Herbert Marcuse’s Critique of Technological Rationality:
An Exegetical Reading
By Marcelo Vieta
March, 2006 Draft
“[W]hen technics becomes the universal form of material production, it circumscribes
an entire culture; it projects a historical totality – a world.”
~Herbert Marcuse, 1964, One-Dimensional Man, p. 154
“In the exigencies of thought and in the madness of love is the destructive refusal of
the established ways of life. Truth transforms the modes of thought and existence.
Reason and freedom converge.”
~Herbert Marcuse, 1964, One-Dimensional Man, p. 127
1
I. Introduction: Technological Rationality within One-Dimensional Society
For Herbert Marcuse, “technological rationality” is a rationality of domination and social control
characteristic of advanced industrial societies. Underpinned by a formal rationality that overrides the more
substantive, values-laden forms of reason distinguishing pre-industrial societies, technological rationality
fashions everyday life into a “technological reality” that encloses the subject’s perceptions, experiences, and
thoughts by projecting the world’s objects and nature as a “ a world of instrumentalities” (Marcuse, 1964, p.
218). Sharing intellectual ground with Horkheimer’s (1974) critique of “instrumental reason” (p. 97) and
Adorno and Horkheimer’s (2002) notion of “technical rationality” (p. 95), for Marcuse a technologically
rational world “predefines” the very “form” of the appearance of objects for the subjects that apprehend and
manipulate them as empirically “value-free” materials – detached, fungible, and orderable things that are
emptied of any transcendent meaning beyond perhaps their exchange-value (Marcuse, 1964, p. 219). At the
disposal of willful subjects operating in a world without objective limits, objects now enter into the
abstracted realm of equivalencies, differentiated only by a competitive rationale and the predetermined and
stunted choices of the marketplace.
The critique of technological rationality woven throughout One-Dimensional Man also draws from
and parallels Marx’s critique of the commodity form and the rationality of capitalist markets (Feenberg,
2002). Technological rationality both makes up and drives the social control of a society subdivided into
hierarchical social divisions of production, ownership, and aggressive competition under the profit motive.
Moreover, Marcuse’s dialectical and historically materialist diagnosis of technological rationality reveals that
technocratic social control in modern advanced industrial societies is practiced diffusely under the
assumption that social hierarchies are extrinsic to “neutral systems and machines” (Feenberg, 2002, p. 66).
Marcuse’s materialist analysis in One-Dimensional Man sets out to question and lay bare the contradictions
in this assumption. Subsequently supported by myriad social and historical studies of technology,1 Marcuse’s
dialectical reflection reveals that in actuality the systems and machines of control are not neutral but
politically inscribed in their very structures:
2
[T]he notion of the ‘neutrality’ of technology can no longer be maintained. Technology as
such cannot be isolated from the use to which it is put; the technological society is a system of
domination which operates already in the concept and construction of technique. (Marcuse, 1964, p.
xvi)2
In this paper I set out to exegetically work through Marcuse’s dialectically enfolded and historically
materialist concept of “technological rationality” as it is presented in One-Dimensional Man. In the process, I
will first continue to outline what Marcuse means by “technological rationality” and clarify how he situates
the concept within his broader critique of the ideology and practices of advanced industrial society. Second, I
will sketch out Marcuse’s complex dialectical sojourns that diagnose how we have become “preconditioned”
to think one-dimensionally (Marcuse, 1964, p. 8) and how this technologically rationalized preconditioning
both differs from its roots in “pre-technological rationality” and yet is presupposed by this genealogical
inheritance. And lastly, I will attempt to articulate how Marcuse’s “post-technological rationality” envisions
civilizational change not only depending on redirecting the goals and ends of technological systems but,
more vitally, on transforming the very rationality that permeates technology’s logic and advanced industrial
society’s technological base.3
II. The Modes of Technological Reason
Marcuse’s critique of technological rationality is fundamentally an ideology critique of advanced
industrial society that, in part, springboards from Adorno and Horkheimer’s (2002) seminal work in
Dialectic of Enlightenment (Feenberg, 2002). In the technologically rationalized reality of advanced
industrial society, alienation from our work and each other extends beyond Marx’s industrial nightmare of
the factory and now permeates every nook and cranny of life. Our alienation, however, propagated by the
cultural industry’s manipulation of thought, is now veiled by the ideology of efficiency and the promises of
affluence that permeate one-dimensional society. “The efficiency of the system,” writes Marcuse, “blunts the
individual’s recognition that it contains no facts which do not communicate the repressive power of the
whole” (Marcuse, 1964, p. 11). Saturated in abundance and a cultural imaginary of wellbeing, alienation as a
concept “seems to [now] become questionable when the individuals identify themselves with the existence
which is imposed upon them and have in it their own development and satisfaction,” Marcuse continues (p.
3
11). But these satisfactions, he clarifies, are false ones, actually belonging to “a more progressive
stage of alienation” (p. 11).
Herein lies the sophistication of a technologically rationalized system that both provides abundantly
to individuals yet, to use Heidegger’s term, “enframes” their thoughts and controls their behaviours and
practices by “prescrib[ing] attitudes and habits” (p. 12). By accepting this material abundance we
paradoxically submit to endless servitude as workers and consumers that have had our time, experiences, and
consciousness captured by advanced industrial society’s technocratic means. Moreover, individuals now
tacitly uphold the totalizing and alienating tendencies of the system by actively and even earnestly
participating in the means of production and consumption that, on the one hand, deliver them the goods ever
more efficiently while, at the same time, extending and reproducing the repetitious, numbing patterns and
behaviours of the workplace into their everyday lives. In our technologically rationalized society, autonomy
and the subversive capacities of thought and the imagination are mollified and contained by the closed
“universe of discourse” (p. 23). Instead, in their tacit collusion with the system, technologically rationalized
people find empty solace in the glimmering but vapid products of the marketplace. Our manufactured
patterns of thought and experience further alienate us within the “technological veil that conceals the
reproduction of inequality and enslavement” (p. 32). Alienated and not aware of our alienation, unfree in our
freedom, living “euphor[ically] in unhappiness” (p. 5), submission to our technologically mediated reality, it
seems, is a Faustian bargain.
This technological structuring of society – its “technical necessity” and its logic of technology
(Marcuse, 1968, p. 212) – is historically prefigured by the development of formal and deductive logic that
paved the road for the emergence of “scientific thought – the first step only, for a much higher degree of
abstraction and mathematization” that modified reason and the experiences mediated by it for technical
means (p. 137).4 As a result of this historical materialist diagnosis, Marcuse shows the contradiction inherent
in the claim that technical-scientific reason is neutral. Under Marcuse’s scrutiny, technologically rationalized
society is revealed for what it is: a hegemonic ordering driven by technocratic means.
4
Indeed, despite the claims of current technical-scientific discourse, our contemporary
technological enclosures are not neutral but rather political and socio-historically determined, burdened with
the values of control, hierarchic order, and capitalist logics of production and accumulation. Further, it is not
technology per se which is the problem but a technology shaped by the dominative, operationalist, and
instrumentalized rationality that undergirds society’s technological base and that falsely deems this
technological base to be a deterministically evolutionary given of “progress.” For Marcuse, it is the “project”
of industrialization and the logic of a society administered from above that has captured the technical into a
system that perverts technological means. Once applied, this technology embodies the politics that underlies
it within its very structures and takes on a “logic of its own independent of the goals it serves” (Feenberg,
2004, p. 98). Consequently, merely changing the goals of technology would not transform its dominative
logic. Rather, Marcuse believed that a move towards a new civilizational project that was more sensitive to
the affirmation of life; the reduction of “toil, aggressiveness, misery, and injustice” for all (Marcuse, 1964, p.
5); and the possibilities for self-actualization, depended on qualitatively changing the very rationality that
drove the technological base by transforming it into another kind of rationality. This new, “post-
technological rationality” (p. 239) would be one that both recognized the capacity for science and technology
to “[translate] values into technical tasks – the materialization of values [ – ]” (p. 232) while also
recognizing the need to transform technical-scientific logic and “break with the prevailing technological
rationality” (p. 231).
Marcuse’s proposal for a post-technological project was not a call for a regressive return to a pre-
modern state of nature, nor was it a resignation into quietism. Rather, it called for a reworking of the
technological base. This, for Marcuse, would be a “completion of the technological project” (p. 231,
emphasis added). It would also see a transformation of modernity’s project that had paradoxically “rendered
possible the satisfaction of needs[,]…the reduction of toil,” and the escape from myth while in the process
also capturing nature and human experience within the technical-scientific concept of a “universally
controllable nature” projected “as endless matter-in-function,” a “technological universe…of mental and
physical instrumentalities,” pure means (p. 168). A project towards a post-technological rationality was the
5
“transcendent project” (p. 220) that Marcuse attempted to lay out – provisionally and in
fragmentary form – in the last half of One-Dimensional Man. This transcendent project called for a “higher
rationality” that would: 1) unveil the current state of domination; 2) strive to “falsify this established reality;”
and 3) demonstrate its own higher rationality by “preserving and improving” the achievements of civilization
for reducing the toil and suffering in the struggle for existence – what Marcuse viewed as an accomplishment
of modern civilization – but that would also set the stage for the “pacification of existence” from its
dysfunctional, perverse capture within the current technocratic framework (p. 220). To accomplish this,
Marcuse believed that the new rationality he was calling for required the rending of reason away from the
value-neutrality of pure science, which had prefigured and entered into current modes of technocratic
institutions. In Marcuse’s transcendent project, rationality was to be re-entrenched with the sort of value
judgments that more traditional societies upheld – albeit now materialistically contextualized. This new
technological rationality would be able to assess the “truth” of this transcendent civilizational project
according to life affirming values. These values would be arrived at through the subversive power of an
aestheticized rationality guided by a negative dialectics; the desublimated and oppositional forces of artistic
expressions and sensuous life; and, broadly, the “productive imagination” (p. 227-246). Marcuse’s
“normative conception of truth” (Feenberg, 2004, p. 102) and his call for the materialization of values were
thus grounded in a project that proposed the optimization of “the free development of human needs and
faculties” (Marcuse, 1964, pp. 220).
Marcuse’s proposal for a post-technological project and the new technological reason that was to
undergird it would see the transformation of the means of technology, not just its ends, and would be rooted
in new values disclosed and affirmed by the oppositional power of aesthetics and erotics to put into relief the
inauthenticity of current societal conditions. This technological change cannot, however, be merely a moral
one – i.e., simply changing the ends of current technocratic systems while leaving its structures intact, such
as the “welfare state” or the current management trends of open-concept workspaces. Moralistically driven
changes within the current system would leave in place the linchpins of domination within capitalist power:
intuitional hierarchies and their technocratic frameworks. For a true alternative, Marcuse believed that not
6
only the technical base needed to be change, but also the institutional “superstructures” (Feenberg,
2004, p. 98). A post-technological society must create a different kind of science and a new type of
technology. Further, these new rational dispositions and redesigned technical structures must not conflict
with nature but be in harmony with it; they must “treat nature as another subject instead of as mere raw
materials” (p. 98). Our untapped societal and individual potentialities – i.e., the possibilities that lay beyond
the already exhausted potentialities of routinization, domination, and the profit motive – must be the new aim
undergirding human life. Thus, Marcuse was not advocating ridding ourselves of the technological base and
structures tout court. Indeed, freedom from the toil of constantly provisioning for our necessities depended
on technical progress. Science and technology could still be vehicles of freedom. Rather, science’s and
technology’s means, directions, and goals would have to change. Technology must be liberated from its
current forms of technics and must be transformed into a “technology of liberation” (Marcuse, 1964, p. 19).
In doing so, our very reality would also be transformed through a new technical-scientific imagination that
would be “free to project and design the forms of a human universe without exploitation and toil” (p. 19).
But what could Marcuse possibly mean by freedom in technical progress? How can we have a
“technology of liberation”? If it was the ideology of technical progress that dominated and enframed
humanity in the first place, how could it also provide liberation? His view for a new rationality, a post-
technological one, lay with what he implicitly considered to be the ambiguousness – or in Feenberg’s (2002)
terms, the “ambivalence” (p.79) – of technological rationality. Inherently ambivalent, then, Marcuse saw the
possibility to root technological rationality in the soil of different values. By reason being ambivalent,
Marcuse is thinking of something akin to the “ambiguous” and “open horizons” of the Platonic dialectic
(Marcuse, 1964, p. 131) (see next section). In particular, the ambivalence of reason – its underdetermined
openness to comprehend and imaginatively move beyond the given and begin to realize other “potentialities”
to the given – could transcend the given’s ideologically congealed contingencies by returning value
judgments into the realm of the rational. Thus, reason, particularly a negatively dialectical one, could also be
subversive. As such, the possibility for a technology of liberation also rested with the potentialities that a
subversive reason could reveal. Marcuse believed that this new, subversive, and dialectic rationality would
7
be able to keep the tension between subject and the object open and that, borrowing from Hegel
while also echoing Adorno, the object would no longer be feared. A new, post-technologically rationalized,
two-dimensional thought would replace a one-dimensional one. Finally, the capacity for reason to re-
conceptualize reality with the help of the productive imagination would lead us to another type of
technology, wresting it away from “the metaphysics of domination” and tapping it into “the metaphysics of
liberation” (p. 167).
III. From Pre-Technological Rationality to Technological Rationality
Before “technological man” could take flight and sore above “technological nature” (Marcuse, 1964,
p. 138), the mind had to first be made to think a certain way. For Marcuse, to think of nature in an abstracted
way that allowed us to calculate, dissect, capture, and control it was an historical project. The beginnings of
this project were dictated by necessity – humans need to control and take from nature to some extent in order
to survive. Our rational capacities have helped us do this. But, all thinking tends towards universalizing and
identifying (pp. 138-139), towards comprehending reality by grasping and knowing what appears through the
concepts we give it. Here, Marcuse discloses his Frankfurt School inheritance. Marcuse posits that “all
objects of thought are universals” (p. 139). In a similar vein, Adorno (1973) writes that “[t]o think is to
identify” (p. 5). “Conceptual order is content to screen what thinking seeks to comprehend” (p. 5). In further
agreement with the rest of the Frankfurt School, Marcuse (1964) contends that universal concepts, however,
are never “merely…formal” but are rather materialistically contextualized and constituted “in the
interrelationship between the (thinking and acting) subjects and their world” (p. 139). Moreover, there is for
Marcuse a fundamental difference between the ways moderns and ancients apply universals; modern,
instrumentally rationalized ways of satiating necessity and comprehending the world differs from the pre-
technologically rational ways of the Greeks – Marcuse’s exemplars for pre-modernist thinking. What we
could learn from the Greeks, Marcuse thought, were the ways in which they continued to respect the objects
they engaged with by not tearing them away from the meanings and values bestowed on them by a greater
objective realm. But paradoxically, the formation of “technological man,” Marcuse argues, also begins with
the Greeks.
8
Techné vs. Modern Technological Reason. Implicit in Marcuse’s discussion of pre-
technological rationality and its links to a post-technological one is the notion of the Greek concept of techné
and its role in the process of bringing things forth from nature rather than challenging nature in the processes
of making (Marcuse, 1964, p. 238). To the ancients, techné was one way of bringing things into existence
and closer to their essential forms. Technai are the activities and skills of craft work and represent the arts of
both mind and hand that act within a mode of “truth revealing” linked to creative making, poiesis
(Heidegger, 1977, pp. 13, 21). Since the concept of techné finds art and technique in kinship, it would help
Marcuse begin to ground his proposed post-technological project (Marcuse, 1964, p. 238; also see: Feenberg,
2004, pp. 1-20). While the word techné does not appear anywhere in One-Dimensional Man,5 it is clear that
he is discussing this notion of Greek revealing while contrasting it to modern technics in at least two brief
passages in One-Dimensional Man (see for example: pp. 153-154, 239). Notwithstanding the absence of the
term, the appeal of the concept of techné for Marcuse implicitly rested in its potentiality for reconciling art
and technology within the value judgments that are intrinsic to the concept. What was most promising for
Marcuse was that techné intimately involved homo faber in the movement of things from existence into their
essences within a greater telos, entrenching human-made things within a greater finality that did not privilege
humans but found them co-responsible with nature in the movement towards the essential. Modern
technological reason, on the other hand, elides any kind of such finality and bestows on the human sole
responsibility for controlling nature.
Pre-Technological Rationality vs. Technological Rationality. Unlike the willful, masculinist forms
of modern control over socio-economic life and nature, and the abstractive, congealing tendencies of
technical-scientific rationality, the “pre-technological rationality” of the Greeks also showed that humans and
nature, subjects and objects, were all infused with “modes of Being” already-always in “movement” (p. 127).
For the Greeks, “[f]inite Being,” Marcuse reminds us, was already-always incomplete, “subject to change”
(p. 138). Things for the Greeks were never static but a Dynamis, filled with an energy and a striving towards
some higher form of essentialness beyond what merely appears (Feenberg, 2004, p. 86). These movements of
Being showed the ancients: 1) that subjects and objects were already-always united in a tension and
9
antagonism between existence and a becoming essence; 2) that objects are possessed by the
potentiality to become other than what they appear; 3) that humans are not separate from nature but
intimately ensconced within it; and 4) that values and objective meanings are essential aspects of things that
can begin to be logically and imaginatively comprehended by subjects. In other words, pre-technological
rationality was grounded in “a philosophic quest [that proceeded] from the finite world to the construction of
a reality which is not subject to the painful difference between potentiality and actuality, which has not
mastered its negativity” (p. 126). For the ancients, then, the struggle of Being striving towards the essential,
which things-as-givens never attain but always aspire towards, was evidenced negatively in experience, in
our suffering and our striving (Feenberg, 2004, p. 86). The “is” of things possessed the implicitness of an
“ought” in the struggle and movement towards the essential (Marcuse, 1964, p. 138).
The discovery of the tensions of reality between “is” and becoming, Marcuse continues to remind us,
was for the ancients “the work of Logos and Eros,” the two principal concepts that assigned the “two modes
of negation” (p. 126) to thought. These two modes of reason – logic and erotic cognition, what gives order
and what gives pleasure – served to “break hold of the established reality and strive for a truth incompatible
with it” (p. 126). Consideration of reality for the Greeks was thus mediated by these two modes of thought
that, together and in tension with each other, revealed those “untrue and unfree” modes of existence that do
not aspire to realize their potentialities. These “untrue” modes of existence were embodied by individuals
that spent their entire life, or a fair part of it, “procuring the prerequisites of existence” (pp. 127-128).
For Marcuse however, the “real dividing line between pre-technological and technological
rationality” was not one based on freedom and unfreedom. Like our one-dimensional society, ancient Greek
society also had social classes whose entire lives were spent procuring a living for themselves or for others,
blocking the possibilities for a vast number of people from accessing a free human existence and arresting
the opportunity for self-actualization (p. 128). The difference between the projects of pre-technological and
technological societies for Marcuse rested rather with “the manner in which the subordination to the
necessities of life – to ‘earning a living’ – is organized and, in the new modes of freedom and unfreedom,
truth and falsehood which correspond to this organization,” (p. 128, emphasis added). Thus, as long as there
10
is enslavement of any kind – pre-capitalist slave ownership, capitalist wage-slavery, our
contemporary unhappy euphoria of consumerism, or our capture within a closed universe of discourse –
thinking about the good and the beautiful, corralled by the privileged few, remains inaccessible to most.
Indeed, thought is unfree when it is horded by “the master[s] of pure contemplation” (p. 128). In a world
where haves and have-nots exist side-by-side, and where the “free” enjoy their freedom off the backs of
those that remain captured, freedom is merely an illusion.
Thus, while the reason of the ancients showed the vestiges of a more truthful relation between subject
and object, existence and becoming, humanity and nature, they nevertheless also remained unfree because, in
Marcuse’s materialist definition, the truthfulness of human existence lies in the degree of “freedom from
material necessities” (p.128-129). On the one hand, the Greeks underscore for Marcuse that the quest for
truth and the comprehension of reality are two-fold; Being is in constant tension with its becoming, the given
with its potentiality. For the Greeks, as for Marcuse, this two-foldedness to reality was the “ontological
condition” (pp. 125, 129, 130). On the other hand, any “societal division of labour” made up of inequality
and injustice – plaguing us and the ancients – becomes an “historical barrier” blocking our “quest for truth,”
arresting the potentiality for “the reduction of toil,” and elevating truth “safely above the historical reality”
(p. 129). Hence, within one-dimensional society, the given hierarchical power structures inherent with
advanced industrial divisions of labour become barriers for coming to realize their historical contingencies.
The result: Objective meanings that for the ancients still shaped value judgments now get separated out from
reason, and the intimate relationship between reason and objective values are forgotten. To rationalize the
world with both Logos and Eros is two-dimensional thought. The rupture of Logos from Eros that takes root
with the first articulation of the Western tradition gets us well on our way to one-dimensional thinking.
Why, then, have we become one-dimensional thinkers, where a logos of the “universal valid,”
abstracted from individual instances and historical conjunctures, was constituted in order to then blanket all
particulars, where logical reason won over erotic reason, where “material content” was “neutralized” (p.
137), where the “principle of identity” was torn away from the “principle of contradiction,” and where
contradictions were rendered invalid as a form of “incorrect thinking” (p. 137)? Why was the struggle for
11
truth – for the just, the good, and the beautiful – divorced from “the value of Reason” (Marcuse,
1964, p. 220)? Because, answers Marcuse, the technologically rationalized mind had to be “made susceptible
to abstract generalization” (p. 138) and “truth” limited to factual qualities. For the Greeks, truth and
falsehood are not merely about propositions as they were to later become for analytic philosophy. The true
and the false were about the disclosure of Being before statements about Being. The separation of the logical
from the erotic, of “is” from “ought,” and the potentiality afforded by the idea of the thing from its given, is
rooted, however, in the first days of formal logic where the “distinction was made between the universal,
calculable, ‘objective’ and the particular, incalculable, subjective dimension of thought” (p. 138). This
sundering began to take its deep roots with Aristotle’s Organon and its advocacy of formal universals and a
deductively logical world over the substantive Ideas and universals of Plato.6
We thus come to Marcuse’s implicit question woven throughout One-Dimensional Man: What
happens when an entire culture is shaped by formal universals (Feenberg, 2004)? His answer: Things lose
their potentiality beyond mere human will and preference. For Marcuse, the transition from substantive to
formal universals resulted in a shift in the project of reason from “‘What is…?” to ‘How…?’,” establishing a
“practical (though by no means absolute) certainty” which pulls reason away from any commitment to the
object (Marcuse, 1964, p. 151). Not beholden to any extrinsic meaning within which the object resides,
besides its mere categorization, operation, and function, things are freed from any consideration of the social-
historical contingencies that also layer into their reality. Now, with techno-scientific rationality, Marcuse
tells us that “the transformation of man and nature has no other objective limits than those offered by the
brute factuality of matter” (p. 151), and humans and nature lose all other meaningful objective limits to the
quantitative facts of thing observed. Thus, for Marcuse, formalist thinking begins the extraction of all
extrinsic values from cognition’s practices. With modern technological rationality, matter is now nothing but
a “(hypothetical) system of instrumentalities” predetermining experience by projecting onto nature these
instrumentalities and transforming things into abstracted qualities and quantities. At the same time the
abstractive instrumentalist move “organizes the whole,” framing our entire world-view (p. 154). Scientific-
technological reason’s abstractive and neutralizing tendencies excuse it from the realm of judgment (ethics)
12
because it shuts out any value-laden understanding of the myriad potentialities of the thing being
considered. “Being-as-such” gives way to “Being-instrument” (p. 152). Everything can now be dissected,
manipulated, and controlled to our own ends. As Feenberg writes, things are now “simply there,
unresistingly available for human use” (Feenberg, 2004, p. 87). This, for Marcuse, is the original violence of
modern reason: the “abstention from any judgment as to what is accidental and what essential,” placing
reason at the service of the status quo while canceling out whatever values sit outside of neutral science as
irrational (p. 87; see also: Marcuse, 1964, pp. 146, 148). Essentiality gives way to preferentiality, the sacred
to the scientific, becoming to congealment..
IV. Conclusion: Towards a Post-Technological Rationality
“However,” writes Marcuse, “another alternative seems possible” (Marcuse, 1964, p. 47). Marcuse’s
way out of technological domination and its invalidation of true freedom is to reclaim technological
rationality and the means it inscribes onto an entire society for other means and ends rooted in other values.
The redemption of technology would for Marcuse begin with a negatively dialectical form of reason. This
would give us a new disposition through a new form of reason that could also begin to reveal the
contradictions inherent within contemporary one-dimensional, technocratic society. Firmly ensconced in the
tradition of the Frankfurt School, Marcuse appeals to the subversive power of a negative dialectics to counter
the “scientific subversion of immediate experience” (p. 140). A negative dialectical mode of reason would
reconstitute the concrete and the experiential as oppositional forces (Feenberg, 2004, pp. 89-98). The
reclaimed subversive power of reason would in turn drive the development of new concepts “which carry in
themselves the protest and the refusal” to the established ways of life (Marcuse, 1964, p. 140). For Marcuse,
as for Adorno and Horkheimer, dialectic reason contains “the judgment that condemns the established
reality” (p. 140). Scientific-technological reason merely affirms it (p. 140).
Marcuse’s call for a dialectically rationalized “technological logos” (p. 236) is the cornerstone of his
“transcendent project.” Such a project would rupture scientific rationality and technologically mediated
practices from their dominative projects by reworking the technical in order to place it into the service of the
pacification of nature and the eradication of surplus labour, toil, and injustice. Thus, with the goal of re-
13
materializing the values that uphold life over those that contain and arrest it, values would have to
be placed firmly within reason. His “post-technological rationality” (Marcuse, 2004, p. 238) was to be a new
logos (p. 236) – a “new direction of technological progress” that would be the “catastrophe of the established
direction” of advanced industrial society (p. 228). A post-technological rationality would allow for new
“essential potential[ities]” (p. 132) that would blanket the rationality of the technical with new values, now
directed towards the reduction of “toil, aggressiveness, misery, and injustice” (p.5) and the affirmation of
self-actualizing modes of life. This new technological rationality was to be redirected towards the perfection
of objects rather than their domination (Feenberg, 2004, p. 89), resonating with Adorno’s notion of
reconciling the subject with the object by giving the object its due primacy within experience (Adorno,
2002). Most crucially, materialized values ensconced within a post-technological rationality would be
focused on the reduction of labour time, the creation of more disposable time, and would strive towards the
restructuring of the “productive apparatus” from the logics that administered people (Marcuse, 1964, p. 250).
Marcuse at one point calls post-technological reason “the technological rationality of art” (Marcuse,
1964, p. 238); post-technological rationality was to also be an astheticized reason. Experience would now be
comprehended by converging the subversive capacities of reason and aesthetic expression (p. 238). For
Marcuse, as for Adorno, artful ways of living possessed elements of “determinate negation” (p. 228)
whereby the aesthetic dimension would offer an oppositional force to the current forms of instrumentalized
control. With the unleashing of “free play and even the folly of the imagination” (p. 228), Marcuse believed
that passionate and joyful practices would render the ugliness of contemporary, one-dimensional existence an
offense to the “life instincts” (Feenberg, 2004, p. 93). An “aestheticized reduction” would peel away the
immediate contingency of objects and societal conditions that arrest and contain objects and experience
(Marcuse, 1964, p. 239). For Feenberg (2004), Marcuse’s notion of aesthetic reduction was to help us “[strip]
away the contingent aspects of objects…to get at what they could be if released to their free development”
(p. 97). The aesthetic reduction thus holds a translational power for Marcuse that would, on the one hand,
violate the oppressive tendencies of the current “natural” order – which would be the aesthetic reduction’s
14
negative dialectical moment – while, at the same time, mapping different potentialities for objects,
events, and situations (Marcuse, 1964, pp. 239-240).
But not only art had this reductive, oppositional power for Marcuse. So too did the cultural practices
of marginalized groups. Marginal practices could also challenge the givens of the status quo and show us
ways through to another world because both the aesthetic and the marginal operate on another plane of
reason and imagination that place into relief the ugliness of established reality. Like artistic practices, the
practices of marginalized groups also make us aware of different horizons to life. For instance, as the May
Events of 1968 and the New Left had shown Marcuse, the cultural and political practices of myriad
contemporary social justice movements around the world are providing countless examples of how
alternative cultural expressions can merge with and uphold rematerialized values of love, joy, resistance, and
direct democracy. As such, the “newest social movements” of today (Day, 2005, p. 8) are offering viable
alternatives to and communal freedom from neoliberal forms of oppression, exploitation, and exclusion
(McNally, 2002).
In a post-technologically rationalized universe, logos and eros would once again be reconciled within
particular conjunctures and socio-cultural contexts. Immanent needs under an ethics of care for one another
would undergird a new rational paradigm. The “Logos of technics” would be guided by values striving for
the pacification of existence. The enframing logic of modern technology would be contained via the
legislation of these new values. “[B]y virtue of [technology’s] own method and concepts” (Marcuse, 1964, p.
166), a liberated society would render to technological apparatuses the technical capacity to reduce the
struggle for the provisioning of the necessities for life. This technology already does well. A liberated society
would rend technical devices from their dominative projects. At the same time, a “technological eros” would
unleash our capacities for redesigning technological existence and the means and ends of technology via the
capacities of our “productive imagination” to choose from an array of possibilities for our own liberation,
and to strive for the “art of life” and freedom (p. 230) rather than the art of war and domination. In other
words, a post-technological rationality would ground itself in and aspire towards values focused on the
“affirmation of life.”
15
Endnotes
1
See, for example: Feenberg, 1999, 2002; Noble, 1977; 1984; Winner, 1986.
2
See also: Marcuse, 1964, p. 158.
3
For Marcuse, changing technology’s ends while leaving its means untouched would be a futile task
given the non-neutrality of technology. Thus, attempts to reconfigure the direction of technology
must always include the consideration of technical means, as well. I will clarify this throughout this
paper.
4
Crucially for Marcuse, technological rationality’s logic – “techno-logy” (Marcuse, 1964, p. 156) – is
grounded in a project of social domination for the benefit of the private ownership and control of the means
of production. Technologically rationalized existence solves in part capital’s conundrum of the variable costs
of “necessary labour time” that always remains in tension with the capitalist’s drive for increasing surplus
value (Marx, 1967, pp. 312-321, 359-368, 508-518). As such and at core, the drive of “technological
reason…in modern industrial society” presumes for Marcuse “the separation of the workers from the means
of production…[as]…a technical necessity… [and as a]…highly material, historical fact of the private
capitalist enterprise” (Marcuse, 1968, p. 212, quoted in Feenberg, 2002, p. 66). Modern industrial society’s
drive for accumulation is thus an “historical project” that “organizes matter” and its subjects as a “choice”
among a “range of possibilities” that “precludes alternative possibilities incompatible with it” (Marcuse,
1964, p. 219). For Marcuse, then, the historical project of techno-logy is the “new rationality” which
“projects and responds to a technological reality,” a reality whereby scientific practice and discourse is
deemed “neutral” and is neither structured toward nor has a telos itself (pp. 167, 169). This reality, Marcuse
points out throughout One-Dimensional Man, carries with it the ideological bias of one-dimensional society.
I will be discussing what Marcuse means by the logic of technology in the following pages.
5
Perhaps this was because the concept of techné was so closely associated with his teacher, Martin
Heidegger, with whom he had distanced himself personally but, in many ways, not philosophically
(Feenberg, 2004).
6
On the other hand, with the Platonic dialectic, concepts like Being/Non-Being, Movement, the One and the
Many, Identity and Contradiction, are kept methodically “open and ambiguous, not fully defined,” Marcuse
reminds us (1964, p. 131). They have “an open horizon” and a “universe of meaning…which is never
closed” (p. 131). The movement towards the truth of forms is a struggle, never fully attained but always
palpable within the horizons of the given. In the struggle for truth Platonic propositions are worked out via
dialogue where the usually unquestioned aspects of the universe are put in question in order to “go beyond
that which is given” to the philosopher (p. 131). Concepts have multifold meanings and their logical
unfolding “responds to the process of reality;” that is, reality is processual (p. 131). Truth and falsehood are
not merely about propositions as they were to later become for analytic philosophy. The true and the false
were about the disclosure of Being before statements about Being.
16
References
Adorno, T.W. (1973). Negative dialectics. New York: The Continuum Publishing Group.
Adorno, T.W. (2002). “Subject and object.” In A. Arato & E. Gebhardt (Eds.), The Essential Frankfurt
School Reader (pp. 497-511). New York: Continuum.
Adorno, T.W. & Horkheimer, M. (2002). Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical fragments. Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press.
Day, R.J.F. (2005). Gramsci is dead: Anarchist currents in the newest social movements. Toronto: Between
the Lines / New York: Pluto Press.
Feenberg, A. (2002). Transforming technology: A critical theory revisited. Oxford: University Press.
Feenberg, A. (2002). Heidegger and Marcuse: The catastrophe and redemption of history. New York:
Routledge.
Heidegger, M. (1977). The question concerning technology and other essays. New York: Harper & Row.
Horkheimer, M. (1974). Eclipse of reason. New York: Seabury Press.
McNally, D. (2002). Another world is possible: Globalization and anti-capitalism. Winnipeg, Canada:
Arbeiter Ring Publishing.
Marcuse, H. (1964). One-dimensional man: Studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society. Boston:
Beacon Press.
Marcuse, H. (1968). “Industrialization and capitalism in the work of Max Weber.” In Herbert Marcuse,
Negations: Essays in critical theory (pp. 201-226). Boston: Beacon Press.
Marx K. (1967). Capital, volume 1: A Critique of Political Economy: A critical analysis of capitalist
production. New York: International Publishers
Noble, D.F. (1977). America by design: Science, technology, and the rise of corporate capitalism. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Noble, D.F. (1984). Forces of production: A social history of industrial automation. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Winner, L. (1986). The whale and the reactor: A search for limits in an age of high technology. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press.