomic problem, and to that end I mentioned Plato's
Timaeus to Robert. I asked him if he was in general agreement
with Plato's belief that all material things consist of small units,
that there must be ultimate particles into which all matter can
be divided. I gained the impression that he took a rather skepti-
cal view of the whole question.
He confirmed this when he said: “Your whole manner of
posing the problem, of going so far beyond the world of direct
experience, is quite foreign to me. I feel much closer to the world
of human beings, to lakes and forests, than I do to atoms. | know
that we can ask what happens if we keep dividing and subdivid-
ing matter, just as we can ask whether the distant stars and their
planets are inhabited by living beings. But I myself can't say I
have much interest in such questions, Perhaps I don’t even want
to know the answers. I believe we have far more important tasks
than that.”
“I don’t wish to argue with you about the relative importance
of our respective tasks,” I told him. “I myself have always been
fascinated by science, and I know that many serious people are
anxious to learn more about nature and her laws. Who knows
but that their work may not prove of the utmost importance for
the whole of mankind? But that is not what matters to me at the
moment. What worries me is this: it looks very much as if—and
Kurt has been saying just that—modern developments in science
and technology have brought us very close to the point where we
can see individual atoms, or at least their effects, where we can
start to experiment with them, Admittedly, we ourselves still
know very little about the subject, simply because our studies
have not taken us far enough. But, if my prognosis is correct,
what would you, as a disciple of Malebranche, say about it?”
“I should expect that atoms would, in any case, behave quiteFIRST ENCOUNTER WITH THE ATOMIC CONCEPT 13
differently from the objects of everyday experience. I could
imagine that attempts to divide matter even further might lead
us to fluctuations and discontinuities from which it would be
quite possible to conclude that matter has a grainy structure, But
I also believe that the new structures will elude all our attempts
to construct tangible images, that they will prove to be abstract
expressions of natural laws rather than things.”
“But what if we could see them?”
“We shall never be able to see atoms themselves, only their
effects.”
“That’s a poor excuse of an answer. For the same remark
applies to things in general. In the case of a cat, too, all you can
see is the reflection of light rays, i.e., the effects of the cat, and
not the cat itself. And when you stroke its fur, the situation is
much the same!”
“I'm afraid I can’t agree with you. I can see a cat directly, for
when I look at it, I can—indeed, I must—transform my sense
impressions into a coherent idea. In the case of the cat we come
face to face with two aspects: an objective and a subjective one—
the cat as a thing and as a notion. But atoms are quite a different
matter. Here notion and thing can no longer be separated,
simply because the atom is neither the one nor the other.”
Kurt joined in the discussion once again. “The two of you are
much too learned for me; you make free with philosophical
speculations, when, in fact, you should be consulting experience.
Perhaps our studies may one day introduce us to experiments
about or with atoms, and then we shall know what atoms really
are. We shall probably discover that they are just as real as all
other things which lend themselves to experiment. For if it is
true that all material things consist of atoms, then it follows that
atoms must be just as real as material things.”
“No,” replied Robert, “I think your conclusion is highly
questionable. You might just as well say that, because all living
beings are made up of atoms, atoms are fully alive. Clearly, that
is nonsense. Only the combination of a great many atoms into
larger structures endows these structures with their characteristic
qualities or properties.”
“And so you think that atoms don’t actually exist, that they
are not real?”
“You exaggerate again. Perhaps what we are arguing about is14 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
not so much our knowledge of atoms as the meaning of the words
‘actually’ or ‘real.’ You have mentioned the Timaeus and told us
that Plato identifies the smallest particles of matter with mathe-
matical forms, with regular bodies. Even if he was wrong in
fact—and Plato had no experience with atoms—he could have
been right in principle. Would you call such mathematical forms
‘actual’ or ‘real’? If they express natural laws, that is the central
order inherent in material processes, then you must also call
them ‘actual,’ for they act, they produce tangible effects, but you
cannot call them ‘real,’ because they cannot be described as res,
as things. In short, we do not know what words we should use,
and this is bound to happen once we leave the realm of direct
experience, the realm in which our language was formed in pre-
historic times.”
Kurt remained unconvinced. “I should like to leave even this
decision to experiment. I cannot believe that the human imagi-
nation can tell us anything about the smallest particles of matter
before crucial experiments have familiarized us with them. Only
careful investigations, conducted without any preconceptions,
can help us here. That is precisely why I am so skeptical about
philosophical generalizations on so difficult a subject. They
merely cement mental prejudices and hinder rather than foster
true understanding. I sincerely hope that scientists will come to
grips with atoms long before you philosophers have.”
By now, the rest of the party had lost patience with us. “For
God’s sake, can’t you ever stop your bickering?” one of them
pleaded. “If you want to bone up for your examinations, please
do so at home. How about a song?” We began to sing, and the
bright sound of young voices, the colors of the blossoming
meadows, were suddenly much more real than all our thoughts
about atoms, and dispelled the fancies to which we had sur-
rendered.2
The Decision
to Study Physics (1920)
From school I did not go straight on to the university; there was
a sharp break in my life. After my matriculation, I went on a
walking tour through Franconia with the same group of friends,
and then I fell seriously ill and had to stay in bed for many
weeks. During my long recuperation, too, I was locked away with
my books. In these critical months I came across a work that I
found extremely fascinating, though I was unable to understand
it fully. The author was the famous mathematician, Hermann
Weyl, and the book was entitled Space, Time and Matter. It was
meant to provide a mathematical account of Einstein’s relativity
theory. The difficult mathematical arguments and the abstract
thought underlying that theory both excited and disturbed me,
and, in addition, confirmed me in my earlier decision to study
mathematics at the University of Munich,
During the first days of my studies, however, a strange and,
to me, most surprising event took place, which I should like to
report in brief. My father, who taught Middle and Modern Greek
at the University of Munich, had arranged an interview with
Ferdinand von Lindemann, the professor of mathematics, famous
for his solution of the ancient problem of squaring the circle. I
intended to ask permission to attend his seminars, for which I
imagined my spare-time studies of mathematics had fully prepared
me; but when I called on the great man, in his gloomy first-floor
office furnished in rather formal, old-fashioned style, I felt an
almost immediate sense of oppression, Before I could utter a16 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
word of greeting to the professor, who rose from his chair very
slowly, I noticed a little black dog cowering on the desk, and was
forcefully reminded of the poodle in Faust’s study. The little
beast looked at me with undisguised animosity; I was an unwel-
come intruder about to disturb his master’s peace of mind. I was
so taken aback that I began to stammer, and even as I spoke it
dawned on me that my request was excessively immodest. Linde-
mann, a tired-looking old gentleman with a white beard, ob-
viously felt the same way about it, and his slight irritation may
have been the reason why the small dog now set up a horrible
barking. His master tried to calm him down, but the little beast
only grew more hysterical, so that we could barely hear each
other speak. Lindemann asked me what books I had recently
been reading, and I mentioned Weyl’s Space, Time and Matter.
As the tiny monster kept up his yapping, Lindemann closed the
conversation with “In that case you are completely lost to mathe-
matics,” And that was that.
Clearly mathematics was not for me. A somewhat wearing
consultation with my father ended with the advice that I ought
to try my hand at theoretical physics. Accordingly, he made an
appointment with his old friend Arnold Sommerfeld, then head
of the Faculty of Theoretical Physics at the University of Munich
and generally considered one of the most brilliant teachers there.
Sommerfeld received me in a bright study with windows over-
looking a courtyard where I could see a crowd of students on
benches beneath a large acacia. The small squat man with his
martial dark mustache looked rather austere to me. But his very
first sentences revealed his benevolence, his genuine concern for
young people, and in particular for the boy who had come to ask
his guidance and advice. Once again the conversation turned to
the mathematical studies I had pursued as a hobby while still at
school, and to Weyl’s Space, Time and Matter. Sommerfeld's
reaction was completely different from Lindemann’s.
“You are much too demanding,” he said. “You can’t possibly
start with the most difficult part and hope that the rest will
automatically fall into your lap. I gather that you are fascinated
by relativity theory and atomic problems. But remember that
this is not the only field in which modern physics challenges basic
philosophical attitudes, in which extremely exciting ideas areTHE DECISION TO STUDY PHYSICS 17
being forged. To reach them is much more difficult than you
seem to imagine. You must start with a modest but painstaking
study of traditional physics. And if you want to study science at
all, you must first make up your mind whether you want to
concentrate on experimental or theoretical research. From what
you have told me, I take it that you are much keener on theory.
But didn’t you do experiments and dabble with instruments at
school?”
I said that I used to like building small engines, motors and
induction coils. But, all in all, I had never been really at home in
the world of instruments, and the care needed in making rela-
tively unimportant measurements had struck me as being sheer
drudgery.
“Still, even if you study theory, you will have to pay particular
attention to what may appear trivial little tasks, Even those who
deal with the larger issues, issues with profound philosophical
implications—for instance, with Einstein's relativity theory or
with Planck’s quantum theory—have to tackle a great many
petty problems. Only by solving these can they hope to get
an over-all picture of the new realms they have opened up.”
“Even so, I am much more interested in the underlying philo-
sophical ideas than in the rest,” I said rather bashfully.
But Sommerfeld would have none of this. “You must remem-
ber what Schiller said about Kant and his interpreters: ‘When
kings go a-building, wagoners have more work.’ At first, none of
us are anything but wagoners. But you will see that you, too, will
get pleasure from performing minor tasks carefully and con-
scientiously and, let's hope, from achieving decent results.”
Sommerfeld then gave me a few more hints about my pre-
liminary studies, and said that he might well come up with a
little problem connected with recent developments in atomic
theory on which I could try my mettle. And it was decided that I
would join his classes for the next few years.
This, my first conversation with a scholar who really knew his
way about in modern physics, who had personally made impor-
tant discoveries in a field impinging on both relativity and
quantum theory, had a lasting effect upon me. Though his call
for care in small details struck me as eminently reasonable—I
had heard it often enough from my own father—I felt dejected at18 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
the thought that I was still such a long way from the field that
really interested me. No wonder that this interview became the
subject of many discussions with my friends. I remember one of
these particularly well: it bore on modern physics and the cul-
ture of our time.
That autumn, I saw a great deal of the boy who had played
Bach’s Chaconne so magnificently in Prunn Castle. We would
meet in the house of our mutual friend, Walter, himself a fine
cellist, and practice for a private recital of Schubert's B Major
Trio, Walter's father had died at an early age, and his mother
had been left to care for her two sons in a large and very
elegantly furnished house in Elisabeth Strasse, just a few min-
utes’ walk from my parents’ house in Hohenzollern Strasse. The
magnificent Bechstein grand in the living room was an added
reason for our frequent visits. After we had finished playing, we
would often talk deep into the night, and it was on one such
occasion that the conversation came round to my proposed
studies. Walter’s mother wondered why I had not decided to
make music my career.
“From the way you play and speak about music, I get the
impression that you are much more at home with art than with
science and technology, that you prefer the muses to scientific
instruments, formulae and machinery. If I am right, why ever
have you chosen natural science? After all, the future of the
world will be decided by you young people. If youth chooses
beauty, then there will be more beauty; if it chooses utility, then
there will be more useful things. The decision of each individual
is of importance not only to himself but to the whole of man-
kind.”
“I can’t really believe that we are faced with that sort of
choice,” I said rather defensively. “Quite apart from the fact that
I probably wouldn’t make a very good musician, the question
remains in which field one can contribute most. Now I have the
clear impression that in recent years music has lost much of its
earlier force. In the seventeenth century music was still deeply
steeped in the religious way of life; in the eighteenth century
came the conquest of the world of individual emotions; in the
nineteenth century romantic music plumbed the innermost
depths of the human soul. But in the last few years music seemsTHE DECISION TO STUDY PHYSICS 19
to have quite deliberately entered a strange, disturbed and
rather feeble stage of experimentation, in which theoretical
notions take precedence over the desire for progress along estab-
lished paths. In science, and particularly in physics, things are
quite different. Here the pursuit of clear objectives along fixed
paths—the same paths that led to the understanding of certain
electromagnetic phenomena twenty years ago—has quite auto-
matically thrown up problems that challenge the whole philo-
sophical basis of science, the structure of space and time, and
even the validity of causal laws. Here we are on terra incognita,
and it will probably take several generations of physicists to dis-
cover the final answers. And I frankly confess that I am highly
tempted to play some part in all this.”
My friend Rolf, the violinist, demurred. “As far as I can see,
your remarks about modern physics apply equally well to mod-
ern music. Here, too, the path seems to be clearly mapped. The
old tonal barriers are collapsing and we find ourselves on promis-
ing virgin soil, with almost complete freedom to choose what
sounds and rhythms we like. Hence the musician has every
chance of discovering as many riches as the scientist.”
‘Walter now raised several objections of his own. “I don’t really
know whether ‘freedom of expression’ and ‘promising virgin soil’
are necessarily the same thing. At first sight it admittedly looks as
if greater freedom must necessarily mean enrichment, wider
possibilities; but this I know to be untrue in art, with which Iam
more familiar than with science. I would think that progress in
art takes place in the following way: First a slow historical pro-
cess transforms the life of men in spite of themselves, and thereby
throws up fresh ideas. A few talented artists then try to give these
ideas a visible or audible form by wresting new possibilities of
expression from the material with which they work—from colors
or musical instruments. This interplay or, if you like, this
struggle between the expressive content and the limitations of the
expressive medium is, I think, a sine qua non of the emergence of
real art. If the limitations of the expressive medium were taken
away-—if in music, for instance, we could produce any sounds we
liked—then the struggle would be over, and the artist’s effort
would reach into a void. For that reason I am skeptical about too
much freedom.20 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
“In science,” Walter continued, “a continuous flow of new
experiments is made possible by new techniques; there are new
experiences and as a result new contents may be produced. Here
the means of expression are the concepts by which the new ideas
are grasped and made explicit. For instance, I have read that
Einstein's relativity theory, which interests you so much, was
born from the failure of certain experiments designed to demon-
strate the motion of the earth through space by means of the
interference of light rays. When this demonstration misfired, it
became clear that the new results, or, what amounts to the same
thing, the new ideas, called for an extension of the means of
expression, i.e., of the conceptual system proper to physics. Quite
likely, no one anticipated that this would demand radical
changes in such fundamental concepts as space and time. It was
Einstein's great achievement to appreciate before anyone else
that the ideas of space and time were not only susceptible to
change but, in fact, had to be changed.
“What you have said about recent developments in physics
could reasonably be compared with developments in music in the
middle of the eighteenth century. At that time, a gradual his-
torical process had led to a growing awareness of the emotional
world of the individual—as all of us know from Rousseau and
later from Goethe’s Werther—and it was then that the great
classicists—Haydn, Mozart, Beethoven and Schubert—succeeded
in extending the means of expression and so discovered the
musical language needed for depicting this emotional world, In
modern music, on the other hand, the new contents appear to be
highly obscure and implausible, and the plethora of possible
expressions fills me with deep forebodings. The path of modern
music seems to be determined by a purely negative postulate: the
old tonality has to be discarded because we believe that its
powers have been exhausted, and not because there are new and
more forceful ideas which it is incapable of expressing. Musicians
are entirely in the dark about the next step; at best they grope
their way forward. In modern science the questions are clearly
posed, and the task is to find the right answers. In modern art,
however, even the questions are uncertain. But perhaps you had
best tell us a bit more about the new fields you intend to explore
in the world of physics.”THE DECISION TO STUDY PHYSICS 21
I tried to convey what little bits of knowledge I had gleaned
during my illness, mainly from popular books on atomic physics.
“In relativity theory,” I told Walter, “the experiments you
have mentioned, together with other experiments, caused Ein-
stein to discard the prevailing concept of simultaneity. That in
itself was exciting enough. Every one of us thinks that he knows
precisely what the word ‘simultaneous’ means, even if it refers
to events that take place at great distances. But we are mis-
taken. For if we ask how one determines whether two such
events are, in fact, simultaneous and then evaluates the various
means of verification by their results, nature herself informs us
that the answers are not at all clear-cut but depend on the ob-
server's state of motion. Space and time are therefore not inde-
pendent of each other, as we previously believed. Einstein was
able to express the ‘new’ structure of space and time by means of
a simple and coherent mathematical formula. While I was ill, I
tried to probe into this mathematical world, which, as I have
since learned from Sommerfeld, has already been opened up
fairly extensively and has therefore ceased to be unexplored
territory.
“The most interesting problems now lie in a different field, in
atomic physics. Here we come face to face with the fundamental
question why the material world manifests ever-recurring forms
and qualities—why, for example, water with all its characteristic
properties is invariably reproduced during the melting of ice, the
condensation of steam or the combustion of hydrogen. This has
been taken for granted in physics, but has never been fully ex-
plained. Let us suppose that material bodies—in our case, water
—are composed of atoms. Chemistry has long made successful use
of this idea. Now, the Newtonian laws we were taught at school
cannot tell us why the motions of the particles involved should
be as stable as they, in fact, are. Only quite different natural laws
can help us to explain why atoms should invariably rearrange
themselves and move in such a way as to produce the same sub-
stances with the same stable properties. We first caught a glimpse
of these laws twenty years ago, in Planck’s quantum theory. Since
then, the Danish physicist, Niels Bohr, has combined Planck’s
theory with Lord Rutherford's atomic model. In so doing, he was
the first to throw light on the curious stability of atoms which I22 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
have just mentioned. But Sommerfeld believes that in this sphere
we are still a long way from a clear understanding of the ways of
mature. Here we have a vast unexplored field, in which new
relationships may be discovered for decades to come. By the ap-
propriate reformulation of natural laws and with correct new
concepts we might, for instance, be able to reduce the whole of
chemistry to atomic physics. In short, I firmly believe that in
atomic physics we are on the track of far more important rela-
tions, far more important structures, than in music. But I freely
admit that 150 years ago things were the other way round.”
“In other words,” Walter asked, “you believe that anyone con-
cerned with cultural progress must necessarily make use of the
historical possibilities of the age in which he lives? That, if
Mozart had been born in our day, he, too, would be writing
atonal and experimental music?”
“Yes, I suspect just that. If Einstein had lived in the twelfth
century, he would not have been able to make important scien-
tific discoveries.”
“Perhaps it is wrong to keep bringing up such great men as
Mozart and Einstein,” Walter's mother said. “Few individuals
get the chance to play such decisive roles. Most of us must con-
tent ourselves with working quietly in a small circle, and ought
to ask simply whether playing Schubert's B Major Trio is not
more satisfactory than building instruments or writing mathe-
matical formulae.”
I agreed that I myself had quite a few qualms and mentioned
Sommerfeld’s quotation from Schiller: ‘“When kings go a-build-
ing, wagoners have more work.”
“We all feel the same way about it,” Rolf declared. “Those of
us who want to become musicians have to take infinite pains to
master their instruments, and even then can only hope to play
pieces that hundreds of better musicians have played much more
proficiently. And you yourself will have to spend long hours with
instruments that others have built much more competently, or
retrace the mathematical thoughts of the masters. True, when all
this has been done, the musical wagoners among us are left with
no small sense of achievement: constant intercourse with glorious
music and the occasional delight of a particularly successful
interpretation, Likewise, you scientists will occasionally manageTHE DECISION TO STUDY PHYSICS 23
to interpret a relationship just that little bit better than anyone
before you, or determine a particular process more accurately
than your predecessors. But none of us ought to count on the fact
that he will be doing trail-blazing work, that he will make deci-
sive discoveries. Not even when he works in a field where a great
deal of territory has still to be opened up.”
Walter's mother, who had been listening attentively, now said
something, more to herself than to us, as if she were trying to
formulate her thoughts as she spoke:
“The parable of the kings and the wagoners may have quite a
different import. Of course, superficially it looks as if the glory is
entirely the kings’, as if the wagoners’ work were purely sub-
sidiary and unimportant. But perhaps the very opposite is true.
Perhaps the kings’ glory rests on the work of the wagoners, on the
fact that the wagoners have put in many years of laborious
effort, reaping joy and success. Perhaps men like Bach or Mozart
are kings of music only because, for two long centuries, they have
offered so many lesser musicians the chance of reinterpreting
their thoughts with love and conscientious attention to detail.
And even the audience participates in this careful work as it
hears the message of the great musicians.
“I£ you look at historical developments—in the arts no less
than in the sciences—you will find that every discipline has long
periods of quiescence or of slow growth. Even during these
periods, however, the important thing is careful work, attention
to detail. Everything that is not done with utter devotion falls
into oblivion and, in fact, does not deserve to be remembered.
And then, quite suddenly, this slow process, in which general
historical developments introduce changes in the contents of a
particular discipline, opens up new possibilities, quite unex-
pected contents. Talented men feel an almost magical attraction
for the process of growth they can sense at work here, and so it
happens that, within a few decades, a relatively small region of
the world will produce major works of art or scientific discoveries
of the greatest importance. In the late eighteenth century, for
instance, classical music poured forth from Vienna; in the fif-
teenth and sixteenth centuries painting had its heyday in the
Netherlands. True, great men are needed to express the new
spiritual contents, to create the forms in which further develop-24 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
ments can be molded, but they do not actually produce these new
contents.
“Of course, it is quite possible that we are on the threshold of
an exceptionally fruitful scientific epoch, in which case it would
be wrong to dissuade any young man from participating in it. It
seems unlikely that important developments will take place in
more than one branch of art or science at one time; we ought to
be grateful enough if it happens in any one area, if we can share
in its glory either as bystanders or as active participants. It would
be foolish to expect more. That is precisely why I find popular
attacks on modern art—be it painting or music—so unjust. Once
music and the plastic arts had solved the great problems posed to
them in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, there just had
to be a more restful period, in which much of the old could be
preserved and new things were tested by trial and error. To
compare modern compositions with the finest achievements of
the great epoch of classical music seems utterly unfair. Perhaps
we ought to finish the evening with the slow movement of
Schubert’s B Major Trio. Let’s see how well you can play it.”
We did as we were asked, and from the way in which Rolf
played the somewhat melancholic C major figures in the second
part of the movement, I could sense how sad he was at the
thought that the great epoch of European music might be gone
forever.
A few days later, when I walked into the hall where Sommer-
feld usually gave his lectures, I spotted a dark-haired student
with a somewhat secretive face in the third row. Sommerfeld had
introduced us during my first visit and had then told me that he
considered this boy to be one of his most talented students, one
from whom I could learn a great deal. His name was Wolfgang
Pauli, and for the rest of his life he was to be a good friend,
though often a very severe critic. I sat down beside him and
asked him if, after the lecture, I might consult him about my
preparatory studies. Sommerfeld now entered the hall, and as
soon as he started to address us Wolfgang whispered in my ear:
“Doesn't he look the typical old Hussar officer?” After the lec-
ture, we went back to the Institute of Theoretical Physics, where
I asked Wolfgang two questions. I wanted to know how much
experimental work had to be done by someone interested chieflyTHE DECISION TO STUDY PHYSICS 25
in theory, and what he thought of the respective importance of
relativity and atomic theory.
“I know,” Wolfgang told me in reply to my first question,
“that Sommerfeld lays great stress on experimental studies, but I
myself am not cut out for them; I hate the whole business of
handling instruments. I quite agree that physics is based on
experimental results, but once these results have been obtained,
physics, at least modern physics, becomes much too difficult a
subject for most experimental physicists. This is probably so
because the sophisticated instruments of modern physics take us
into realms of nature that cannot be adequately described with
everyday concepts. We are forced to employ an abstract kind of
mathematical language and one that presupposes a considerable
amount of training in modern mathematics. It is a sad fact but
true that we all have to specialize. I find abstract mathematical
language quite easy, and hope to put it to good use in my work.
Needless to say, I realize that some knowledge of the experimental
side is absolutely essential. The pure mathematician, however
good, understands nothing at all about physics.”
I then repeated my conversation with old Lindemann, and
told Wolfgang about his black lap dog and his reaction to my
reading Weyl’s Space, Time and Matter. My report obviously
caused Wolfgang the greatest amusement.
“That's just what I would have expected,” he said. “Weyl
really does know a lot about relativity theory, and for Linde-
mann such knowledge is enough to disqualify anyone from
bearing the title of serious mathematician.”
As to the respective importance of relativity and atomic
theory, Wolfgang had this to say: “The so-called special theory of
relativity is now a closed chapter; you simply have to learn it and
use it like any other theory in physics. Nor is it of particular
interest to anyone anxious to make new discoveries. However, the
general theory of relativity, or, what comes to much the same
thing, Einstein’s theory of gravitation, is still wide-open, But it
is rather unsatisfying in that, for each experiment, it will give
you a hundred pages of theory with the most complicated
mathematical derivations, No one can really say whether the
whole thing is correct. Nevertheless it opens up new possibilities
of thought, and for that reason must be taken seriously. I have26 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
recently written a fairly lengthy article on the general theory of
relativity; perhaps that is one of the reasons why I find atomic
theory so much more interesting.
“In atomic physics we still have a wealth of uninterpreted
experimental results: nature’s evidence in one place seems to
contradict that in another, and so far it has not been possible to
draw an even halfway coherent picture of the relationship in-
volved. True, Niels Bohr has succeeded in associating the
strange stability of atoms with Planck’s quantum hypothesis—
which has not yet been properly interpreted either—and more
recently Bohr is said to have given a qualitative explanation of
the periodic system of the elements and of their chemical prop-
erties. But I can’t for the life of me see how he could have done
so, seeing that he, too, is unable to get rid of the contradictions I
have mentioned. In other words, everyone is still groping about
in a thick mist, and it will probably be quite a few years before it
lifts. Sommerfeld hopes that experiments will help us to find
some of the new laws. He believes in numerical links, almost in a
kind of number mysticism of the kind the Pythagoreans applied
to the harmony of vibrating strings. That’s why many of us have
called this side of his science ‘atomysticism,’ though, as far as I
can tell, no one has been able to suggest anything better. Perhaps
it’s much easier to find one’s way if one isn’t too familiar with the
magnificent unity of classical physics. You have a decided advan-
tage there,” Wolfgang added with a malicious grin, “but then
lack of knowledge is no guarantee of success.”
Despite this little broadside, Wolfgang had confirmed every-
thing I myself had been thinking before I decided to make
physics my career. I was very glad not to have tried my hand at
pure mathematics, and I looked back on Lindemann’s little dog
as “part of that power which still produceth good, whilst ever
scheming ill.”3
“Understanding”
in Modern Physics (1920-922)
My first two years at Munich University were spent in two quite
different worlds: among my friends of the Youth Movement and
in the abstract realm of theoretical physics. Both worlds were so
filled with intense activity that I was often in a state of great
agitation, the more so as I found it rather difficult to shuttle
between the two. In Sommerfeld’s seminar, talks with Wolfgang
Pauli constituted the most important part of my studies. But
Wolfgang's way of life was almost diametrically opposed to my
own. While I loved the daylight and spent as much of my free
time as I could mountain-walking, swimming or cooking simple
meals on the shore of one of the Bavarian lakes, Wolfgang was a
typical night bird. He preferred the town, liked to spend his
evenings in some old bar or café, and would then work on his
physics through much of the night with great concentration and
success. Quite naturally, and to Sommerfeld's dismay, he would
rarely attend morning lectures; it was not until noon that he
generally turned up. This difference in our styles of living was
the subject of quite a bit of ribbing, but did not otherwise mar
our friendship—our common interest in physics saw to that.
When I think back on the summer of 1921, and try to compress
my many memories into a single picture, my mind’s eye conjures
up a camp that stood on the edge of a forest. Below, still in the
gray light of dawn, lay the lake in which we had swum the day
before, and across it, in the distance, the broad crest of the
Benedictine Ridge. My comrades would still be asleep when I left28 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
my tent and took the footpath for an hour's walk to the nearest
railway station. From there, the early-morning train would carry
me to Munich in time to attend Sommerfeld’s g a.m. lecture. The
footpath led down to the lake through marshy ground, then on to
a moraine with a view over the Alpine chain, from the Benedic-
tine Ridge as far as the Zugspitze. On the blossoming meadows, I
could see the first mowing machines, and I was sorry that I was
no longer a farm worker on the Grossthalerhof in Miesbach.
Three years earlier, using a pair of oxen, I would have done my
best to cut the meadow so straight that no strip of grass, or, as the
farmer called it, no “pig,” was left behind. And so, my thoughts
filled with a colorful medley of everyday impressions from my
farming days, with the beauty of the landscape, and with Som-
merfeld’s coming lecture, I was convinced I was the happiest
mortal on earth,
An hour or two after the end of Sommerfeld’s lecture, Wolf-
gang would appear in the seminar, and our conversation would
go something like this:
Wolfgang: “Good morning. If it isn’t our prophet of nature!
You look for all the world as if you have been living by the
principles of St. Jean-Jacques. Wasn't it he who said, ‘Back to
nature, up into the trees, you apes’?”
“The second part of the quotation is not from Rousseau,” I
would explain, “and none of us goes in for climbing trees. In any
case, it isn’t morning; it’s twelve o'clock, if my watch is correct.
One day you simply must introduce me to one of your nightly
haunts so that I, too, can get a whiff of your physical inspiration.”
“That wouldn't help you in the least. Still, you might perhaps
care to tell me what you have managed to find out about
Kramers’ work, on which you're supposed to lecture our class.”
And so our talk would change quickly from good-humored
insults to more pressing matters. When we talked about physics,
we were often joined by our friend, Otto Laporte, whose sober,
pragmatic approach made him an excellent mediator between
Wolfgang and myself. He and Sommerfeld were later to publish
important papers on the multiplet structure of atomic spectra.
It was probably due to him that the three of us—Wolfgang,
Otto and I—decided to go on a bicycle tour that took us from
Benediktbauern across the Kesselberg to Lake Walchen and“UNDERSTANDING” IN MODERN PHYSICS 29
on into the Loisach Valley. This was probably the only time
Wolfgang dared to enter my world—with the most beneficial
results for myself: the talks we began during that tour and con-
tinued in Munich were to have a lasting effect.
Meanwhile we spent a few happy days on the road. Once we
had reached the saddle of the Kesselberg, laboring uphill with
our bicycles, we could ride effortlessly along a road boldly cut
into the mountain slope past the steep western shore of Lake
Walchen—at the time I had no idea how important this little
spot of earth was to become for me one day. We passed the very
place where an old man and his daughter had once joined
Goethe’s coach en route to Italy, she the model of his future
Mignon, he of the old harpist in Wilhelm Meister! Across this
dark lake, Goethe caught his first glimpse of the snow-covered
Alps. And while we, too, delighted in the glorious landscape, our
conversation kept returning to our studies and to science in
general.
Thus Wolfgang asked me—I think it was one evening at an
inn in Grainau—whether I at long last understood Einstein's
relativity theory, on which Sommerfeld laid so much stress. I could
only say that I did not really know what was meant by “under-
standing” in physics. The mathematical framework of relativity
theory caused me no difficulties, but that did not necessarily
mean that I had “understood” why a moving observer means
something different by “time” than an observer at rest. The
whole thing baffled me, and struck me as being quite “incompre-
hensible.””
“But once you have grasped the mathematical framework,”
Wolfgang objected, “you can surely predict what an observer at
rest and a moving observer ought to observe or measure. And we
have good reason to assume that a real experiment will bear out
these predictions. What more can you ask?”
“That is precisely my problem,” I replied, “that I don’t know
what more I can ask. I feel somewhat cheated by the logic of the
new mathematical framework. You might even say that I have
grasped the theory with my brain, but not yet with my heart. I
think that I don’t have to study physics to know what ‘time’
after all, our every thought and action presupposes a naive time
concept. Perhaps I could put it like this: our thought depends on30 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
the fact that this time concept works, that we can operate with it.
But if our naive time concept has to be changed, then we can no
longer tell whether our language and thought remain useful
working tools. In saying this, I am not trying to hark back to
Kant, for whom time and space were a priori forms of the intui-
tion. In other words, to Kant, as to the earlier physicists, time
and space were absolutes. I only want to stress the fact that our
language and thought become vague whenever we try to change
such basic concepts, and uncertainty goes ill with true under-
standing.”
Otto found my scruples quite unnecessary.
“That's how it may look in the schoolmen’s philosophy,” he
said, “but if they ascribed definite, immutable meanings to the
concepts of time and space, that only goes to show that their
philosophy was false. I can't do anything with beautiful phrases
about the ‘essence’ of space and time. You've probably read more
philosophy than is good for you. Remember this splendid defini-
tion: ‘Philosophy is the systematic misuse of nomenclature spe-
cially invented for the purpose.’ All absolute claims must be
rejected a priori. We ought only to use such words and concepts
as can be directly related to sense perception, with this proviso,
of course, that we may substitute complex physical observations
for direct perception. It is precisely this return to observable
phenomena that is Einstein's great merit. In his relativity theory,
he quite rightly started with the commonplace assumption that
time is what you read off a clock. If you keep to this common-
place meaning, you will have few problems with relativity the-
ory. As soon as a theory allows us to predict the results of an
observation, it gives us all the understanding we need.
Wolfgang now brought up a number of objections: “What you
say is true only under certain conditions, and these ought to be
stated. To begin with, you have to be certain that your theoreti-
cal predictions are unambiguous and self-consistent. In the case
of relativity theory, this is probably guaranteed by the simple
mathematical framework. Next it must be quite clear from the
conceptual structure of a theory to which particular phenomena
it applies and to which it does not. In the absence of this
qualification every theory can be refuted at once, simply because
no theory can predict all the phenomena in the world, But even“UNDERSTANDING” IN MODERN PHYSICS 31
if all these conditions are met, I am still not altogether certain
whether the ability to predict phenomena in a particular area
entitles one to claim full understanding. Conversely, it may be
quite possible to understand a particular realm of experience
completely without being able to predict all the results of future
observations.”
I now tried to show that correct predictions were not neces-
sarily a sign of true understanding by quoting an historical
example. “You know, of course, that the Greek astronomer,
Aristarchus, considered the possibility that the sun might occupy
the center of our planetary system. This view was rejected by
Hipparchus, and then fell into oblivion. Ptolemy started with
the assumption that the earth was the central body, and he
treated the orbits of the planets as superimposed cycles and
epicycles. This enabled him to predict eclipses of the sun and the
moon very precisely, so precisely that for fifteen hundred years
his doctrine was considered the certain foundation of astronomy.
But did Ptolemy really understand the planetary system? Was it
not Newton who, knowing the law of inertia, and introducing
force as the cause of changes of momentum, was the first to give a
proper explanation of planetary motions in terms of gravitation?
Was he not the first to have really understood this type of
motion? This, to me, is a crucial question.
“Or let us take an example from the more recent history of
physics. At the end of the eighteenth century, when electrical
phenomena became better known, physicists were able to make
very precise calculations of the electrostatic forces governing the
behavior of charged bodies, treating them as centers of force in
the manner of Newtonian mechanics. That much at least I gath-
ered from Sommerfeld. But it was only when Faraday changed
the entire problem and inquired into fields of force, i.e., into the
distribution of forces in time and space, that he provided a true
understanding of electromagnetic phenomena, and laid the foun-
dations on which Maxwell could later base his mathematical
formulae.”
Otto did not find my examples particularly convincing. “I can
see only differences in degree, but no basic distinction. Ptolemy's
astronomy must have been very good, else it would not have
lasted for fifteen hundred years. Newton’s didn’t seem much32 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
better at first; it took quite some time before astronomers came to
appreciate that it led to more accurate predictions of the motions
of the planets than Ptolemy's cycles and epicycles. I cannot really
grant you that Newton did something fundamentally better than
Ptolemy. He merely gave a different account of planetary mo-
tions, one that happened to prove more successful in the long
run.”
Wolfgang found this argument too one-sided and much too
positivistic. “I, for one, see a basic distinction between Newton's
astronomy and Ptolemy's,” he said. “To begin with, Newton
posed the whole problem quite differently: he inquired into the
causes of planetary motions and not into the motions themselves.
These causes, he discovered, were forces, and in our planetary
system they happen to be much simpler than the motions. He
described them by means of his law of gravitation. If we say that
Newton helped us to understand the motion of the planets, we
only mean that more precise observations have shown that it is
possible to reduce the complicated motions of the planets to
something very simple, namely, to gravitational forces, and to
explain them in that way. Admittedly, Ptolemy could describe all
the complicated motions of the planets by the superposition of
cycles and epicycles, but he had to treat them as empirical facts.
Moreover, Newton was also able to show that the motions of the
planets are governed by the same laws as those that determine
the motion of a projectile, the oscillation of a pendulum or the
spinning of a top. The mere fact that Newton’s mechanics
reduced all these different phenomena to a simple principle,
namely, ‘mass x acceleration = force,’ shows that his planetary
system is vastly superior to Ptolemy’
Otto still refused to admit defeat. “The word ‘cause’ and the
assertion that force is the cause of motion all sound very well, but
in fact only take us a slight step forward. For we are then com-
pelled to ask the next question: What are the causes of forces in
general and of gravitation in particular? In other words, accord-
ing to your own philosophy, we can only claim ‘real’ understand-
ing of planetary motions once we know the cause of gravitation,
and so on ad infinitum.”
Wolfgang objected strongly to this argument. “Of course we
can keep on asking questions,” he said, “but isn’t that the basis““UNDERSTANDING” IN MODERN PHYSICS 33
of all science? Your argument is not relevant to the point under
discussion. ‘Understanding’ nature surely means taking a close
look at its connections, being certain of its inner workings. Such
knowledge cannot be gained by understanding an isolated phe-
nomenon or a single group of phenomena, even if one discovers
some order in them, It comes from the recognition that a wealth
of experiential facts are interconnected and can therefore be
reduced to a common principle. In that case, certainty rests
precisely on this wealth of facts. The danger of making mistakes
is the smaller, the richer and more complex the phenomena are,
and the simpler is the common principle to which they can all be
brought back. The fact that still wider connections may yet be
discovered makes no difference at all.”
“And so you think,” I asked, “that we can trust in relativity
theory on the grounds that it helps us to combine under a
common heading, or reduce to a common root, a great wealth of
phenomena, for instance in electrodynamics? If I understand you
correctly, you are maintaining that, since in this case a uniform
connection is readily established and can be shown to be mathe-
matically transparent, we get the feeling that we have ‘under-
stood’ relativity, even though we are forced to give the words
‘space’ and ‘time’ a new, or let us say a changed, meaning.”
“Yes, I do mean something like that. The decisive steps of
Newton and of Faraday were, in each case, their new way of
asking questions and of formulating concepts by which the
correct answers could be obtained. ‘Understanding’ probably
means nothing more than having whatever ideas and concepts
are needed to recognize that a great many different phenomena
are part of a coherent whole. Our mind becomes less puzzled
once we have recognized that a special, apparently confused
situation is merely a special case of something wider, that as a
result it can be formulated much more simply. The reduction of
a colorful variety of phenomena to a general and simple prin-
ciple, or, as the Greeks would have put it, the reduction of the
many to the one, is precisely what we mean by ‘understanding.’
The ability to predict is often the consequence of understanding,
of having the right concepts, but is not identical with under-
standing.”
Otto murmured: “ ‘The systematic misuse of nomenclature34 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
specially invented for the purpose.’ I cannot for the life of me see
why it is necessary to speak in such complicated ways about
simple things. If we use language to refer to direct sense impres-
sions, then few misunderstandings can arise—every word has a
precise meaning, and if a theory sticks to that limitation, it will
always be comprehensible, even without a lot of philosophizing.”
But Wolfgang refused to accept this. “Your suggestion, which
sounds so terribly plausible, has already been made, by Mach
and others. It has even been said that Einstein arrived at his
theory of relativity simply by sticking to Mach’s doctrine, But
this strikes me as a crude oversimplification. It is well known that
Mach did not believe in the existence of atoms, on the grounds
that they cannot be observed. For all that, atoms were needed to
explain a host of physical and chemical phenomena that had
eluded scientists in the past. Mach himself was obviously led
astray by the very principle you defend, and, as far as I am
concerned, this was not by chance.”
“Everybody can make mistakes,” Otto said, trying to calm us
down. “But mistakes are no excuse for making things more
complicated than they are. The theory of relativity is so simple
that anyone can grasp it. But when it comes to atomic theory,
things are very much more obscure.”
This brought us to our second theme, which kept us busy long
after our bicycle tour was over. It was to become the source of
keen arguments in our Munich seminar, often in Sommerfeld’s
presence.
The central subject of Sommerfeld’s seminar was Bohr’s atomic
theory. Basing his ideas on decisive experiments by Rutherford,
Bohr had depicted the atom as a tiny planetary system with a
central nucleus which, though considerably smaller than the
atom, carried most of its mass. About this nucleus, a number of
extremely lightweight electrons revolved like so many planets.
However, while the orbits of planets were determined by known
forces and the past history of the system, and hence subject to
perturbations, the orbits of electrons were said to call for
additional postulates of a special kind, postulates that helped to
explain the peculiar stability of matter when exposed to external
influences. Ever since Planck had published his famous work in
1g00, these additional postulates were known as quantum con-“UNDERSTANDING” IN MODERN PHYSICS 35
ditions, and it was they which had introduced into atomic physics
that strange element of number mysticism to which I referred
earlier. Certain magnitudes that could be computed from an
orbit were said to be integral multiples of a basic unit, namely,
Planck's quantum of action. Such rules were highly reminiscent
of Pythagorean ideas, according to which two vibrating strings
were in harmony if, with equal tension, their lengths were in
simple proportion. But what did the orbits of electrons have to
do with vibrating strings? Even more confusing was the new ex-
planation of light emission by atoms. In this process, a radiating
electron was said to jump from one quantum orbit to the next,
and to emit the energy thus liberated as a whole packet, or light
quantum. Such ideas would never have been taken seriously had
they not helped to explain a whole range of experiments with
great accuracy.
This peculiar mixture of incomprehensible mumbo jumbo and
empirical success quite naturally exerted a great fascination on
us young students. Soon after the beginning of my studies,
Sommerfeld set me a test: from the observations which an experi-
mental physicist of his acquaintance had communicated to him, I
was to deduce the electron orbits and quantum numbers in-
volved. The task itself was not difficult, but the results proved
extremely perplexing; apart from integral quantum numbers, I
was also forced to admit halves, and this ran counter to the spirit
of quantum theory and of Sommerfeld’s number mysticism.
Wolfgang suggested that I would soon have to introduce quarters
and eighths as well, until finally the whole quantum theory would
crumble to dust in my capable hands. And try as I might, I could
not get rid of the embarrassing fraction.
Wolfgang had set himself a more difficult task. He wanted to
find out whether in a more complicated system, one that could
only be determined by astronomical computations, Bohr’s theory
and the Bohr-Sommerfeld quantum conditions would still lead
to experimentally valid results. In fact, during our Munich dis-
cussions, some of us had begun to feel that the earlier successes of
the theory might have been due to the use of particularly simple
systems, and that the theory would break down in a slightly more
complicated one.
In this connection, Wolfgang asked me one day: “Do you36 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
honestly believe that such things as electron orbits really exist
inside the atom?”
My answer may have sounded a little labored. “To begin
with,” I told him, “we can observe the path of an electron in a
cloud chamber: it leaves a clear trail of fog where it has passed.
And since there is such a thing as an electron trajectory in the
cloud chamber, we may take it that it will occur in the atom as
well. But I have some reservations on that score. For while we
determine the path itself by classical Newtonian methods, we use
quantum conditions to account for its stability, thus flying in the
face of Newtonian mechanics. And when it comes to electrons
jumping from one orbit into the next—as the theory demands—
we are careful not to specify whether they make high jumps, long
jumps or some other sorts of jump. It all makes me think that
something is radically wrong with the whole idea of electron
orbits. But what is the alternative?”
Wolfgang nodded. “The whole thing seems a myth. If there
really were such a thing as an electron orbit, the electron would
obviously have to revolve periodically, with a given frequency.
Now, we know from electrodynamics that if an electrical charge
is set in periodic motion, it must emit electrical vibrations, i.e.,
radiate light of a characteristic frequency. But this is not sup-
posed to happen with the electron; instead, the frequency of
vibration of the emitted light is said to lie somewhere between
the orbital frequency before the mysterious jump and the orbital
frequency after the jump. All this is sheer madness.”
“*Though this be madness, yet there is method in 't,’” I
quoted.
“Yes, perhaps. Niels Bohr claims that he can tell the electron
orbits of every atom in the periodic system, and the two of us do
not even believe in the existence of such orbits. Sommerfeld
perhaps disagrees with us. And, in fact, anyone can see electronic
orbits in a cloud chamber. Quite likely Niels Bohr is right in a
sense, though we cannot tell precisely in what sense.”
Unlike Wolfgang, I felt optimistic about the issue, and I may
have said something like this: “I find Bohr's physics most fasci-
nating, difficulties and all. Bohr must surely know that he starts
from contradictory assumptions which cannot be correct in their
present form. But he has an unerring instinct for using these very“UNDERSTANDING” IN MODERN PHYSICS 37
assumptions to construct fairly convincing models of atomic
processes. Bohr uses classical mechanics or quantum theory just
as a painter uses his brushes and colors. Brushes do not deter-
mine the picture, and color is never the full reality; but if he
keeps the picture before his mind's eye, the artist can use his
brush to convey, however inadequately, his own mental picture
to others. Bohr knows precisely how atoms behave during light
emission, in chemical processes and in many other phenomena,
and this has helped him to form an intuitive picture of the
structure of different atoms; a picture he can only convey to
other physicists by such inadequate means as electron orbits and
quantum conditions. It is not at all certain that Bohr himself
believes that electrons revolve inside the atom. But he is con-
vinced of the correctness of his picture. The fact that he cannot
yet express it by adequate linguistic or mathematical techniques
is no disaster. On the contrary, it is a great challenge.”
Wolfgang remained skeptical. “I must first of all find out
whether the Bohr-Sommerfeld assumptions will lead to reason-
able results in the case of my problem. If not—and I almost sus-
pect that I shall discover just that—I shall at least know what
does not work, and that, too, is a great step forward.” Then he
added reflectively: “Bohr’s pictures may be right after all. But
what are we to make of them, and what laws do they express?”
Some time later, Sommerfeld asked me rather unexpectedly,
after a long talk about atomic theory: “Would you like to meet
Niels Bohr? He is about to give a series of lectures in Géttingen.
I have been invited, and I should like to take you along.” I
hesitated for a moment—the fare to Géttingen and return was
quite beyond my financial resources. Perhaps Sommerfeld saw
the shadow flit across my face. In any case, he quickly added that
he would see to my expenses, whereupon I accepted with grati-
tude and alacrity.
In the early summer of 1922 Gottingen, that friendly little
town of villas and gardens on the slopes of the Hain Mountain,
was a mass of blooming shrubs, rose gardens and flower beds.
Nature herself seemed to approve the name we later gave those
wonderful days: the Géttingen Bohr Festival. I shall never
forget the first lecture. The hall was filled to capacity. The great
Danish physicist, whose very stature proclaimed him a Scandi-38 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
navian, stood on the platform, his head slightly inclined, and a
friendly but somewhat embarrassed smile on his lips. Summer
light flooded in through the wide-open windows. Bohr spoke
fairly softly, with a slight Danish accent. When he explained the
individual assumptions of his theory, he chose his words very care-
fully, much more carefully than Sommerfeld usually did. And
each one of his carefully formulated sentences revealed a long
chain of underlying thoughts, of philosophical reflections, hinted
at but never fully expressed. I found this approach highly excit-
ing; what he said seemed both new and not quite new at the
same time. We had all of us learned Bohr's theory from Sommer-
feld, and knew what it was about, but it all sounded quite
different from Bohr’s own lips. We could clearly sense that he
had reached his results not so much by calculation and demon-
stration as by intuition and inspiration, and that he found it
difficult to justify his findings before Géttingen’s famous school
of mathematics. Each lecture was followed by long discussions,
and at the end of the third lecture I myself dared to make a
critical remark,
Bohr had been talking about Kramers’ contribution—the sub-
ject on which I had been asked to speak in Sommerfeld’s seminar
—and he concluded that, although the basis of Kramers’ theory
was still unexplained, it seemed certain that the results were
correct and would one day be confirmed by experiment. I then
rose and advanced objections to Kramers’ theory based on our
Munich discussions.
Bohr must have gathered that my remarks sprang from pro-
found interest in his atomic theory. He replied hesitantly, as
though he were slightly worried by my objection, and at the end
of the discussion he came over to me and asked me to join him
that afternoon on a walk over the Hain Mountain, There we
might go more deeply into the whole problem.
This walk was to have profound repercussions on my scientific
career, or perhaps it is more correct to say that my real scientific
career only began that afternoon. A well-tended mountain path
took us past a popular coffeehouse, Zum Rohns, to a sunlit
height, from which we looked down on the small university town,
dominated by the spires of the old churches of St. John and St.
Jacob and, beyond, across the Leine Valley.“UNDERSTANDING” IN MODERN PHYSICS 39
Bohr opened the conversation. “This morning,” he said, “you
expressed some reservations about Kramers’ work. I must tell you
at once that I fully understand the nature of your doubts. Per-
haps I ought to explain where I stand myself. Basically, I agree
with you much more than you might think; I realize full well
how cautious one has to be with assertions about the structure
of atoms. I had best begin by telling you a little about the history
of this theory. My starting point was not at all the idea that an
atom is a small-scale planetary system and as such governed by
the laws of astronomy. I never took things as literally as that, My
starting point was rather the stability of matter, a pure miracle
when considered from the standpoint of classical physics.
“By ‘stability’ I mean that the same substances always have the
same properties, that the same crystals recur, the same chemical
compounds, etc. In other words, even after a host of changes due
to external influences, an iron atom will always remain an iron
atom, with exactly the same properties as before. This cannot be
explained by the principles of classical mechanics, certainly not if
the atom resembles a planetary system. Nature clearly has a
tendency to produce certain forms—I use the word ‘forms’ in the
most general sense—and to recreate these forms even when they
are disturbed or destroyed. You may even think of biology: the
stability of living organisms, the propagation of the most compli-
cated forms which, after all, can exist only in their entirety. But
in biology we are dealing with highly complex structures, subject
to characteristic, temporary transformations of a kind that need
not detain us here. Let us rather stick to the simpler forms we
study in physics and chemistry. The existence of uniform sub-
stances, of solid bodies, depends on the stability of atoms; that is
precisely why an electron tube filled with a certain gas will
always emit light of the same color, a spectrum with exactly
the same lines. All this, far from being self-evident, is quite
inexplicable in terms of the basic principle of Newtonian physics,
according to which all effects have precisely determined causes,
and according to which the present state of a phenomenon or
process is fully determined by the one that immediately preceded
it. This fact used to disturb me a great deal when I first began to
look into atomic physics.
“The miracle of the stability of matter might have gone un-40 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
noticed even longer had experiments during the past few decades
not thrown fresh light on the whole subject. Planck, as you know,
discovered that the energy of an atomic system changes discon-
tinuously; that when such a system emits energy, it passes
through certain states with selected energy values. I myself later
coined the term ‘stationary states’ for them. Next came Ruther-
ford’s crucial studies of the structure of the atom. It was in
Rutherford’s Manchester laboratory that I first became ac-
quainted with the problems involved. At the time, I was barely
older than you are today, and I kept plying Rutherford with
long questions, Physicists had just begun to take a closer look at
luminous phenomena and were busily determining the character-
istic spectral lines of the various chemical elements; needless to
say, chemists, too, produced a wealth of information on the
behavior of atoms. These developments, which I was privileged
to witness at close quarters, naturally made me wonder how all
these things hung together. The theory I tried to put forward was
meant to do no more than establish that connection.
“Now, this was really a hopeless task, quite different from
those physicists normally tackle. For in all previous physics, or in
any other branch of science, you could always try to explain a
new phenomenon by reducing it to known phenomena or laws.
In atomic physics, however, all previous concepts have proved
inadequate. We know from the stability of matter that New-
tonian physics does not apply to the interior of the atom; at best
it can occasionally offer us a guideline. It follows that there can be
no descriptive account of the structure of the atom; all such
accounts must necessarily be based on classical concepts which, as
we saw, no longer apply. You see that anyone trying to develop
such a theory is really trying the impossible. For we intend to say
something about the structure of the atom but lack a language in
which we can make ourselves understood. We are in much the
same position as a sailor, marooned on a remote island where
conditions differ radically from anything he has ever known and
where, to make things worse, the natives speak a completely alien
tongue. He simply must make himself understood, but has no
means of doing so. In that sort of situation a theory cannot
‘explain’ anything in the usual strict scientific sense of the word.
All it can hope to do is to reveal connections and, for the rest,“UNDERSTANDING” IN MODERN PHYSICS 4.
leave us to grope as best we can. That is precisely what Kramers’
calculations were intended to do; perhaps I failed to stress this
sufficiently at my lecture. And to do more than that is quite
beyond our present means.”
From Bohr's remarks it was quite obvious that he was familiar
with all the doubts we ourselves had been expressing. But to
make doubly sure that I had understood him, I asked: “If that is
all we can do, what is the point of all those atomic models you
produced and justified during the past few lectures? What ex-
actly did you try to prove with them?”
“These models,” Bohr replied, “have been deduced, or if you
prefer guessed, from experiments, not from theoretical calcula-
tions. I hope that they describe the structure of the atoms as well,
but only as well, as is possible in the descriptive language of
classical physics. We must be clear that, when it comes to atoms,
language can be used only as in poetry. ‘The poet, too, is not
nearly so concerned with describing facts as with creating images
and establishing mental connections.”
“But in that case how are we ever to make progress? After all,
physics is supposed to be an exact science.”
“It seems likely that the paradoxes of quantum theory, those
incomprehensible features reflecting the stability of matter, will
become sharper with every new experiment. If that happens, we
can only hope that, in due course, new concepts will emerge
which may somehow help us to grasp these inexpressible proc-
esses in the atom. But we are still a long way from that.”
Bohr's remark reminded me of Robert’s comment, during our
walk near Lake Starnberg, that atoms were not things. For
although Bohr believed that he knew a great many details about
the inner structure of atoms, he did not look upon the electrons
in the atomic shell as “things,” in any case not as things in the
sense of classical physics, which worked with such concepts as
position, velocity, energy and extension. I therefore asked him:
“If the inner structure of the atom is as closed to descriptive
accounts as you say, if we really lack a language for dealing with
it, how can we ever hope to understand atoms?”
Bohr hesitated for a moment, and then said: “I think we may
yet be able to do so, But in the process we may have to learn
what the word ‘understanding’ really means.”42 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
Our little walk had taken us to the peak of the Hain Mountain,
to the famous Kehr Inn, so called because since olden times peo-
ple used to turn back here [umkehren]. We, too, now made for the
lowland, this time in a southerly direction, and looked down
over the hills, woods and villages of the Leine Valley, long since
incorporated into Géttingen town.
“We have talked about so many difficult subjects,” Bohr con-
tinued, “and I have told you how I myself first got into this
whole business; but I know nothing at all about you. You look
very young. From your questions, it almost seems as if you started
with atomic theory first, and then went on to take a look at
orthodox physics. Sommerfeld must have introduced you to this
adventurous world of atoms at a very early age. Do tell me about
it and also about what you did in the war.”
I confessed that, being twenty, I was only in my fourth term at
the university, and that I knew very little indeed about general
physics. I went on to tell him about Sommerfeld’s class, where I
had been especially attracted by the mysterious, inexplicable
features of quantum theory. I added that I had been too young
to serve in the army, but that my father had fought in France as
a reserve officer and I had been very anxious about him. He was
wounded in 1916 and was sent back home. During the last year
of the war, I worked as a farm laborer in the Lower Bavarian
Alps, to keep body and soul together. Otherwise I had been
spared by the war.
“I should like to hear a lot more from you,” Bohr said, “‘and to
learn more about conditions in your country, of which I know so
little. And about the Youth Movement, of which I have heard so
much from my colleagues in Géttingen. You must pay us a visit
in Copenhagen; perhaps you could stay with us for a term, and
we might do some physics together. And then I'll show you round
our small country and tell you about its history.”
As we approached the edge of the town, the conversation
turned to Géttingen’s leading physicists and mathematicians—
Max Born, James Franck, Richard Courant and David Hilbert,
all of whom I had only just met. Bohr suggested that I might do
part of my studies under them, Suddenly the future looked full
of hope and new possibilities, which, after seeing Bohr home, I
painted to myself in the most glorious colors all the way back to
my lodgings.4
Lessons in Politics
and History (1922-1924)
The summer of 1922 ended on what, for me, was a rather sadden-
ing note. My teacher, Sommerfeld, had suggested that I attend
the Congress of German Scientists and Physicians in Leipzig,
where Einstein, one of the chief speakers, would lecture on the
general theory of relativity. My father had bought me the return-
trip ticket from Munich, and I was looking forward greatly to
this chance of hearing the discoverer of relativity theory in
person. Once in Leipzig, I moved into one of the cheapest inns in
the poorest quarter of the city—I could afford nothing better.
Then I made for the meeting hall, where I found a number of
the younger physicists whose acquaintance I had made in Gét-
tingen during the “Bohr Festival,” and asked them about Ein-
stein’s lecture, scheduled within a few hours. I noticed a certain
tension all around me, which struck me as being rather odd, but
then Leipzig was not Géttingen. I filled in the waiting time with
a walk to the Memorial (to the great Battle of Leipzig), where,
hungry and exhausted by the overnight railway journey, I lay
down on the grass and at once fell asleep. I was wakened by a
young girl who had decided to pelt me with plums. She sat down
beside me, and made her peace with me with generous offerings
of fruit from her ample basket.
The lecture theater was a large hall with doors on all sides. As
I was about to enter, a young man—I learned later that he was
an assistant or pupil of a well-known professor of physics in a
South German university—pressed a red handbill into my hand,
warning me against Einstein and relativity. The whole theory44 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
was said to be nothing but wild speculation, blown up by the
Jewish press and entirely alien to the German spirit. At first I
thought the whole thing was the work of some lunatic, ‘for
madmen are wont to turn up at all big meetings. However, when
I was told that the author was a man renowned for his experi-
mental work, to whom Sommerfeld had often referred in his
lectures, I felt as if part of my world were collapsing. All along, I
had been firmly convinced that science at least was above the
kind of political strife that had led to the civil war in Munich,
and of which I wished to have no further part. And now I made
the sad discovery that men of weak or pathological character can
inject their twisted political passions even into scientific life.
Needless to say, my immediate reaction was to drop any reserva-
tions I may have had with regard to Einstein's theory, or rather
to what I knew about it from Wolfgang’s occasional explana-
tions. For if I had learned one thing from my experiences during
the civil war, it was that one must never judge a political
movement by the aims it so loudly proclaims and perhaps
genuinely strives to attain, but only by the means it uses to
achieve them. The choice of bad means simply proves that those
responsible have lost faith in the persuasive force of their origi-
nal arguments. In this instance, the means applied by a leading
physicist in his attempt to refute the theory of relativity were so
bad and insubstantial that they could signify only one thing: the
man had abandoned all hope of ever refuting the theory with
scientific arguments.
Still, so upset was I by this spectacle that I failed to pay proper
attention to Einstein himself, and, at the end of the lecture,
forgot to avail myself of Sommerfeld’s offer to introduce me to
the speaker. Instead, I returned somberly to my inn, only to
discover that all my possessions—rucksack, linen, socks and sec-
ond suit—had been stolen. Luckily I still had my return ticket. I
went to the station and took the next train to Munich. I was in
utter despair because I knew that my father would find it
extremely hard to make up my loss. And so, upon discovering
that my parents were out of the city, I took a job as a woodman
in Forstenried Park, south of the town. The pines there had
been attacked by bark beetles, and a large number of trees had to
be felled and their bark burned. Only when I had earned enoughLESSONS IN POLITICS AND HISTORY 45
money to replenish my meager wardrobe did I return to my
studies,
I have mentioned this whole unhappy episode, not to resurrect
events that are best forgotten, but because it later cropped up in
my conversations with Niels Bohr and affected my behavior in
the dangerous no-man’s land between science and politics. At
first, the Leipzig experience left me with a deep sense of disap-
pointment and with doubts about the validity of science in
general. For if science, too, was more concerned with private
feuds than with discovering the truth, was it really worth bother-
ing with? Luckily, in the end, memories of my walk with Niels
Bohr prevailed over all such pessimistic thoughts, and I was
hopeful that I might one day avail myself of Bohr’s generous
invitation and have many more talks with him in Copenhagen.
As it happened, a year and a half were to go by before this
came to pass. Meanwhile I spent a term at Géttingen, submitted
a thesis on the stability of laminar flow in fluids, sat for my
examination in Munich and, for another term, served as Max
Born’s assistant in Gottingen. During the Easter vacation of 1924
I finally boarded the Warnemiinde ferry for Denmark. Through-
out the trip I feasted my eyes on a host of colorful boats,
including four-masters in full rig. At the end of the First World
War, a large part of the world’s merchant fleet had ended up at
the bottom of the sea, with the result that the old sailing boats
had to be brought out again, and the seascape looked all the
brighter for it—much as it had done a hundred years before.
When I eventually disembarked, I had some trouble with cus-
toms—I knew no Danish and could not account for myself
properly. However, as soon as it became clear that I was about to
work in Professor Bohr’s Institute, all difficulties were swept
out of the way and all doors were opened to me. And so from
the very outset I felt safe under the protection of one of the
greatest personalities in this small but friendly country.
Not that my first few days in the Institute were particularly
easy for me. I suddenly came face to face with a large number of
brilliant young men from every part of the world, all of them
greatly superior to me, not only in linguistic prowess and world-
liness, but also in their knowledge of physics. I saw very little of
Bohr himself; he obviously had his hands full with administra-46 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
tive tasks, and I obviously had no right to make greater claims on
his time than had other members of the Institute. But after a few
days, he came into my room and asked me to join him for a few
days’ walking tour through the island of Zealand. In the Insti-
tute itself, he said, there was little chance for lengthy talks, and
he wanted to get to know me better.
And so the two of us set out with our rucksacks. First we took
the trolley to the northern edge of the city, and from there we
walked through the Deer Park, once a hunting preserve. We
admired the beautiful little Hermitage Castle right in its center,
and watched large herds of deer graze in the clearings. Then we
made for the north, sometimes hugging the coast, sometimes
walking through forests and past peaceful lakes, studded with
summer houses still sleeping behind closed shutters—it was early
spring and the trees were only just putting out their first tender
shoots. Our talk turned to conditions in Germany, and Bohr
asked what I remembered about the outbreak of war, ten years
before.
“I have heard a great deal about those days,” he told me.
“Friends of ours who traveled through Germany early in August
1914 spoke of a great wave of enthusiasm that gripped not only
the whole German nation but even outsiders, whose emotions,
however, were tempered with horror. Isn’t it odd that a whole
people should have gone into war in a flush of war fever, when
they ought to have known how many friends and enemies alike
that war would swallow up, how many injustices would be
committed by both sides? Can you explain any of this?”
“I was only twelve at the time,” I replied, “and obviously my
opinions were based on what I picked up from conversations
between my parents and grandparents. Still, I don’t think the
words ‘war fever’ quite describe the situation. No one I knew was
happy about what lay before us, and no one was pleased that the
war had started. If you ask me to describe what happened, I
would say we suddenly realized that things had become serious.
We felt that we had all been living in a world of dreams, and
that this beautiful world had suddenly been shattered by the
murder of the heir to the Austrian crown. Suddenly we were face
to face with reality, with a call none of us could refuse, a call we
had to answer come what may—with heavy hearts, but with all
our hearts nonetheless. Needless to say, we were all convinced ofLESSONS IN POLITICS AND HISTORY 47
the justice of the German cause, for Germany and Austria were
like one country, and the murder of the Archduke Francis Ferdi-
nand and his wife by members of a secret Serbian society struck
us as a crime against us all. So we had to defend ourselves, and,
as I have said, most Germans decided to do so wholeheartedly.
“Now, such popular decisions have something highly seductive
about them, something quite uncanny and irrational—even 1
could feel that in August 1914. I was traveling with my parents
from Munich to Osnabriick, where my father, who was a captain
in the Reserves, had to report for duty. All the railway stations
were filled with shouting crowds of excited people; freight cars,
decorated with flowers and branches, were packed with soldiers
and guns. Young women and children stood alongside them;
there was much crying and singing until the train left the
station. You could address any stranger you wanted to as if you
were old friends; everyone helped everyone else—we had all
become brothers in fate. I should not like to eradicate this day
from my memory. And yet this incredible, this unimaginable
day, a day no one who witnessed it could forget, had nothing to
do with what is commonly called war fever. I think that the
whole thing was distorted after the event.”
“You must realize,” Bohr said, “that we, in our small country,
take quite a different view of such matters. Look at it historically.
Perhaps Germany's expansion during the last century proved just
a little too easy. There was first of all the war against our country
in 1864, which caused so much bitterness among us, then your
victory over Austria in 1866 and over France in 1870. To Ger-
mans, it must have looked as if a great Central European Empire
could be built almost overnight. But things aren’t ever that
simple. To found empires one must first win the hearts of the
people. This the Prussians, for all their efficiency, obviously failed
to do; perhaps because their way of life was too hard, or perhaps
because their ideas of discipline did not appeal to others. By the
time Germany came to realize that, it was too late. In any case, the
German attack on the small country of Belgium struck the out-
side world as an act of blatant aggression, in no way justified
even by the assassination of the Austrian heir. After all, Belgium
had nothing to do with the assassination, nor was it a party to
any alliance against Germany.”
“Certainly we Germans committed a great many wrongs in48 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
that war,” I had to admit, “just as our opponents did. But then
war is bound to lead to wrongs. And I must also admit that the
only tribunal competent to decide the issue—world history—has
found against us. Otherwise, I am probably much too young to
judge which politicians made the right or wrong decisions in
which places. But there are two things that have always bothered
me, and I should like to know what you think about them.
“I told you that when war was declared, the whole world
seemed completely changed. All petty, everyday cares suddenly
disappeared. Personal and family relationships, once the very
center of our lives, gave way to the broader solidarity of a whole
nation sharing a common fate. Houses, streets, forests—every-
thing looked quite different, or, as Jakob Burckhardt has put it,
‘Heaven itself took on a fresh hue.’ My best friend, a cousin
from Osnabriick, who was a few years older than I, became a
soldier. I do not know whether he was conscripted or whether he
volunteered. Such questions were never even asked. The great
decision had been made, everyone who was physically fit joined
the army. My cousin would never have had the least wish to
make war on anyone, or to fight for German conquests, though
he was certain of our victory. So much I gathered from our last
conversation just before he left. All we knew was that he was
expected to offer his life, like all the rest. He may for a
moment have been deeply frightened, but still he said yes like
everyone else. Had I been a few years older, I would probably
have done the same thing. My cousin died in France. Do you
think he ought to have told himself that the whole war was
nonsense, a fever, mass suggestion, and have refused this call on
his life? Who has the right to decide? A young man who could
not possibly hope to see through the machinations of world
politics, who knew no more than a few facts, difficult enough to
grasp in themselves: a murder in Sarajevo or our invasion of
Belgium?”
“What you tell me makes me very sad,” Bohr replied, “for I
think I can see what you are getting at. Perhaps what these
young men felt as they went to war, certain of their cause, is part
of the greatest happiness men can experience. But surely that is a
terrible truth, When men go to war, don’t you feel that they some-
how resemble migratory birds who flock together in the autumnLESSONS IN POLITICS AND HISTORY 49
before heading south? None of these birds knows which has
decided on the flight or even why they must migrate, but each is
gripped by the same prevailing agitation, the same wish to join
in, even if the flight leads to death. In human beings, the re-
markable fact is that, on the one hand, the reaction is as ele-
mental and as uncontrollable as, for instance, a forest fire or any
other natural phenomenon, while, on the other hand, it releases
a sense of almost boundless individual freedom. The young man
who goes to war has thrown off the burden of his daily cares and
worries. When life or death is at stake, petty reservations, all
those qualms that normally restrict our lives, are cast to the winds.
We have only one aim—victory—and life seems simple and clear
as never before. There is probably no more beautiful description
of this unique situation in the life of a young man than the
trooper’s song in Schiller’s Wallenstein. You must know the last
lines: ‘Who would share life must risk it, and none who refuse
the hazard shall gain it—who risks it may lose!’ This is probably
quite true. Yet for all that, we must say no, must make every
effort to avoid wars, indeed all international conflicts from which
wars arise. Our walk through Denmark may be a small step in
that direction.”
“I should like to put my second question, if I may,” I con-
tinued. “You have spoken of the Prussian sense of discipline, and
have told me that it does not appeal to other people. I myself
grew up in southern Germany, and our tradition is such that we
think somewhat differently from people born between Magde-
burg and Kénigsberg. Yet the principles of Prussian life—the
subordination of individual ambition to the common cause,
modesty in private life, honesty and incorruptibility, gallantry
and punctuality—have always attracted me. Even though these
principles have been misused by politicians, 1 cannot really
despise them. Why do you Danes, for instance, feel so differ-
ently?”
“I believe,” Bohr said, “that we do appreciate the virtues of
this Prussian attitude. But we prefer to give greater scope to the
individual, to his dreams and plans, than the Prussian principle
permits. We wish to be part of a community of free people, each
of whom fully recognizes the rights of all the others. Freedom
and individual independence are more important to us than50 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
strength derived from external discipline. It is very strange, isn’t
it, that our ideas of the good life should so often be molded by
historical models, which have survived only in myths or legends,
and yet retain their hold on us. The Prussian, I believe, models
himself on the Teutonic knight, who swore the monk's vow of
poverty, chastity and obedience, who spread the Christian light,
sword in hand. We in Denmark prefer the heroes of the Icelandic
sagas, the poet Egill, son of Skallagrim, who at the tender age of
three defied his father, fetched himself a horse and followed
Skallagrim on his long ride. Or the wise Njall, who was better
versed in the law than all men on the island, and whose advice
was sought in all disputes. These men, or their ancestors, had
gone to Iceland because they did not want to bend to the will of
the mighty Norwegian kings. They refused to serve masters who
could order them into a war that was the king's and not their
own, They were all of them brave warriors and I am afraid lived
chiefly on piracy. When you read these sagas, you will probably
be horrified by all the talk of fighting and killing. But these men
wanted above all to be free, and they respected the right of
others to be as free as they were themselves. They fought over
possessions or honor, but not for power over others.
“Naturally, we cannot tell to what extent these sagas are based
on historical fact. But within these terse chronicles of life in
Iceland we can sense a great poetic force, so that it is not surpris-
ing that they should have continued to mold our ideas of
freedom to this day. Life in Britain, also, where the Normans
were once so prominent, has been stamped by this spirit of
independence. The British form of democracy, the Englishman's
sense of fairness and respect for the ideas and interests of others,
his high regard for justice and law, may well derive from the
same source. No doubt, that is why the British were able to build
up a great empire. Admittedly, they, too, were guilty of acts of
violence, much as the old Vikings were.”
It was afternoon now, and we were walking close to the shore,
through small fishermen’s villages. Across the Gresund we could
see the Swedish coast a few miles away bathed in the setting sun.
‘When we reached Helsingér, it was getting dark, but we decided
to take a quick walk through the precincts of Kronborg Castle,
which dominates the narrowest part of the Gresund, and whoseLESSONS IN POLITICS AND HISTORY 51
ramparts still bristle with old guns, symbols of a power long since
gone. Bohr began to tell me about the history of this castle.
Frederick I] of Denmark had it built toward the end of the
sixteenth century, in the Dutch Renaissance style. The walls no
less than the bastion jutting out far into the Gresund serve as
reminders of its military past. In the seventeenth century Swedish
prisoners of war were still locked up in its casements. But now, as
we stood next to the old guns in the dusk looking alternately
across at the sailing boats on the Gresund and the tall Renais-
sance building behind us, we clearly sensed the harmony of a
spot in which struggle had long since ceased. True, you still feel
the pull of forces that once drove men against one another,
destroying ships, raising cries of victories and screams of despair,
but you also know that they no longer shape people’s lives. One
gets a direct, almost physical sense of peace all around.
Kronborg Castle, or rather the spot on which it stands, is
connected with the legend of Hamlet, the Danish Prince who
went mad or shammed madness to escape the machinations of his
murderous uncle. Bohr mentioned the legend and went on to
say: “Isn't it strange how this castle changes as soon as one
imagines that Hamlet lived here? As scientists we believe that a
castle consists only of stones, and admire the way the architect
put them together. The stones, the green roof with its patina, the
wood carvings in the church, constitute the whole castle. None of
this should be changed by the fact that Hamlet lived here, and
yet it is changed completely. Suddenly the walls and the ram-
parts speak a quite different language. The courtyard becomes an
entire world, a dark corner reminds us of the darkness in the
human soul, we hear Hamlet's ‘To be or not to be.’ Yet all we
really know about Hamlet is that his name appears in a thir-
teenth-century chronicle. No one can prove that he really lived,
let alone that he lived here. But everyone knows the questions
Shakespeare had him ask, the human depths he was made to
reveal, and so, he, too, had to be found a place on earth, here in
Kronborg. And once we know that, Kronborg becomes quite a
different castle for us.””
While we were talking, dusk had turned almost into night; a
cold wind was blowing across the Gresund and forced us to leave.
By next morning, the wind had freshened considerably. The52 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
sky was swept clean, and across the bright blue Baltic we could
see the Swedish coast as far as Kullen Peninsula in the north. We
walked westward along the northern shore of Zealand, some
seventy to a hundred feet above sea level and here and there
sheer above the waves. Looking across to Kullen, Bohr said: “You
grew up in Munich close to the mountains, and you have told me
a great deal about your mountain walks. I know that mountain-
dwellers must find Denmark terribly flat and boring. Perhaps you
will never be able to like my country. But to us the sea is all-
important. As we look across it, we think that part of infinity lies
within our grasp.”
“I can sense that,” I replied, ‘and I noticed it particularly in
the faces of the fishermen we met yesterday on the beach—people
here have a distant, serene look. In the mountains things are
quite different. There the eye passes from the nearby detail over
rather complicated rock formations or icy peaks straight up to
the sky. Perhaps that is why our people are so gay.”
“We have only one mountain in Denmark,” Bohr explained.
“It is just over five hundred feet high and strikes us as so mag-
nificent that we call it the Heavenly Peak. It is said that,
when one of our compatriots tried to impress a Norwegian friend
with this splendid phenomenon, the visitor looked at it disdain-
fully and said, ‘That's what we call a dump in Norway.’ I hope
you won't be so hard on our landscape. But please tell me some-
thing about your own mountain walks with friends from the
Youth Movement.”
“We often set out for several weeks at a time. Last summer we
went from Wiirzburg across the Rhén Mountains as far as the
southern edge of the Harz Mountains, and from there by way of
Jena and Weimar back into the Thuringian Forest and on to
Bamberg. When it's warm enough, we usually sleep out in the
open, but more often we sleep in a tent, or, if the weather is too
bad, in a farmer's hay barn. Sometimes to pay for our shelter, we
help with the harvest, and occasionally, if we make ourselves
particularly useful, we get all sorts of wonderful farm fare as
well. Otherwise we cook for ourselves, generally over a campfire
in the forest, and in the evenings we read stories by the light of
the logs or we sing or play music. Members of the Youth Move-LESSONS IN POLITICS AND HISTORY 53
ment have collected many old folk songs and have arranged them
for parts with violin and flute accompaniment. Such music-
making gives us all a great deal of pleasure, even though we
often play it badly rather than well.
“Perhaps we sometimes imagine ourselves in the medieval role
of traveling scholars, and compare the catastrophe of the last war
and the subsequent political strife with the hopeless confusion of
the Thirty Years’ War, which in spite of its horrors is said to have
inspired many of these songs. A feeling of kinship with that age
seems to have seized young people all over Germany. I remember
being stopped in the street by an unknown boy, who asked me to
join a mass meeting of young people in an ancient castle. And,
indeed, when I got there, scores of young people were already
streaming toward the place, which stands in a most picturesque
spot in the Swabian Jura and looks down from an almost vertical
rock into the Altmithl Valley. I was quite overcome by the forces
generated at this spontaneous gathering, much as I was on the first
of August, 1914. Otherwise, our Youth Movement has very little
to do with political issues.”
“The life you describe seems highly romantic, and I would be
quite tempted to share it. Moreover, I can see that you are
swayed by the chivalrous ideals of which we spoke yesterday. But
you don’t have to take an oath, do you, before you join, as the
Freemasons do?”
“No, there is no written or even unwritten rule to which we
have to adhere. Most of us are far too skeptical for any such
rituals, But perhaps I ought to add that we do observe certain
rules, although no one orders us to. For instance, we don’t smoke,
we drink very little, we dress far too simply for our parents’
liking, and I don’t think any of us are very interested in night
life or in bars—but there is no written code.”
“And what happens if one of you breaks these rules?”
“I don’t know, perhaps we simply laugh at him. But it just
doesn’t happen.”
“Isn't it uncanny, or perhaps I should say marvelous,” said
Bohr, “how much magical power the old images retain? That
after so many centuries they should still affect people, without
written laws or external coercion? We spoke yesterday of monas-54 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
tic vows, and the monk's first two rules are highly commendable.
Nowadays they amount to modesty and a willingness to adopt a
somewhat harder, more continent life. But I hope you won't
stress the third rule, obedience, too soon, or else there may be
dangerous political consequences. You know that I think far
more highly of the two Icelanders, Egill and Njall, than of the
masters of your Prussian orders.
“But you have told me that you were present during the civil
war in Munich. You must surely have wondered about such
general questions as the role of the state in the life of society.
What bearing does all this have on your life in the Youth
Movement?”
“During the civil war,” I replied, “I sided with the govern-
ment because the whole fight seemed quite senseless to me, and I
hoped that it would end more quickly that way. But I must
admit that I had a rather bad conscience toward our opponents.
Ordinary Germans, and particularly the workers, had fought
wholeheartedly for our victory in the war, had made the same
sacrifices as everyone else. Their criticism of the ruling classes was
absolutely justified, for our rulers had confronted the German
people with an insoluble problem. Hence I felt that it was abso-
lutely essential to make friendly contacts with the workers as
soon as the civil war was over. That was also the view of a great
many members of the Youth Movement.
“Four years ago, for instance, we helped run extracurricular
classes in Munich, and I myself was rash enough to give a series
of lectures on astronomy, pointing out the various constellations
to some hundreds of workers and their wives, describing the
motions of the planets and their distances from each other, and
trying to interest them in the structure of our Milky Way. With a
young lady, I also helped give a course of lectures on the German
opera. She sang arias and I accompanied her on the piano; and
afterward she would give brief summaries of the history and
structure of the various operas. The whole thing was amateurish
in the extreme, but I do believe that the audience appreciated
our good intentions and that they enjoyed our recitals as much as
we did. This was also the time when many young people in the
Youth Movement turned to elementary school teaching, as a
result of which I imagine that many of our elementary schoolsLESSONS IN POLITICS AND HISTORY 55
have much better teachers than quite a few of our so-called high
schools.
“I quite understand why people abroad might look upon our
Youth Movement as too romantic and idealistic, and why they
are afraid it might be diverted into the wrong political channels.
But I have no fears on that score, certainly not in the immediate
present—atter all, a great deal of good has already come out of
the movement. I am thinking particularly of the revival of
interest in old music—in Bach, plain song and ballads—of at-
tempts to revive the old handicrafts, to bring beauty into the
homes of even the very poor, and of all the efforts to awaken
interest in the arts through amateur dramatic or music groups.”
“I’m glad to see that you're so optimistic,” Bohr said. “But
now and then our papers also tell us about more ominous, anti-
Semitic, trends in Germany, obviously fostered by demagogues.
Have you come across any of that yourself?”
“Yes, in Munich such groups have begun to make quite a bit
of a noise. They enjoy the support of some of the old officers
who've been unable to come to terms with Germany's defeat. But
we don't take these groups very seriously. After all, you can’t base
rational politics on resentment alone. What is far worse is that
reputable scientists should see fit to repeat all this stuff like so
many parrots.”
And I told him of my experiences in Leipzig, where relativity
theory had been the subject of political slanders. At the time
neither of us had the least idea just what terrible consequences
would one day spring from these apparently unimportant politi-
cal aberrations, but more of this later. At the time Bohr’s reply
was directed at the resentful old officers as much as at the physi-
cist who refused to come to terms with relativity theory.
“You see, once again I prefer the English attitude to the
German. The English try to play the game, but they also try to
be good losers. Prussians, on the other hand, think that losing is a
disgrace, though they, too, preach magnanimity in victory,
and that I find highly creditable. But the English go one step
further: they expect the vanquished to be magnanimous to the
victor, to accept their defeat and to bear no grudges. If they can,
they have achieved the next best thing to victory. They are free
men among free people. 1 am reminded of the old Vikings again.56 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
Perhaps that makes me a romantic in your eyes, but I take the
whole thing much more seriously than you may perhaps believe.”
“Oh, no, I see how serious you are,” I told him.
We had meanwhile reached Gilleleje, on the northern tip of
Zealand. The beach, which in summer is crowded with happy
holiday makers, was utterly deserted on this cold day. We picked
up a few flat stones and tried our skill at making them skim the
water, or aimed them at old fishermen’s baskets or bits of drift-
wood. Bohr told me that, shortly after the war, he had visited
this beach with Kramers, and that they had spotted a German
mine with its detonator sticking up above the waves. They had
tried to throw stones at the detonator but had merely kept hit-
ting the mine itself—until they realized that if either of them
had scored a bull’s-eye, there would have been no one to tell the
tale.
On the rest of our walk, too, Bohr and I amused ourselves by
flinging stones at distant objects. On one occasion this activity
again gave rise to a conversation about the powers of the imagi-
nation. I happened to see a telegraph pole quite a long distance
away, almost too far to be reached with a stone. When the
improbable nevertheless happened, and I hit it on my first
attempt, Bohr became reflective: “If you had thought first about
your aim, or about the correct angle of your arm and wrist, you
wouldn't have had the least chance of scoring a hit. But since you
were unreasonable enough to imagine that you could hit the
target without special effort, why, you did it.” We then had a
lengthy discussion about the role of images and concepts in
atomic physics. But more of this in another chapter.
We spent the night in a lonely inn at the edge of a forest in the
northwestern part of the island. Next morning Bohr showed me
around his country house in Tisvilde, in which we were later to
have so many conversations about atomic physics. At this time of
the year, the house was not yet ready to receive guests. Then we
made our way back to Copenhagen and stopped briefly in
Hilleréd, catching a glimpse of Frederiksborg Castle, a splendid
Renaissance building in the Dutch style. It was surrounded by a
lake and parklands and had obviously once served as a royal
hunting lodge. I could sense that Bohr had a much greater likingLESSONS IN POLITICS AND HISTORY 57
for Hamlet’s castle in Kronborg than for this rather trivial
monument to the courtly life. No wonder, therefore, that the
conversation turned back to atomic physics, a subject that was to
fill so many of our future thoughts and perhaps the most impor-
tant part of our lives.5
Quantum Mechanics and
a Talk with Einstein (1925-1926)
During these critical years, atomic physics developed much as
Niels Bohr had predicted it would during our walk over the
Hain Mountain. The difficulties and inner contradictions that
stood in the way of a true understanding of atoms and their
stability seemed unlikely to be removed or even reduced—on the
contrary, they became still more acute. All attempts to surmount
them with the conceptual tools of the older physics appeared
doomed to failure.
There was, for instance, the discovery by the American physi-
cist, Arthur Holly Compton, that light (or more precisely X-
rays) changes its wavelength when radiation is scattered by free
electrons. This result could be explained by Einstein's hypothesis
that light consists of small corpuscles or packets of energy, mov-
ing through space with great velocity and occasionally—eg.,
during the process of scattering—colliding with an electron. On
the other hand, there was a great deal of experimental evidence
to suggest that the only basic difference between light and radio
waves was that the former are of shorter length; in other words,
that a light ray is a wave and not a stream of particles. Moreover,
attempts by the Dutch physicist, Ornstein, to determine the
intensity ratio of spectral lines in a so-called multiplet had pro-
duced very strange results. These ratios can be determined with
the help of Bohr's theory. Now it appeared that, although the
formulae derived from Bohr’s theory were incorrect, a minor
modification produced new formulae that fitted the experimentalQUANTUM MECHANICS AND A TALK WITH EINSTEIN 59
results. And so physicists gradually learned to adapt themselves
to a host of difficulties. They became used to the fact that the
concepts and models of classical physics were not rigorously
applicable to processes on the atomic scale. On the other hand,
they had come to appreciate that, by skillful use of the resulting
freedom, they could, on occasion, guess the correct mathematical
formulation of some of the details.
In the seminars run by Max Born in Gottingen during the
summer of 1924, we had begun to speak of a new quantum
mechanics that would one day oust the old Newtonian
mechanics, and whose vague outlines could already be discerned
here and there. Even during the subsequent winter term, which I
once again spent in Copenhagen, trying to develop Kramers’
theory of dispersion phenomena, our efforts were devoted not so
much to deriving the correct mathematical relationships as to
guessing them from similarities with the formulae of classical
theory.
If I think back on the state of atomic theory in those months, I
always remember a mountain walk with some friends from the
Youth Movement, probably in the late autumn of 1924. It took
us from Kreuth to Lake Achen. In the valley the weather was
poor, and the mountains were veiled in clouds. During the
climb, the mist had begun to close in upon us, and, after a
time, we found ourselves in a confused jumble of rocks and
undergrowth with no signs of a track. We decided to keep
climbing, though we felt rather anxious about getting down
again if anything went wrong. All at once the mist became so
dense that we lost sight of one another completely, and could
keep in touch only by shouting. At the same time it grew
brighter overhead, and the light suddenly changed color. We
were obviously under a patch of moving fog. Then, quite sud-
denly, we could see the edge of a steep rock face, straight ahead
of us, bathed in bright sunlight. The next moment the fog had
closed up again, but we had seen enough to take our bearings
from the map. After a further ten minutes of hard climbing we
were standing in the sun—at saddle height above the sea of fog.
To the south we could see the peaks of the Sonnwend Mountains
and beyond them the snowy tops of the Central Alps, and we all
breathed a sigh of relief.60 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
In atomic physics, likewise, the winter of 1924-1925 had obvi-
ously brought us to a realm where the fog was thick but where
some light had begun to filter through and held out the promise
of exciting new vistas.
In the summer term of 1925, when I resumed my research work
at the University of Géttingen—since July 1924 I had been
Privatdozent at that university—I made a first attempt to guess
what formulae would enable one to express the line intensities of
the hydrogen spectrum, using more or less the same methods that
had proved so fruitful in my work with Kramers in Copenhagen.
This attempt led to a dead end—I found myself in an impene-
trable morass of complicated mathematical equations, with no
way out. But the work helped to convince me of one thing: that
one ought to ignore the problem of electron orbits inside the
atom, and treat the frequencies and amplitudes associated with
the line intensities as perfectly good substitutes. In any case, these
magnitudes could be observed directly, and as my friend Otto had
pointed out when expounding on Einstein's theory during our
bicycle tour round Lake Walchensee, physicists must consider
none but observable magnitudes when trying to solve the atomic
puzzle. My attempt to apply this scheme to the hydrogen atom
had come to grief on the complications of this particular problem.
Accordingly, I looked for a simpler mathematical system and
found it in the pendulum, whose oscillations could serve as a
model for the molecular vibrations treated by atomic physics. My
work along these lines was advanced rather than retarded by an
unfortunate personal setback.
Toward the end of May 1925, I fell so ill with hay fever that I
had to ask Born for fourteen days’ leave of absence. I made
straight for Heligoland, where I hoped to recover quickly in the
bracing sea air, far from blossoms and meadows. On my arrival I
must have looked quite a sight with my swollen face; in any case,
my landlady took one look at me, concluded that I had been in a
fight and promised to nurse me through the aftereffects. My room
was on the second floor, and since the house was built high up on
the southern edge of the rocky island, I had a glorious view over
the village, and the dunes and the sea beyond. As I sat on my
balcony, I had ample opportunity to reflect on Bohr’s remark
that part of infinity seems to lie within the grasp of those who
look across the sea.QUANTUM MECHANICS AND A TALK WITH EINSTEIN 61
Apart from daily walks and long swims, there was nothing in
Heligoland to distract me from my problem, and so I made much
swifter progress than I would have done in Gottingen. A few
days were enough to jettison all the mathematical ballast that
invariably encumbers the beginning of such attempts, and to
arrive at a simple formulation of my problem. Within a few days
more, it had become clear to me what precisely had to take the
place of the Bohr-Sommerfeld quantum conditions in an atomic
physics working with none but observable magnitudes. It also
became obvious that with this additional assumption I had
introduced a crucial restriction into the theory. Then I noticed
that there was no guarantee that the new mathematical scheme
could be put into operation without contradictions. In particu-
lar, it was completely uncertain whether the principle of the
conservation of energy would still apply, and I knew only too
well that my scheme stood or fell by that principle.
Other than that, however, several calculations showed that the
scheme seemed quite self-consistent. Hence I concentrated on
demonstrating that the conservation law held, and one evening I
reached the point where I was ready to determine the individual
terms in the energy table, or, as we put it today, in the energy
matrix, by what would now be considered an extremely clumsy
series of calculations. When the first terms seemed to accord with
the energy principle, I became rather excited, and I began to
make countless arithmetical errors. As a result, it was almost
three o'clock in the morning before the final result of my compu-
tations lay before me. The energy principle had held for all the
terms, and I could no longer doubt the mathematical consistency
and coherence of the kind of quantum mechanics to which my
calculations pointed. At first, I was deeply alarmed. I had the
feeling that, through the surface of atomic phenomena, I was
looking at a strangely beautiful interior, and felt almost giddy at
the thought that I now had to probe this wealth of mathematical
structures nature had so generously spread out before me. I was
far too excited to sleep, and so, as a new day dawned, I made for
the southern tip of the island, where I had been longing to climb
a rock jutting out into the sea. I now did so without too much
trouble, and waited for the sun to rise.
What I saw during that night in Heligoland was admittedly
not very much more than the sunlit rock edge I had glimpsed in62 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
the autumn of 1924, but when I reported my results to Wolfgang
Pauli, generally my severest critic, he warmly encouraged me to
continue along the path I had taken. In Géttingen, Max Born
and Pascual Jordan took stock of the new possibilities, and in
Cambridge the young English mathematician Paul Dirac devel-
oped his own methods for solving the problems involved, and
after only a few months the concentrated efforts of these men led
to the emergence of a coherent mathematical framework, one
that promised to embrace all the multifarious aspects of atomic
physics. Of the extremely intensive work which kept us breathless
for a few months I shall say nothing here; instead, I shall report
my talk with Albert Einstein following a lecture on the new
quantum mechanics in Berlin.
At the time, the University of Berlin was considered the strong-
hold of physics in Germany, with such renowned figures as
Planck, Einstein, von Laue and Nernst. It was here that Planck
had discovered quantum theory and that Rubens had confirmed
it by special measurements of thermal radiation; it was here that
Einstein had formulated his general theory of relativity and his
theory of gravitation in 1916. At the center of scientific life was
the so-called physics colloquium, which probably went back to
the time of Helmholtz and which was generally attended by the
entire staff of the physics department. In the spring of 1926, I was
invited to address this distinguished body on the new quantum
mechanics, and since this was my first chance to meet so
many famous men, I took good care to give a clear account of the
concepts and mathematical foundations of what was then a most
unconventional theory. I apparently managed to arouse Ein-
stein’s interest, for he invited me to walk home with him so that
we might discuss the new ideas at greater length.
On the way, he asked about my studies and previous research.
As soon as we were indoors, he opened the conversation with a
question that bore on the philosophical background of my recent
work. “What you have told us sounds extremely strange. You
assume the existence of electrons inside the atom, and you are
probably quite right to do so, But you refuse to consider their
orbits, even though we can observe electron tracks in a cloud
chamber. I should very much like to hear more about your
reasons for making such strange assumptions.”QUANTUM MECHANICS AND A TALK WITH EINSTEIN 63
“We cannot observe electron orbits inside the atom,” I must
have replied, “but the radiation which an atom emits during
discharges enables us to deduce the frequencies and correspond-
ing amplitudes of its electrons. After all, even in the older physics
wave numbers and amplitudes could be considered substitutes
for electron orbits. Now, since a good theory must be based on
directly observable magnitudes, I thought it more fitting to re-
strict myself to these, treating them, as it were, as representatives
of the electron orbits.”
“But you don't seriously believe,” Einstein protested, “that
none but observable magnitudes must go into a physical theory?”
“Isn’t that precisely what you have done with relativity?” I
asked in some surprise. “After all, you did stress the fact that it is
impermissible to speak of absolute time, simply because absolute
time cannot be observed; that only clock readings, be it in the
moving reference system or the system at rest, are relevant to the
determination of time.”
“Possibly I did use this kind of reasoning,” Einstein ad-
mitted, “‘but it is nonsense all the same. Perhaps I could put it
more diplomatically by saying that it may be heuristically useful
to keep in mind what one has actually observed. But on prin-
ciple, it is quite wrong to try founding a theory on observable
magnitudes alone. In reality the very opposite happens. It is the
theory which decides what we can observe. You must appreciate
that observation is a very complicated process. The phenomenon
under observation produces certain events in our measuring
apparatus. As a result, further processes take place in the appa-
ratus, which eventually and by complicated paths produce sense
impressions and help us to fix the effects in our consciousness.
Along this whole path—from the phenomenon to its fixation in
our consciousness—we must be able to tell how nature functions,
must know the natural laws at least in practical terms, before we
can claim to have observed anything at all. Only theory, that is,
knowledge of natural laws, enables us to deduce the underlying
phenomena from our sense impressions. When we claim that we
can observe something new, we ought really to be saying that,
although we are about to formulate new natural laws that do not
agree with the old ones, we nevertheless assume that the existing
laws—covering the whole path from the phenomenon to our64 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
consciousness—function in such a way that we can rely upon
them and hence speak of ‘observations.’
“In the theory of relativity, for instance, we presuppose that,
even in the moving reference system, the light rays traveling from
the clock to the observer's eye behave more or less as we have
always expected them to behave. And in your theory, you quite
obviously assume that the whole mechanism of light transmission
from the vibrating atom to the spectroscope or to the eye works
just as one has always supposed it does, that is, essentially accord-
ing to Maxwell's laws. If that were no longer the case, you could
not possibly observe any of the magnitudes you call observable.
Your claim that you are introducing none but observable mag-
nitudes is therefore an assumption about a property of the theory
that you are trying to formulate. You are, in fact, assuming
that your theory does not clash with the old description of radia-
tion phenomena in the essential points. You may well be right, of
course, but you cannot be certain.”
I was completely taken aback by Einstein's attitude, though I
found his arguments convincing. Hence I said: “The idea that a
good theory is no more than a condensation of observations in
accordance with the principle of thought economy surely goes
back to Mach, and it has, in fact, been said that your relativity
theory makes decisive use of Machian concepts. But what you
have just told me seems to indicate the very opposite, What am I
to make of all this, or rather what do you yourself think about
in”
“It’s a very long story, but we can go into it if you like.
Mach’s concept of thought economy probably contains part of
the truth, but strikes me as being just a bit too trivial. Let me
first of all produce a few arguments in its favor. We obviously
grasp the world by way of our senses. Even when small children
learn to speak and to think, they do so by recognizing the possi-
bility of describing highly complicated but somehow related
sense impressions with a single word, for instance, the word ‘ball.’
They learn it from adults and get the satisfaction that they can
make themselves understood. In other words, we may argue
that the formation of the word, and hence of the concept, ‘ball’ is
a kind of thought economy enabling the child to combine very
complicated sense impressions in a simple way. Here Mach doesQUANTUM MECHANICS AND A TALK WITH EINSTEIN 65
not even enter into the question which mental or physical
predispositions must be satisfied in man—or the small child—
before the process of communication can be initiated. With
animals, this process works considerably less effectively, as every-
one knows, but we shan’t talk about that now. Now Mach also
thinks that the formation of scientific theories, however complex,
takes place in a similar way. We try to order the phenomena, to
reduce them to a simple form, until we can describe what may be
a large number of them with the aid of a few simple concepts.
“All this sounds very reasonable, but we must nevertheless ask
ourselves in what sense the principle of mental economy is being
applied here. Are we thinking of psychological or of logical econ-
omy, or, again, are we dealing with the subjective or the objec-
tive side of the phenomena? When the child forms the concept
‘ball,’ does he introduce a purely psychological simplification in
that he combines complicated sense impressions by means of this
concept, or does this ball really exist? Mach would probably
answer that the two statements express one and the same fact.
But he would be quite wrong to do so. To begin with, the asser-
tion ‘The ball really exists’ also contains a number of statements
about possible sense impressions that may occur in the future.
Now future possibilities and expectations make up a very impor-
tant part of our reality, and must not be simply forgotten.
Moreover, we ought to remember that inferring concepts and
things from sense impressions is one of the basic presuppositions
of all our thought. Hence, if we wanted to speak of nothing but
sense impressions, we should have to rid ourselves of our lan-
guage and thought. In other words, Mach rather neglects the fact
that the world really exists, that our sense impressions are based
on something objective.
“I have no wish to appear as an advocate of a naive form of
realism; I know that these are very difficult questions, but then I
consider Mach’s concept of observation also much too naive. He
pretends that we know perfectly well what the word ‘observe’
means, and thinks this exempts him from having to discriminate
between ‘objective’ and ‘subjective’ phenomena. No wonder his
principle has so suspiciously commercial a name: ‘thought econ-
omy.’ His idea of simplicity is much too subjective for me. In
reality, the simplicity of natural laws is an objective fact as well,66 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
and the correct conceptual scheme must balance the subjective
side of this simplicity with the objective. But that is a very diffi-
cult task. Let us rather return to your lecture.
“I have a strong suspicion that, precisely because of the
problems we have just been discussing, your theory will one day
get you into hot water. I should like to explain this in greater
detail. When it comes to observation, you behave as if everything
can be left as it was, that is, as if you could use the old descriptive
language. In that case, however, you will also have to say: in a
cloud chamber we can observe the path of the electrons, At the
same time, you claim that there are no electron paths inside the
atom. This is obvious nonsense, for you cannot possibly get rid of
the path simply by restricting the space in which the electron
moves.”
I tried to come to the defense of the new quantum mechanics.
“For the time being, we have no idea in what language we must
speak about processes inside the atom. True, we have a mathe-
matical language, that is, a mathematical scheme for determining
the stationary states of the atom or the transition probabilities
from one state to another, but we do not know—at least not in
general—how this language is related to that of classical physics.
And, of course, we need this connection if we are to apply this
theory to experiments in the first place. For when it comes to
experiments, we invariably speak in the traditional language.
Hence I cannot really claim that we have ‘understood’ quantum
mechanics. I assume that the mathematical scheme works, but no
link with the traditional language has been established so far.
And until that has been done, we cannot hope to speak of the
path of the electron in the cloud chamber without inner contra-
dictions. Hence it is probably much too early to solve the diffi
culties you have mentioned.”
“Very well, I will accept that,” Einstein said. “We shall talk
about it again in a few years’ time. But perhaps I may put
another question to you. Quantum theory as you have ex-
pounded it in your lecture has two distinct faces. On the one
hand, as Bohr himself has rightly stressed, it explains the stability
of the atom; it causes the same forms to reappear time and again.
On the other hand, it explains that strange discontinuity or
inconstancy of nature which we observe quite clearly when weQUANTUM MECHANICS AND A TALK WITH EINSTEIN 67
watch flashes of light on a scintillation screen. These two aspects
are obviously connected. In your quantum mechanics you will
have to take both into account, for instance when you speak of
the emission of light by atoms. You can calculate the discrete
energy values of the stationary states. Your theory can thus
account for the stability of certain forms that cannot merge con-
tinuously into one another, but must differ by finite amounts
and seem capable of permanent re-formation. But what happens
during the emission of light? As you know, I suggested that,
when an atom drops suddenly from one stationary energy value
to the next, it emits the energy difference as an energy packet, a
so-called light quantum. In that case, we have a particularly clear
example of discontinuity. Do you think that my conception is
correct? Or can you describe the transition from one stationary
state to another in a more precise way?”
In my reply, I must have said something like this: “Bohr has
taught me that one cannot describe this process by means of the
traditional concepts, i.e., as a process in time and space. With
that, of course, we have said very little, no more, in fact, than
that we do not know. Whether or not I should believe in light
quanta, I cannot say at this stage. Radiation quite obviously
involves the discontinuous elements to which you refer as light
quanta. On the other hand, there is a continuous element, which
appears, for instance, in interference phenomena, and which is
much more simply described by the wave theory of light. But you
are of course quite right to ask whether quantum mechanics has
anything new to say on these terribly difficult problems. I believe
that we may at least hope that it will one day.
“T could, for instance, imagine that we should obtain an inter-
esting answer if we considered the energy fluctuations of an atom
during reactions with other atoms or with the radiation field. If
the energy should change discontinuously, as we expect from
your theory of light quanta, then the fluctuation, or, in more
precise mathematical terms, the mean square fluctuation, would
be greater than if the energy changed continuously. I am in-
clined to believe that quantum mechanics would lead to the
greater value, and so establish the discontinuity. On the other
hand, the continuous element, which appears in interference
experiments, must also be taken into account. Perhaps one must68 PHYSICS AND BEYOND
imagine the transitions from one stationary state to the next as so
many fade-outs in a film. The change is not sudden—one picture
gradually fades while the next comes into focus so that, for a
time, both pictures become confused and one does not know
which is which. Similarly, there may well be an intermediate state
in which we cannot tell whether an atom is in the upper or the
lower state.”
“You are moving on very thin ice,” Einstein warned me. “For
you are suddenly speaking of what we know about nature and no
longer about what nature really does. In science we ought to be
concerned solely with what nature does. It might very well be
that you and I know quite different things about nature. But
who would be interested in that? Perhaps you and I alone. To
everyone else it is a matter of complete indifference. In other
words, if your theory is right, you will have to tell me sooner or
later what the atom does when it passes from one stationary state
to the next.”
“Perhaps,” I may have answered. “But it seems to me that you
are using language a little too strictly. Still, I do admit that
everything that I might now say may sound like a cheap excuse.
So let's wait and see how atomic theory develops.”
Einstein gave me a skeptical look. “How can you really have so
much faith in your theory when so many crucial problems
remain completely unsolved?”
I must certainly have thought for a long time before I pro-
duced my answer. “I believe, just like you, that the simplicity of
natural laws has an objective character, that it is not just the
result of thought economy. If nature leads us to mathematical
forms of great simplicity and beauty—by forms I am referring to
coherent systems of hypotheses, axioms, etc.—to forms that no
one has previously encountered, we cannot help thinking that
they are ‘true,’ that they reveal a genuine feature of nature. It
may be that these forms also cover our subjective relationship to
nature, that they reflect elements of our own thought economy.
But the mere fact that we could never have arrived at these forms
by ourselves, that they were revealed to us by nature, suggests
strongly that they must be part of reality itself, not just of our
thoughts about reality.
“You may object that by speaking of simplicity and beauty IQUANTUM MECHANICS AND A TALK WITH EINSTEIN 69
am introducing aesthetic criteria of truth, and I frankly admit
that I am strongly attracted by the simplicity and beauty of the
mathematical schemes with which nature presents us. You must
have felt this, too: the almost frightening simplicity and whole-
ness of the relationships which nature suddenly spreads out
before us and for which none of us was in the least prepared.
And this feeling is something completely different from the joy
we feel when we have done a set task particularly well. That is
one reason why I hope that the problems we have been discussing
will be solved in one way or another. In the present case, the
simplicity of the mathematical scheme has the further conse-
quence that it ought to be possible to think up many experi-
ments whose results can be predicted from the theory. And if the
actual experiments should bear out the predictions, there is little
doubt but that the theory reflects nature accurately in this par-
ticular realm.”
“Control by experiment,” Einstein agreed, “‘is, of course, an
essential prerequisite of the validity of any theory. But one can’t
possibly test everything. That is why I am so interested in your
remarks about simplicity. Still, I should never claim that I really
understood what is meant by the simplicity of natural laws.”
After talking about the role of truth criteria in physics for
quite a bit longer, I took my leave. I next met Einstein a year
and a half later, at the Solvay Congress in Brussels, where the
epistemological and philosophical bases of quantum theory once
again formed the subject of the most exciting discussions.6
Fresh Fields (1926-1927)
If I were asked what was Christopher Columbus’ greatest
achievement in discovering America, my answer would not be
that he took advantage of the spherical shape of the earth to get
to India by the western route—this idea had occurred to others
before him—or that he prepared his expedition meticulously and
rigged his ships most expertly—that, too, others could have done
equally well. His most remarkable feat was the decision to leave
the known regions of the world and to sail westward, far beyond
the point from which his provisions could have got him back
home again.
In science, too, it is impossible to open up new territory unless
one is prepared to leave the safe anchorage of established doc-
trine and run the risk of a hazardous leap forward. With his
relativity theory, Einstein had abandoned the concept of simul-
taneity, which was part of the solid ground of traditional physics,
and, in so doing, outraged many leading physicists and philoso-
phers and turned them into bitter opponents. In general, scientific
progress calls for no more than the absorption and elaboration
of new ideas—and this is a call most scientists are happy to heed.
However, when it comes to entering new territory, the very struc-
ture of scientific thought may have to be changed, and that is far
more than most men are prepared to do. How great their reluc-
tance could be had been brought home to me at the Leipzig Con-
gress, and I fully expected that similar obstacles would be placed
in the path of atomic physics.
During the first few months of 1926, at about the same time
that I delivered my lecture in Berlin, Géttingen first becameFRESH FIELDS m
familiar with the work of the Viennese physicist, Erwin Schré-
dinger, who was approaching atomic theory from an entirely
fresh side. The year before, Louis de Broglie in France had
drawn attention to the fact that the strange wave-particle dual-
ism which, at the time, seemed to prevent a rational explanation
of light phenomena might be equally involved in the behavior of
matter, for instance of electrons. Schrédinger developed this idea
further and, by means of a new wave equation, formulated the
law governing the propagation of material waves under the in-
fluence of an electromagnetic field. In Schrédinger’s model, the
stationary states of an atomic shell are compared with the sta-
tionary vibrations of a system, for instance of a vibrating string,
except that all the magnitudes normally considered as energies
of the stationary states are treated as frequencies of the sta-
tionary vibrations. The results Schrédinger obtained in this
way fitted in very well with the new quantum mechanics, and
Schrédinger quickly succeeded in proving that his own wave
mechanics was mathematically equivalent to quantum mechan-
ics; in other words, that the two were but different mathematical
formulations of the same structures. Needless to say, we were
delighted by this new development, for it greatly strengthened
our confidence in the correctness of the new mathematical formu-
lation, Moreover, Schrédinger’s procedure lent itself readily to
the simplification of calculations that had severely strained the
powers of quantum mechanics.
Unfortunately, however, the physical interpretation of the
mathematical scheme presented us with grave problems. Schré-
dinger believed that, by associating particles with material waves,
he had found a way of clearing the obstacles that had so long
blocked the path of quantum theory. According to him, these
material waves were fully comparable to such processes in space
and time as electromagnetic or sound waves. Such obscure ideas
as quantum jumps would completely disappear. I had no faith in
a theory that ran completely counter to our Copenhagen concep-
tion and was disturbed to see that so many physicists greeted
precisely this part of Schrédinger’s doctrine with a sense of
liberation. The many talks I had had with Niels Bohr, Wolfgang
Pauli and many others over the years had convinced me that it
was impossible to build up a descriptive time-space model of