Karen Barad 1996 - Meeting The Universe Halfway. Realism and Social Constructivism Without Contradiction
Karen Barad 1996 - Meeting The Universe Halfway. Realism and Social Constructivism Without Contradiction
1. INTRODUCTION
The morning after giving an invited lecture on the socially constructed nature of
scientific knowledge, I had the privilege of watching as a STM (scanning tunneling
microscope) operator zoomed in on a sample of graphite, and as we approached
a scale of thousands of nanometers ... hundreds of nanometers ... tens of nano-
meters ... down to fractions of a nanometer, individual carbon atoms were imaged
before our very eyes. The experience was so sublime that it sent chills through my
body - and I stood there, a theoretical physicist who, like most of my kind, rarely
ventures into the basements of physics buildings experimental colleagues call
"home", conscious that this was one of those life moments when the amorphous
jumble of history seems to crystallize in a single instant. How many times had I
recounted for my students the evidence for the existence of atoms? And there they
were - just the right size and grouped in a hexagonal structure with the interatomic
spacings as predicted by theory! "If only Einstein, Rutherford, Bohr, and especially
Mach, could have seen this!" I found myself exclaiming. And as the undergraduate
students operating the instrument (that they had just gotten to work the day before
by carefully eliminating sources of vibrational interference - we're talking nano-
meters here!), disassembled the chamber which held the sample so that I could see
for myself the delicate positioning of the probe above the graphite surface, expertly
161
L. H. Nelson and J. Nelson (eds), Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science, 161-194.
© 1996 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
162 KARENBARAD
cleaved with a piece of scotch tape, I mused outloud that "seeing" atoms will
quickly become routine for students (as previous generations in turn found the
examination of cells by visual light microscopes to be and then the structure of
molecules by electron microscopes so) and that I was grateful to have been brought
up in a scientific era without this particular expectation.
At this point in my story, I imagine there will be scientific colleagues who will
wonder whether this presented a moment of intellectual embarrassment for your
narrator who had on the previous night insisted on the socially constructed nature
of scientific knowledge. In fact, although I was profoundly moved by the event I
had just witnessed, standing there before the altar of the efficacy of the scientific
enterprise, I was unrepentant. For as social constructivists have tried to make clear,
empirical adequacy is not an argument that can be used to silence charges of con-
structivism. The fact that scientific knowledge is socially constructed does not
imply that science doesn't "work", and the fact that science "works" does not mean
that we have discovered human-independent facts about nature. (Of course, the fact
that empirical adequacy is not proof of realism is not the endpoint, but the starting
point for constructivists, who must explain how it is that our constructions work -
an obligation that seems all the more urgent in the face of increasingly compelling
evidence that the social practice of science is conceptually, methodologically, and
epistemologically allied along particular axes of power.')
On the other hand, I stand in sympathy with my scientific colleagues who want
science studies scholars to remember that there are cultural and natural/material
causes for knowledge claims. While most social constructivists go out of their way
to attempt to dispel the fears that they are either denying the existence of a human-
independent world or the importance of material factors in the construction of
scientific knowledge, the bulk of the attention has been on cultural factors. To be
fair, this is where the burden of proof has been placed: social constructivists have
been responding to the challenge to demonstrate the falsity of the worldview that
takes science as the mirror of nature. Nonetheless, as both the range and sophis-
tication of constructivist arguments have grown, the charge that they embrace an
equally extreme position - that science mirrors culture - has been levied against
them with increasing vigor. While few constructivists actually take such an extreme
position, we would be remiss in simply dismissing this charge as a trivial over-
simplification and misunderstanding of the varied and complex positions that come
under the rubric of constructivism. For the anxiety being expressed, though admit-
tedly displaced, touches upon the legitimate concern about the privileging of epi-
stemological issues over ontological ones in the constructivist literature. Ontological
issues have not been totally ignored, but they have been overshadowed.
The ontology of the world is a matter of discovery for the traditional realist. The
assumed one-to-one correspondence between scientific theories and reality is used
to bolster the further assumption that scientific entities are unmarked by the dis-
coverers: that is, nature is taken to be transparently given. Acknowledging the
importance of Cartwright's (1983) philosophical analysis decoupling these assump-
tions and her subsequent separation of scientific realism into two independent
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 163
positions - realism about theories and realism about entities - Hacking (1982), like
Cartwright, advocates realism towards entities. Shifting the traditional emphasis in
science studies away from theory construction to the examination of experimental
practice, Hacking grounds his position on the ability of the experimenter to man-
ipulate entities in the laboratory. Galison (1987) also centers experimental practice
in his constructivist analysis comparing three different periods of twentieth-century
physics experimentation, wherein he generalizes Hacking's criterion for the reality
of entities by underlying the importance of the notions of stability (i.e., invariances
of results under changing experimental conditions, rather than the narrower cat-
egory of manipulation) and directness (i.e., epistemologically, but not necessarily
logically, non-inferential). There are other constructivist approaches which go
further in interrogating the transparency of our representations of nature. Latour
(1993) prioritizes stability as well, posing it as one variable of a two-dimensional
geometry whose other axis connects the poles of Nature and Society. Essence then
becomes the trajectory of stabilization within this geometry that is meant to charac-
terize the variable ontologies of quasi-objects. In contrast, Haraway (1988) em-
phasizes instability: it is the instability of boundaries defining objects that is the
focal point of her explicit challenge not only to conceptions of nature that claim to
be outside of culture, but also to the separation of epistemology from ontology.
Interestingly, the instability of boundaries and Haraway's insistence that the objects
of knowledge are agents in the production of knowledge, feature her notions of
cyborgs (1985) and material-semiotic actors (1988) which strike up dissonant and
harmonic resonances with Latour's hybrids and quasi-objects (1993). Moving to
what some consider the opposite pole of the traditional realist position is the post-
structuralist position. To many scientists as well as science studies scholars,
Derridian forms of poststructuralism that disconnect sign from signified seem to be
the ultimate in linguistic narcissism. While insisting that we are always already in
the "theater of representation", Hayles (1993) takes exception to extreme views that
hold that language is groundless play, and while she does not provide us with
access to the real she does attempt to place language in touch with reality by re-
conceptualizing referentiality. Hayles' theory of constrained constructivism (1993)
relies on consistency (in opposition to the realist notion of congruence) and the
semiotic notion of negativity to acknowledge the importance of constraints offered
by a reality that cannot be seen in its positivity: as she puts it, "Although there may
be no outside that we can know, there is a boundary" (p. 40, original emphasis).
These attempts to say something about the ontology of our world are exceptions
rather than the rule in the constructivist literature. There is a need to elaborate
further upon the crafting of ontologies. We need to understand the technologies by
which nature and culture interact. Does nature provide some template that gets
filled in by culture in ways that are compatible with local discourses? Or do specific
discourses provide the lenses through which we view the layering of culture upon
nature? Does the full "texture" of nature get through or is it partially obliterated or
distorted in the process? Is reality an amorphous blob that is structured by human
discourses and interactions? Or does it have some complicated irregular shape that
164 KARENBARAD
The inspiration for agential realism comes from my reading of Niels Bohr's philo-
sophy-physics. (I use this hyphenated structure, instead of the usual "philosophy
of physics", to emphasize Bohr's unwillingness to think of these interests as
distinctive in any sense, contrary to the sharp disciplinary boundaries that are
166 KARENBARAD
I then show how agential realism can be used to address particular concerns that
social constructivist approaches to science make apparent, including some of the
ones enumerated in the previous section. I diverge from Bohr in strategy here, but
not in spirit. Bohr's methodological approach was to draw out the epistemological
lessons of quantum theory for other fields of knowledge by essentially trying to
guess what the relevant Complementary variables would be in each arena. This
analogic strategy often failed: both because he proposed a set of variables that
turned out not to be Complementary, and because the implications drawn on this
basis watered down the complexity and richness of the "epistemologicallessons".9
My approach will be to examine specific implications by directly taking on a dif-
ferent set of epistemological and ontological commitments. That is, I will not use
the notion of Complementarity as a springboard; instead I directly interrogate
particular philosophical background assumptions that underlie specific concerns.
Finally, I want to make explicit the distinction between my approach and a host
of analogical (mis)appropriations of quantum theory that are more common in the
literature than physicists would wish. I will not put forward any argument to the
effect that quantum theory of the microworld is analogous to situations that interest
us in the macroworld - be they religious, spiritual, psychological, or even those en-
countered in science studies. My focus is on the development of widely applicable
epistemological and ontological issues, that can be usefully investigated by a rigor-
ous examination of measurement processes as explicated by Bohr's understanding
of quantum physics. To ask whether it is not suspect to apply arguments made
specifically for microscopic entities to the macroscopic world is, in this case, to
mistake the approach as analogical. The epistemological and ontological issues are
not circumscribed by the size of Planck's constant (see note 12). That is, I am not
interested in mere analogies but rather widely applicable philosophical issues such
as the conditions for objectivity, the appropriate referent for empirical attributes,
the role of natural as well as cultural factors in scientific knowledge production, and
the efficacy of science.
3. MEASUREMENT MATTERS
Often the development of physics has taught us that a consistent application of even the most elementary
concepts indispensable for the description of daily experience, is based on assumptions initially un-
noticed, the explicit consideration of which is, however, essential if we wish to obtain a classificatIOn of
more extended domains of experience as clear and as free from arbitranness as possible .... This de-
velopment has contributed to the general philosophical clarification of the principles underlying human
knowledge (Bohr. 1937.289-290).
Common to the schools of so-called empirical and critical philosophy. an attitude therefore prevailed of
a more or less vague distinction between objective knowledge and subjective belief. By the lesson re-
garding our position as observers of nature, which the development of physical science in the present
century has given us, a new background has, however, been created just for the use of such words as ob-
jectivity and subjectivity. From a logical standpoint, we can by an objective description only understand
172 KARENBARAD
a communication of experience which does not admit of ambiguity as regards the perception of such
communicatIOns (Bohr, quoted in Folse, 1985, 15).
4. METHODOLOGICAL INTERLUDE
Einstein once remarked of Bohr, "He utters his opinions like one perpetually groping and never like one
who believes to be in possession of definite truth"' (Einstein, quoted in Pais, 1982, 417).
174 KARENBARAD
Many of the philosophers, historians, and the few physicists who have tried to read
Bohr's works have commented on the difficulty of this task. Bohr's style is atypical
of most science writing. His writing reflects a self-conscious regard of his own de-
scriptive process, which is consistent with his thorough-going examination of the
role of description in scientific knowledge production, fundamental to his approach
to understanding quantum physics. In like manner, I have tried to remain attentive
to my own descriptivelinterpretative process in my reading of Bohr. Consequently,
I make no claims here to have discovered what Bohr was actually thinking or
intending, as separate from my own interpretative apparatus; rather I attempt to
provide a consistent reading within the context of particular ways of resolving
ambiguities. (Recall that for Bohr descriptions refer to phenomena, not to some
independent reality.) There are clear parallels between this methodology and
feminist and other located-know ledges methodologies. This is not mere co-
incidence but, as will become clear later, a reflection of a common critical
reflexivity.
My presentation of the major features of Bohr's post-Newtonian framework and
corresponding epistemology come from more than a decade of extensive study of
Bohr's writings. Interpretative questions about quantum theory plagued me as a
graduate student in theoretical particle physics. (It may seem peculiar to non-
scientists to discover that physics graduate school is not the appropriate context for
engaging such questions. 21 ) By the time I was an assistant professor of physics, my
focus broadened to include the larger philosophical issues in Bohr's post-
Newtonian framework.
The ideas as I have presented them so far are in considerable agreement with
individual features of many of the standard secondary texts on Bohr's philosophy
of physics, including the work of Feyerabend (1962), Hooker (1972), Bohm (1985),
Folse (1985), Petersen (1985), Honner (1987), and Murdoch (1987). It is important
to point out that the views of these scholars are widely divergent on many crucial
points. I do not agree in toto with the views presented in any of these other
accounts, though as I read through the primary texts time and again from the per-
spective of a theoretical particle physicist, various aspects of these works have been
and continue to be helpful to me while I formulate my own evolving views on
Bohr's philosophy-physics.
As a measure of the disagreement among Bohr scholars, consider the question of
the nature of Bohr's interpretative framework. Most Bohr scholars, and many other
scholars who have not studied Bohr, attribute some form of antirealism to Bohr, who
has been called a positivist, an idealist, an instrumentalist, a (macro)phenomenalist,
a relativist, a pragmatist, and a (neo)Kantian. Folse has been one of the strongest
proponents of the minority view that sees Bohr as a realist. As I indicated in the
Introduction, one of the difficulties in resolving the ambiguities in Bohr's position is
that Bohr focuses on epistemological issues in his writings and he never spells out
his ontological commitments. Consequently, it is difficult to discern the nature of
any correspondence he may hold between theory and reality. Without a clear-cut
presentation of a coherent Bohrian ontology, the task of determining what kind of
realist or antirealist position is consistent with Bohr's philosophy-physics seems
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 175
doomed. In the next section, I present an ontology I believe to be consistent with
Bohr's views, and I then address the question of a correlative interpretative stance.
I will argue that Bohr's philosophy-physics can be understood to be consistent
with a particular form of realism, that I label "agential realism". But at I noted from
the outset, my aim is not so much to provide a faithful representation of Bohr's'
philosophy-physics, as to propose a framework for thinking about critical epistemo-
logical and ontological issues, particularly in science studies. In addressing these
issues in the remainder of the paper it would be just as dishonest to attribute the full
development of this framework to Bohr as it would be to deny that my thinking
about Bohr's philosophy-physics is everywhere present in my formulation.
Bohr has often been badly misunderstood, I believe, because his readers have insisted on reading the
classical ontological and epistemological assumptions into ... [his] remarks ... it presupposes some auto-
nomously existing atomic world which is describable independently of our experimental investigation of
it. There is no such world for Bohr. ... There is no godlike approach possible to the physical world
whereby we may know it as it is "absolutely in itself; rather we are able to know only as much of it as
can be captured in those situations which we can handle conceptually - that is, those situations where
unambiguous commumcation of the results IS possIble .... This is in complete contrast to the classical
realist metaphysics and epistemology where the world is concerned as being the way classical theory
says it is. Independently of our experimental exploratIOn of it. ... (Clifford A. Hooker, 1972, 155-6)
emphasizes the positive feature of this passage - that Bohr offers his own definition
of physical reality in the final sentence:
From our point of view we now see that the wording of the above-mentioned criterion of physical reality
proposed by Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen contains an ambIguity as regards the meaning of the
expression "without in any way disturbing the system". Of course there is in a case like that just con-
sidered no question of a mechanical disturbance of the system under investigation during the last critical
stage of the measuring procedure. But even at this stage there is essentially the question of an influence
on the very conditions which define the possible types of predictions regardinR the future behaviour of
the system. Since these conditions constitute an inherent element of the description of any phenomenon
to which the term "physical reality" can be properly attached, we see that the argumentation of the
mentioned authors does not justify their conclusion that quantum-mechanical description is essentially
incomplete (original italics, Bohr, 1935, 700).
In discussing Bohr's use of the word 'phenomenon' earlier, I pointed out that the
conditions which define the possible types of predictions constitute an inherent
element of the description of any phenomenon. Therefore, the first phrase of the
last sentence is consistent with Bohr's use of the term phenomenon. 24 The last sen-
tence then indicated that the term 'physical reality' can properly be attached to the
phenomenon. Phenomena are constitutive of reality. Reality is not composed of
things-in-themselves or things-behind-phenomena, but things-in-phenomena.
This interpretation is consistent with the following point made by von Weiz-
sacker:
The fact that classical physics breaks down on the quantum level means that we cannot describe atoms
as "little things". This does not seem to be very far from Mach's view that we should not invent "things"
behind the phenomena. But Bohr differs from Mach in maintaining that "phenomena" are always "phe-
nomena involving things", because otherwise the phenomena would not admit of the objectification
without whIch there can be no science of them. For Bohr, the true role of things is that they are not
"behind" but "in phenomena" (quoted in Honner, 1987, IS).
Notice that in this last sentence we are told that scientific theories describe physical
phenomena. Since phenomena constitute agential reality, and it is phenomena that
scientific theories describe, it follows that scientific theories describe agential
reality. Were it not for the crucial adjective "agential", emphasizing the non-
objectivist nature of Bohrian ontology, as I've described it here, the conclusion of
this syllogism would sound like the proclamation of a die-hard realist who is ad-
vocating a classical correspondence theory of truth. However, the correspondence
in question is between theories and agential reality, not an observer-independent
reality. Hence, I conclude that Bohr's framework is consistent with a particular
notion of realism, which I label "agential realism". Agential realism is compatible
with the point I made earlier in this section that any notion of realism that is con-
sistent with Bohr's philosophy must not be parasitic on subject-object / culture-
nature / word-world distinctions. 26
That Bohr subscribed to some sort of realism is also supported by his practice of
science. A particularly poignant example of how different philosophical positions
guided the efforts of different segments of the physics community during the 1920s
is given by considering a range of reactions to the notion of "wave/particle duality".
These reactions constitute the twentieth-century contribution to a long historical
debate about the nature of light.
To say that light consists of particles is to insist that light consists of localized
object that occupy a given location at each moment in time. On the other hand, to
say that light consists of waves is to insist that light consists of objects with ex-
tension in space, occupying more than one position at any moment of time, like
ocean waves that move along a stretch of beach; and furthermore, different waves
can overlap and occupy the same position at any moment of time, unlike particles.
Obviously, the concepts of "wave" and "particle" are mutually exclusive: an object
178 KARENBARAD
Throughout the field of meanings constituting science, one of the commonalities concerns the status of
any object of knowledge and of related claims about the faithfulness of our accounts to a "real world",
no matter how mediated for us and no matter how complex and contradictory these worlds may be
(Haraway, 1991, 197)
(1) Agential realism grounds and situates knowledge claims in local experiences:
objectivity is literally embodied.
On the one hand, feminists and other Enlightenment critics have expressed
skepticism towards objectivism, especially
180 KARENBARAD
[tlhe idea of a basic dichotomy between the subjective and objective; the conception of knowledge as
being a correct representation of what is objective; the conviction that human reason can completely free
itself of bias, prejudice, and tradition; the ideal of a universal method by which we can first secure firm
foundations of knowledge and then build the edifice of a universal science; the belief that by the power
of self-reflection we can transcend our historical context and horizon and know things as they really are
in themselves (Bernstein, 1983,36).
In the post-Kuhnian era in which we live, the arguments against objectivism have
been robust and extensive, reaching across disciplinary boundaries and out into the
world beyond the academy, so that few scholars currently find it tenable to sub-
scribe to the set of Enlightenment doctrines outlined above. Enlightenment
defenders are hard-pressed to show how objectivism can bootstrap its way out of
the murky waters of spacetime contingencies. Ironically, mainstream anti-
Enlightenment theorists, including Derrida, Foucault, and Lyotard, have ignored
crucial social markers such as gender and race in their critiques of the universal-
izing tendencies characteristic of the Enlightenment project. However, it is not only
the limitations of these critiques that have concerned feminists, but their thorough-
going rejection of the entire set of Enlightenment goals as well. Feminist theorists
have taken exception with anti-Enlightenment scholarship that abandons the pos-
sibility of positive epistemologies in their embrace of interpretationism, relativism,
and strong social constructivism. 30
Haraway's theory of situated knowledges presents a direct challenge to the ob-
jectivist "view from nowhere", the "godtrick" of infinite passive vision, and the
equally irresponsible relativist "view from everywhere", posing embodied sight -
the view from somewhere, along with the responsibility that that entails - as the
key to feminist objectivity. According to Haraway:
There is no unmediated photograph or passive camera obscura in scientific accounts of bodies and
machines; there are only highly specific visual pOSSibilities, each with a wonderfully detailed, active,
partial way of organizing worlds .... Understanding how these Visual systems work, technically, so-
cially, and psychically, ought to be a way of embodying feminist objectivity (1988, 583).
(2) Agential realism privileges neither the material nor the cultural: the apparatus
of bodily production is material-cultural, and so is agential reality.
While theoretical constructs are not to be understood as representing trans-
parently given observation-independent properties possessed by independent
material objectslbeings as they exist in isolation from all observational interactions,
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 181
neither are we to interpret these constructs as artifacts of the observational process,
purely discursive gestures imprinted on the blank slate of passive matter. As Bohr
tell us:
These problems were instructively commented upon from different sides at the Solvay meeting .... On
that occasion an interesting discussion arose also about how to speak of the appearance of phenom-
ena .... The question was whether, as to the occurrence of individual effects, we should adopt a ter-
minology proposed by Dirac, that we were concerned with a choice on the part of "nature" or, as
suggested by Heisenberg, we should say that we have to do with a choice on the part of the "observer"
constructing the measuring instruments and reading their recording. Any such terminology would,
however, appear dubious since, on the one hand, it IS hardly reasonable to endow nature with volition in
the ordinary sense, while, on the other hand, it is certainly not possible for the observer to influence the
events which may appear under the conditions he [sic] has arranged. To my mind, there is no other alter-
native than to admit that, in this field of experience, we are dealing with individual phenomena and
that our possibilities of handling the measunng instruments allow us only to make a choice between the
different complementary types of phenomena we want to study (Bohr, 1949,223).31
There are three important points that we can take from this passage: (i) nature has
agency, but it does not speak itself to the patient, unobtrusive observer listening for
its cries - there is an important asymmetry with respect to agency: we do the repre-
senting, and yet (ii) nature is not a passive blank slate awaiting our inscriptions, and
(iii) to privilege the material or the discursive is to forget the inseparability that
characterizes phenomena.
As evidenced in the above quote, when Bohr and other physicists engaged in dia-
logue about quantum theory they spoke about the "choice made on the part of the
experimenter," as if the experimenter is a liberal humanist actor of individual will. 32
There is no reference to the social dimensions of scientific knowledge production.
(It is interesting to note though that Bohr does acknowledge the role of linguistic
constraints.) However, without intending any anachronistic projections, it must be
the case that material-semiotic apparatuses are fully cultural (i.e., social, linguistic,
historical, political, etc.) frameworks, not the result of individual will, since repro-
ducibility and unambiguous communication are the criteria for objectivity. That is,
scientists make meanings within specific communities, they do not do so au-
tonomously. Therefore, according to agential realism, the apparatus that is
theorized must be a multidimensional material-cultural framework.
Furthermore, agential realism provides an account of the simultaneously material
and cultural nature of the ontology of the world. Saying that something is socially
constructed doesn't mean that it isn't real - on the contrary, according to agential
realism, reality is itself material-cultural,33 There is no opposition here between
materiality and social construction: constructedness does not deny materiality. The
materiality of the body is not dissipated by its constructedness since reality is con-
stituted by the "between ", the inseparability of nature-cultural / world-word /
physical-conceptual / material-discursive. Culture does not displace or replace
nature, but neither do things exist outside of culture. Phenomena are material-
cultural be-in's. Haraway makes a similar point, I think, in designating objects as
"material-semiotic actors". She uses this term "to portray the object of knowledge
as an active, meaning-generating part of the apparatus of bodily production,
without ever implying the immediate presence of such objects .... Boundaries are
182 KARENBARAD
drawn by mapping practices; 'objects' do not preexist as such. Objects are bound-
ary projects" (Haraway, 1988, 595). In other words, the apparatus of bodily produc-
tion, qua agencies of observation, are not separable from phenomena.
(3) Agential realism entails the interrogation of boundaries and critical reflexivity.
Wholeness, according to agential realism, does not signify the dissolution of
boundaries. On the contrary, boundaries are necessary for making meanings.
Theoretical concepts are only defined within a given context, as specified by con-
structed boundaries. Wholeness is not about the prioritizing of the innocent whole
over the sum of the parts; wholeness signifies the inseparability of the material and
the cultural. Wholeness requires that delineations, differentiations, distinctions be
drawn; differentness is required of wholeness. Utopian dreams of dissolving bound-
aries are pure illusion since by definition there is no agential reality without con-
structed boundaries. There are two common ways to attempt to deny responsibility
for boundaries: (1) claim that they are natural, or (2) claim that they are arbitrary
partitionings of a holistic oneness, existing outside of human space and time. In
contrast, agential realism explicitly shows that boundaries are interested instances
of power, specific constructions, with real material consequences. There are
not only different stakes in drawing different distinctions, there are different
ontological implications.
Furthermore, boundaries are not fixed. Productive and creative tensions are set
up in consideration of different possible placements of agentially situated cuts.
Consideration of mutually exclusive intra-actions, constituting opposing shifts in
the conceptual terrain, reminds us that descriptive concepts do not refer to an
observer-independent reality, but to phenomena. In fact, descriptions reflect back
upon the specification of boundaries, since descriptions refer to phenomena and
boundaries are in phenomena (i.e., the conceptual scheme is tied to the physical ap-
paratus and the descriptions refer to the phenomenon, which by definition includes
the apparatus; therefore the description refers back to the constructed conceptual
scheme). The placement of the boundary becomes part of what is being described:
human conceptual schema are part of the quantum wholeness. Descriptions of
phenomena are reflexive, and the shifting of boundaries constitutes a meta-critique.
The acknowledgement and interrogation of context is common to many feminist
epistemologies. For example, both Longino's theory of contextual empiricism and
Harding's theory of strong objectivity call for a critical examination of background
assumptions. Harding writes:
In an important sense, our cultures have agendas and make assumptions that we as individuals cannot
easily detect. Theoretically unmediated experience. that aspect of a group's or an individual's experi-
ence in which cultural influences cannot be detected. functions as part of the evidence for sCientific
claims. Cultural agendas and assumptions are part of the background assumptions and auxiliary
hypotheses that philosophers have identified. If the goal is to make available for critical scrutiny all the
evidence marshaled for or against a scientific hypothesis, then this evidence too requires critical exam-
ination within scientific research processes (1991.149).
The notion of complementarity, Bohr also wants to say, can be seen to arise out of the nature of our con-
sciousness of what is "other" to us, out of the unresolvable tension between content and form, between
reality and concept, and between theory and experience. Our representations of reality do not so much
involve a pnvileged mental mirroring of external reality, in which object and subject are absolutely
distant from each other, as a successful compromise between language and activity .... Yet for Bohr the
relationship between word and world is not seen as entirely relative, with the implication that our words
have no anchorage in world; instead given the nature of our conscIOusness of what is demonstrably
"other" to us, a relationship between word and world is accepted as necessarily denying complete
resolution (Honner, 1987, 103).
184 KARENBARAD
As a scientist I have been very interested in feminist science studies in part because
the scholars in this field, many of whom are scientists as well, have resisted the po-
larization often found in contemporary discussions about the nature of science as
posed by the more traditional and monodisciplinary approaches. Evelyn Keller
identifies two noncommunicating discourses about science,
... one an increasingly radical critique that fails to account for the effectiveness of science, and the other
a justification that draws confidence from that effectiveness to maintain a traditional, and essentially
unchanged, philosophy of science. What is needed is a way of thinking and talking about science that
can make sense of these two very different perspectives - that can credit the realities they each reflect
and yet account for their differences in perception (Keller, 1985, 6).
I think these tensions are quite productive and, in my opinion, Keller's challenge
marks one of the most important issues for contemporary science studies.
If the "discovery model" of science, that sees the production of scientific knowl-
edge as a one-actor show - nature at center stage with a passive audience of
observers patiently looking on - is no longer acceptable, and neither is some
extreme version of social constructivism that presents science as an arbitrary com-
pendium of power-laden rhetorical moves, then is it possible to give a detailed
understanding of the interaction of nature and culture in the production of scientific
knowledge? Agential realism provides a framework that can be useful for re-
theorizing a range of issues generated by reliance on classical epistemologies and
ontologies. In this section, I will explore the implications of agential realism for
science studies. I have in mind the following questions: How can we reconcile the
claim of science studies scholars that scientific knowledge is a socially constructed
product that is conceptually, methodologically, and epistemologically allied along
particular axes of power with both the liberatory and oppressive interventions that
are possible because of the reliability of empirically adequate scientific knowl-
edges? What, if anything, can be said about the ontology of our world through our
investigations of it? Is there a notion of realism that is consistent with the assertion
that scientific knowledge claims are culturally specific?
The scientific method, which was our Enlightenment birthright, promised to
serve as a giant distillation column, removing all cultural influences, and allowing
patient practitioners to collect the pure distillate of Truth. The transparency of
Newtonian physics to the process of measurement grew out of and helped re-
inforce this cultural milieu of objectivism that made the successes of science
unparadoxical: science works because scientists are able to obtain the facts about
the world as it exists independently of us human beings. The Enlightenment notion
of science is premised on a separation between knowing subjects and observation-
independent objects. Agential realism challenges this conceptualization of science
on epistemological and ontological grounds.
According to agential realism, scientific concepts obtain their meaning by
reference to a particular physical apparatus marking the placement of an agentially
constructed cut between the "object" and the "agencies of observation". In tum, the
point of reference for objective description of phenomena is "from permanent
marks ... left on the bodies which define the experimental conditions"34 (Bohr,
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 185
1963c, 3). Therefore, bodies serve as both the endpoint and starting point for
objective accounts of our intra-actions. In other words, agential realism gives us an
embodied account of objectivity.
Scientific results are not reproducible because we are able to measure the
observer-independent properties of an independent reality. Reproducibility is pos-
sible because scientific investigations are embodied, grounded in experience, in
praxis. Reproducibility means the possibility of the reproduction of phenomena,
and phenomena are written on the "body"; phenomena are the place where matter
and meaning meet. Reproducibility of phenomena does not require or serve as
proof for access to the transcendent. "The overall force of Bohr's argument is that
we are without absolute foundation in our participation in the world, despite the
acceptance that our language works by being anchored in everyday experience of
reality" (Honner, 1987, 222). Reproducibility of phenomena is not innocent - it
depends upon the choice of some constructed cut for which the ambiguity is only
temporarily, contextually decided in such a way as to lend meaning to certain con-
cepts, at the exclusion of others. Reproducibility is not a filter for shared biases; the
apparatus of bodily production is culturally situated. The scientists marking off the
boundaries are marked by the cultural specificities of race, history, gender, lan-
guage, class, politics, etc. In stark contrast to the classical framework, there is a
sense of agency and therefore accountability. Since reproducibility is the corner-
stone of Western science, in the context presently under discussion, science has
meaning, but not in any classical sense. 35 According to agential realism, science is
movement between meanings and matter, word and world, interrogating and
redefining boundaries, a dance not behind or beyond, but in "the between ", where
knowledge and being meet.
Scientific knowledge is not an arbitrary construction independent of "what is out
there", since it is not separate from us; and given a particular set of constructed
cuts, certain descriptive concepts of science are well-defined and can be used to
achieve reproducible results. However, these results cannot be decontextualized.
Scientific theories do not tell us about an independent reality; scientific concepts are
not simple namings of discoveries of objective attributes of an independent Nature
with inherent demarcations. Scientific concepts are not innocent or unique. They
are constructs which can be used to describe "the between", rather than some inde-
pendent reality. (Why would we be interested in such a thing as an "independent
reality" anyway? We don't live in such a world.) The point is that phenomena con-
stitute reality. That is, reality itself is material-cultural. And according to agential
realism, scientific know ledges are situated knowledges describing agential reality.
My revision of an important quote by Niels Bohr goes like this: "It is wrong to
think that the task of physics is to find out how nature is. Physics concerns what we
can say about [our intra-actions within] nature." We are in reality, we must be in
our theories. In other words, scientific theories describe agential reality - which is
just what we are interested in (we don't live in a transcendent reality). For scientific
theories to be able to describe agential reality, scientific knowledge must take
material-cultural factors into account since they are in agential reality, otherwise
186 KARENBARAD
8. CONCLUSIONS
So, I think my problem and "our" problem is how to have simultaneously an account of radical historical
contingency for all knowledge claims and knowing subjects, a critical practice for recognizing our own
"semiotic technologies" for making meanings, and a no-nonsense commitment to faithful accounts of a
"real" world, one that can be partially shared and friendly to earth-wide projects of finite freedom, ad-
equate material abundance, modest meaning in suffering, and limited happiness (Haraway, 1991, 187).
Agential realism denies the innocence of naive realism; instead, it entails a con-
scious, critical reflexivity. Dualisms, binary oppositions, dichotomies, and other de-
marcations are not secured with natural status as Cartesian cuts which form the
foundation of all knowledge - not even in physics. The lines drawn are power-
laden epistemological moves with stakes in a given conceptual scheme. This
doesn't mean that we can't justify drawing lines, or that crafted conceptual schemes
are unusable. Just because science is exposed as being socially constructed doesn't
mean that it doesn't work. And empirical adequacy is not an argument that can be
used to silence charges of constructivism. But neither is constructivism a proof of
epistemological relativism. I have argued that reliable theories about our intra-
actions are necessarily socially constructed theories with real material con-
sequences. We need knowledge systems that are both reliable and accountable
guides to action. Agential realism creates an alternative to objectivist accounts of
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 187
knowledge production that deny the situated nature of know ledges and social
constructivist accounts that do not address the effectiveness of knowledge systems.
Agential realism is not a call for feminists and others to bow down once again to
the hegemony of science in finding a new epistemology. On the contrary, agential
realism undermines the hegemony of science (though not its effectiveness).
Agential realism insists that science incorporate a reflexive critical discourse, like
all other human endeavors. Bohr argued that quantum physics, considered by many
to be the most highly esteemed field of science, requires a new framework for
understanding the role of descriptive concepts in scientific knowledge production.
The notions of wave and particle deconstruct one another, exposing the limitations
of the classical framework. There is irony, though perhaps little surprise, in the fact
that our interactions with light - oh light! that ever resilient metaphor for knowl-
edge illuminating the dark terrain of ignorance - plays a central role in under-
mining the hegemony of Newtonian physics, that bright star of the En-light-
enment, deconstructing the objective-subjective and nature-culture dualisms that
have plagued many attempts to understand the nature of scientific knowledge.
What I am proposing is not some holistic approach in which subject and object
reunite into some apolitical relativized whole, but a theory which insists on the
importance of constructed boundaries and also the necessity of interrogating and
refiguring them. The intra-action involving the subject-object problematizes
natural, pure, and innocent separations, but not in a way which reaches for the rapid
dissolution of boundaries. Boundaries are not our enemies; they are necessary for
making meanings, but this does not make them innocent. Boundaries have real
material consequences - cuts are agentially positioned and accountability is man-
datory. The shifting of boundaries often helps bring to the surface questions of
power which the powerful often try to submerge. Agential realism insists that
mutually exclusive, shifting, mUltiple positionings are necessary if the complexity
of our intra-actions are to be appreciated. 36 Multiple contestations of agentially po-
sitioned boundaries keep concepts alive, and protects them from reification and
petrification. Our goal should not be to find less false boundaries for all spacetime,
but reliable, accountable, located temporary boundaries, which we should anticipate
will quickly close in against us. Agential realism will inevitably be a casualty of its
own design, but I suggest that there is power there presently for some of our pur-
posesY Agential realism involves located or situated knowledges (Haraway, 1988),
knowledges that reject transcendental, universal, unifying master theories in favor
of understandings that are embodied and contextual.
Who are the agents in agential realism? The history of science parallels the
history of knowledge in other arenas: the powerful effectively portray their own
knowledge systems as universal, denying their own agency. Within this tradition,
agency has been an issue quite separate from authorship. Rivalries over primary
authorship are common in the history of science, but what is at stake is cleverness
and ingenuity; what is "discovered" is presumed unmarked by its "discoverer". The
claim is that the well-prepared scientist can read the universal equations of Nature
that are inscribed on G-d's blackboard: Nature has spoken. The paradox is that the
188 KARENBARAD
objects being studied are given all the agency, even and most especially when they
are seen as passive, inert things, culture-free and existing outside of human space
and time, moving aimlessly in the void. Completing this Enlightenment scenario,
are the passive human observers who are without agency. The overdetermination of
Enlightenment discourse is revealed in the juxtaposition of this mythology with the
liberal humanist story that provides man with individual will and dominion over
nature.
The nature-culture and object-subject dualisms are constructed cuts passed off
as inherent and fixed in the service of this legacy. Agential realism makes other
moves: shifting and destabilizing boundaries. Here knowledge comes from the
"between" of nature-culture, object-subject, matter-meaning. The Cartesian split
between the agencies of observation and the object is a classical illusion. Agency
cannot be designated as residing in one or the other in isolation. The observer does
not have total agency over passive matter - not any representation of reality will do -
since not any result one can think of is possible: the world "kicks back". Neither does
the object have total agency, whispering its secrets, mostly through the language of
mathematics, into the ear of the attentive scientist - knowledge is not so innocent; it
doesn't "just come out that way" all by itself. Nature is neither a blank slate for the
free-play of social inscriptions, nor some immediately present, transparently given
"thingness". Agential realism acknowledges the agency of both subjects and objects
without pretending that there is some utopian symmetrical wholesome dialogue,
outside of human representations. Science is not the product of some interaction
between two well-differentiated entities: nature and culture, since it flies in the face of
any matter-meaning dichotomy, like an electron that tunnels through boundaries set
up to confine its motion. Meaning and matter are more like interacting excitations of
non-linear fields - a dynamic, shifting dance we call science. 38
Phenomena are the intra-actions of knowledge and being, word and world, culture
and nature. Phenomena are material-cultural be-in's. Agential realism relies on a
non-classical ontology. The material is not fixed and prior to discursive signification,
but in it. Jeanette Winterson writes in her recent novel Written on the Body: "That is
how I know you. You are what I know" (Winterson, 1992, 120). Intra-acting is an
activity that theorizes the mechanics of an embodied objectivity. In our attempt to
understand we actively participate within reality. Realism is not about representa-
tions of an independent reality, but about the real consequences, interventions,
creative possibilities, and responsibilities of intra-acting within the world.
Finally, materiality matters: there are social and material reasons for knowledge
claims - the intra-actions of the material and the discursive are the technologies of
embodied objectivity - and socially constructed know ledges have real material con-
sequences. These conceptions of materiality are opposed to the immediacy of
matter in naive realist accounts and its neglect in some social constructivist
accounts. It seems to me that giving up on realism would be as hasty as giving up
on objectivity. Feminists have interrogated, redefined, and retheorized objectivity;
agential realism is an attempt to formulate a feminist notion of realism. Agential
realism goes beyond the recognition that there are material and cultural reasons for
knowledge claims, beyond the reconceptualization of description in knowledge
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 189
systems, to providing us with a positive sense of the ontology of our world and
some important clues as to how to intra-act responsibly and productively within it.
Judy Grahn suggests that: "To understand, to get to the basis, the root or hidden
meaning, is the wrong tool to bring" to our own work. "Perhaps interstand [or
better yet intra-stand] is what we do, to engage with the work, to mix with it in an
active engagement, rather than 'figuring it out'. Figure it in" (Grahn, 1989, 39).
Knowledges are not innocent representations, but intra-actions of natures-<:ultures:
knowledge is about meeting the universe halfway.
Pomona College,
Claremont, CA
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The original version was presented at the Pew Gender and Science Workshop, Lake
Arrowhead, CA, September 1991. Successive versions were presented at numerous
conferences and public lectures. I am grateful to Ruth Wilson Gilmore, Donna
Haraway, Sandra Harding, Martin Krieger, Helen Longino, Lynn Hankinson
Nelson, Jennifer Rycenga, Sharon Traweek, and Roanne Wilson for their insightful
comments and support.
NOTES
I A less obvious point is that the success of scientific theories is not automatic for realists either, as
IS realist, he tags Bohr's interpretation of quantum physics as antirealist, and furthermore, the existence
of thIS concrete example of underdetermination means that it would be very difficult to make the case
for realism. Although I will be argumg here for a realist interpretation on the part of Bohr. this diver-
gence in and of itself does not weaken the underdeterminatlOn aspect of Cushmg's argument. (There are
a few mdependent issues however. One is the fact that the empirIcal eqUIvalence of these theories
depends upon the resolutIOn of the measurement problem for the Copenhagen interpretation (see fn. 6)
since rigorously speaking without such a resolutIOn the Copenhagen interpretatIOn does not offer definite
predictions (see Albert. 1992). And of course. it still remains to be seen whether Bohm's theory and the
Copenhagen theory are empirically coinCIdent in all respects.)
3 This is not a cIrcularIty. As I will explain later, it is indIcative of a critical reflexiVIty .
.. The destabilization of lIberal humamst conceptIOns of identity that follow from the framework of
agential realIsm will not be my focus here. My focus here will be primarily on science. For more details
on agential realism and identity see Barad, forthcoming.
5 The collected volumes of Bohr's writmgs have been made available thanks to Rosenfeld, (1972- ).
6 While physicists talk of the Copenhagen interpretation, in one sense there are really many
Copenhagen InterpretatIOns. or to put It another way there IS no well-defined, coherent, and complete
Copenhagen interpretation. This is due to the fact that the physicists who are seen as the contrIbutors had
strong philosophical/interpretative differences, so that what is taken to be the Copenhagen interpretatIOn
is actually a superpositIOn of the views of Bohr (complementarity), Heisenberg (uncertamty), Born
(probability), and Von Neumann (collapse), to name a few of the key players.
7 For more details see Cushing, 1994. (Although Bohr's philosophy-physics is not a primary focus for
Cushmg, I note that my reading of Bohr diverges substantially from Cushing's. As I speCify in more
190 KARENBARAD
detail later, my reading has much more overlap with interpretations presented by a number of Bohr
scholars.)
8 There are an increasing number of quantum textbooks that do not mention any of Bohr's contributions
to the field (except for reference to his pre-quantum theory atomic model). That is, there is often no
mention of his principle of correspondence and the role it played in the development of the quantum
theory, or Complementarity and its importance to an understandIng of quantum theory.
9 For Bohr, Complementary means simultaneously necessary and mutually exclusive (as explained in
detail in the next section. NB: I capitalize 'complementary' when it is used in Bohr's sense of the term).
See Bohr (I 963b ) for examples for this approach. An attempt by Bohr to resolve the vitalism-mecha-
nism debate in biology failed because he assumed, from his limited technological perspective, that the
conditIons for examimng the underlying mechanics of life processes and the conditions for maintaining
the life of the specimen under investigation were mutually exclusive.
iO Although one is free to give antirealist interpretation of Newtonian physics, the "classical realist" one
articulated here is particularly seductive to our Enlightenment Intuitions, and I have heard variations of
this classical realist tenet espoused tIme and again to students in undergraduate physics classes. (It is of
course iromc to attribute a realist stance towards the phYSICS of one who was unwilling to feign any
hypothesis, but not many students would pick up on this since physics courses overwhelmingly lack any
overt discussion of the different interpretative stances with regard to science. See Barad (1995) for the
pedegogical implications of thiS widespread inattention to metatheoretIcal issues and the lack of critical
reflexivity.)
II A re-visioning of the nature of light is common to both of the major conceptual revolutIOn of
twentieth century physics: special relativity and quantum theory. Special relativity will not be con-
sidered in this paper, but a few words to distingUish some of the more popular implications of this theory
from quantum mechanics may be helpful to some readers. The special theory of relavity is based on the
empirically verified invariance and finiteness of the speed of light (llspeed of light = l/constant =
lie #- 0). Einstein transformed Galilean relatIvity into a new theory of relativity, redesignating certain
previously held invariant quantities as relalive and vice versa. (Einstein had thought of calling this
theory "the theory of invariances", and he may have been better off doing so given the political climate
in Europe during the first half of the 20th century.) The theory of relativity gives the measurement
process some limited viSibility: concepts such as "time" and "length" are defined relalive to a particular
frame of reference In which the measurements are performed. (It is not that time appears to slow down;
time is what you measure with a clock.) The theory of relativity may have undermIned the universality
of certain concepts, but the assumption that measurements are continuous and determinable is never
questioned. That is, according to the speCial theory of relativity there still IS a well-defined separation of
object and measuring instrument, i.e., a clear subject/object distinction is preserved. The properties
measured are attributable to an independent object as measured relative to a particular frame of
reference. (The frame of reference simply specifies which "time" we are talking about, that is, what we
mean by "time" in each case.)
12 It is Important to note that the fact that Newtoman phYSICS "works" in the macroscopic domain does
not mean that the assumptions of measurement transparency are true in that domain. On the contrary,
this simply explains why the assumptions lay hidden for centuries. That IS, the fact that Newtonian
phYSICS makes predictions that are approximately the same as those made by quantum theory in the
macroscopic domain is due to the fact that in that regime the ratio of Planck's constant to the mass of the
particle is smaller than the accuracy required of the macroscopic situation in question - but it IS not zero.
ThiS is why Bohr refers to the general epistemological lessons of quantum theory.
13 A rough, intuitive picture is the follOWIng: think of catching a ball, the relalive amount by which your
all, 'arbitrary' is misleading since the cut is not totally arbitrary in that the cut must be made in such a
way that the measuring device is always macroscopIc (thiS is necessary since the use of classical con-
cepts is predicated on a subject/object split). Secondly, the term 'arbitrary' carries misleadIng con-
notations such as the inappropriate associations of relativism. The point that I think Bohr IS out to
emphasize in using the term 'arbitrary' is that since there is no inherent/Cartesian distinction some non-
inherent distinction still must be drawn. SInce the choice of a conceptual apparatus necessarily draws
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 191
this distinction, I will use the term 'constructed' in the hope that this term will connote agency. The full
contrast is that classical physics is premised on an inherent/naturally occurring/fixediuniversallCartesian
distinction while quantum physics requires constructedlagentially positionedimovable/locall"Bohrian"
cuts, positioning Bohr as Descartes counterpart.
15 Another way of expressing this quantum quandary is by noticing that this means that the act of mea-
suring can be accounted for only if the measuring device IS itself treated as an object, defying its purpose
as a measuring instrument.
16 See Barad (1995) for a more detailed discussion of this example.
17 "Bohr's provocative tendency, especially in earlier writings, to 'emphasize the subjective character of
all experience' (Bohr, 1963a, I) brought his entire Interpretation of quantum theory into peril" (quoted
in Honner, 1987, 65), parallel to terminological choices made by some science studies scholars early on
that proved equally rhetorically disadvantageous.
18 Bohr interchanges the phrases "language of everyday experience" and "language of classical
physics". The connection for Bohr is that everyday experiences take place within the macroscopic
realm to which the language of claSSical phYSICS is applied. However, he does suggest that the lan-
guage of everyday experience may include "suitable generalizations" of the language of classical
physics.
19 Bohr: "It is just arguments of this kind which recall the Impossibility of subdividing quantum
phenomena and reveal the ambiguity in ascribing customary physical attributes to atomic objects"
(Bohr, 1963b, 51).
20 This detailed mapping of the relationship between classical concepts and phenomena is meant to
clarify Bohr's position with respect to the necessity of using classical concepts in the description of
quantum phenomena. Confusion about this issue is widespread in the literature. Many physicists trying
to understand Bohr's interpretative framework have accused Bohr of conservatism with respect to the
future development of physical theories: why they asked should we limit our descriptive concepts in this
way? It is also not uncommon to find philosophers describing this aspect of Bohr's theory as Kantian. I
hope that I have clearly communicated here why I think it is that Bohr was not denying the possibility
for future creative developments in physics, nor was he advocating transcendental idealism in his insis-
tence on the use of empirically grounded classical concepts even within a nonclassical framework
(which is already admitting the possibility of the evolution of Ideas). An important related fact is that
Bohr offers the observation that "everyday" languages are based on subject-predicate forms (a point that
he unfortunately makes without qualification); that is, everyday languages structurally assume
subject-object distinctions. I believe that this a contributing factor to what is commonly described as the
obscurity of Bohr's writings, since he uses many circumlocutIOns to try to talk about things that are not
inherently structured along this distinction.
21 See Keller's "Anomaly of a Woman in Physics" (1977) for one telling of a graduate school experi-
ence in the US that is typical in its discouragement of reflexiVity and contemplation of interpretative
questIons in physics, though specific in its gendering.
22 This quote is from Petersen, 1985, 302. Petersen goes on to say that Bohr had no use for an ontology.
Perhaps Bohr didn't feel the need to articulate one, but this is not to say that he held a thorough-gOing
pragmatIc or positivist view. In fact, I will argue later In this section that Bohr had a realIstIc attitude
towards wave-particle duality, for example, though his views diverged dramatically from classical
realism. Honner (1987) also argues for a realistic interpretation and against pragmatic or positivist per-
spectives, although the version of realism that Honner ascribes to Bohr does not address the issue of a
reference for our representations. Folse (1985) also advocates for an interpretation which sees Bohr as a
realist, but Folse seems to take phenomena as the result of an underlying reality.
23 Einstein et al., 1935 and Bohr, 1935. In an article entitled "Discussion with Einstein on
Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics", for a volume honoring the epoch-making contributions
of his long time friend Albert Einstein, Bohr quotes extensively from this particularly Important passage
of his 1935 paper (see Bohr, 1949,234).
24 I have presented what may seem like a pedantic analysis of Bohr's use of the term 'phenomenon' in
this passage, but I do so because as of 1935 his use of this term was still somewhat inconsistent, and
it is therefore crucial to justify by the context of his usage of this term that it indeed is consistent
with the specific signification he assigns to it in his later writings. In fact, Bohr's usage of 'phenomenon'
192 KARENBARAD
to signify the wholeness in the interaction between "objects of investigation" and "agencies of
observation" is consistent throughout this particular 1935 article.
25 This fact motivates my introduction of the term 'intra-action' at the end of this section since phenom-
realists cannot expect to rely on an independent external reality, but also antirealists would be hard
pressed to argue against realIsm on the basis of some postulated inaccessible independent reality.
n This mutual exclusivity highlights the problematics of an instrumentalist stance for Bohr. How does
the instrumentalist account for the non-arbitratriness of this feature? (What auxiliary criterion must be
applied?)
28 After a few weeks of intensive discussion, Heisenberg finally acqUIesced to Bohr's point of view and
added a postscript to his article on the uncertainty principle in which he states: "In this connection Bohr
pointed out to me that I have overlooked essential points in some of the discussion of this work. Above
all the uncertainty in the observation does not depend exclusively on the occurrence of discontinuities,
but is directly connected with the necessity of doing justice simultaneously to the different experimental
data which are expressed in the corpuscular theory on the one hand and the wave theory on the other
[i.e., wave-particle duality]" (quoted in Murdoch, 1987,51) Recent papers m quantum optics (e.g., see
Scully et al., 1991) give empirical evidence in support of Bohr's interpretation of the uncertainty prin-
ciple over the one given by Heisenberg which is not consistent with these findings. NB: it IS
Heisenberg's analysis (without Bohr's corrections) that is taught to physics students. See Barad (1995)
for more details. The divergence of Bohr's and Heisenberg's interpretations of the uncertainty principle
highlights their philosophical (realist and instrumentalist, respectively) differences. The construction of
scientific theories is influenced by philosophical attitudes.
29 Other pivotal aspects of the framework of agential realism are developed in Barad, forthcoming. In
particular, there is a more in-depth discussion of the issues of agency and identity. The fact that agential
realism can be used to think about rather disparate issues from the destabilization of identity to the
destabilization of science is not a matter of a more parallelism, but different instances of the same
epistemological and ontological issues.
30 For a more detailed discussion see Harding (1990) and other articles in FeminismiPostmodernism,
ed. Nicholson.
31 The positions that Heisenberg and Dirac articulate here are consistent with the former's
privileged position of the transcendent once again, resulting in further claSSical epistemological
astigmatism.
34 Bohr makes direct note of this point himself: "the description of atomic phenomena has in these
respects a perfectly objective character, in the sense that no explicit reference is made to any individual
observer and that therefore ... no ambiguity is involved in the communication of information" (Bohr,
1963c, 3).
35 Notice that experiments in some fields, like high energy physics, are rarely repeated due to constraints
imposed by lImited resources or other community priorities, but the Issue here is not whether or not the
results have actually been reproduced, the issue is the possibility of reproducibility due to the literal
embodiment of objectivity. Also, note that reproducibility is still an issue for scientists studying chaotic
systems (which are highly sensitive to initial conditions) in the sense that chaotic systems do not behave
differently for different observers (it is just that it is very difficult, to start an experiment with the very
same initial conditions, but simulations of chaotiC systems are often reproduced). Other criteria delineat-
MEETING THE UNIVERSE HALFWAY 193
ing science (read "Western science") from nonscience have been offered (see Harding, 1993). This
project of delineation is of course part and parcel of Western imperialism's focus on distinguishlOg "us"
from "them". Nonetheless, thIS same dIstinction along these lines is extremely common in the science
studies literature and it is therefore useful in this context.
36 Kondo (1989) and Sandoval (1991) make a similar pomt. Anzaldua (1987) theorizes the constructed
nature of boundaries.
37 Feminist scientists, economIsts, political scientIsts, historians, psychologIsts, geographers and literary
critics are among those who have expressed seeing the utility of agential realism for theIr projects.
38 "Tunneling" is a quantum phenomenon whereby classically confined particles escape. This is the
result of the uncertainty principle and it explains many different physical phenomena such as nuclear
decay, transistors, etc.
REFERENCES
Albert, DaVId Z.: 1992, Quantum Mechanics and Experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Anzaldua, Gloria: 1987, Borderlands/La Frontera. San Francisco: Spinsters/Aunt Lute Book Co.
Barad, Karen: 1995, 'A Feminist Approach to Teaching Quantum Physics', in Teaching the Majority:
Breaking the Gender Barrier In Science. Mathematics, and Engineering, edIted by Sue V. Rosser.
NY: Teachers College Press.
- - : 1996, 'GettlOg Real: Technologies of Embodiment and Materiality', keynote address, Gender,
Technology, Place Conference, Rutgers University, March 30, 1996.
- - : forthcomlOg, Meeting the Universe Halfway, Book Manuscript.
Bernstein, Richard J.: 1983, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science. Hermeneutics. and Praxis.
Phila: U. of Penn. Press.
Bohm, David.: 1985, 'On Bohr's Views Concern 109 Quantum Theory'. in Niels Bohr: A Centenary
Volume, ed. French, A. P. and Kennedy, P. J. Cambridge. MA: Harvard U. Press.
Bohr, Niels: 1935, 'Can Quantum-Mechamcal Description of Physical Reality Be Considered
Complete?', Physical Review, 48, 696-702.
- - : 1937, 'Causality and Complementarity', Philosophy of Science, 4.
- - : 1949, 'Discussion WIth Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics', in Albert
Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, ed. P. A. Schilpp. Evanston: Northwestern U. Press.
- - : 1963a, The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. I: Atomic Theory and the DeSCription of
Nature. Woodbridge, Conn: Ox Bow Press.
- - : 1963b, The Philosophical Writings Of Niels Bohr. Vol. II: Essays 1933-1957 on Atomic Physics
and Human Knowledge. Woodbridge, Conn: Ox Bow Press.
- - : 1963c, The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr. Vol. III: Essays 1958-1962 on Atomic Physics
and Human Knowledge. Woodbridge, Conn: Ox Bow Press.
Cartwnght, Nancy: 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. New York: Clarendon Press.
Cushing, James T.: 1994. Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Hegemony.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
EinstelO, A., Podolsky, B., and Rosen, N.: 1935, 'Can Quantum-Mechanical Descnption of Physical
Reality Be Considered Complete?' Physical Review, 47. 777-780.
Feyerabend, P. K.: 1962, 'Problems in MIcrophysics', in Frontiers of Science and Philosophy,
ed. Robert G. Colodny. Pittsburgh: U. of Pitt.
Fine, Arthur: 1984, 'The Natural OntologIcal Attitude', in Scientific Realism, ed. by J. Lephn. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Folse, Henry: 1985, The Philosophy of Niels Bohr: The Framework of Complementarity. NY:
North-Holland.
Fulton, Ahce: 1990, Powers of Congress. Boston: DaVId R. Godine.
Galison, Peter: 1987, How Experiments End. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Grahn, Judy: 1989, Really Reading Gertrude Stein, Freedom, CA: Crossing Press.
Hacking, Ian: 1982, 'Expenmentation and ScientIfic Realism', Philosophical Topics, 13,71--87.
194 KARENBARAD
Haraway, Donna: 1985, 'Manifesto for Cyborgs: Science, Technology, and Socialist Feminism in the
1980s', Socialist Review, 80, 65-108, (reprinted in Haraway, 1991).
- - : 1988, 'Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism as a Site of Discourse on the
Privilege of Partial Perspective', Feminist Studies, 14(3),575-599, (reprinted in Haraway, 1991).
- - : 1991, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. NY: Routledge Press.
Harding, Sandra: 1990, 'Feminism, Science, and the Anti-Enlightenment Critiques', in
FeminismlPostmodemism, ed. Linda J. Nicholson. NY: Routledge.
- - : 1991, Whose Science? Whose Knowledge?: Thinking from Women's Lives. Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
- - (editor): 1993, The "Racial" Economy of Science: Towards A Democratic Future. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
Hayles, N. Katherine: 1993, 'Constrained Constructivism: Locating Scientific Inquiry in the Theater of
Representation', in Realism and Representation: Essays on the Problem of Realism in Relation
to Science, Literature, and Culture, ed. by George Levin. Madison: The University of Wisconsin
Press.
Honner, John: 1987, The Description of Nature: Niels Bohr and the Philosophy of Quantum Physics.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hooker, Clifford A.: 1972, 'The Nature of Quantum Mechanical Reality', in Paradigms and Paradoxes,
ed. R. G. Colodny, Pittsburgh: U. of Pittsburgh Press.
Keller, Evelyn Fox: 1977, 'The Anomaly of a Woman in Physics', in Working It Out, ed. Ruddick and
Daniels.
- - : 1985, ReflectIOns on Gender and Science. New Haven: Yale U. Press.
Kondo, Dorinne: 1989, Crafting Selves: Power, Gender, and Discourses of Identity in a Japanese
Workplace. Chicago: Chicago Univ. Press.
Latour, Bruno: 1993, We Have Never Been Modem. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Laudan, Larry: 1981, 'A Confutation of Convergent Realism', Philosophy of Science, 48, 19-48.
Longino, Helen: 1990, Science as Social Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.
Murdoch, Dugald: 1987, Niels Bohr's Philosophy of Physics. NY: Cambridge U. Press.
Pais, Abraham: 1982, 'Subtle is the Lord... ': The Science and Life of Albert Einstein. NY: Oxford Umv.
Press.
Petersen, Aage: 1985, 'The Philosophy of Niels Bohr', in Niels Bohr: A Centenary Volume, ed. French,
A. P., and Kennedy, P. J. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press.
Pickering, Andrew: 1984, Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
- - : 1994, 'After Representation: Science Studies in the Performative Idiom'. Talk given at the
Philosophy of Science Association Annual Meeting New Orleans, 14-16 October, 1994.
Rosenfeld, Leon (general ed.): 1972- ,Collected Works. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
Sandoval, Cheyla: 1991, 'U.S. Third World Feminism: The Theory and Method of Oppositional
Consciousness In the Postmodem World.' Genders, 10.
Scully, Marian 0., Englert, Berthold-Georg, and Walther, Herbert: 1991, 'Quantum Opical Tests of
Complementarity', Nature, 351, 111-116.
Traweek, Sharon: 1988, Beamtimes and Lifetimes: The World of High Energy Physicists. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard U. Press.
Winterson, Jeanette: 1992, Written on the Body. NY: Vintage Books.