Final Causes
Author(s): Timothy L. S. Sprigge and Alan Montefiore
Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 45 (1971), pp. 149-
192
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The Aristotelian Society
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4106579
Accessed: 12-03-2016 19:24 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The Aristotelian Society and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES
by Timothy L. S. Sprigge
and Alan Montefiore
I Timothy L. S. Sprigge
Two types of explanation for the occurrence or existence of
something have long been contrasted by philosophers; explana-
tion by final causes (also called teleological explanation) and
explanation by efficient causes (also called simply causal expla-
nation). The first type tells us of something else for the sake
of which that something exists or occurs; the second type tells
us of some previous existent or occurrent which produced it in
conformity with some law governing the development of things
or events out of each other.
It seems natural today to think of the latter type of explanation
as relevant to a much wider range of phenomena than the former,
and there is a tendency to think that in the last resort every
proper explanation of an occurrence or existence is of the latter
sort. Still, the idea that after all the existence of this whole
scheme of things, or of human life, may have a final cause which
explains it more fundamentally than does any efficient cause
remains an attractive speculation. Certainly, philosophers have
thought of final causes as somehow more basic than efficient
causes.
There do seem, however, to be rather plausible grounds for
insisting than an explanation by final causes is bound, on quite
a priori grounds, to be somehow secondary to explanation by
efficient causes, at least in the sense that there could be efficient
causes without final causes, but not vice versa.
For it may be suggested, first, that the basic sense of the
assertion that one thing X occurred for the sake of another Y,
is that some being possessed of forethought produced X, because,
wanting Y, he recognised or believed that X was a suitable means
to the production of Y. In that case, X can only occur for the
sake of Y if I) some such intelligent being knows about, or
believes in, some system of efficient causes (and we may note in
I49
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
150 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
passing that the notion of such a belief both occurring and being
wrong, not simply in detail, but in postulating such a system at
all, would be a strange one) and 2) the activity of such a being
is an efficient cause of X. (Such activity might consist merely in
willing).
The nature of the world we know could only be explained by
final causes in this sense of the phrase, if both the world and some
demiourgos belong to a universe governed by laws of efficient
causation and either itself without, or included in a vaster
system without, any such final cause whatever. Note especially
how impossible it is that the fundamental laws of efficient
causation operating in the universe as a whole should have a
final cause for being as they are. If some being were capable of
creating laws of nature by some fiat for the sake of some end
which they made possible, or for the sake, say, of their aesthetic
appeal, our "nature" would belong to a nature of which the
fundamental law of efficient causation would be that a desire
for X on that being's part produced X, and the holding of this
law would be, or would rest on, a law of efficient causation with-
out a final cause.
It is evident, then, that there could not be final causes in this
sense without efficient causes, while the converse does not hold.
But is this the only proper, or even the most important, sense of
"final cause"?
Perhaps not, but one may still incline to say the following.
X cannot occur for the sake of Y in any sense unless either X is
or tends to be an efficient cause of Y, or X is somehow connected
within a system of efficient causation to a belief that this is so.
Note that this still holds where the final cause of the existence
of an object is said to be something that it does, as with the heart
pumping blood or the eye seeing, for it is assumed that the
pumping action is the efficient cause of the circulation of the
blood, or that events in the eye are efficient causes of visual
consciousness. Thus explanations in terms of final causes always
refer, at least implicitly, to efficient causes, while presumably for
most senses of "final cause" the converse would not hold.
These are mere first impressions. I shall now consider various
alternative interpretations of the idea of one thing existing or
occurring for the sake of another, and see in what light they put
relations between efficient and final causes.
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 151
II
Our suggestion that final causes may presuppose, without being
presupposed by, efficient causes, did not imply that statements
about the former were either somehow reducible to, or might
with the advance of knowledge always be replaced by, statements
about the latter. However, the drift of modern thought has long
favoured one or other of these latter claims.
One reason for this seems to be the feeling that it is absurd to
explain an event in the present, even a human action, by
reference to an event in the future, said to be that for the sake
of which it occurs. The true explanation of events, including
human activities, must lie in prior events, it is felt, and it is only
some sort of illusion which pictures future events as somehow
pulling previous history towards them.
This response rather begs the question, for it amounts to the
complaint that final causes are not efficient causes. The notion
that the cause cannot succeed the effect applies only to efficient
causes. This is not even the most usual use of "cause" today in
ordinary speech, for the ordinary man, I suppose, uses the word
"cause" most often in such phrases as "the cause of world
brotherhood".
Why may not the efficient cause of an event succeed it ? Is this
merely a matter of definition ? May the distinction between final
and efficient causes simply be one between posterior and prior
causes ?
Such a view is too superficial. The idea that what makes a
thing happen, in the sort of way in which the striking of a match
makes a flame occur, could happen after it, is surely not objec-
tionable merely because it goes against an easily changed verbal
convention. On the other hand, it will not do to say that the
future cannot make things happen because it does not exist, for
the belief that the future is somehow less real than the past, or
for that matter than the present, seems to me totally mistaken.
A more fundamental explanation is that the before-after relation
is definable in terms of the concept of one event making another
happen rather than vice versa.
There is, however, a less controversial way of grounding a
feeling that final causation conceived as a later event making an
earlier event happen is fishy, namely pointing out that the final
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
152 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
cause of an event need not have existence in the future. For
instance, the final cause of Sir Alec Douglas-Home's resignation
as leader of the Conservativts may have been the hoped for
Conservative victory at the next election.
To stay this puzzlement some philosophers (e.g., Bentham)
have reduced final causation in human behaviour to efficient
causation by saying that for X to occur for the sake of Y is for X
to have been efficiently caused either directly by a desire for Y,
or by a desire for X itself efficiently caused by a desire for Y. This
is one possible interpretation of the analysis of final causation
sketched in section I.
Against it, it has been argued that, even if there sometimes
occur states of consciousness such as desirings, aspirings, or
willings of future events (which is sometimes denied) the fact of
an activity being directed towards a certain goal can be ascer-
tained without ascertaining the occurrence of any such events,
and that therefore such events are not required for purposive-
ness. Another argument claims that causation of an event by a
mental act which intends it, goes against the external nature of
the (efficient) causal relation. But the existence of the one is logi-
cally independent of the existence of the other and this is all the
externality required. The most serious objection is that an
organism's movements might be efficiently caused by a desire
without being inspired by it, so that philosophers taking this view
must be asked to specify a special type of efficient causation as
that which is in question. But rather than discuss the peculiar
difficulties of this theory I shall consider objections to the more
general thesis of I, that to explain by final causes is to invoke an
agent who has plans.
III
Is it possible that a thing should exist for the sake of something
without having been deliberately brought into existence as a
means to it ?
The Darwinian explanation of the fitness of organisms for their
environment in terms of natural selection on a basis of mutations
occurring in some way not explained within the theory was
certainly one of the main death blows to the teleological
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 153
explanations advanced in support of theism by such as William
Paley, but it is also true that Darwinism leaves a placeof a sortfor
explanation in terms of final causes. One may frame an answer
to a question as to what the survival value of some organ is by
saying that its purpose or function is such and such, or that it
exists for the sake of such and such. Teleological (or "functional")
explanation in the social sciences may be of this sort. One might
ask: "What do prisons exist for the sake of?" and get an answer
which really points out some survival value of these institutions.
Confusion between this and other ways of taking such questions
is sometimes harmful.
If statements saying that one thing exists for the sake of another
thing or for the sake of something which it does, may be inter-
preted thus, then there is no doubt that some room for teleologi-
cal explanation remains, even when there is no question of the
thing explained being part of someone's conscious plan. Such
final causes do not offer a rival explanation to one in terms of
efficient causation, and are really reducible to the existence of
efficient causes for a thing coming into existence and remaining
in existence (e.g., via the mechanism of heredity) and a lack of
efficient causes for its going out of existence.
IV
Is there any other sense in which it may be true that something
exists for the sake of its effects or its doings, without having been
created as a means to these effects or doings by a being possessed
of forethought ?
Well, certainly it has sometimes been felt that there is some
end towards which the universe as a whole, or certain elements
in it, are somehow reaching out, without their having been
created as a means to this end. Samuel Butler, Bernard Shaw,
and possibly Bergson, thought of life or the life force as reaching
towards some end which it had not been created as a means
towards, and of which it did not itself possess forethought, and
thought that evolutionary changes occurred for the sake of this
end in a way not explicable along Darwinian lines. Moreover,
people sometimes ask vague questions, such as "What is life for ?"
"What is the purpose of suffering ?", "Why are deformed babies
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
154 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
born ?"which seem to be as to what these things occur for the
sake of, and which are not always taken as answerable only along
such lines as we have so far considered. Other more fortunate
people sometimes experience, or think that they experience,
some sort of reality which they suppose to be that for the sake
of which life or the world exists.
Maybe such people are asking questions or making assertions
which really only make sense against theistic presuppositions as
to a world designed by a creator with an end in view, but which
they continue to repeat like emotional parrots even when these
presuppositions are abandoned. As I would always prefer to
find sense than nonsense I shall suggest another possible inter-
pretation of these questions later.
The views of Shaw, Butler, and Bergson are of a rather
different kind. The model which they have in mind is that of
a human being who is vaguely and incoherently searching for
something he cannot say quite what. In some cases the object
of such a search is found, as perhaps in the discovery of a life's
vocation. Teleological explanations of this kind of the develop-
ment of new species, or of the development of the whole world,
compare life or the universe to such a human being. In doing
so, they both insist on a kind of teleology, most obviously
present in human action, which is not allowed for in the analyses
discussed above in sections I and II, and extend its application
to individuals which are primafacie very different in status from
human beings. Whether this extension is correct or not is a
factual question. That they are right on the conceptual point
can be seen quite well in connection with human teleology.
It is certainly often true that that for the sake of which my
doings occur is that which I have deliberately produced them
as a means towards. If I write a letter applying for a job, the
letter itself has been brought into existence after having been
envisaged as a means to my having the job. Still, the actual
movements of my hand in writing are purposive, having as
their immediate goal the leaving of certain definite marks on
the paper and as their remoter goal again the getting of the
job, and it seems quite wrong to suggest that they were
deliberately produced in the recognition that they would have
this result. The very notion of an active being whose every
purposive activity is deliberately selected as a means to its goal
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 155
seems incoherent. (Surely this is not because there can be
purposive activity without a goal. Purposive activity which is
not for the sake of something beyond it, occurs for the sake of
itself exemplifying some universal.) Thinking itself, for one
thing, is a kind of purposive activity, and some of the thinking
which deliberately selects a goal must itself have a goal not
previously thought out. This suggests that the view of final
causation mentioned in section I, and still more that mentioned
in II, is somewhat inadequate, which is not to say that the
insistence that final causation (apart from the Darwinian type)
demands a purposive agent whose activities function as efficient
causes of the occurrences explained by final causation, does
not still stand.
Dissatisfied, partly for such reasons as I have mentioned, with
the account of final causation mentioned in I, and still more
with that mentioned in II, various contemporary philosophers,
in particular C. Taylor in his The Explanation of Behaviour, have
suggested that to explain a stretch of some object's activity as
occurring for the sake of a goal, is to exhibit it as an instance
of a general tendency on the part of that object to do whatever
is required in any situation, at least within some very wide
range of situations, to bring about a certain state of affairs (or
at least to maximise the chances of its coming about) in the
most 'economical' (however that be defined) way, and subject
perhaps to certain restrictions on the means employed. One
thereby explains an individual occurrence as an instance of
some general truth (perhaps applying only to one individual,
more probably applying to all of a certain description) and
one gives grounds for prediction as to how the activity will
proceed under various possible circumstances.
It would seem that on such a view one can ascribe a goal to
an object without ascribing any sort of consciousness to it,
whether volitional or otherwise. Even if implications regarding
consciousness are implicit in our ordinary ascriptions of pur-
poses to each other, it is a virtue of this view to have isolated
from these ordinary ascriptions, a component concept of a
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
156 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
more or less behaviourist kind (though Taylor does not think
of it as such) which is intelligible on its own.
On the face of it, it would seem that various mechanisms to
which consciousness is not ordinarily ascribed, do have goals
in his sense, for the sake of which their activities occur. The
movements of an artefact such as a homing rocket, for instance,
can be said to occur for the sake of its reaching its moving
target, and this in a sense which does not depend upon its
having been designed by some other agent who had this goal.
Thus the homing rocket would have had this goal once
launched, even if its existence, and perhaps its launching, had
come about in some utterly different manner.
Recognition of the possibilities implicit in mechanistic feed-
back systems has encouraged the suspicion that all human
behaviour which is described as having goals is explicable in
this way. It seems a mistake to present this as the possibility
that human behaviour does not really have goals, which it
certainly does on the definition just mentioned. We should say
rather that the behaviour which at one level is explained and
predicted in terms of its goals, may also, at a more fundamental
level, be explicable and predictable in terms of efficient causes.
Taylor, however, insists that an individual's activities are
not goal-directed in the proper sense unless an explanation of
the kind I have indicated above is the fundamental explanation
of its activities, fundamental in the sense that the general truth
in question about that object, or about objects of its type, is
not deducible from an account of its, or their, structure
together with laws of efficient causation.
This restriction, though some of its motives may be under-
standable, is rather bizarre. The observable fact that human
behaviour is goal-directed in the sense indicated, would not be
conjured out of existence, or shown to be an illusion, by its
being discovered that it could be explained in terms of efficient
causes. The possibility or probability that there is a complete
efficient causal explanation of Mr. Nixon's verbal and other
activities scarcely throws in doubt my belief that over a long
period much of his activity had as its final cause the gaining of
the Presidency.
It has, indeed, been urged that no such possibility exists,
and that there can be no efficient causal explanations of human
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 157
actions, on the ground that the concepts of the various recog-
nized types of human actions either could not, or obviously will
not, figure in the causal laws propounded by scientists in
explaining human movements. However, many of the movements
which I notice in nature or in art (the roughness of the sea,
the weather, or the movements of the hands on a clock) are
classified by me in ways of a non-scientific sort, but I do not
conclude that they are without causal explanation. Some of the
properties used in this classification are doubtless epipheno-
menal with reference to the properties mentioned in physics
(and perhaps in other natural sciences) and thus, not being
logically connected with more typically "scientific" properties,
they must be contingently connected by laws which mention
them or their logical associates,-but others of them are such
that their occurrence is entailed by the co-occurrence of
properties mentioned in scientific laws, though they are not
mentioned there themselves. Action-concepts (which, after all,
are used for classifying particulars which are movements, even
if not qua movements) may cover both types of property, but
I see no need to regard them as referring to some third type of
property, which cannot have its occurrence explained in terms
of efficient causation.
It seems, then, that a goal can be ascribed to Mr. Nixon and
reference to it serve to explain his behaviour, in the sense that
one explains individual items as having occurred because they
were just what was required to make it most likely, in the
simplest way and subject to certain restrictions, that Mr.
Nixon would end up as President, while leaving it open whether
this tendency to do what is likely to have this result, is grounded
in efficient causes or not. The type of reference made here to the
goal object or situation explains why it can thus figure as a
final cause without actually being a real event in the future-
as in the case of a similar explanation of Mr. Nixon's conduct
eight years earlier, for instance.
Perhaps the Shavian view that the evolutionary process is
striving towards some fairly definite goal is, likewise, not in-
compatible with its having a (not purely Darwinian) mecha-
nistic explanation.
VI
Taylor's thesis, and my discussion of it, relies on a sharp
6*
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
158 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
contrast between teleological laws (general truths of the kind
indicated above) and (efficient) causal laws, the difference
between us being as to whether the former cease to be genuinely
explanatory when shown to be derivative from the latter.
Regarding this sharp contrast I have my doubts, my airing of
which in this section will constitute something of a digression.
Is the distinction between a teleological law and efficient
causal law perhaps just a difference in the way in which a
certain recurrent pattern in the world is described, certain
descriptions expressing an interest in how processes arise or
can be made to do so, while other descriptions express rather a
dramatic interest in the upshot of such processes ?
Might one perhaps say of any system of material things
governed by certain efficient causal laws that it will always do
what is required in order that it shall be in a state in which the
relations between its parts, and itself and its environment, shall
be such as the causal laws describe as holding? For instance,
the goal of the solar system may be regarded as the preservation
of certain relations between its elements, and between itself
and the rest of the universe. Or, in particular situations one may
always call the goal of a system that to which it will move if
the environment does not alter too much. The appropriateness
of talking of such a state as its goal will depend on the range of
different environmental circumstances in which it will still
move towards it, and will thus be a matter of degree.
May one perhaps make a complementary transformation of
any apparently radically teleological law governing biological
systems into a sort of causal law itself, even if it should turn out
not to be derivable from any more fundamental physical laws ?
Suppose that there is a certain organism, the behaviour of
which is continually adjusted in the way required to preserve
a certain relation between its parts, and between it and its
environment, and suppose that these relations are not of a type
which figures in laws governing other sorts of material object.
Suppose further that they cannot be seen as a special con-
sequence in special circumstances of material laws of universal
application. We have still (so it may be suggested) not come
across a law of a radically different kind from those more
widely applicable laws. It is simply an extra law in the universe
that organisms of that type do (at least under a wide range of
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 159
circumstances) whatever is required to keep their parts in
certain relations to each other and to the environment. To
explain something as a mechanism is, essentially, to exhibit its
activities as instances of some general laws describing the habits
of matter. This essence of mechanistic explanation is still
present if the laws to which appeal is made describe a special
set of habits which matter always adopts when the operation
of other laws has got it into a certain state, such as could not
be anticipated on the basis of matter's habits prior to being
thus organized.
Taylor claims that teleological laws differ from causal laws
in the following respect. The causal law says that when things
of a certain kind are in a situation of a certain definite kind,
they will exhibit developments of a certain definite kind. The
teleological law says that when things of a certain kind are in
any situation (falling within a certain range, one should surely
add) they will exhibit developments of whatever kind are
requisite in that situation to keep them in or bring them into a
certain state (or perhaps one should add: which are required if
this is to be achieved with maximum economy and subject to
certain further limitations) which state, in virtue of this law,
can be called their goal .
Incidentally, Taylor often writes as though these laws con-
cerned simply particular individuals, rather than all individuals
of a certain kind, but unless they apply to individuals as being
of a certain kind (e.g., of a certain internal structure) they can
hardly be called laws. This, however, doesn't much effect present
issues. If there were certain quasi-laws applying to certain
nameable individuals rather than to all individuals of a certain
kind, the question whether they were teleological quasi-laws
or efficient causal quasi-laws would still arise.
To explain particular developments in things by laws of
either of these sorts will be to show them as instances of what
things of a certain kind always do in situations of a certain
kind, but if one appeals to a teleological law one will be classi-
fying the particular situation not in terms of its own 'intrinsic'
character but as one in which those developments are required
if those things are going to continue in or move towards a
certain state, while if one appeals to a causal law one will
classify the particular situation and likewise the developments
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
I60 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
in a more 'intrinsic' way which makes no reference to the
serviceableness of those developments for keeping the things in,
or moving towards, a certain state. One might think that one
could always replace a teleological explanation simply by
classifying the situation and developments on some more
'intrinsic' basis. However, Taylor's view seems to be that such
a replacement will never work in the properly teleological case,
for the correlation between situations answering to that more
intrinsic specification and developments of the kind being
explained will not hold in all cases, but only in such cases as
the being in such a situation makes developments of that kind
requisite if the things are going to keep in or move towards
that state. But in saying this, I don't think that Taylor quite
appreciates that the situation must fall under some more
'intrinsic' description such that whenever things of that sort
are in it, developments of that sort are required if they are to
remain in or move towards that state. One can only talk of
the situation making those developments requisite for that
state to be preserved or reached, if there are causal laws
applicable to the whole state of affairs in virtue of some
'intrinsic' description of it which determines that by those
developments and only by those developments will the state
in question be preserved or reached (or if the formulation is
qualified as above, that it will be preserved or reached in the
most economical way by those developments). It must then
be true that whenever that 'intrinsic' description applies, the
object will do that thing, and this seems to constitute a law of
efficient causation.
Taylor might still claim that the teleological law has a
special status in cases of genuine teleology in the sense that,
though in all specific cases one could substitute a causal law
of this kind, one would arrive thereby at sundry disconnected
causal laws which could not be subsumed under any common
principle other than one of a teleological kind, namely a law
to the effect that things of that kind will develop in all situa-
tions, or in all situations within some range, in the way required
if they are to remain in or move towards such a state. Well, the
first thing to note is that if there are a finite number of causal
laws sufficient for determining what in any causally possible
situation is required if they are to remain in or move towards
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 161
that state, then it will be possible (in virtue of the finite formula
for the ways in which that goal state may be, so to speak,
preserved or tended towards) to produce a finite set of laws
the conjunction of which will do the same job as the teleological
law, while if there are an infinite number of such laws (not all
derivable from some finite conjunction of laws) there will still
in some sense be an infinite conjunction of such laws which
would do the same job as the teleological laws. In either case,
Taylor's claim that the teleological law is basic and not
derivable from causal laws will fail, but he may make the
rather weaker claim that if the things in question are genuinely
teleological systems, this finite or infinite conjunction of such
laws will be subsumable under a common principle only by
appealing to the teleological law. In such a case, especially
where the causal laws are not all derivable from some finite
conjunction of laws of efficient causation, one might well say
that the teleological law offered a more fundamental explana-
tion than any of the causal laws.
But what is it about such ultimately teleological laws, laws
which though equivalent to, still offer a unifying principle for,
a finite, or just possibly infinite conjunction of independent
causal laws, which marks them off as teleological? For do not
basic causal laws in effect say that in any situation, things of a
certain kind, or perhaps material things in general, will do
whatever is required in order that they remain in certain
relations one to another, or in order that they continue to
move in a certain direction of change ?
Someone might try to defend Taylor's distinction between
causal and teleological laws by suggesting that the word
"required" really has a different force in each case. When it is
said that the solar system will always do what is required in
order to preserve certain relationships in being that fact that
what the solar system does (as it might be specified at some
particular junction) is that which is required to preserve these
relations is a logical truth. The only relevant description of
what it does, entails or is equivalent to the statement that it
preserves these relationships in being. On the other hand,
when an organism such as Taylor might consider genuinely
teleological does what is required to preserve certain relation-
ships in being, that what it does (as this might be specified at
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
162 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
some particular juncture) is that which is required is probably
not a logical truth. Rather, it is what is required, granted
certain basic laws of matter, granted, that is, something con-
tingent. In other words, the basic laws of matter determine
what it is that is required as a matter of contingent fact in order
that the organism shall remain in or move towards a certain
state. They cannot, in the same way, be said to determine what
is required, as a matter of contingent fact, in order that
material things shall stay in the mutual relations they them-
selves describe.
This difference is apparent rather than real, however. For
if one says that the aim of the organism is that, while preserving
those relations between its parts, and between itself and its
environment, which the so called basic laws of matter specify,
it should at the same time sustain certain other states or rela-
tions in being, or move towards a certain state or set of
relationships, then the aims of the organism become aims in a
sense no different from that in which the material world as a
whole has the aims specified by the basic laws of matter. For
now, that what it does (as it might be specified at some par-
ticular juncture) is what is required if its aims are to be
fulfilled, comes out as a logical truth. The sole difference is
that while what Taylor might think of as the non-teleological
parts of the world, are dedicated to keeping one limited set of
relations in being, what he might think of as the teleological
parts of the world are dedicated to this and dedicated also to
preserving certain other relations in being at the same time as
the basic ones. The most that Taylor could claim for his
teleological parts of the world is that their dedication to this
second aim is not deducible from their dedication to the first
aim. He would also have to hold that their dedication to the
first aim allowed of a certain latitude in behaviour, and thus
that the ordinary physical laws of nature do not determine
every detail of what happens, which is left for determination
by their dedication to the second aim. This latitude could either
be peculiar to the so-called teleological systems, or common to
all material things. If the latter, and if no other pattern settled
the issue between the alternatives which the 'basic' laws left
open, a humorist might say that the non-teleological parts of
nature were alone free, since they alone would not be bound
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 163
by the dedication to secondary aims to come down one definite
way where the primary aims of matter left some latitude. If
the first, then the dedication to the primary aims of matter
would partially lapse in the case of the so-called teleological
systems. One could not take it as wholly lapsing, since it is only
in virtue of their allegiance to the primary aims that one can
think of what they do as required for obtaining their secondary
aims.
These considerations rather suggest that a teleological
explanation of the kind under discussion and a mechanistic
one are not at bottom of different types, such divergence as
there seems to be lying rather in whether one's interest in a
particular case is in the drama of results or in the mechanics
of transformation. Events make each other happen conformably
with certain time spanning patterns such that when one begins
there is a good chance of its completing itself, and there is a
certain dedication, as one may put it, on the part of the
matter which has displayed the beginning of the pattern to
seeing the pattern completed. It does not make much difference
whether this dedication is or is not derivative from the basic
dedication of all matter to the preservation of certain relations
between its parts. That is, it does not make the sort of difference
as to how one should regard the basic fates and duties of men,
which it is thought to make by those who look upon mechan-
istic explanations as threatening the dignity or freedom of
man; for purposes of specific social and medical policies it
may make a great difference.
There is doubtless some difference between a law which says
that when matter is organized in a certain way it will, subject
to sticking to certain basic laws of matter, also do whatever is
required, logically, for keeping certain relations in being, e.g.,
to keeping certain variables constant functions of certain other
variables, and saying that it will, subject to these same
restrictions, do whatever is required in order that the matter
thus organized should pass into some new state or set of relation-
ships. However, the latter law, though it is developmental
rather than simply functional, is still in a sense quite mechan-
istic (and certainly no less deterministic than a functional law)
for it simply tells one that a given type of situation will pass
into a given other type of situation and thus conforms to the
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
164 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
simplest "A follows B" model of a causal law. The law that a
lion will do whatever is required (subject to certain limitations)
in order to kill an antelope which it sees, if thought to be a
basic law, would say that Lion seeing antelope is (within a certain
range of circumstances) regularly followed by Lion killing
antelope in the most economical manner conformable to more
basic laws of nature. Similarly with developmental laws
regarding society which simply say that one social system
will be followed by another social system. Thus if some develop-
mental laws are not derivative from efficient functional causal
laws on the principle of negative feedback they seem to come
out themselves simply as rather odd laws of the simplest efficient
causal type.
Incidentally, Taylor might have done better to have his
teleological laws say that a system will do whatever is required
to maximise the chances of a particular result, than simply what
is required to bring about the result. Assimilability of the two
types of law might then be more problematic, though I suspect
that one could still regard a teleological law as a special sort
of causal tendency law.
VII
I have ignored so far a complication which must be brought
into the account of teleology described in section V, if it is to
constitute a plausible account of human, or even animal
purposiveness. Taylor distinguishes two types of teleological
laws. The first tells us that an object will do whatever is required
to bring about a certain result, describable as a goal. The
second tells us that an object will do whatever is required, as it
seems to the agent, to bring about a certain result, describable
as its goal. (It seems desirable to add in each case: "or at least
maximise the chances of its being brought about.") The latter
is distinguished as an intentional teleological law. I shall call
goals of the first type controlling goals, those of the latter type
intended goals.
It seems probable that the analysis of X occurring for the
sake of Y which was mentioned in section I could be taken in
such a way as to be reducible to statements about behaviour
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 165
governed by intentional teleological laws. Some, but not all,
purposive behaviour of the unplanned kind discussed in section
IV would seem to be governed by non-intentional teleological
laws. It is to be noticed that if the intentional law introduces a
reference to consciousness (and it is not necessary to construe
it as doing so) it is, rather oddly, to consciousness of a purely
cognitive kind. No volitional consciousness is required by
Taylor's formula.
It may at first look as though the relation between teleo-
logical and causal laws is bound to be radically different accord-
ing as to whether the former are intentional or not, If, however,
intentional teleological laws are in fact only a special case of
non-intentional ones this will not be so. I suspect that inten-
tional teleological laws can be reformulated as non-intentional
teleological laws in which the controlling goal is a certain
belief-state of the individual.
It may be objected that, if for X to be my intended goal is
for me to be doing what is required to make me believe (or be
nearer believing than I would otherwise be) that I am pro-
ducing X, then my having this goal might manifest itself in
some such way as my getting myself hypnotised into this
belief. But if I did this, it may be said, I would show that
achieving X was not my real goal. This objection can be met
along some such lines as that of saying that my intended goal
is X provided only that my controlling goal is believing that
I am going to produce X by methods which do not involve
passing through a belief that I am going to end up with a false
belief that I am going to produce X. (Some more complicated
formulation may be required to get round some even more
tortuous objections of the same general kind.)
It should be noticed, perhaps, that while the intended goal
might either be a state of affairs lying in the future or the con-
tinuous sustaining of some state of affairs over a period, the
controlling goal would seem bound to be of the latter kind.
It may be asked why the intended goal is thought of as more
aptly described as that for the sake of which activity occurs,
than is the controlling goal, namely the state of believing that
the intended goal will be reached. For an interesting suggestion
bearing on this point, I refer the reader to D. M. Armstrong's
A Materialist Theory of the Mind (pp. 263-4).
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
166 TIMOTHY L. S,. SPRIGGE
But what is a belief? I suggest that the sense of the word
"belief" which is likely to be most useful in the present context
is one in which to ascribe a belief to someone is, in effect, to
claim that it is just as if the fact believed in were represented
on a map, states of which are controlling goals of the organism,
and which represents the organism's environment (and the
organism itself) with substantial correctness according to a
certain projection. It is much more likely than not that there
really are such maps thus connected with the beings who are
said to have beliefs, but if there are not, they would have to be
regarded as theoretical fictions. The sensible and intelligible
patterns immediately given to consciousness are very much as
though they were fragments of such a map, but it seems that
there is no actually existing map containing them, and I do
not know of what other elements such a map might be com-
posed but the physical constituents of the brain.
If the belief that a certain situation holds can be correlated
with, or identified with, some pattern in the brain which
represents the state of affairs believed in, then the preservation
of this pattern in the brain map may be regarded as the
controlling goal of the behaviour having the state of affairs
thus represented as its intended goal. Behaviour may then be
explained by reference to the intended goal, considered as a
final cause, without prejudice to more fundamental efficient
causal explanations which may underlie the tendency of the
organism to do what is required to preserve that pattern in
the brain.
I conclude that in so far as the ascription of goals to indi-
viduals is a matter of bringing their activities under teleological
laws, whether intentional or otherwise, then the having of goals
is compatible with being a mechanism and compatible with
being non-conscious.
VIII
Still, whether human beings are mechanisms or not, they are
conscious, and one form which consciousness takes in them is
that of a conscious desiring or willing of envisaged future
situations, a recognition of them as good, or of a conscious
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 167
aversion to certain possible situations envisaged in the future
and a recognition of them as evil. Surely some mention of these
forms of consciousness is required in a discussion of teleology?
Of course it is. Purpose without consciousness would certainly
be Hamlet without the Prince.
In the present state of philosophy, it is possible that I may
be challenged to say what I mean by "consciousness". I shall
offer a hint as to the meaning of the expression, without
thinking it incumbent upon me to establish (for anyone absurd
enough to doubt it) that there actually are such phases of
existence.
One is wondering about the consciousness which an object
possesses whenever one wonders what it must be like being that
object. Concerning an object deemed non-conscious one cannot
thus wonder. To wonder what it is like being an object is to
concern oneself with a question different from any scientific or
practical question about the observable properties or behaviour
of that object or about the mechanisms which underlie such
properties or behaviour. A behaviouristically or physicalistic-
ally minded psychologist might be very good at knowing what
a psychopath was like, without having any idea what it was
like being a psychopath.
One may find it very difficult to imagine what it must be
like to be another human being. (Let us not confuse this with
the meaningless attempt to imagine oneself being another
human being.) Moreover, when one does think oneself capable
of doing so, one is probably more often than not imagining that
other person's consciousness, at least in part, incorrectly.
Actually, there are also great difficulties in imagining what it
is like being oneself. One cannot think about one's present
conscious state (which is always the envisaging of something
other than itself) and one can only rely on memory with
regard to one's past conscious states. However, in reading a
good novel one does imagine quite vividly what it would be
like to be (not, I repeat, for oneself to be) a person of a certain
kind in circumstances of a certain kind both fairly remote from
one's own. If the novel represents a type which actually exists,
one gains thereby some insight into the consciousness of certain
other types of being. One is always likely to be wrong in
particular cases, but one may be right in supposing that the
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
168 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
moments of consciousness which one imagines are what people
do sometimes live through. Moreover, there is no reason to
suppose that one is always grossly wrong in particular cases.
When one imagines another's conscious state, there is no
conclusive way of checking up whether one has done so correctly
or not. This by no means implies that one's guess may not in
fact be more or less correct. Presuming that the object (that is,
at least normally, the organism) with which one is concerned,
is indeed conscious, then being that organism will have a certain
definite complex quality at every walking moment, and what
one imagines will (if one is right) be, in fact, a more or less
correct reproduction, or (alternatively) symbolic representa-
tion, of that complex quality. Physical science makes no
reference to qualities of this kind.
Thus consciousness is that which one characterises when one
tries to answer the question what it is or might be like to be a
certain object in a certain situation. This use of "be" (which I
have no time to discuss further) though suggestive, is most
peculiar, for it is not the same thing to characterise the con-
sciousness of an organism and to characterise that organism.
An inanimate (or rather, a non-conscious) object has a definite
character at every moment and is plenty of things, but there
is nothing which is being that object in the relevant sense.
It is not impossible to use words to designate some of the
more generic characteristics of moments of consciousness, and
many moments of consciousness come under the heading of
being envisagements of future situations as good or desirable.
Mr. Nixon, one may be sure, lived through many such moments
of consciousness on election night 1968 in which future possible
events such as his making the President's inaugural speech
flashed upon his consciousness as infinitely good and desirable.
A sense of final causation was mentioned in section II which
introduced these forms of consciousness as causes. Yet it seems
incongruous to regard consciousness or awareness as a causal
agent in that world of which it is an awareness. Certainly an
organism's consciousness of things is typically of them as good
or evil, and this reflects the direction of the organism's activity
towards or away from them. (In the absence of such reflection
that consciousness, even if caused by the brain states of that
organism, would not be that organism's consciousness, but
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 169
rather a demonic spirit attached to it.) This is not to say that
this awareness of a thing as good can itself contribute to bring-
ing that thing about. It seems more likely that such human
behaviour as has intended goals in the sense described in the
last section has efficient causes which evoke a conscious
envisagement of those goal states as good, or if the goals are
avoidances, of the situations avoided as evil.
This suggests a sense of "for the sake of" in which an activity
does not occur for the sake of some result unless not only is
that result its intended goal in the sense of section VII, but the
activity was also associated with a conscious envisagement of
it as good (or if it is an avoidance, of that of which it is an
avoidance as evil). If that result is envisaged as good partly or
wholly for its leading on to something else, and if the belief
that it would thus lead on (in the sense of belief specified in
section VII) is an efficient cause of its being an intended goal,
then it also occurred for the sake of that something else, in an
associated meaning of the phrase. The movements of homing
rockets occur for the sake of the destruction of a plane in the
latter but not the former sense.
We have here, finally, what are surely the most important
senses of "final cause", for the question how far events in the
universe have final causes in one or other of these senses, is the
question how far the occurrence of consciousness of things as
being good or evil is a likely predictor of their occurrence. The
greater number of events which have such final causes the
better the universe is likely to be (except indeed where, as so
often happens, their tendencies conflict) for surely the universe
is good in so far forth as it satisfies the conscious yearnings in it.
To learn that the range of events which have such final causes
is very limited is to learn depressing, though doubtless truthful,
news; but the claim that an event has this sort of final cause is
not to be equated either with any claim that it did not have
efficient causes or that moments of consciousness were among
its efficient causes.
It is a mistake to think that the human situation is somehow
better if our sense of things as good or evil has causal efficacy.
This mistake depends on a confusion between efficacy and
fulfilment. The conscious envisagement of X as evil might just
as well have been the efficient cause of X as the envisagement
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
I70 TIMOTHY L. S. SPRIGGE
of it as good; one could not say in the former case that
it occurred for the sake of X, so that there is no equivalence
between the view that consciousness is efficacious and the view
that conscious desires tend to be fulfilled.
To ask what a thing exists for the sake of in this present
sense is to make the optimistic assumption that it tends to
produce what is good, at least in the sight of some consciousness
concerned with it. Now I remarked in section IV that people
sometimes ask what something (such as life or suffering) exists
for the sake of, even when they have dropped any idea that it is
brought about by the goal-directed activity of some agent. I
suggest that the question here has a sense derivative from the
one we have been considering, and amounts to this: "Granted
that its tendency to produce something envisaged as good may
have had nothing to do with its coming into existence, since
it does exist, and we must put up with it somehow, surely it
tends to produce something, or itself has some character,
which we can envisage as good-but what ?" In short, to ask
what a thing exists for the sake of is here the same as to ask
what it is good for. A satisfying answer is like an explanation
for the thing's existence inasmuch as it stops us worrying
about it.
If, at one level, the fact that a human or other animal pursues
certain goals is a physical fact about a physical thing, one can
now point out that in the sense of "final cause" just explained,
the final cause of such physical facts is something on a quite
different plane, namely the union of consciousness with a felt
good. Thus not only is consciousness (something quite im-
material in its nature) necessary, as we mentioned before, to
convert a system which is intentional and teleological in the
kind of way with which a physicalist can deal into a genuinely
purposive being, but also, when it reaches certain heights, it is
the sole justification which we can find for a world in which
such physical, and perhaps mechanistic, systems have
developed.1
REFERENCE
1 Many of the ideas advanced in this paper, derive from George
Santayana. See especially, Reason in Common Sense, Chaps. VIII-XI; The
Realm of Matter, Chaps. VI-VIII; The Realm of Spirit, Chaps. IV and VI;
Animal Faith and Spiritual Life (ed. J. Lachs) Section IV.
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES
by Timothy L. S. Sprigge
and Alan Montefiore
II Alan Montefiore
The central part of Mr. Sprigge's paper is given to a discussion
of Charles Taylor's views on the nature of teleological explana-
tion. My contribution to this symposium records an attempt
to make up my own mind on the main issues between them. I
have also tried to take some account of the views of Denis
Noble2 and Robert Borger3, both of whom use arguments that
for some distance at least run parallel to certain arguments
used by Sprigge and to both of whom Taylor has himself
replied in print.4 Partly in the interests of brevity and partly
because I have to admit that my own technical competence is
often stretched to, and sometimes beyond, its limits in some
aspects of these matters, my own account will be presented in
no doubt dangerously over-simplified terms.
It is worth beginning by trying simply to get straight the
present state of these arguments as to whether there really is
any substantial difference between a teleological explanation
and one in terms of efficient causation, when both are somehow
interpreted, as they appear to have been throughout most of
this controversy, in terms of their associated Humean regulari-
ties. Sprigge puts this question as follows: "Is the distinction
between a teleological law and an efficient causal law perhaps
just a difference in the way in which a certain recurrent pattern
in the world is described, certain descriptions expressing a
greater interest in beginnings ... while other descriptions express
an interest rather in results ?" Or to quote Noble in his Analysis
article of January 1967: "Whenever a teleological explanation
of the kind described by Taylor can be given, it is necessarily the
case that a non-teleological account can also be given."
Borger's version of this point comes out rather differently in as
much as he argues that "explanations in terms of purpose and
mechanistic explanations are not rivals, provided they are
171
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
172 ALAN MONTEFIORE
considered in the context of two different types of enquiry" ;
but he does also maintain that "when we are listing the pro-
perties of a substance (or situation) S, rather than singling out
one of them in the context of some explanation, it makes no
difference as far as the claims about the nature of S are con-
cerned, whether we say of S 'it requires B to turn it into G'
or 'S has the property of being turned into G by B'. All the
potentially unlimited number of sequences of events, in which
S can be an element, provide the basis for possible descriptions
of it, and these could be expressed in equivalent intrinsic or
teleological forms".'
The core of these arguments-Sprigge's and Noble's at any
rate-seems to lie in the fact that if reference to an end-state
or goal G is to serve as an explanation of why a system in
state SE should emit behaviour B, there must exist relation-
ships of regular sequence between SE, B and G such as would
entitle us to predict (if, indeed, Humean regularities ever entitle
one to predict) that every time the system and its environment
are in the requisite state, the behaviour in question will follow
to be followed in turn by arrival at the goal.
Taylor, of course, fully recognises this fact-see, for example,
his reply to Noble in Analysis, Mar. 1967. He then goes on in
effect to make much the sort of claim that Sprigge suggests
that he "might still" make, namely, to quote Sprigge, "that
though in all specific cases one could substitute a causal law
of this kind, one would arrive thereby at sundry disconnected
causal laws which could not be subsumed under any common
principle other than one of a teleological kind . . . ". More
precisely, Taylor maintains that it must remain an empirical
question whether or not one could arrive at any general
principle of efficient causation which would serve to link all
the otherwise "sundry disconnected causal laws". There seems
to be no reason why he should be particularly impressed by,
though he would doubtless acknowledge, the further fact that
it may always be possible to produce some sort of finite or
infinite conjunction under which to subsume any finite or
infinite collection of such otherwise disconnected causal regu-
larities; nor by Sprigge's contention that his claim that teleo-
logical laws may be-not, incidentally, 'are'-basic for certain
ranges of phenomena, and not derivable from laws of efficient
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 173
causation, must fail on this account. In fact, the claim that he
is actually interested in making amounts to all intents and
purposes to "the rather weaker claim" that Sprigge suggests
that he might make: "that", in Sprigge's words, "if the things
in question are genuinely teleological systems, this finite or
infinite conjunction of such laws will be subsumable under a
common principle only by appealing to the teleological law."
As Sprigge immediately comments, "in such a case, especially
where the causal laws are not all derivable from some finite
conjunction of laws of efficient causation, one might well say
that the teleological law offered a more fundamental explana-
tion than any of the causal laws."
This, surely, is just what Taylor would want to say-backing
up this claim by reference to the crucial importance of the
possibilities of further extrapolation and prediction that any
'useful' law must offer. To quote from his Analysis reply to
Noble: "Suppose it be the case that the set of correlations
(SE) I --(B) I,(SE)2-+(B)2 ... (SE)n-+(B)n exhibit no intrinsic
order, so that they leave us just as incapable of predicting
what will happen in situation (SE)n + I as we would have
been before establishing this set of correlations; suppose in
other words it be the case that these correlations are not
instances of a general non-teleological law, B = f (SE); then we
would clearly have a teleological account without a correspond-
ing non-teleological one. For the correlations (T) I-+(B) I . . .
(T)n-+-(B)n do permit extrapolation to new cases ... ."
Both Sprigge and Noble, however, go on to present further
arguments against this, the so-called weaker claim. The central
argument of Noble's reply to Taylor in their Analysis contro-
versy (Dec. 1967) is not, as it stands, altogether clear to me,
but may, I think, be construed as a stronger version of Sprigge's
"finite or infinite conjunction" argument. We know that for
any set of correlations, "provided that the correlations are
regular, there must be some order to which the correlations
conform." This means that for any set of n correlations there
must be some order to which, along with this set, all its own
sub-sets must necessarily at the same time conform. But if to
any order to which the set n conforms, its sub-set n--I must
likewise conform, it must in principle have been possible for
the scientist to whom only the n--I correlations were available,
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
174 ALAN MONTEFIORE
to have found for that set the order which would fit the more
inclusive set n, an order which would have enabled him on the
basis of the n--I correlations alone to have predicted the nth.
In other words, for any set of correlations for which it may be
possible to find a teleologically formulated order, it must also
be possible to find some non-teleological order which would in
principle permit of whatever predictions the teleological order
would permit; although, as Noble points out, "this is not to
say that it might not be conceptually difficult to discover nor
that it might not sometimes be rather odd or implausible."
The context in which Noble produces this argument is that
of his contention that the question whether we choose to work
with, or to accept as explanatory, the teleological or the non-
teleological order in cases like this, cannot itself be considered a
purely empirical, in no way conceptual matter. (This point
seems to be different from, though it may be related to, Sprigge's
point about different descriptions reflecting different interests.)
Noble is here concerned to rebut Taylor's explicit insistence
that it is a purely empirical question whether any given range
of phenomena is governed by laws of teleological or non-
teleological form-though Taylor in fact makes it clear, in
Chapter V of The Explanation of Behaviour,' that he does not
really believe in any invariable, sharp line of demarcation
between the areas of the empirical and the purely conceptual.
On the other hand, he would, if I understand him rightly,
wish to resist this particular argument of Noble's on the grounds
that considerations of a mathematical type as to the possibilities
of producing unending varieties of order under which to sub-
sume any given set of n--I, n or n+ otherwise disconnected
correlations would of themselves provide no help at all to the
scientist faced with his n--I correlations and trying to guess
which of the orders under which he could subsume them might
help him to extrapolate most accurately to the nth.
In fact, the empirical question/conceptual question aspect of
this matter hardly seems to provide any very substantial ground
for major dispute. Whether any particular form of order will
continue to fit a given range of phenomena as further facts about
it continue to come to light is obviously an empirical question;
whether any given ordering of the phenomena may seem close
enough to what the scientists concerned may regard as the
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 175
acceptable corpus of established science to be counted as having
any genuine explanatory power or as being able justifiably to
take the weight of such successful predictions as may be based
on it, is very largely a conceptual one. It hardly seems to be of
urgent relevance to ask whether scientists in general may find
it more helpful to try to think of some overtly teleological
formula rather than to spot that non-teleological order which
may best fit the n--I instances and still continue to work for
the nth and the nth + I. The immediate issue is surely whether
a teleological principle of the sort that Taylor seems here to
be thinking of is or is not equivalent to some overall Humean
generalisation rather than whether either of them is equivalent
to (or can lead directly to the discovery of) some theoretical
ordering of all the possible mechanisms or routes through which
the general teleological or Humean principle, whichever it
may be, may in practice be realised. In fact, of course, as soon
as one starts talking of different forms of ordering relationships
and of their relations to established bodies of scientific theory,
one is already implicitly going beyond the realm of simple
Humean generalisations. But we shall have to return to this
point.
What about Sprigge's arguments against Taylor's so-called
weaker claim? A main point to notice is that Sprigge quite
explicitly pushes his argument through to claim not only that
all teleological laws can be given an (efficient) causal form, but
that the converse also holds, namely that causal laws, including
the most basic ones, can be given a teleological form; for do
they not "in effect say that in any situation, things of a certain
kind, or perhaps material things in general, will do whatever
is required in order that they continue to move in a certain
direction of change ?" In this way he brings out very clearly
the ground of the claim that it must always be possible to
replace a teleological law by an effectively equivalent law of
efficient causation; it is that the Humean regularities on which
the one must be based can always be regarded as the basis for
the other. (Perhaps it would be more accurate to speak of
both causal and teleological explanation being seen as actually
consisting in differently weighted presentations of, or references
to, the same relevant Humean regularities.)
How should one interpret Taylor as reacting against this
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
176 ALAN MONTEFIORE
argument? Presumably somewhat as follows: Of course one
can say, if one likes, that things will do whatever is required
for them to behave in precisely the way in which they will
as a matter of fact behave. But there would not normally be
much point in stressing this logical truth. What one wants in
practice is always some kind of law or collection of laws or
theory which will tell us in what particular ways things will
happen in contrast to the ways in which they will not. And
there may be cases in which we may only be able to get this
from the teleological form of the law.
It is to this last assertion that Taylor consistently returns;
and it is just this that Sprigge is now calling into question. As
debate has repeatedly appeared to get stuck over this point,
it will be as well to try following it through in the detail of
one or two examples. One that Taylor himself has suggested
on occasion is that of a scatter of fallen leaves which have the
odd behavioural characteristic of reforming themselves directly
into a given pattern from whatever other order or disorder
into which they may have fallen or been disturbed. Surely,
Taylor has claimed, we should have to say that the leaves do
whatever is required to return by the most direct available
routes to their favoured configuration; but this description is
manifestly non-intrinsic and we can hardly hope to arrive in
advance of the occurrence of the movements to be predicted
or explained at just that unitary overall formula of intrinsic
description which will cover the infinitely varied alternative
movements, which the leaves may go through in order to return
to the 'goal-configuration' from the infinitely varied alternative
orders and disorders into which they may fall or be disturbed.
But just why should this be so? First, let us make explicit
note of the equivalence at what we may call the outer level
of the teleological law 'Under appropriate conditions these
leaves (and, presumably, any others relevantly like them) will,
ceteris paribus, move in whatever ways are required in order to
arrive by the shortest routes at configuration G' with the Hum-
ean generalisation 'The event of leaves of the relevant sort
finding themselves in any one of the relevantly possible family
of configurations other than G is followed by their regular
movement by the shortest routes to G'. The expression 'under
appropriate conditions' points to the same limits as the phrase
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 177
'the relevantly possible family of conditions'; that is to say,
we may suppose that if the leaves are too grossly disturbed,
they may no longer exhibit the specified pattern of behaviour-
if, perhaps, a certain distance between those furthest from
each other is exceeded, or that between any one leaf and its
nearest neighbour. Of course, there may appear not to be any
such restriction; and of course, too, we may get our initial
characterisation wrong of such restrictions as there appear to
be. But these empirical uncertainties affect both the teleological
and the Humean forms of the law in equal degree. Similarly,
the ceteris paribus clause may be taken in just the same way in
each formulation to refer to those abnormal but explicable
intervening conditions which may modify or even prevent the
normal direct movement-to-G behaviour from taking place.
So far, so good. But now we approach the crunch of this
example. On what basis are we going to be able to predict the
movement behaviour of the leaves on the next occasion that
they are disturbed from the configuration G? Suppose that we
answer in the following apparently simple way: As soon as the
precise terms of the disturbance are specified, it is a straight-
forward geometrical exercise to work out the paths along which
the leaves would have to move to return to G by the most
direct routes; if there are certain types of obstruction lying
along these routes, certain physical calculations may be
involved as well. We still have to insist on the question of
whether we are to say that a prediction based on such a
calculation would be making use of the teleological or the Hum-
ean form of the law. According to Taylor's criterion, an in-
trinsic, non-teleological description of the behaviour B that is
to be predicted or explained, should not include any in-
eliminable reference to the end-state G towards which the
behaviour is tending; if we are struck with any such reference,
we have to say that the behaviour is directed. So are we to say
that the specification of the routes of leaf movement from dis-
turbed order D to the stable configuration G contains, in its
reference to G, an irreducibly teleological element ?
Despite the apparently direct clarity of this question, I in
fact find myself inclined both to agree that a reference to G is
bound to be implicit, if not actually explicit, in any specification
of B; and yet that in this type of case at any rate this ought not
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
178 ALAN MONTEFIORE
to be counted as sufficient to mark the behaviour as teleological.
After all, do we not have the simple observational sequence of
leaves finding themselves in any of a set of positions D being
followed by their movement to G-and what is unHumean
about this description? The ambivalence arises perhaps from
the way in which D must itself be specified. For the specification
of a set D must in effect amount to one of a set of positions,
falling within a given range, that are not themselves G. In this
case to speak of a move from a D to G is ipso facto to speak of
a move from a within-the-range not-G to G; and the expression
'not-G' can certainly be held to include a reference to G. But
surely one does not therefore have to regard a move from not-G
to G as teleologically oriented in virtue of this form of descrip-
tion? After all, any move whatsoever may be regarded as a
move from not-G to G, and any regular set of such moves may
be regarded as exhibiting a Humean law, providing only that
the relevant range of positions other than G be specified
accurately and, perhaps, narrowly enough. But if we can say
that Ds (or not-Gs) within the relevant range are regularly
transformed into G, and if furthermore we can exhaustively
specify the environmental constraints that may exist on the
movements of objects such as leaves-constraints which may
themselves be specified in strictly causal terms and which will
not therefore introduce any independent elements of teleology,
then we can specify the paths through which such a regular
transformation must take place in any specific set of cir-
cumstances D (or not-G), if all other relevant known regularities
are to be maintained. They are those paths which are jointly
'determined' by the Humean law 'Not-Gs become G' and all
those other Humean (and geometrical) laws which, in so far as
they in fact hold, must be taken as describing the moves
physically open to objects such as leaves as they pass from
not-Gs to G. We can, of course, say, if we like, that the leaves
have taken, are taking, will take the particular set of paths, say,
(D)n + 3--G, because these are the paths that the situation
(D)n + 3 requires them to take if they are to get to G by the
shortest available routes; we can equally well say that the
leaves will take these paths if the sequences 'D (or not-G) -+G'
and all other relevant Humean sequences continue as regularly as
hitherto.
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 179
It may be that the peculiarly spatial, geometric aspects of
this example serve to obscure as well as to simplify the main
shape of the argument; so let us see how it applies to antelopes
and lions. We notice, as Sprigge points out, that the event of a
lion seeing an antelope is (within a certain range of cir-
cumstances) regularly followed by that of the lion killing the
antelope "in the most economical manner conformable to more
basic laws of nature". But what manner precisely is that ? Have
we not got to specify it as whatever manner may be required
in the particular situation in which the lion next finds itself, if
the killing of the antelope is to follow? Well, yes-in a sense.
But we can also say that once we are able to give a full specifica-
tion of the set of circumstances under which the lion will next
see an antelope, then the Humean generalisation "'Lion sees
antelope' is followed by 'Lion kills antelope' " together with all
the other Humean generalisations, which may be taken as
summing up the observed boundary conditions of what lions do
or not do in such specified physical circumstances, must fully
specify the path which the lion will take towards the killing of
the antelope, if all these sequences are to continue with their
hitherto observed regularity.
Taylor could, of course, perfectly well insist that we are most
unlikely to approach with any close degree of accuracy either
a full specification in intrinsic terms of the next 'Lion sees
antelope' situation or a full listing of all those other relevant
Humean generalisations which would enable us to make the
full interlocking set of essentially separate ceteris paribus predic-
tions about lions' behaviour in situations such as those specified.
Quite so. But the same imprecisions must equally affect the
parallel, apparently teleologically based prediction. "The lion
will do whatever is required in situation (D)n+3 in order to
kill the antelope." But again, what is that precisely? We have
to specify the full environmental situation. And once the
situation is fully specified, how do we then know that it is
precisely this form of behaviour rather than that which will be
produced ? Well, only if we have a full knowledge of the range
of behaviour open to lions in situations such as that specified,
on the assumption that all the known normal regularities of
lion behaviour are to continue to hold. In that case we shall
indeed be able to work out what will be the lion's most
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
180 ALAN MONTEFIORE
economical available route to the killing of the antelope. But
now we are going round in Spriggean circles. The lion will do
whatever is required for it to do in order to maintain all known
regularities of lion behaviour, including that relating to the
regular killing of antelopes-or else some of these regularities
will turn out not to be constant after all. Is this a mechanical, a
teleological or a merely Humean situation?
It might still be argued, however, that Taylor has already
dealt with this whole family of arguments on page 13 of The
Explanation of Behaviour in his discussion of Nagel's system S,
which, like a thermostat, maintains a state G through the
operation of the compensatory mechanisms of its three com-
ponents A, B and C ? For as long as we characterise the changes
in B and C as 'compensating' for any change in A that would
carry S out of G, our account remains teleological in form. We
escape from teleology only if we can produce generalisations of
the form "whenever A changes from Am to An, then B changes
from Bx to By and C. . . , etc. Thus, for instance, we would be
able to express the antecedents for a given change in B, say,
which in fact produces G, in terms of the states of A and C."
But even to talk of the paths which the leaves must take if the
regularity 'configuration D--- configuration G' is to hold, or of
the behaviour which the lion must emit if the regularity 'lion
sees antelope-* lion kills antelope' is, along with all the other
allegedly relevant regularities, to continue constant, is to
characterise the behavioural changes by reference to the
relevant G.
The answer to this is: Yes, it is true if one knows all the
generalisations relevant to the behaviour of, say a thermostat,
one will be able to characterise its behaviour in response to
relevant changes in its environment step by step and without
referring to G until one gets there, so to speak.8 It is also true,
however, that one may have noted the constancy of its return
to G before knowing anything very much about the constancies
involved in the varying changes of A, B and C. At that stage
one will be able to predict only (i) that the thermostat will,
within the limits of whatever boundary conditions obtain, con-
tinue to return to G from whatever other (non-G) state may,
temporarily, be imposed upon it: (ii) that it will do this through
whatever changes in A, B and C (a) respect all known and
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 181
discoverable regularities in the behaviour of As, Bs and Cs
under the relevant conditions, and (b) lead through regular
sequence to G. (b) may sound teleological in Taylor's terms,
but it is only the restatement of the regularity that was noted
at the beginning and which one may suppose will continue as
such. To the extent that we may suppose ourselves to know all
the relevant intervening regularities as well as those which we
need in order to delimit the normally relevant boundary con-
ditions, the restatement of (b), the spanning regularity so to
speak, becomes otiose. But we must notice that until we
accumulate all this knowledge, it will not help us to fully
specific prediction of the detailed compensatory mechanisms of
the (thermostatic) system that we recast our generalisation
about S's regular return to G in openly teleological terms. 'S
will do whatever is required to return to G'; but what exactly
is that? "Well, in Dn+3 it requires certain adjustments of A,
B and C." But what adjustments precisely? Perhaps there
is more than one set of adjustments that would do; or perhaps
there is only one set that could lead to G. Could there be more
than one set available to the system in the particular (intrinsic)
situation in which it would find itself at Dn + 3 ? If so, what
might determine the set of adjustments that the system actually
undergoes ? At any rate we know that there must be at least
one set, if our hitherto observed regularity that S does return to
G is to continue to hold; so this, taken together with our
knowledge of other regularities concerning the behaviour either
of systems such as S or of certain of its constituent elements,
may give direction to our search for and, hopefully, discovery
of more detailed 'intervening' regularities. There is--of course
-a continual process of adjustment, of filling in and of reformu-
lation of broader and narrower, more general and more
specific statements of regularities of all these sorts.
So far, so-on the whole-Sprigge. But it is at this point that
I should tentatively part company with him to rejoin what I,
again tentatively, think should have been, or perhaps really is,
something more like Taylor's position. Let us return to our
examples.
As Taylor himself shows clearly enough in the first part of
his article in the Borger/Cioffi collection-a section with
which Borger, incidentally, expresses himself in almost total
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
182 ALAN MONTEFIORE
agreement-a mere collection of regularities goes comparatively
little way to explaining the regular occurrence of the events
over which they range. We find a set or sets of fallen leaves
which regularly behave in the surprising ways outlined above;
the leaves regularly move from any configuration D to con-
figuration G or they do whatever is required to maintain
configuration D. Either way their behaviour still seems extra-
ordinary; we want an explanation. Consider, then, the two
following possible outline accounts: A. The leaves are somehow
magnetised in such a way as to act upon each other (as long as
they fall into a D which leaves them within acting range) so as
to propel or to attract each other into configuration G. The
regularity of their movements reflects the nature of the under-
lying forces involved. B. The leaves have some conception of the
configuration G as a preferred state and somehow seek to main-
tain or to return to it in the light of this conception. Both of
these are putative explanations, however unlikely they may
seem of this anyhow unlikely event, in that they go deeper and
are more general than the regularities that they seek to explain.
Both are fully compatible with an account of the phenomena
in terms of (sets of) regularities, whether that account be given
in Humean causal or in what we have so far been calling
teleological form. (Indeed, they must be so compatible, if we
are to be able to identify the regularities to be explained in
terms independent of the theories that may variously be pro-
posed in an attempt to explain them.) But they are not, as
explanations, compatible with each other. Why not ?
The brief answer, or a brief and rough formulation of the
answer, to this question seems to me to be that both these
accounts, A and B, involve not merely sets of contingently
linked, contingent regularities, each relating to groups of
logically 'separate existences', but in addition the more or less
fully articulated structures of internally self-interlocking
theories; and that there can be no explanatory room for two
theories of these particular sorts, each claiming to give different,
but in principle full-bloodedly explanatory accounts of the
same fact.9
It is a fundamental condition of Humean objects or events
that they must be fully identifiable in terms which in no
way encroach on the contingency of the relationships into
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 183
which they may enter or of the generalisations which, as good
Humeans, we may be able to form about them. It is no doubt
because of the manifest importance of insisting on the irreduc-
ible element of contingency that must be carried by any
scientific explanation that the impulse is still so strong, even at
times in those who are most fully aware of the structural element
also irreducibly embodied in any scientific-or, I should be
inclined to say indeed, pre-scientific-identification of objects,
to account for the nature of efficient causal explanation in
straightforwardly Humean terms. Within the terms of an
essentially diachronical and fully structured theory, however,
the identification of a set of objects at one moment in time is
linked, logically, if one likes to say so, or at any rate concep-
tually, to the identification of other objects at other moments
of time.
It will be evident that in risking this bald assertion, I am
venturing, very uncomfortably, on to the ground of overlap
between a number of centrally controversial issues in the theory
of knowledge and the philosophy of science; and happily or
unhappily the limits of a contribution to a Joint Session
symposium hardly allow one to be more than speculatively
provocative on such complex matters. Moreover, I should be
quite incapable of following through my fantasy of the magne-
tised leaves in the proper detail of modern magnetic theory. So
to stick once again to stark and simple outline: If one considers
the structure of a paradigmatically mechanical theory of a
classically Newtonian type, one knows very well that if the
values of all variables but one are given, then the value (or the
range of permissible values) of the remaining variable is
uniquely determined. This means to say that insofar as we take
the theory to apply to a given range of phenomena, and insofar
as we have been able to establish the relevant measurements
for all items except one of a given sub-system, then if our
measurement of this one remaining item falls outside the limits
of variation allowed by the demands of the theory, we have to
conclude either that there has been some error of measurement
or that the theory is in part or totally incorrect (or that we have
made some mistake in establishing the boundary conditions of
the sub-system in question) or that we have in fact misidentified
one or more of the phenomena. That is to say, the phenomena
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
184 ALAN MONTEFIORE
of different instants are so related through the structure of the
theory that, as long as we accept our theory as providing proper
forms of identification for the phenomena, we have to say that
what we discover about the phenomenon of one instant tells us
something (necessary) about the phenomena of other instants.
Contingency is preserved not in the regular link between one
phenomenon and another insofar as both the phenomena and
the link between them are characterised as established within
the structure of the theory, but in the application of the theory
as a whole to the range of phenomena in question-here
identified, of course, through terms remaining at least partially
independent of the theory that is proposed.
Of course, this statement of the position, which would any-
how not apply in this form to, say, quantum mechanics, skates
over some large and crucial problems, in particular those of the
different sorts of relationships, taxonomic or causal, that may
be established between the terms of different levels of theoretical
discourse and those through which one may first identify the
range of phenomena to which the theory in particular question
may or may not be judged to apply. If the two were identical
and if the theory were both fully structured and fully deter-
minate, contingency would effectively disappear from the scene;
on the other hand, the notion of theoretically wholly innocent
terms, which would be neutral with respect to any conceptually
interlocking structure, is surely a myth. In the temptations of
the first possibility may lie a central error of rationalist theories
of explanation; in the latter insight, their central truth. But
however this may be, it seems inevitable that in many practical
situations of scientific advance there should be varying types of
interrelationships between terms having primary roots in
theoretical structures of different levels, where often, no doubt,
the precise nature and extent of these interrelations is only more
or less imperfectly perceived as they undergo a continual pro-
cess of adjustment and readjustment.
Nevertheless, when all due allowance has been made for the
crudities of this present sketch, it may serve to point towards
the source of that air of partial unreality which seems to infect
some stretches of the Sprigge/Taylor/Noble debates. Naturally,
there are no theoretical constraints governing our understand-
ing of such concepts as 'leaf', 'configuration', 'lion', 'kill',
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 185
'antelope' and so on, such as to encroach in any way on the
contingency of the regularities presumed in the examples that
we have taken. (Which is by no means to say, of course, that
they are so free of all theoretical or semi-theoretical constraints
that any event in the specification of which one of these terms
occurred could conceivably be followed by any other event
whatsoever; for example, "'Lion killing antelope' is regularly
followed by 'Lion running after antelope' ". I do not know
whether such a sequence might not feature intelligibly within
some framework of mythology; it could not do so within that
of our present non-mythological understanding of the animal
kingdom.) But any more basic (Newtonian) mechanical
explanation of the regularities which constitute any of the
examples we have used would be couched in terms which
carried much more systematically interlocking commitments.
Insofar as the elements to be explained (or predicted) were then
reidentified through these theoretically structured terms, the
regularities would be transposed out of their Humean key into
one of theoretically necessary connections and hence, when
temporal direction is taken into account, of production of later
events by earlier ones.
What was 'unreal', then, about, for instance, the earlier treat-
ment of our examples in terms of purely Humean generalisa-
tions came out pretty clearly in my attempted reference to the
existence of boundary conditions under which alone the leaves
might return by the most direct routes to G or lions proceed
in the most economical fashion to the killing of antelopes. For
where, in those contexts in which I was striving for at any rate
surface consistency, I was talking of the regularities exhibited
in the behaviour of the one or the other under given physical
conditions, it would actually have been more natural and more
appropriate to talk of the conditions under which such move-
ments were physically possible. Indeed, this was the way in
which, somewhat improperly and inconsistently, I allowed my-
self to speak for some of the time. For within the terms of
reference of a mechanically orientated structure of explanation,
all events are in principle to be understood as fully determined
by the nature of their relationships to surrounding events, and
reciprocally; and while it is true that within this perspective
the future may be taken as specifying the present and past just
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
186 ALAN MONTEFIORE
as much as it is specified by them, for immediate purposes the
crucially relevant aspect of this interrelationship is that the past
and the present fully specify the future. And this is a specifica-
tion which is quite independent of that which is carried, linking
present to future, by the intentional commitments of fully
teleological language.
'Quite independent'; but does independence here involve
incompatibility? John Lucas has recently put the matter in
the following way: " . . . it seems to follow from there being a
complete causal explanation of something that no other
explanation of it could be admitted, except in a merely deriva-
tive capacity. If we have given a complete regularity explana-
tion of everything, there is nothing else for any rational
explanation to explain . ". "10 In the immediate context in
which he makes it, his point seems to come out a little differently
from that which I am here suggesting in that Lucas there
writes of rational explanation rather than of teleological
explanation in general and in terms of apparent identification
of explanations in terms of causal efficiency with explanations
in terms of regularities; and as I have tried to indicate, it seems
to me rather that the contingent regularities in the phenomena,
which must certainly exist at some level of relatively non-
theoretical description if any fully determinate mechanical
theory is to hold true of them, cannot at the level of their con-
tingence be identifiable solely through terms which are already
embedded within the structure of such an explanatory theory.
Nevertheless, if one allows for the relevant transpositions, it
seems to me that Lucas' point holds. As Taylor is, of
course, fully aware, a genuinely teleological explanation
involves the characterisation of the relevant present event in
terms which depict it as determined in its present state by
reference to some future event. But what can be meant by this
expression 'by reference to some future event'? Enough has
been written about the difficulties, if not the absurdities, of
backward causation; this is not an occasion on which to return
to that reasonably well-trodden ground. But neither can it be
satisfactory to try simply to translate out this non-contingent
reference to the future in terms of the independently identifiable
contingent regularities, which again must certainly obtain at
some appropriate level of conceptualisation, in traditionally
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 187
Humean manner, if the explanation in terms of intentional
concepts is to hold. The Humean regularities would be the
same, whether the underlying explanation turn out to be
mechanical or teleological;"1 which itself might seem a fair
indication of the impossibility of actually translating either of
these theoretically structural explanations in terms of simple
regularities. (Though if one does make this translation, of
course, then one must in all consistency take the Spriggean line
of regarding the explanations in mechanical and teleological
terms as themselves intertranslatable.)
So what is the nature of the teleological reference to the
future ? Without necessarily wanting to endorse all that he has
said on the matter, it seems to me that Taylor has himself done
quite sufficient work on intentional concepts, most notably
perhaps in his article on 'Explaining Actions',12 to make it sur-
prising that he should at times appear to go so far along with
the acceptance of Humean regularities as constituting the
proper terms of debate between him and his opponents. As he
makes clear, to explain an action in intentional terms is, but at
the same time is not simply, to explain it as arising by way of
not necessarily invariable succession to some kind of conception
which the agent will have had of some relevant future state of
affairs. We all know not only that intentions, desires, etc., are
not simple sufficient causes of the actions that it is intended or
desired should take place, but also that there is no logical
invariability about the passage from intention to intended
action. We simply do not always do what we intend, desire,
want, etc. to do. But equally it is inconceivable both that we
should never act on our intentions, desires, wants, etc., and that
our actions should always fail. The logically or conceptually
necessary connections between the intention, the act and the
future result are not ones of invariable sequence, but they are
necessary ones all the same.
It is this intentionally, non-invariable but still necessary
connection that provides a basis, perhaps the only 'real' basis,
for our understanding of truly teleological explanation. Its full
articulation obviously demands much more space than is here
available, even if I felt that I knew exactly how to articulate it.
But, to return a last time to our examples, we can say that if the
leaves seek to return to configuration G in virtue of their own
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
188 ALAN MONTEFIORE
or of some 'designer's' conception of it as a preferred state of
affairs, or if the lion-more plausibly-seeks to kill the antelope
in virtue of his (maybe we have to say quasi-) conception of it
as a source of desired food, then we can start to spell out afresh
the nature of our explanation of the relevant B as taking place
for the sake of a G, which either the subjects themselves or some
underlying 'designer' had already conceived of as a to-be-
aimed-at future state while the system was still in SE; always
remembering that if SE did include this conception of G as
desirable or to be aimed at, then we must suppose that, if not
on this particular occasion, at least on a significant proportion
of similar occasions the holding of such conceptions must be
(have been/will be) followed both by a B likely, or thinkable
of as likely, to be a sufficient productive cause of G and, on
some significant further sub-set of occasions, by G itself.
Clearly there may be cases in which the disjunction between the
immediate and remoter 'agent's' and 'designer's' conception or
purpose is not an exclusive one, and there may be various
relations of compatibility or tension between them.
Now, an explanation based on this form of diachronically
interlocking structure is incompatible with one given in terms
of mechanically efficient causation. The events (phenomena) to
be explained cannot be equally and simultaneously reinter-
pretable out of the terms of their initial identification as separate
Humean existences into those of two different but each more
or less systematically interlocking diachronic structures. More-
over, if we find ourselves in a situation where each of such
different (and in principle mutually independent) explanatory
structures is on offer, Taylor is right, as Lucas is right, to insist
that it is the mechanical explanation which will drive out the
teleological one. This obviously does not mean that the homing
rocket will no longer present those systematic behavioural
regularities which enable us to continue talking of it, without
internal inconsistency, in teleological terms. But once we know
that the underlying explanation is mechanical, we know ipso
facto that its behaviour is in one very important sense not
'really' or autonomously goal-directed; either it has no con-
ception of what it is doing or, if it does, its conceptions have no
directly causal relevance to what it does; if it alters course in a
given direction, it is sufficient, to explain its movements as
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 189
necessary, that we refer to what has gone before; a reference
to a final G may, certainly, be implied by, but does not have
to be referred to as a necessary part of the explanation. (Except,
no doubt, in the sense that we may wish to speak of the purposes
of the designer.)
Thus, although a predictive reference to a final G must be
taken as being contained within the terms of a 'full' mechanical
explanation, the distinguishing point remains that, once the
temporal direction is given, the path of mechanical explana-
tion is, so to speak, linear, while that of teleological explanation
is not; or to put it another way, one's account of a strictly
mechanical system is temporally invertible, while that of a
teleological system is not. For example:-In mechanical
explanation we have an initial stimulus leading to a form of
behaviour, which in turn leads on to a state which may be
called the goal; the behaviour may be accompanied by a con-
ception held by the agent of the goal-(the notion of accompani-
ment may be taken as covering a certain variety of possible
temporal relations), but for the explanation to be fully mechani-
cal it cannot depend on the conception for any intervening
causal efficacy. In teleological explanation we have a stimulus
leading to the holding of a conception, which in turn only leads
to the relevant behaviour via its necessary forward reference to
the goal state, G, to which in a significant number of cases the
behaviour must lead by paths now of normal causal efficiency.
Here the conception is no mere accompaniment with no further
causal contribution of its own to make in the production of G
of which it is a conception; it is on the contrary an integral link
in the teleological causal chain.
Seen from this point of view, it is Sprigge's view that "it seems
incongruous to regard consciousness or awareness as a causal
agent in that world of which it is an awareness" that is itself
incongruous. Certainly, his view is entirely and admirably con-
sistent both with his own equation of efficient and teleological
causation on the basis of their common analysis in terms of
Humean regularities and/or with a wholehearted acceptance of
a fully mechanistic model of explanation at the expense of a fully
teleological one. (Though even this needs qualifying: as far as
the formal structure of either the independent regularity or the
fully mechanistic views are concerned, consciousness could
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
g190 ALAN MONTEFIORE
perfectly well turn out to be a causal agent of one sort or
another-for example, it might cause sweating; the point is
simply that it could not be a causal agent in what might be
called its own conscious or intentional direction.) But-as Taylor
again makes clear in his Inquiry article-it is quite incompatible
with all the assumptions of our ordinary ways of conceiving
mental or intentional phenomena, and hence quite incompatible
with the categories of teleological explanation in the sense in
which I have been trying to explicate it.
I am conscious both of exceeding my proper ration of space
and yet of having done no more than skate rather messily on only
a part of the surface of this tangled set of questions. I must end,
however, with just two final and abrupt points.
The first is simply that one way of stating the modification that
I should propose to Taylor's position, as he has hitherto tended
to express it, is that one should regard teleological explanation
as resting not so much on the form of laws taken in apparent
independence each of all others, but on the characteristic struc-
ture of systems-theoretical systems or, if one prefers to look at
it in that way, systems at the level at which the phenomena may
be seen as organised.
The second concerns my half suggestion that it might be only
those systems to which conceptions can be thought of as some-
how 'belonging' that may be countable as fully teleological. The
point that I had in mind was that only a system in which the
order of theoretically necessary explanation binds present and
future events in some temporally 'non-linear' way would seem
to be countable as teleological in the relevant sense; and I have
tried to illustrate the nature of such a binding by reference to
certain action directed conceptions and their intentional nature.
I can not at present think of any other way in which such a
binding could be illustrated. This should not be taken, however,
as constituting any sort of a priori exclusion of, say, a physiological
theory some of whose basic concepts might exhibit the same
logical structure and which might provide, therefore, a much
more intelligible foundation for that physiological 'mapping' of
belief states of which Sprigge, among others, speaks. One may
suspect, no doubt, that any relaxation of tension which such a
physiology might achieve in its relations with psychology would
be purchased at the price of an increase in tension elsewhere in
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
FINAL CAUSES 191
its relations with the other physical sciences. But one may suspect,
too, that one can never hope finally to eliminate such tensions,
but at best to shift them around. At any rate this is an appro-
priately speculative note on which to stop.
REFERENCES
1 Among the many friends who have helped me with critical discussions
of earlier versions of this paper, particularly grateful thanks are due to
Charles Taylor, Denis Noble, David McFarland and Rom Harr6 (all of
whom, I should add, continue to disagree with me on one point or another).
2 Analysis, Jan. 1967 and Dec. 1967.
3 Explanation in the Behavioural Sciences, Eds. R. Borger and F. Cioffi, pp.
8o-88.
4 Analysis, Mar. 1967 and Explanation in the Behavioural Sciences, pp. 89-95.
One should mention also, of course, Taylor's discussion of the views of
Ernest Nagel ("Teleological Explanations and Teleological Systems" in
Feigl and Brodbeck (Eds.), Readings in the Philosophy of Science) on p. 13 of
The Explanation of Behaviour.
1 Op. cit., p. 8o.
6 Op. cit., p. 84-
SSee, for example, p. io6.
8 Some people would appear to argue that as good a way as any of
marking the distinction between teleological and non-teleological systems
is to make it coincide with that between those systems which do and those
which do not include elements of physical feed-back. On this view a thermo-
stat would come out as a fully teleological system. Within the present limits
of space all I can say on this point is (i) that the distinction is, of course, a
real one, but (ii) that it is maybe not so clear as all that (can one draw a
really sharp line between mathematical and physical feed-back?); and
(iii) that the crucial questions will still concern the nature of the theory
through which one may account for the mechanisms by which the system
achieves its feed-back results.
9 I am not suggesting, however, that it is never possible to give two quite
different explanatory accounts of the same set of facts, which may be com-
plementary to rather than incompatible with each other. Denis Noble has
pointed out to me that we can quite consistently imagine someone giving
alternative thermodynamic and kinetic accounts of the movements of the
leaves, accounts which would be neither equivalent nor obvious all-out
rivals to each other. Unfortunately, lack of space here prevents me from
trying to comment on Noble's further suggestion that thermodynamics
might be considered as an in some sense teleological system; or on the fact,
pointed out by David McFarland, that a more adequate account of the
leaves example would have to allow for their having in reality not one,
but two "goals", that of economy of movement as well as the final con-
figuration G, and for the various ways in which these goals may interfere
with or have to be set off against each other. It would also have to allow
for the possibility of their making what might be interpreted as detours on
their way to their goals. A mathematical version of such an account might
typically lead one to speak of the system of leaves as either tending to or
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
192 ALAN MONTEFIORE
aiming at the maximisation of certain mathematical functions. Suffice it
here to say that while such varied considerations would certainly involve
further complications, I do not (at present) think that they would compel
any fundamental changes in my present consciously over-simple presenta-
tion of the position.
10 The Freedom of the Will, p. 49.
1x If this by now appears obvious with respect to non-verbalising
"systems" such as lions, it may seem less so in the case of at least partly
articulate "systems" such as man. Clearly, we have not to understand
"reasons for actions" in terms of the same patterns of regularly succeeding
events as "causes of behaviour". Nevertheless, if we are to give sufficient
differential explanations or predictions of actions (as compared with merely
showing them to be intelligible or likely), then we must refer, at least
implicitly, to some associated sets of regularities-which must include,
incidentally, a significant number whose integrating explanation will be
in terms of ordinary efficient causation. Of course, some people might hold
that it is an important feature of teleological systems that we must under-
stand why it must be that some of their actions may remain partially
inexplicable.
12 Inquiry, Summer, 1970.
This content downloaded from 130.237.29.138 on Sat, 12 Mar 2016 19:24:02 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions