Should A Good Lawyer Do The Right Thing? David Luban On The Morality of Adversary Representation
Should A Good Lawyer Do The Right Thing? David Luban On The Morality of Adversary Representation
Recommended Citation
David Wasserman, Should a Good Lawyer Do the Right Thing? David Luban on the Morality of Adversary Representation, 49 Md. L. Rev.
392 (1990)
Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr/vol49/iss2/6
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Academic Journals at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has been accepted for
inclusion in Maryland Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. For more information, please contact
[email protected].
Review Essays
SHOULD A GOOD LAWYER DO THE RIGHT THING? DAVID
LUBAN ON THE MORALITY OF ADVERSARY
REPRESENTATION
INTRODUCTION
* Research Scholar, Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy, University of Mary-
land; B.A., Yale University, 1975;J.D., University of Michigan, 1978; M.A., University of
North Carolina, 1984 (Psychology). This Review Essay was written while the author was
a Fellow in Ethics and the Professions at Harvard University. It has benefitted greatly
from criticism and suggestions by Douglas MacLean, Judith Andre, Greg Dees, Amy
Gutmann, Dennis Thompson, Alan Strudler, Henry Richardson, and David Luban.
1. D. LUBAN, LAWYERS ANDJUSTICE (1988).
2. See id. at xix-xxvi.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers andJustice 393
3. Id. at 35-43.
4. Id. at 47-49.
5. Id. at 128-47.
6. Id. at 145-47.
7. Id. at 265-66.
8. Id. at 240-66.
9. Id. at 148-49.
10. Id. at 50-92.
11. Id.
12. Id. at 68-74.
394 MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
22. Id.
23. See A. GOLDMAN, THE MORAL FOUNDATIONS OF PROFESSIONAL ETHICS 2-6 (1980).
24. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 139-40.
25. Id. at 116-27.
26. Id. at 117-20.
27. Id. at 58-66.
28. Id. at 120-23.
396 MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL., 49:392
35. Id.
36. The consequentialist character of the approach is reinforced by Luban's con-
trasting example of an anthropological research team in the same village. Although the
researcher's silence is necessary to advance anthropological knowledge, that advance's
importance does not outweigh the loss of an innocent life. Id. at 133.
37. The moral value in sustaining the institution, however, would still be considera-
ble, if there were high "replacement costs" in distrust, disruption, and public resistance
in substituting an equally adequate institution.
38. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 131.
39. David Ross has argued generally that those who make utilitarian arguments for
such practices as promise-keeping, typically overestimate the harm done to the practice
by a single breach. D. Ross, THE RIGrr AND THE GOOD 39 (1930).
40. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 58-66. Luban confuses the issue somewhat by sug-
gesting that the lawyer who helps win the acquittal of a client he believes to be guilty,
commits a morally-dissonant role act. Id. at 59. If this is true, so does the jury which
believes the defendant guilty but acquits him because of a reasonable doubt about his
guilt. If the lawyer's belief in his client's guilt arises solely from the evidence and im-
pressions available to the jurors, and not from his client's confidences, he does not, any
more than they, need to justify his actions in terms of the distal goal of overprotecting
defendants' rights. The claim that it is better to acquit a hundred guilty defendants than
convict one innocent person, id. at 58, does not prescribe a ratio for "overprotection;" it
expresses a sense of comparative evil. We believe that it is inherently wrong to deprive a
person of his liberty unless his guilt is nearly certain, and a lawyer's efforts to assure that
398 MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
his client is not convicted without the requisite level of certainty need no extrinsic justifi-
cation. It may be that this high standard of proof has external, consequentialist origins,
but it certainly has become internalized in our culture.
41. Id. at 148.
42. Id. at 53-54.
43. Id. at 53.
44. Id.
45. Id. at 149.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers andJustice 399
46. Id.
47. Id.
400 MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
dentiality. ' ' 48 If this refers to the duty that binds the lawyers, it is
not necessary for an adequate criminal defense. If it refers to the
practice that is necessary for that institutional task, it requires noth-
ing of these lawyers."9
If the Lake Pleasant lawyers had reasoned like the Oxfam logis-
tics officer, they might have felt far less constrained by their role and
its duties. Even taking into account not only the indirect conse-
quences of their actions, but their own tendency to underestimate
those consequences and overestimate the immediate harm in con-
forming to their role, they might well have concluded that the harm
in satisfying their role obligation far outweighed the harm in violat-
ing it. It is unclear how the four-fold root would hinder them in
reaching that conclusion. If the concealment in the Lake Pleasant
case contributed significantly to the larger good of criminal defense,
Luban certainly has not shown it. Accordingly, it is difficult to see
how the concealment is justified by that good.
The same difficulty occurs in Luban's explanation of the crimi-
nal lawyer's duty of confidentiality in terms of the client's "morally
based legal right" to compel his attorney's silence. 50 Luban argues
that "[a] morally based right against self-incrimination will serve
just as well as a moral right to establish the lawyer's duty of confi-
dentiality."'" To the contrary, it does not serve as well. While a
moral right would "trump" the considerable gains in utility that fre-
48. Id.
49. John Rawls introduced the distinction between "justification of a rule or prac-
tice" as a system of rules to be applied and enforced and the "justification of a particular
action falling under [these rules]." Rawls, Two Concepts of Rules, 64 PHIL. REV. 3, 4
(1955). Rawls illustrates the distinction with the examples of punishment and promise-
keeping, justified as practices by their long-term social benefits but unjustified in partic-
ular applications by moral duties for which consequences are largely irrelevant. Id. at 4-
18. He does not explain why practices justified by their consequences should generate
or correspond with independent nonconsequential moral duties, and that remains one
of the unsolved mysteries of role morality.
Unless there is a fortuitous or providential correspondence between justified prac-
tices and moral duties, then either: (1) we will not always have a duty to adhere to
practices that justifiably permit no exceptions; or (2) the justification for the practice will
generate an unconditional duty of adherence. The former is not acceptable to those
who think that the demands of morality must be consistent, but the latter is a difficult
claim to defend. Why should we have a duty to conform to a generally beneficial prac-
tice when our conformity confers no marginal benefit? It is hard to see why we should
be constrained by the possibility that the benefits of the practice would be lost if every-
one reasoned as we did, when we know that everyone will not. We can hardly be ac-
cused of free-riding if we violate the practice to achieve what is, all things considered,
the greater good.
50. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 192-97.
51. Id. at 196.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers andJustice 401
52. This is somewhat analogous to the claim that the admission of highly probative
but unconstitutionally obtained evidence against a defendant is justifiable when there
would be no marginal deterrence in excluding it, if the sole purpose for its exclusion is
to deter police misconduct. A defendant suffers no injustice, because she did not have a
right to its exclusion, which is only an incidental benefit derived from a deterrent policy.
Of course, the claim that its exclusion has no marginal deterrent value is highly ques-
tionable: unlike a single act of role-breaking by an individual attorney, a court's admis-
sion of illegally obtained evidence may indeed have a subversive effect on the policy
underlying the rule.
53. See, e.g., D. LYONS, FORMS AND LIMITS OF UTILITARIANISM 27-29 (1965).
54. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 62-63.
55. Id. at 58 n. 17.
56. Luban discusses the interest of the experienced defense attorney "in playing ball
with the prosecution and encouraging the client to plea bargain." Id. at 60. Thus, Luban
implicitly recognizes the temptation to acquiesce to state power.
MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
57. This justification for unqualified zeal has much the same structure, and the same
tension, as the utilitarian justification for per se prohibitions against lying and promise
breaking. As Philip Devine explains,
[t]he gist of the argument... is that only if the obligation to tell the truth and
keep one's promises is given force in excess of that provided by the utility of
specific acts of truth telling and promise keeping can the utilities resulting from
honesty as a social practice be realized.
Devine, The Conscious Acceptance of Guilt in the Necessary Murder, 89 ETHIcs 221, 223 (1979).
While the reasons for excessive force may be quite different in the case of zealous advo-
cacy, the resulting tension is similar: the conscientious moral agent inevitably will find
herself in the position of endorsing the policy while having good, and sometimes com-
pelling, moral reasons for refusing to conform to it. Devine argues that this position
ultimately is indefensible, or immoral, id. at 224, but recognizes that some variation on it
underlies a large number of policies, from nuclear deterrence, id. at 228, to civil disobe-
dience. Id. at 229-33.
58. See D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 138-39.
59. Luban himself recognizes that a single act of role-breaking rarely has more than
a negligible effect on the role and the institution. He comments that the effect of a role
violation "cannot amount to much" unless the violation is widespread. Id. at 138 n.7.
60. Id. at 138-39.
61. This is not surprising because as I have argued, the four-fold root provides a
strictly consequentialist justification. As Rawls pointed out 35 years ago, "utilitarian
arguments are appropriate with regard to questions about practices .... " Rawls, supra
note 49, at 5. Using the example of punishment, Rawls argued that while sentences
should be assigned by the judge on retributive or "just-deserts" grounds, the institution
of punishment is established by the legislature on the basis of deterrent and other utili-
tarian considerations. Id. at 6-8.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers and Justice 403
62. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 138. While the role-agent "takes the institution, the
role, and the role obligations as givens[,]" the legislator looks upon these as vehicles for
regulation. Id.
63. Id. at 72-73.
64. Id. at 138-39.
65. Id.
66. Id.
67. The difference between the Lake Pleasant case and its civil counterpart may be
that the strong policy underlying adversary, criminal defense will justify placing role-
agents in moral dilemmas that it cannot resolve, while the weak policy underlying adver-
sary civil defense will not. Perhaps civil lawyers should not elicit incriminating confi-
dences; even if having done so, they are obliged to honor them, while criminal lawyers
are justified in eliciting such confidences, although the obligation to honor them has the
same nonconsequentialist source as for civil lawyers.
68. A general critique of the four-fold root has been developed by Judith Andre,
using the issue of obligations to one's children and the institution of the family:
MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
[O]ne can and should ask about obligations to one's children, say, without also
asking whether the institution of the family is morally good. This is a separate
and important question; but however one decides, it remains a fact that these
children are as a matter of fact-and as a result of a social role which might not
be justified-particularly dependent on their parents.
J. Andre, Role Morality as a Complex Instance of Ordinary Morality (June 17, 1989) (to
be published in AM. PHIL. Q.). There is, however, no reason to believe that such ordi-
nary moral obligations always are available to support a role-act with a consequentialist
justification. See supra note 49.
A related point is that a wide range of deceptive, dilatory, and coercive legal tactics
are excused, if not justified, by the fact that they are employed by one's adversary. As
Professor Dees has pointed out, the case against "unilateral disarmament" is often pow-
erful, albeit treacherous, and those who rely on that defense may have a moral obliga-
tion to reduce the need to use it by working for multilateral disarmament. J. Dees, I'd
Be a Fool Not To! (May 5, 1989) (unpublished manuscript) (available from author at
Harvard University, Graduate School of Business Administration).
69. See D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 48-49.
70. See id.
1990] REVIEW ESSAY-Lawyers andJustice 405
dural" approach would have been consonant with his later emphasis on political legiti-
macy in a democratic state. Id. at 239-40.
78. Id. at 37-38. Consistent with Luban, I use "consent" to include acceptance and
"acceptance" to include what contract law calls "ratification," for example, drawing
water from the well constructed by our neighbors. Id. at 36-38. Simmons uses the term
"participation" to cover these and other forms of voluntary involvement in a coopera-
tive scheme. A. SIMMONS, MORAL PRINCIPLES AND POLITICAL OBLIGATIONS 127-36
(1979).
79. A. SIMMONS, supra note 78, at 127-29.
80. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 39.
81. Id. at 41-42.
1990] REVIEW ESSAY-Lawyers and Justice 407
at 45. Respect is a far more imperfect duty than fair play, rarely requiring us to shoulder
burdens proportionate to unaccepted benefits.
Luban is unclear about the relationship between the duty not to disrespect our
fellow citizens and the duty to play fairly with them. Towards the end of his discussion,
he states:
[T]he obligation to join in the clean-up is an obligation of fair play. The obliga-
tion of fair play arises out of an obligation not to exhibit disrespect for one's
moral equals by free riding. But noncooperation in extenuating circumstances
(such as minding the baby) exhibits no disrespect for one's moral equals.
When I am minding the baby, I am playing fair, even though I do not join in the
clean-up. So there is no obligation to join in the clean-up.
Id. While the logic of this argument is obscure, it seems clear that disrespect, and not
fair play, must wear the pants. While we satisfy the duty to avoid disrespect by playing
fairly, we need not satisfy the duty of fair play to avoid disrespect. Luban's claim that we
play fairly by minding the baby distorts the usual understanding of fair play, which re-
quires burdens proportionate to benefits within a scheme of cooperation. Our perform-
ance of tasks external to that scheme, like child-care, may exempt us from the duty of
fair play, but it does not satisfy that duty. Had we given our prior consent to the scheme,
we might be obliged to compensate the others if child care prevented us from taking
part. We are free-riding when we mind the baby instead of cleaning up the glass, but we
show no disrespect in so doing because of the personal importance of our alternative
chore. If Luban wants to define the duty of fair play so that it always is satisfied when we
display respect, it will not require us to assume burdens proportionate to the benefits we
receive.
1990] REVIEW ESSAY-Lawyers and Justice 409
we feel toward the person who fails to comply does not depend on
his having received, or being likely to receive, any benefits from the
scheme, (2) that the role of the cooperative scheme is not to create a
duty of fair play, but to make it feasible to satisfy that duty, thereby
removing an excuse for its violation, and (3) that we would not even
acknowledge a duty to comply unless we thought that the underly-
ing distribution of inconvenience was fair, independent of any
scheme for effecting it.
In the bus-queue case, Luban may be correct in claiming that
queuing benefits even those who arrive last, by expediting the
boarding process and by reducing their average standing-time over
the long run.8 7 I, however, do not think that our indignation at the
person who cuts in front is aroused by her ingratitude at these fairly
slight advantages. We would be equally indignant even if the cir-
cumstances denied her any short- or long-term advantage from the
queuing arrangement, for example, if she cut ahead of a relatively
short queue to board the Heathrow-Gatwick bus on her only pas-
sage through England.
Our sense of obligation arises from the fact that the queue al-
lows us to honor our pre-existing duty to defer to those who have
arrived first. A rule of "first come, first served" equalizes the bur-
den of waiting in settings in which variations in need are relatively
slight and impractical to ascertain: it is appropriate for a bus stop,
not for an organ transplant. Most of us would acknowledge a duty
to yield to those who have arrived before us, but would feel com-
pelled to honor that duty only if we could do so at reasonable cost.8 8
In the absence of a cooperative scheme, the cost often will be
excessive. In the free-for-all of a Manhattan bus stop, we may not
even know who came before us, and if we did, our attempt to defer
to them might allow dozens of late arrivals to squeeze ahead. There
is no practical way of giving our predecessors priority without losing
our place to our successors. The London queue provides the an-
swer to the dilemma. We are obliged to respect it because it does
not create the obligation and removes a strong defense for breach-
ing it. 89
The lane-closing case 9° is somewhat intermediate between the
bus queue and the glass clean-up, because a turn-taking rule for a
lane obstruction may seem less obviously fair than a first-come, first
served rule at the bus-stop: cars side-by-side at the obstruction may
have suffered very disparate delays in reaching that point. If, how-
ever, we think that a turn-taking rule is the fairest way to distribute
the delay from a closed lane, the arrangement Luban describes al-
lows us to do so without unreasonable cost. It would ask too much
to require us to let in the car on our right unless we could count on
the cars behind it to wait their turn, but the arrangement we observe
gives us the assurance that they will.
Luban may assert correctly that a turn-taking arrangement at
the blocked lane confers a significant benefit by expediting the flow
of traffic. 9 ' Again, however, I do not think that it is this benefit that
obliges us to comply. As in the bus-queue case,9 2 our obligation is
not conditioned on having benefited from the scheme, but on the
assurance it provides that we can act fairly without too great a bur-
den. If we felt that turn-taking was equitable, we would be obliged
to wait our turn without a pre-existing arrangement, e.g., if we were
among the first to arrive at the obstruction, if our predecessors in
the left lane simply had barreled ahead, or if the lead driver in the
right lane had been too timid to take his turn. Assuming we could
safely yield, it would be inconsiderate not to permit the car to our
right to enter, even if we were the first driver to do so.
In both the bus-queue and blocked-lane cases,9 3 the obligation
we feel to comply with the cooperative scheme is contingent upon
our acceptance of the priority rule it enforces. 94 If we reject that
rule altogether, we feel little or no obligation to comply. Thus, if we
regard highway driving as a lottery in which drivers took the luck of
their lane, like customers in separate lines at a bank or a McDon-
89. This implies that if circumstances permit us to defer to earlier arrivals without
risk, we are obliged to do so even in the absence of a queuing arrangement. I fully
accept this implication. Thus, if we are the last to arrive at a Manhattan bus stop, it
would be rude of us to board before the earlier arrivals.
90. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 40.
91. Id. at 40-41.
92. Id. at 40.
93. Id.
94. Alternatively, we may feel obliged just because we come to accept the consensus
expressed in the cooperative scheme about the appropriate priority rule. If our own
beliefs about the correct rule are uncertain or inconsistent, it may be reasonable to defer
in this way to the "decent opinion" of our fellow citizens. If we do, however, their con-
duct has caused us to recognize an obligation; it has not created one.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers andJustice
95. Luban might respond that, given our "moral baseline," we would receive no
benefit on this occasion from the turn-taking arrangement-it certainly would not get us
through as fast as a "tough luck" approach. This, however, would relativize the benefits
of a scheme to the recipient's preferred alternative: people who were delayed equally by
the obstruction would be benefited unequally by the turn-taking scheme, if they favored
different alternatives which would have resulted in different delays. It is absurd to claim
that the more self-serving the preferred alternative, the less the benefit conferred and
the corresponding burden imposed by the turn-taking scheme.
96. An obligation to take turns also might arise from the fact that in so doing, we
contribute to the solution of a coordination problem, while we impair the solution in
refusing to do so. But, as Regan has noted, this is a strictly consequentialist concern,
having nothing to do with a duty of fair play. Regan, Law's Halo, 4 Soc. PHIL. & POL'Y
15, 17 (1986).
97. See D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 39-40.
98. See id. at 39.
99. See id. at 41-42.
100. Luban argues that the obligation to participate in whichever type of cooperative
scheme hinges "on the importance, or at any rate the reasonableness, of the cooperative
scheme in question." Id. at 41.
MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
101. This is true even if we would not in fact have been willing to do anything without
group assistance, because a solo effort would have been futile. What matters is whether
we would have been willing to do as much for ourselves as our "share" of the group
effort required, if that would have gotten the job done. I think we take advantage of our
neighbors by opting out in circumstances in which we would be willing to put "x" effort
into a project which would require greater than "x" to do by ourselves but less than "x"
to do with others. While we would not have done the work if the group had not, because
the effort would have been excessive, we would have done as much for ourselves as the
group scheme required of us if that lesser effort sufficed to get the job done. In this
sense, we are allowing others do our work for us if we do not participate. This suggests
that the strongest case of exploitation will not be the paradigm case of free-riding, in
which the individual is always better off doing nothing. This sense of exploitation re-
quires that there be at least some hypothetical circumstances in which the individual
would be better off by exerting herself.
102. See D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 39-40, 41-42.
103. I think this sense of exploitation explains the duty to participate that Christie
claims to find in a neighborhood campaign to restore basic services cut off by civil war or
natural calamity. G. Christie, On the Moral Obligation to Obey the Law 15 (Oct. 28,
1988) (unpublished manuscript) (paper given at Columbia University Law School Legal
Theory Workshop) (copy on file with Maryland Law Review). We can safely assume that
virtually anyone would work to restore his own services, and thus that the holdouts are
exploiting their neighbors' efforts. Simmons relies on a similar inference from objective
importance to individual disposition in an exchange with Klosko. Klosko, Presumptive
Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation, 16 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 241 (1987); Simmons, The
Anarchist Position: A Reply to Klosko & Senor, 16 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 269 (1987). Klosko
argues for a duty, not conditioned on consent, to contribute to schemes providing goods
that are (1) "presumptively beneficial"-those which, like Rawls' "primary social
goods," everyone is presumed to want, Klosko, supra, at 246 (citingJ. RAWLS, THEORY OF
JUSTICE 62 (1971)); and (2) worth the cost to the typical recipient. Id. at 248. Simmons
contends that to the extent that such a duty rests on fairness rather than general benefi-
cence, presumptive benefits will be binding only because they can be presumed to elicit
participation; in other words, because it can be presumed that almost anyone would
want them at the price. Simmons, supra, at 273-74. Simmons further contends that
schemes providing only "discretionary" goods do not bind just because participation in
obtaining them cannot be presumed. Id. at 274.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers and Justice 413
104. But not if we only had decided after seeing the results of the planting that it
would have been worth the effort to us to take part. In these circumstances, we would
not have been exploiting our neighbors at the time of the planting when we sincerely
believed that we would not have made the effort independently.
105. The case would be even stronger, but quite different, if we were unwilling to join
in because we did not own a car. In that case, we would receive objectively less benefit
from the clean-up, and it might be unfair to impose the same burden. I believe that a
notion of fair play requires an objective measure of benefits and burdens, although I
recognize the distinction may be hard to draw. I also think certain reasons for opting out
may be inherently disrespectful, e.g., the belief that street-cleaning is "beneath our
dignity."
106. See D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 42-43.
107. Id. at 44.
108. See id. at 49.
109. For someone who regarded duties of fair play as antecedent to any cooperative
scheme for enforcing them, the absence of such a scheme would at most excuse non-
compliance. For Luban, however, the duty to comply would not even arise, since fair
MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
play is based on reciprocity, and in the absence of an effective scheme there would be no
benefits to reciprocate.
110. Regan, supra note 96, at 16.
111. Luban implicitly acknowledges this in accepting that the compliance of most citi-
zens is a condition of the obligation to obey the law. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 38. He,
however, fails to recognize that this condition significantly attenuates the connection
between fair play and the obligation to obey even a small subset of laws.
112. Id.
113. Id.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers andJustice 415
120. Id. at 240-41. Luban concedes that access to equal legal services would be a
"better interpretation of the meaning of equal access," but feels that it would be a pro-
hibitively expensive, politically impossible goal. Id.
121. Wertheimer, supra note 117, at 320-2 1. Wertheimer believes that universal ac-
cess would be harder to defend against a libertarian objection than would "negative"
equalization, because it is less restrictive of liberty to prohibit a rich litigant from over-
spending on legal services than to require a third party to pay for a poor litigant's access
to those services. Id. I doubt that many libertarians would find it more objectionable to
take money from someone by taxation than to prohibit that person from spending it on
protecting what she believed to be her entitlements. To appeal to libertarians, the dis-
tinction would have to rely on the acceptance of the judicial system as a legitimate func-
tion of the minimal state, allowed to impose spending limits on disputing parties. But if
people can be taxed to set up the court, why can they not be taxed to subsidize access to
it?
122. These two forms of redistribution have complementary deficiencies. Equaliza-
tion is impracticable if it is limited to specific disputes, while access is ineffective unless it
is more than minimal. Because private attorneys structure their clients' transactions to
avoid disputes and to ensure success when they occur, equalization in specific disputes is
difficult to achieve without massive handicapping of the more privileged party. Because
the legal problems of the poor often require considerable skill and perseverance, mini-
mal access barely will scratch the surface.
123. Wertheimer, supra note 117, at 304.
124. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 243-44.
125. Wertheimer, supra note 117, at 304.
1990] REVIEW EsSAY-Lawyers andJustice 417
results, which may require that the weaker party receive far greater
legal resources than a powerful adversary.
A similar qualification applies to Luban's argument. Even if
equal access to the courts is required for the legitimacy of the Amer-
ican government, differential access may serve as a corrective to the
injustices produced by that government. Thus, it has been sug-
gested that a moral equilibrium has been achieved in tort law be-
tween access barriers favoring defendants and rules of liability
favoring plaintiffs.14 2 Removing access barriers might well destroy
this equilibrium and iricrease substantive injustice. To achieve jus-
tice in an unjust political order, it may sometimes be necessary to
violate its legitimation principles.
Wertheimer and Luban also suggest another reason why the
state is obliged to provide legal services to those who cannot afford
them. If the government declines to do so, it does not merely fail to
help the poor, but harms them in a way different than denying them
adequate health care or housing. 43 Thus, Luban argues:
[T]he selective exclusion of the poor from the legal system
does not simply fail to confer an advantage on them-it ac-
tively injures them. For a legal system does more than pro-
tect people from each other: it enormously expands our
field of action .... [A] network of practices-of power and
privilege-is set up from which those who have no access
to the system are excluded; and this exclusion itself intensi-
fies the pariah status of the poor. . . . The state has not
been an innocent bystander observing the regrettable spec-
tacle of economic inequality and poverty: it shares primary
responsibility with the legal profession . . . for the fact that
the poor have no meaningful
144
access to justice and are made
worse off by that fact.
Wertheimer draws a specific contrast to medicine:
Although the distribution of medical resources may be
somewhat competitive, it is not directly adversarial. By con-
trast, an improvement in the legal resources available to
one party has a direct negative effect on the interests of
another. For these reasons, the distribution of legal re-
sources-as opposed to the absolute level-is arguably
142. Cf Krier & Gillette, The Un-easy Casefor Technological Optimism, 84 MICH. L. REV.
405 (1985).
143. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 265-66; Wertheimer, supra note 117, at 322. Only
Wertheimer takes his argument to imply the priority of the right to legal services over
the right to health care. Id. at 305.
144. D. LUBAN, supra note 1, at 247-48.
420 MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 49:392
jures the poor in denying them legal than medical services, that
would not settle the issue of priority. While it may be worse, ceteris
paribis, for a government or an individual to harm than to fail to
help, the magnitude of the injury also must be considered. The
stakes in health care may be, in general, much higher than in law: it
may be far worse for the government passively to allow illness and
debility to go untreated than actively to prevent the vindication of
most legal rights. If we believe in the rights to adequate health care,
secure housing or meaningful employment, we may well regard
those rights as more urgent than the right to legal services.
CONCLUSION
152. Less persuasive, and also unnecessary, is Luban's fallback argument, that law,
unlike grocery retailing, is not "a victimless pastime." Id. Luban suggests that the ad-
versarial nature of legal practice creates some sort of compensatory obligation on the
part of those who practice it. Id. at 286-87. Initially, this argument from direct harming
might seem to have more force against lawyers than the government, because lawyers
harm the disadvantaged more directly in representing the advantaged than the govern-
ment does in allowing them to do so. The individual lawyer, however, hardly can re-
dress this harm by representing the actual victims-to the extent they were identifiable,
it would present a conflict of interest for her to represent them. Moreover, it seems odd
to demand redress for an injury while not requiring the lawyer to avoid it in the first
place, by assuming a less adversarial role.
If the lawyer owes no specific compensatory duty to those actually injured by her
actions, it is unclear why she should have a more general obligation to make her services
available to those belonging to the same class as her victims, though something like this
appears to have been the moral logic of robber-barons turned philanthropists. While
the harm of adversary representation may require subsidies for the injured class, it does
not require that those subsidies come out of lawyers' pockets. If lawyers should pay, it is
only because the state's role in creating the legal profession permits it to structure that
profession as it sees fit.
1990] REVIEw ESSAY-Lawyers and Justice 423