Zimmerman
Zimmerman
ISSN: 0832-6193
Volume 30, Number 2 (2014)
1
Later published as “Technological Culture and the End of Philosophy,” Research in Philosophy and
Technology, 2 (1977): 137-145. My first environmental philosophy publication was “Heidegger on Nihilism
and Technique,” Man and World, 8 (November 1975): 399-414. Other of my eco-philosophy publications
from the 1970s include “Beyond Humanism: Heidegger's Understanding of Technology,” Listening, 12
(Fall 1977), 74-83; “Heidegger and Marcuse: Technology as Ideology,” Research in Philosophy and
Technology, 2 (1977): 245-261; and “Marx and Heidegger on the Technological Domination of Nature,”
Philosophy Today, 23 (Summer 1979): 99-112.
2
Holmes Rolston, III, “Is There an Ecological Ethics?” Ethics, 85, no. 2 (January 1975).
3
Holmes Rolston, III, Environmental Ethics: Duties to and Values in the Natural World (Philadelphia:
Temple University Press, 1988).
4
Peter Singer, Animal Liberation: A New Ethics For Our Treatment of Animals (New York: Avon, 1975);
Singer, “Animal Liberation,” The New York Review of Books, April 5, 1978.
were to prove valid, humans could no longer regard nature solely as property to be used
however the owner (private or public) decides to do so.
Aldo Leopold had articulated a number of these ideas thirty years before I spoke in
Berkeley. Moreover, Arne Naess had staked out the basic features of Deep Ecology in his
1973 essay, “The Shallow, and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movements.”5 Still, the
great majority of philosophers (not to mention the vast majority of scholars in academe)
were anthropocentric in their outlook. Despite Darwin’s influence, most philosophers –
and most people – regarded human beings as so uniquely important that everything
non-human was valuable only instrumentally. Many philosophers were still having a
difficult time agreeing to the consequentialism of Bentham and Mill, according to whom
sentience, not intelligence, confers moral considerability. What Sessions and I were
suggesting was beyond the pale: not only do animals, but also plants, life itself, and even
the land (the biosphere, including mountains, rivers, oceans, and even the atmosphere)
have value of their own.
That day in Berkeley, Sessions and I struck up a conversation that would go on for three
decades. Raised in California, Sessions enrolled in the philosophy graduate program at
the University of Chicago. After accepting a position at the Sierra College in California,
where he is still on active faculty as I write this in 2014, he was motivated to find a
philosophically way to articulate and to defend nature against human abuse. Evidence
of such abuse was widespread in California during the go-go years of post-World War II
economic expansion. California already had a long history of efforts to protect wild
nature, as evidenced by the fact that John Muir helped to found the Sierra Club there in
1892. Hence, it is not surprising that Deep Ecology found early exponents in
Californians, including Sessions and Devall.
Deep Ecologists criticized reform environmentalism, which sought to curb pollution and
to save endangered species, but remained committed to anthropocentric modernity’s
commitment to economic growth and a rising standard of living for humans. Deep
Ecologists called for nothing less than a radical version of environmentalism, one that
would challenge modernity’s anthropocentric paradigm. That we were overly optimistic
in our expectations goes without saying.
Although Sessions and I had much in common, we gradually became aware of significant
differences in our understanding of humankind and thus of the humanity-nature
relationship. We agreed that industrial civilization threatened the ecosystems on which
5
Arne Naess, “The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movements,” Inquiry 16 (1973): 95-100.
human life depends. We also agreed that anthropocentrism was the major ideological
problem in the way of transforming the nature-humanity relationship. Sessions was
influenced by thinkers like Spinoza, as well as by realists who resisted the post-Kantian
tendency to view the human mind or human consciousness as responsible for how
“nature” appears to humankind. Sessions emphasized the importance of taking the
“outside-in” approach, rather than the “inside-out” approach to describing the
humanity-nature relationship. According to the former, humankind arises within and is
profoundly structured by terrestrial evolutionary processes. Inherently valuable nature
gives rise to inherently valuable humans only very late in cosmic history. According to
the inside-out approach, in contrast, human consciousness profoundly structures what
shows up to us as nature. Kant’s highly influential critical idealism developed such an
inside-out approach. Years later, as we will see, a number of writers influenced by Kant,
Nietzsche, and postmodern theory developed what is known as the “social construction
of nature,” about which most Deep Ecologists have been sharply critical.
My own way to Deep Ecology was inspired by childhood experiences that revealed the
beauty and complexity of nature. Later, I discovered that such experiences resonated
both with literary Romanticism and also with German philosophy, especially that of
Martin Heidegger and his student, Herbert Marcuse. The latter’s 1964 book, One-
Dimensional Man, offered a highly influential critique of the domination of nature, a
theme important to the Frankfurt School of Critical Theory, of which Marcuse had been
a member, along with Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, Erich Fromm, and others.6
Marcuse’s critique drew on Heidegger’s idea that anthropocentric humanism treated
nature as nothing but a planetary filling station for human projects. One of my first
publications, “Heidegger on Nihilism and Technique” (1975) argued that Heidegger’s
thought was pertinent for environmentalism.
In 1976, the same year we met, Sessions published the first issue of Ecophilosophy, a
newsletter that he disseminated at his own expense long before the Internet existed
and three years before the founding of the journal Environmental Ethics. Via his
newsletter, Sessions provided invaluable information, extensive bibliography, and pithy
commentaries that proved useful for budding environmental philosophers. The fifty-
page long second issue (1979), now available on line, offered a remarkably panoramic
view of the then-current state of English-language environmental philosophy.7 This
6
Herbert Marcuse, One-Dimensional Man (Boston, Beacon Press, 1964).
7
The second issue of Ecophilosophy can be found at: http://iseethics.files.wordpress.com/2011/03/
sessions-Sesssions-ecophilosophy-newsletter-2-may-1979.pdf
8
LaChapelle was such an avid reader that the small library of Silverton, Colorado had the highest demand
for interlibrary loan books of any library in the state.
9
Despite vowing never to venture east of the Mississippi River, LaChapelle graciously accepted my
invitation to lecture at Tulane University in the 1990s.
site necessary for beings to reveal themselves in their intelligibility, and in this sense “to
be.” Heidegger was no subjective idealist, but neither was he a naïve realist. The
“clearing” that opens up through human existence allows beings that were always
already there to show up, although always in limited ways. Unlike many modern
thinkers, Heidegger did not adhere to representationalism, according to which beings
appear within consciousness as “ideas” (somehow) generated by sensory experience.
Instead, humans encounter beings in themselves, at least insofar as those beings reveal
themselves to us. Hence, Heidegger consistently emphasized human finitude, including
humanity’s dependence on the natural world. Humans go astray when they forget their
obligation to “let things be,” and instead regard themselves as masters and possessors
of nature. The human capacity for disclosing beings creates opportunities for us to
utilize them, but also responsibilities for us to care for them. Heidegger shares this point
of view with Holmes Rolston, III.
Despite his criticism of anthropocentric humanism, Heidegger affirmed the importance
of human existence, which bears witness to and increasingly understands to interplay of
beings. The significance of this fact was once again brought home to me recently, when I
watched Earth from Space, a splendid two-hour NOVA special about how satellites
reveal the beauty and interrelatedness of life on Earth. This largely confirms James
Lovelock’s Gaia hypothesis, according to which Earth is a dynamic system that maintains
the conditions needed for terrestrial life. The NOVA special also implicitly demonstrates
something else, namely, that human beings are the only (known) species that can
launch satellites that can study Earth from space. There would be no science of ecology
without humankind, nor would there be any criticism of one species gobbling up too
many resources at the expense of other species. All species are special and perfect in
their own way, but humankind brings with it the self-consciousness and linguistic
capacity that reveals the world as a world. As Aristotle opined, philosophy begins in
wonder, not least wonder at the fact that anything is at all.
Many Deep Ecologists are wary of such assertions, insofar as they seem consistent with
modernity’s arrogant humanism, according to which only humans have any inherent
worth. Heidegger makes no such claim, however. He would agree that despite
modernity’s important achievements, its dark side includes scientific-technological
thinking that reveals nature primarily as raw material for enhancing human power. One
of the tensions within Deep Ecology in the early decades can be described as follows.
Scientific ecology was revealing important findings that could help bolster defense of
wild nature against industrial technology. That same scientific ecology, however, was
itself a product of the techno-science responsible for growing environmental
destruction. Heidegger maintained that techno-science was aimed not only at plants
and animals, but also at humankind itself. In the twentieth century, world wars had
reduced human beings to the status of commodities for enhancing power for its own
sake. Although neither Sessions nor Devall were mollified by my defense of Heidegger’s
perspective, LaChapelle argued that her experiences in powder snow skiing confirmed
for her that Heidegger’s recommendation about letting things be is a crucial insight for
Deep Ecology. Indeed, that slogan soon became popular in Deep Ecology circles and has
remained so far many years.
For many years after the Silverton meeting, I wrote essays and gave presentations about
Deep Ecology. In 1983, I returned to the Pacific Division APA meeting, this time with a
paper called “Heidegger and Deep Ecology.” The previous year, I attended a powerful
workshop led by Joanna Macy, who later became involved with the Deep Ecology
movement. Her workshop took place at a Stanford University gathering to address the
growing danger of nuclear war. Thereafter, I became deeply involved in a campaign
against the nuclear arms race, which I interpreted – once again, calling on Heidegger’s
philosophy – as a suicidal quest for power by the USA and the USSR, whose
anthropocentric worldviews had much in common, despite their political differences.10
In the summer of 1983, Environmental Ethics published my essay, "Toward a
Heideggerian Ethos for Radical Environmentalism," which argued for the applicability of
Heidegger’s thought to environmentalism, especially to Deep Ecology.11 Around this
time, Gibbs Smith of the eponymous publishing company in Layton, Utah, invited me to
write a book about the philosophy of Deep Ecology. In my reply, I recommended that he
invite Sessions and Devall to write the book, in view of their important contributions to
the Deep Ecology movement. Gibbs Smith published the book in 1985 as Deep Ecology:
Living As If Nature Mattered.
The book’s composition process did not go smoothly. While Sessions and I were
camping in Yosemite in the summer of 1985, he complained that Devall was not
consulting enough with him. Sessions feared that the book he wanted to write – a
10
Michael E. Zimmerman, “Humanism, Ontology, and the Nuclear Arms Race,” Research in Philosophy and
Technology 6 (1983): 157-172; Zimmerman, “Anthropocentric Humanism and the Arms Race,” Nuclear
War: Philosophical Perspectives, ed. Michael Fox and Leo Groarke (New York: Peter Lang Publishers,
1985); and Zimmerman, “The Incomplete Myth: Reflections on the ‘Star Wars’ Dimension of the Arms
Race,” in Consciousness Evolution, ed. Stanislav Grof (Albany: SUNY Press, 1988).
11
Michael E. Zimmerman, “Toward a Heideggerian Ethos for Radical Environmentalism,” Environmental
Ethics 5 (Summer, 1983): 99-131. See also Zimmerman, “Implications of Heidegger’s Thought for Deep
Ecology,” The Modern Schoolman 64 (November 1986): 19-43.
12
Arne Naess, “The Deep Ecological Movement: Some Philosophical Aspects,” Philosophical Inquiry 8, 1-2
(1986).
13
Symposium on Culture, Nature, and Theory, Program for the Study of Women and Men in Society,
University of Southern California, March 27-29, 1987.
14
Ariel Kay Salleh, “Deeper than Deep Ecology: The Eco-Feminist Connection,” Environmental Ethics6, no.
4 (1984): 339-345.
15
Michael E. Zimmerman, “Feminism, Deep Ecology, and Environmental Ethics,” Environmental Ethics 9
(Spring 1987): 21-44; “Deep Ecology and Ecofeminism: The Emerging Dialogue,” in Reweaving the World:
The Emergence of Ecofeminism, ed. Irene Diamond (San Francisco: Sierra Books, 1989).
16
Warwick Fox, “The Deep Ecology-Ecofeminism Debate and Its Parallels,” Environmental Ethics 11, no. 1
(Spring 1989): 5-25.
interest either in ecofeminism or in Third World critiques of Deep Ecology and of the
wilderness ideal.17
In 1990, Fox published Toward a Transpersonal Ecology: Developing New Foundations
for Environmentalism, which has some things in common with Ken Wilber’s version of
transpersonal ecology.18 Fox’s book interprets Deep Ecology – especially Naess’s
Ecosophy T – as calling on people to transcend the limits of the modern ego-structure,
which is bound by rational self-interest in the context of nationalistic and ideological
struggles. The ego is detached from and even dissociated from nature, including to
some extent the human body and its desires. When Naess affirmed the self-realization
of all beings, in accordance with his interpretation of Spinoza’s philosophy, he meant
that human self-realization (becoming who we really are) includes discerning our deep
relationship with all other beings. In effect, Naess called for humans to let beings be.
Truly to be who we are entails in part letting other beings be what they are, that is,
letting them realize their own possibilities. This is a profound as well as a demanding
teaching, which the noted Deep Ecologist Alan Drengson has explored over the years.
In 1989, I was invited to contribute a paper to a conference titled "The Wilderness
Condition: A Conference on Environment and Civilization,” which was held at the YMCA
next to Rocky Mountain National Park. The conference also drew noted writers such as
Gary Snyder, Paul Shepard, George Sessions, Curt Meine, Erazim Kohak, Michael P.
Cohen, Peter A.Y. Gunter, Dolores LaChapelle, and Max Oelschlaeger.19 An interchange
took place between Snyder and Sessions, two Californians who had known each other
for years. Expressing dismay at the rate at which industrial civilization was harming the
natural environment, Sessions insisted that the federal government and other national
government would have to intervene. In his ironic but compassionate way, Snyder
intoned that such a move “would be like inviting the fox to guard the henhouse.” Big
Government, in the guise of the military, the Bureau of Land Management, the US
Forest Service, and other such agencies, was responsible for untold environmental
17
See for example Ramachandra Guha, “Radical American Environmentalism and Wilderness
Preservation: A Third World Critique,” Environmental Ethics 11, no. 1 (Spring 1989): 71-83.
18
Warwick Fox, Toward a Transpersonal Ecology: Developing New Foundations for Environmentalism
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1990).
19
My paper, “The Blessing of Otherness: Wilderness and the Human Condition,” along with the papers
presented by the aforementioned people, were published in The Wilderness Condition, ed. Max
Oelschlaeger (San Francisco: Sierra Books, 1992).
damage, including the Glen Canyon Dam against which Edward Abbey and members of
Earth First! had taken symbolic direct action in 1981.
20
Victor Farias, Heidegger and Nazism (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989).
21
See Michael E. Zimmerman, Heidegger’s Confrontation with Modernity: Technology, Politics, Art
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1991). See also Zimmerman, Contesting Earth’s Future: Radical
Ecology and Postmodernity (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1994).
22 See http://www.off-road.com/trails-events/voice/population-and-aids-miss-ann-thropy-earth-first-
1987-16372.html
Foreman's and still sound like a fiery radical who challenges everything
that is anti-ecological in the present realm of ideas. The very words Deep
Ecology, in fact, clue is into the fact that we are not dealing with a body
of clear ideas but with a bottomless pit in which vague notions and
moods of all kinds can be such into the depths of an ideological toxic
dump.23
Although intemperate, uncharitable, and exaggerated, Bookchin’s paper was right in
recommending that Deep Ecologists become informed that environmentalism had once
been enlisted for dark purposes. National Socialism, a virulently anti-modernist
movement, had developed something like ecofascism, as evidenced in the slogan Blut
und Boden, “blood and soil,” which called for racial purity and land purity. Heidegger’s
apparently eco-friendly discourse about “letting things be” was bound up with his
favorable attitude toward at least his own version of National Socialism. After much
soul-searching, I published essays examining ecofascism and possible signs of it in Deep
Ecology.24
Although continuing to believe that Deep Ecology promoted an important perspective
regarding humanity’s place in nature, I also knew that there were other important
perspectives that needed to be taken into account. Having supported the Civil Rights
Movement, and having been a Frankfurt School socialist for a time in the 1970s, I
supported many modernist goals. Among modernity’s shortcomings, however, was its
exploitative attitude toward and treatment of the natural world. What Marx once said
about capitalism’s corrosive and highly productive power, “All that is solid melts into
air,”25 was also applicable to industrial modernity’s relation to nature: “All that is natural
becomes a commodity.”
In 1991, I enlisted Sessions to edit the Deep Ecology section of my anthology,
Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology (1993), the first such
anthology to devote sections not only to Deep Ecology, but also to ecofeminism (edited
23
Murray Bookchin, “Social Ecology versus Deep Ecology: A Challenge to the Ecology Movement,”
originally published in Green Perspectives: Newsletter of the Green Program Project, nos. 4-5 (summer
1987); available online at http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/Anarchist_Archives/bookchin/socecovdeepeco
.html. Devall’s interview with Foreman was published by the Australian periodical Simply Living in 1987.
24
Michael E. Zimmerman, “Rethinking the Heidegger--Deep Ecology Relationship,” Environmental Ethics,
15, no. 3 (Fall 1993): 195-224; Zimmerman, “The Threat of Ecofascism,” Social Theory and Practice, 21
(Summer 1995): 207-238.
25
Karl Marx, Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848), https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/
1848/communist-manifesto/ch01.htm
by Karen J. Warren) and to social ecology (edited by John Clark). J. Baird Callicott edited
the section on environmental ethics.26 Shortly thereafter, I published Contesting Earth’s
Future: Radical Ecology and Postmodernity (1994), which offers a comparative analysis
of the three aforementioned versions of radical environmentalism: Deep Ecology,
ecofeminism, and social ecology. In my view, each had something important to offer
environmental discourse. No single position could adequately represent the multitude
of perspectives that people had toward nature. Indeed, so I argued, environmentalists
would henceforth have to engage in a contest with other people –including ecofeminists
and Third World critics of Western environmentalism – about the status of nature.
In 1996, William Cronon published his highly influential and controversial anthology,
Uncommon Ground: Rethinking the Human Place in Nature, in which he spoke of the
“end of wilderness,” in which he criticized the notion of a nature untouched by human
activity, perception, emotional response, or interpretation. 27 According to the
wilderness ideal embraced by many Deep Ecologists, however, the only kind of nature
worth saving is nature untrammeled by human beings. Except, there isn’t any such
nature. In an essay that appeared two years later in The Trumpeter, Sessions sharply
criticized Cronon’s claim that wilderness is a social construct. Several other
environmentalists also contested what they took to be Cronon’s position.28 The many
insightful essays in his anthology constituted a major intervention in the “social
construction of nature” approach that was becoming widespread in the 1990s.
Feminism’s critique of essentialism, including the idea of an “essential” woman and an
“essential” nature, also played a crucial role in social constructivism. Given that some
social constructionists made claims about nature that verged on subjective idealism,
however, a number of Deep Ecologists dismissed social construction theory as well as
postmodernism and postmodern theory, which were deeply interrelated. 29 This, I
26
Sessions remained editor of the Deep Ecology section until the fourth edition (2005), in which I
introduced a new section (edited by Irene Diamond) on Continental environmental philosophy. Had the
publisher allowed the fourth edition to expand in size, I would have retained the Deep Ecology section.
27
William Cronon, Uncommon Ground: Rethinking the Human Place in Nature (New York: W.W. Norton &
Company, 1996).
28
George Sessions, “Reinventing Nature, the End of Wilderness? A Response to William Cronon’s
Uncommon Ground,” The Trumpeter 13, No. 1 (1996).
29
For an excellent treatment of themes the postmodern construction of nature, see Steve Vogel, “Nature
as Origin and Difference: On Environmental Philosophy and Continental Thought,” Philosophy Today, vol.
42, supplement (1999): 169-181. See also Vogel, Against Nature: The Concept of Nature in Critical Theory
(Albany: SUNY Press, 1996).
believe, was a mistake. A restrained social construction view has much to offer the Deep
Ecology movement.30
30
See, for example, Anna Peterson, “Environmental Ethics and the Social Construction of Nature,”
Environmental Ethics, 21 (Winter 1999): 339-357.
31
In many ways, Wilber’s approach resembles the “new universe story” told by Brian Thomas Swimme
and Mary Evelyn Tucker, Journey of the University (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2011). See also
Swimme and Tucker’s PBS special with the same title.
Major (and typically slow-motion) socio-cultural transitions are typically wrenching and
replete with conflict. One reason for this is that as people move to another phase of
development, they typically portray the previous phase negatively, so as to make it
easier to leave behind. Healthy personal and cultural development involves not only
transcending the previous wave of development, however, but also integrating what
was positive about that wave. This is never easy to do, because the tendency is to
dissociate oneself from the developmental wave with which one previously identified.
During the 1990s I discovered that just as I could no longer wholly identify with
modernity, I also could no longer wholly identify with those variants of postmodernism
and environmentalism that engaged in totalizing critiques of modernity. Deep Ecology’s
relation to pre-modernity, modernity, and postmodernity is complex. Some varieties of
Deep Ecology exhibit mistrust and even contempt for modernity, while revealing
nostalgia for the tribal version of pre-modernity. At the same time, however, Deep
Ecology is often suspicious of traditional religious versions of pre-modernity. The latter
are not only based on agriculture, the spread of which vastly increased human
population while dramatically reducing habitat for non-humans, but also regard
humankind as the centerpiece of Creation. Regarding modernity, Deep Ecology is
ambivalent. On the one hand, modernity not only made possible the science of ecology
that reveals the interdependent complexity of the biosphere, but also set in place civil
liberties allowing people to openly criticize modern governments and related
institutions for mistreatment of the natural world. On the other hand, the growth of
modern science and technology threaten the integrity of the biosphere on which
modern institutions, wealth, and individual liberties depend. Deep Ecology is also
ambivalent about postmodernity. While agreeing with the latter’s critique of modernity
– as an anthropocentrism drive for total control over nature – Deep Ecology is skeptical
about postmodern theory’s deconstructive practices, according to which there is no
one, true “Nature,” but instead many ways in which nature shows up within this or that
culture, and for this or that purpose.
I appreciate the passion of pre-modernists, modernists, Deep Ecologists, and
postmodernists, as well as the ways in which they disagree with one another. Each is an
important way of making sense of complex matters. My attempts to reconcile whenever
possible aspects of modernity, environmentalism, and postmodernism appear in my
book, Contesting Earth’s Future as well as in “On Reconciling Progressivism and
32
Michael E. Zimmerman, “On Reconciling Progressivism and Environmentalism,” in Explorations in
Environmental Political Theory, ed. Joel J. Kassiola (Armonk, New York: M.E. Sharpe, Inc., 2003), 149-177.
33
Michael E. Zimmerman, “Integral Ecology’s Debt to Holmes Rolston, III,” in Integral Ecologies: Nature,
Culture, and Knowledge in the Planetary Era, ed. by Sam Mickey, Sean Kelly, and Adam Robbert (Albany:
SUNY Press), forthcoming.
34
On this matter, see Karen J. Warren, “The Power and the Promise of Ecological Feminism,” in
Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. Michael E. Zimmerman (Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1993).
call into question the principles of modernity itself. Modernity espouses a world-centric
creed of universal human rights, but has often failed to extend rights to some humans,
such as slaves and women. Liberation movements in the 19 th, 20th, and 21st century still
call on modernity’s ideals in pursuit of emancipatory goals. Indeed, environmentalism
itself, which calls in effect for the “liberation” of nature, may be regarded as an
expression of modern ideals.
Many postmodern Greens criticize hierarchy, but nevertheless assume that their view of
nature is in fact superior to, that is, better than, the views of traditionalists and
modernists. In some respects, of course, Green views of nature are superior because
they are more inclusive. They integrate non-humans into the domain of what counts
morally and what deserves respect. At the same time, however, many Greens and
postmoderns speak with contempt for moderns and premodern social organization
oriented around traditionalist religious beliefs, such as Christianity. The contributions of
traditional and modern waves of development are important; hence, they should be
regarded with respect not with disdain. People whose developmental “center of gravity”
is traditional or modern will take seriously the concerns expressed by Green
postmodernists and Deep Ecologists only when the latter take seriously the concerns
and contributions of traditionalists and modernists. Mutual respect is a precondition for
accomplishing anything significant, especially in a contentious democracy.
Today, 70% of the human population remains at the traditional/premodern mode of
consciousness and culture. Given that many premodern people were subjected to
European and American colonization, little wonder that such people are wary of
modernity. According to the integral approach, moderns and postmoderns should affirm
traditional culture, even while being willing to criticize pathological forms of it. Likewise,
it is important to encourage premodern or traditional peoples to develop their own
versions of modernity. This, for example, is the challenge and opportunity facing many
Islamic societies today.
Wilber’s integral developmental model provides an alternative to Heidegger’s
contention, shared by a number of Deep Ecologists, that Western civilization is little
more than the story of decline from ancient beginnings.35 In contrast, the integral
developmental model maintains that nature reveals itself differently to people at
various waves of development. During medieval times, for instance, nature was
35
See Andrew R. Murphy, “Environmentalism, Antimodernism, and the Recurrent Rhetoric of Decline,”
Environmental Ethics, 25, no. 1 (Spring 2003): 79-98.
regarded as Mother Earth. During this era, mining was widely regarded as a violation
because it dug into Earth’s body. In disenchanting the world, however, moderns
gradually dismissed such attitudes as superstitions that impeded progress.36 To take the
place of modern anthropocentrism, many Deep Ecologists promote biocentrism,
according to which humans have no special status, but instead are merely members of
one species among millions of others.
One popular expression of this leveling, anti-hierarchical viewpoint is found in the novel
Ishmael, in which a talking ape condemns the human civilization that followed from the
invention of agriculture.37 The conceit of a talking ape is clever, but the author does not
underscore the irony involved in using human linguistic capacity to describe
environmental problems caused by humankind. No ape could ever do this, although to
say this is not to find any shortcoming with apes. Indeed, they are whole and complete
in their own way. Moreover, environmentalists rightly condemn human actions that
threaten apes with extinction. What must be emphasized, however, is that – so far as
we know –only humans can disclose the world’s history, interpret its complex
structures, envision its possible futures, and encounter its possibly divine aspects. Those
who claim that humans are just one species among others, and this is how I understand
Quinn’s thesis, must then agree that humans are merely trying to maximize their
reproductive fitness just as any other species does. White-tailed deer would take over
the entire planet, for example, if conditions would permit them to do so. What is wrong
for humans – just another organism – to take over the planet?
The only animal capable of posing and answering this question is the human animal.
One answer: taking over might be prudentially wrong, given that we might end up
destroying the conditions needed for our very survival. Another answer: taking over
might be morally wrong, because humans are capable of discerning and respecting the
inherent worthy of other life forms and even the biosphere as such. Only human beings
can provide such answers, however. White-tailed deer in the process of catastrophically
overshooting their resource base do not pause to reflect upon either the prudential or
moral wisdom of such behavior. That humans can pause to reflect in such ways indicates
how humans differ from other animals. The steady success of the animal rights
movement and the environmental movement show that humans are capable of evolving
their moral attitudes toward non-human beings. The core of my disagreements with
36
On these and related matters see Carolyn Merchant, The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology, and the
Scientific Revolution (New York: HarperOne, 1990).
37
Daniel Quinn, Ishmael: An Adventure of the Mind and Spirit (New York: Bantam, 1995).
Sessions and Devall, then, had to do with the human place in the cosmos. Humans are
gifted with an extraordinary capacity of awareness that lends itself to good as well as to
evil. We hold open the historical-linguistic clearing within which things can manifest
themselves and thus “be” in various ways.
Wilber and I shared aspects of this view. He had read my first book on Heidegger, Eclipse
of the Self: The Development of Heidegger’s Concept of Authenticity (1981). 38 I
continued to read his many works with ecological themes, including Sex, Ecology,
Spirituality: The Spirit of Evolution (1995)39 and A Brief History of Everything (1996)40.
Having corresponded with Wilber for years, I finally met him in 1998. After several
brainstorming sessions with Wilber, Sean Esbjörn-Hargens and I wrote Integral Ecology:
Uniting Multiple Perspectives on the Natural World.41 Mark Bekoff, the noted biologist
and animal rights proponent, agreed to write an introduction to the book, because he
appreciated its emphasis on the interiority of all life forms, not merely human life.
Underscoring the importance of interiority, collective and individual, human and non-
human, is another important feature of integral ecology. According to integral ecology,
every phenomenon has both an exterior and an interior. For example, a living cell has a
chemical structure and can be photographed if sufficiently magnified. In other words,
the cell can be understood from the third-person perspective as an object. Each such
cell, however, also has an interior aspect, that is, the cell takes into account is
environment. A cell has proto-experiential capability. More complex organisms have
even greater interiority, which includes an increasing capacity for pleasure and pain.
Influenced by ecological science, which tends to emphasize the importance of species
and thus to discount the importance of individual members of species, and wary of
mentioning interiority because humans are so richly endowed with it, Deep Ecologists
tend to neglect interiority, even though it may go “all the way down” as philosopher of
mind David J. Chalmers has suggested.42
38
Michael E. Zimmerman, Eclipse of the Self: The Development of Heidegger’s Concept of Authenticity
(Athens: Ohio University Press, 1981).
39
Ken Wilber, Sex, Ecology, Spirituality (Boston: Shambhala Publications, 1995).
40
Ken Wilber, A Brief History of Everything (Boston: Shambhala Publications, 1996).
41
Sean Esbjörn-Hargens and Michael E. Zimmerman, Integral Ecology (Boston: Shambhala Publications,
2009).
42
David J. Chalmers, The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1997). See also Thomas Nagel, Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinist Conception of
Nature Is Almost Certainly False (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012).
Contesting the Cartesian atomism held responsible for disintegrating the cosmos, some
Deep Ecologists have promoted as an alternative to it systems theory, according to
which everything is merely a strand of the interconnected web of life, or Gaia. As
valuable as systems theory is, however, it still omits any reference to the interior aspect
of things. One of Aldo Leopold’s major contributions in A Sand County Almanac was to
describe what amounts to the first-person life of animals in Sand County, thereby
encouraging readers to identity with them. Likewise, Holmes Rolston, III maintains that
because of their interior depth organisms have importance of their own, as well as being
tokens of species.43 Organisms are not merely “parts” of the whole, nor are they merely
“strands in the cosmic web,” but are also members of what Leopold called the land
community. There are times when the needs of individual organisms must be sacrificed
to more inclusive goods, but taking into account the well being of individual organisms
ought to be an important aspect of Deep Ecology, just as it is of integral ecology.44
In addition to including the interior as well as the exterior aspects of individual
phenomena, integral ecology also includes the interior and exterior aspects of
collectives. These four domains, or the quadrants, must be taken into account when
representing or interpreting things. For example, a frog can be understood in terms of
four basic domains: its first-hand experience, its structure as an organism, its
intersubjective relations among other frogs in its pond, and finally in terms of its role in
the pond’s ecosystem. If one over lays these four domains with the evolutionary history
of phenomena since the Big Bang, the result is what Ken Wilber calls the AQAL diagram
(all quadrants, all [developmental] levels), reproduced below. Organisms always tetra-
evolve, that is, the conditions needed for an individual organism to emerge must include
all four domains as they pertain to that organism. The organism and its niche--frog and
frog pond--are correlated with and depend upon one another. Details do not concern us
here, but they are explored in Integral Ecology.
43
Rolston’s Environmental Ethics anticipated important aspects of Wilber’s views on environmental
philosophy. See Zimmerman, “Integral Ecology’s Debt to Holmes Rolston, III,” forthcoming.
44
See Michael E. Zimmerman, “Humanity’s Relation to Gaia: Part of the Whole, or Member of the
Community?” The Trumpeter 20, no. 1 (2004): 1-20. See also Zimmerman, “The Threat of Ecofascism,”
Social Theory and Practice 21 (Summer, 1995): 207-238.
AQAL Diagram. Reprinted with permission. Originally published in Ken Wilber, Sex Ecology Spirituality
(Boston: Shambhala Publications, 1995).
45
See Richard White, “‘Are You and Environmentalist, or Do You Work for a Living?’ Work and Nature,” in
Uncommon Ground, ed. William Cronon (New York: Norton, 1996), 171-185.
I would like to conclude with the following self-critical observation. As I moved away
from Deep Ecology to integral thinking, I was at times too critical of Deep Ecology, just
as I was too critical of modernity when I embraced Deep Ecology. The invitation to
contribute to this special issue of The Trumpeter provided the opportunity to correct
this regrettable move, in part by asserting my continuing belief that Deep Ecology
represents an important voice in the conversation about humanity’s relation to nature.
My journey as an environmental philosopher was immeasurably aided by the
commitment and insight of George Sessions. Despite our disagreements over the years,
he helped to open up for me – and for many others – the opportunities and obligations
associated with environmentalism, including the Deep Ecology movement.46
46
My thanks to three anonymous reviewers for comments that improved the quality of this essay.