The Authorship of The Derveni Papyrus, A Sophistic Treatise On The Origin of Religion and Language: A Case For Prodicus of Ceos (2019) .
The Authorship of The Derveni Papyrus, A Sophistic Treatise On The Origin of Religion and Language: A Case For Prodicus of Ceos (2019) .
and Papyrological
Tradition
A Philosophical Reappraisal of the Sources
Proceedings of the International Workshop held
at the University of Trier (22–24 September 2016)
Edited by
Christian Vassallo
Funded by the Schwarz-Liebermann Stiftung im Stifterverband für die Deutsche Wissenschaft
and the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG)
ISBN 978-3-11-066321-1
e-ISBN (PDF) 978-3-11-066610-6
ISSN 1869-7143
www.degruyter.com
Contents
Abbreviations IX
Christian Vassallo
Introduction. The Presocratics from Derveni to Herculaneum:
A New Look at Early Greek Philosophy 1
David N. Sedley
2 The Opening Lemmas of the Derveni Papyrus 45
Richard D. McKirahan
3 Some Controversial Topics in the Derveni Cosmology 73
Marco A. Santamaría
4 Pherecydes of Syros in the Papyrological Tradition 91
Leonid Zhmud
5 The Papyrological Tradition on Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans 111
Kilian J. Fleischer
6 Philolaus’ Book(s) in Philodemus’ Index Academicorum 147
Aldo Brancacci
7 Music and Philosophy in Damon of Oa 161
VI Contents
Graziano Ranocchia
9 Heraclitus’ Portrait in Diogenes Laërtius and Philodemus’
On Arrogance 221
Mirjam E. Kotwick
10 Aphrodite’s Cosmic Power: Empedocles in the Derveni Papyrus 251
Simon Trépanier
11 Empedocles on the Origin of Plants: PStrasb. gr. inv. 1665–1666,
Sections d, b, and f 271
Giuliana Leone
12 Empedocles in the Herculaneum Papyri: An Update 299
Michael Pozdnev
14 Metrodorus the Allegorist as Reflected in Philodemus’ On Poems, Book 2:
PHerc. 1676, col. 2 + N 1081, col. 12 (= 61 A 4 DK; Test. 34.3 Lanata) 415
Enrico Piergiacomi
15 Democritus’ Doctrine of Eidola in the Herculaneum Papyri:
A Reassessment of the Sources 437
Contents VII
Tiziano Dorandi
16 Anaxarchus from Egypt to Herculaneum 473
Andrei Lebedev
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus, A Sophistic Treatise on the Origin
of Religion and Language: A Case for Prodicus of Ceos 491
Jaap Mansfeld
18 Lists of Principles and Lists of Gods: Philodemus, Cicero, Aëtius,
and Others 609
Indices
1 (I) Preliminary remarks
Since the very possibility of establishing the author of the Derveni Papyrus (here-
after PDerv.) has been questioned in the official editio princeps,1 we are obliged
1 Habent sua fata not only libelli, but also conference papers. The original version of this paper
under the title The Derveni Treatise as a Document of Sophistic Atheism was presented at the
international conference on the Derveni Papyrus held at Princeton University on April 25th, 1993
during my Perkins fellowship granted by the Council of Humanities of Princeton University: cf.
Sider (1997) 129 n. 2. It was not included in the proceedings published later. I decided to wait
for the publication of the official editio princeps of the papyrus (KPT) in order to verify the sup-
plements I proposed, but this took quite a while. In the meantime, as a result of the change of
platforms between Mac and PC, the Greek in my paper became unreadable; eventually, it was re-
stored by the Institute of Linguistic Studies of the Russian Academy of Sciences in St. Petersburg
(thanks are due to Nikolai Kazansky and Evgeniia Kriuchkova). I have benefited from several
discussions of my hypothesis. During my fellowship in All Souls College, Oxford (1995–1996)
I was invited by Richard Janko to present my ‘atheistic’ interpretation of PDerv. at his seminar
in the Institute of Classical Studies, London on June 7th, 1996. Additional recent research was
stimulated by the invitation to give a lecture, The Derveni Papyrus and Greek Enlightenment, at
the Department of Classics of New York University on November 3rd, 2016 (thanks are due to
David Sider, Mirjam Kotwick, and other colleagues who took part in the discussion) and by the
participation at the International Workshop Presocratics and Papyrological Tradition, University
of Trier, September 22nd–24th, 2016, organized by Christian Vassallo. Thanks are due to Valeria
Piano for discussing with me on this occasion the possibility of some readings in PDerv., col. IV.6.
All remaining faults are mine. The documentary apparatus of this investigation relies on innu-
merable TLG searches. Special thanks are due to Maria Pantelia who year after year provided me
with immediate assistance whenever I experienced problems with access to the TLG. And last
but not least, I wish to express my deepest gratitude to Christian Vassallo both for his patient
and accurate revision of the entire text with footnotes and bibliography, and for sharing with
me his philosophical objections (above all on the question of Prodicus’ ‘atheism’) and several
https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110666106-018
492 Andrei Lebedev
first of all to explain why we dare to take a different approach to this problem.2
The attribution of classical texts (whether anonymous or disputed) is one of the
commonly recognized tasks of classical philology, from ancient times on. Callima-
chus, in his Catalogues (Pinakes), provided information on the authenticity and
authorship of the books he described. Therefore, to dismiss a limine all attempts
to establish the author of the text under discussion (as well as of any other anon-
ymous text) is counterproductive. Some attributions remain questionable and are
accepted by few or by none (like those discussed in § [F] below), while some are
taken for certain and recognized by everybody or by most, e.g. Timotheus’ Persai
or Aristotle’s Athenaion politeia. Questionable or unlikely attributions are based
on insufficient evidence, superficial similarities, etc. We can take an attribution
seriously only when it is based on precise and unambiguous evidence, above
all on verbatim quotations from the anonymous text in ancient authors with a
direct mention of the author’s name. Apart from the verbatim quotations, refer-
ences to particular ideas, tenets, theories, etc. attested in the anonymous text
and attributed by an external source to a certain writer (as well as his interests,
specific subjects, literary habits, methodology, etc.) will also count as evidence,
with the proviso that they are not too common and widespread, but rather pecu-
liar (and best of all unique) to the supposed author. The attribution of PDerv. to
Prodicus proposed in this article meets these requirements: it is based on verbal
coincidences of peculiar phrases and terms in PDerv. and Prodicus’ fragments;
Prodicus’ peculiar theory of the origin of the names of gods and religion from
agriculture and other τέχναι ‘useful’ for human race is directly attested in PDerv.;
there is also the evidence found in both Aristophanes and Themistius that Prodi-
cus wrote an allegorical interpretation of the Orphic theogony.
The demonstration of our thesis is presented in 11 sections (§) and three
appendices (App.). After preliminary remarks on the necessary distinction of
the two types of pantheism and allegoresis in Greek thought (§ [I]) we define in
§ (II) the literary genre, the general purpose, and the hermeneutical method of
the Derveni treatise, and draw a preliminary intellectual portrait of its author
describing his peculiar features, a kind of ‘composite image.’ In § (III), we argue
for Prodicus as the author of PDerv. and present the 19 testimonia on which this
attribution is based.3 These include both the verbatim quotations with Prodicus’
name that find an exact correspondence in the text of PDerv. (hereafter Derv.T)
papyrological remarks. Unless otherwise specified, the translations of the Greek texts quoted
below are my own.
2 Th. Kouremenos ap. KPT, 58–59. The skeptical attitude is shared by Betegh (2004) 349 and
Kotwick (2017) 22, among others. We cite Janko’s new text from Kotwick (2017).
3 To these testimonia, the evidence of Xenophon in App[endix] (3) should be added.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 493
and the common peculiar features of language and style. In § (IV), we propose
a reconstruction and interpretation of the text of col. IV that contains a quota-
tion from Heraclitus. This column is of primary importance for understanding the
aims and allegorical method of the author in general, as well as for his theory of
names. In § (V), the problems of the original title and the date of the Derveni trea-
tise are addressed, as well as its relation to the psephisma of Diopeithes (432 BC).
In § (VI), the philosophical sources of Derv.T are discussed. Apart from the
Anaxagorean source of the Derveni author’s cosmology and theory of matter rec-
ognized long ago, we discuss the possible influence of Democritus while dismiss-
ing Leucippus, Diogenes of Apollonia, and the Eleatics. We point to Protagoras as
an important source of anthropology for the Derveni author and to Heraclitus as
the source of his philosophy of language (including functionalist semantics) and
criticism of popular religion. In § (VII), we briefly present our reasons for rejecting
the ascription of PDerv. to other authors (Epigenes, Stesimbrotos, Euthydemus,
Diagoras of Melos). § (VIII) expands the discussion of Prodicus’ atheistic sobri-
quet ‘Tantalos’ in § (III) by focusing on two cryptic Tantalos passages in Euripi-
des’ Orestes. Taking the torture of Anaxagoras before his trial as a historical fact
(which the new reconstruction of Philodemus’ account by Eduardo Acosta Méndez
has brought to light, and which Christian Vassallo confirms in this volume,
DAPR, T7), we interpret the tortures of Tantalos as an allusion to Anaxagoras’
trial, a cryptic commemoration of the 20th anniversary of his death, and a
makarismos of the heroic martyr of science, analogous to Euripides’ cryptic com-
memoration of Protagoras’ death in Ixion. § (IX) searches for further reflections
of the ‘avian’ theme (ὀρνίθειον in PDerv., cols. ΙΙ and VI) in Aristophanes’ Birds
and Clouds.4 It starts with the attribution of a neglected comedy fragment in the
Suda Lexicon to Aristophanes’ Seasons and connects the comic passages in the
Clouds on ἀλεκτρυών with Prodicus’ orthoepeia. The passage on ‘Persian cock’ as
a prehistoric king in Birds 481–492 is interpreted as a parody of Prodicus’ theory
of the origin of religion and civilization. § (X) discusses three ‘Heraclitizing’ pas-
sages (apart from col. IV) in cols. V, XX, and XXII, and arrives at the conclusion
that cols. V and XX contain either hidden verbatim quotations from Heraclitus or
4 Janko (2016) 21–22 questions the reading ὀ [ρ]νίθ [ε]ιον πρότερον [ in col. VI.11 (KPT) and pro-
poses φ[ο]ρτίον πρότερον [ἀείρει. This does not fit the context: the connection with prothysia is
lost, ἕνεκ[εν becomes pointless, and what is meant by the “labouring souls” remains unclear.
On the contrary, the reading ὀ[ρ]νίθ[ε]ιον (KPT) or ὀρνίθ ιον (Ferrari, followed by Piano) provides
an immediate link with the air-cosmogony and with prothysia: first offerings are due to the air,
the most ancient ‘god’. On the expression ὀρνίθειον κρέας see also Ferrari (2007) 204. But even
if the reading ὀ[ρ]νί θ[ε]ιον is by any chance incorrect, this will not affect our study of the ‘avian’
parodies of Prodicus in Aristophanes (cf. § [IX]).
494 Andrei Lebedev
paraphrases close to the original text with authentic terms and phrases, whereas
col. XXII contains a summarizing exposition of Heraclitus’ philosophy of lan-
guage and religion (the invention of polytheism by poets due to their ‘ignorance’).
In § (XI), the hypothesis that Euripides may have taken with him to Macedonia a
copy of Prodicus’ work on religion, since he quotes it in the Bacchae on which he
worked at that time, is advanced. A copy of it may have been made for the library
of Archelaus in Pella. In App. (1) we defend the traditional 5th cent. date and the
Preplatonic character of PDerv. in response to Luc Brisson’s Stoic hypothesis. App.
(2) clarifies our use of the term peritrope and explains the Derveni treatise as a
naturalistic peritrope of a religious text. App. (3) identifies a neglected reflection
of Prodicus’ benefaction theory of religion in Xenophon’ Memorabilia with paral-
lels from PDerv.
We distinguish the terms Derveni Papyrus (PDerv.) and Derveni Treatise
(Derv.T). The Derveni Papyrus is a document which we quote by the column and
line of the official edition (KPT). By the Derveni Treatise we mean the original
Sophistic text of the 5th cent. BC which can be reconstructed on the basis both
of the extant columns of PDerv. and other testimonia discussed in § (III) which
partly supplement our knowledge of the lost integral text. The Derveni treatise is
a kind of reconstructed ‘archetype’ of which the extant PDerv. is the best and most
important preserved ‘manuscript.’
In our opinion, the Derveni Papyrus has been often misread and misunder-
stood for six main reasons. (1) First, because the papyrus was falsely labeled as
‘Orphic’ in the very first report.5 (2) Second, because another misleading label –
‘Presocratic’ – was soon after that attached to its author.6 (3) Third, because
the rhetorical/grammatical terms of the Derveni author τὰ κοινά καὶ τὰ ἴδια
(sc. ὀνόματα or ῥήματα) that provide a clue for understanding his theory of lan-
guage and the origin of religion have been misunderstood as alleged ‘echoes’
of Heraclitus’ own terminology. (4) Fourth, because of the failure to distinguish
between two types of pantheism in early Greek thought, the naturalistic and the
ethico-religious. (5) Fifth, because of the failure to distinguish between two types
of allegoresis of myth: constructive (friendly and apologetical in purpose) and
deconstructive (polemical or atheistic). (6) And, last but not least, the widespread
(after Tsantsanoglou [1997]) misinterpretation of πάριμεν in PDerv., col. V as an
alleged indication of the author’s religious profession. Mistake (1) is addressed in
§ (II), mistake (3) in § (IV), mistake (5) in § (II), mistake (6) in § (XI) below. Here is
a brief explanation of what we mean by mistakes (2) and (4).
5 Kapsomenos (1964).
6 Burkert (1968).
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 495
7 Cf. Lebedev (1989a) and (2009), where one can find a summary of my views. A defence of
the ancient (and modern ante-Burnet) idealist interpretation of the metaphysics of Parmenides
and the Pythagoreans is in Lebedev (2017b) and (2017c), respectively. The validity of the term
‘Presocratiсs’ has been, with good reasons, questioned by S. Luria starting from the 1920’s (see
Luria [1970] 5 ff.) and by A. Long in his preface to The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Phi
losophy (Long [1999]). Late M. West, after reading with approval my paper in Lebedev (2009)
replied: “What you say about the Presocratics corresponds to what I have always thought.
Forty-six years ago I wrote (CQ 17, 1967, 1 n. 2): “The term ‘Presocratics’ has so established itself
that we should greatly inconvenience ourselves by abandoning it now. But it has two grave dis-
advantages: it exaggerates the effect of Socrates; and it lumps together an assortment of people,
priests, doctors, vagabond poets, experimental physicists, whose methods and intentions were
very various, and implies that they were somehow united in a common search.” (letter from
March 2nd, 2013).
496 Andrei Lebedev
8 Against the authenticity of the term τὸ ἄπειρον, cf. Lebedev (1978); mechanistic physics, Lebe-
dev (1988); vortex in cosmogony, Lebedev (2016) 597–598.
9 Philop. De aet. mund. 582.24 Rabe: πάντα θεοῦ πλήρη, πάντηι δ᾽ οἵ εἰσι ἀκουαί / καὶ διὰ πετράων
καὶ ἀνὰ χθόνα, καί τε δι᾽ αὐτοῦ / ὅττι κέκευθεν ἐνὶ στήθεσσι νόημα. Attribution to Xenophanes:
cf. Lebedev (1985a).
10 On the meaning of peritrope as polemical device see App. (2) below.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 497
order to understand these Orphic verses in light of some strange remarks the author
makes about mysteries, it has been suggested that he is an ‘enlightened’ Orphic
writing for a local Orphic community and trying to reconcile Ionian philosophy with
Orphic faith. From the Greek point of view, the Derveni author quotes not ‘Orphic
poetry,’ but a ἱερὸς λόγος. Classical authors avoid quoting Orpheus’ verses verba
tim, which is why the bulk of the extant fragments comes from late antiquity, when
the Neoplatonists made the Orphic theogony a Hellenic Bible. It is impossible to
explain col. XX simply as a criticism of superstition, by comparing it, say, with Hip-
pocratic De morbo sacro 2. The Hippocratic doctor does not attack the public cult.
The Derveni author does. In col. XX, he makes derogatory and blasphemic remarks
full of mockery and sarcasm about the mystery cults. The τέχνην ποιούμενοι τὰ ἱερά
are first of all the Orpheotelestes who charged fees for the rites of initiation. How
could an ‘Orphic’ priest or an initiate ridicule his own profession and faith?
It has been rightly pointed out that his interest in Orphic poetry is neither
grammatical nor philological.11 He does not seem to be interested in the text of
Orphic theogony as such. He is not an allegorist in the usual sense of the word,
either. Main-stream philosophical allegorism from Theagenes on has been usually
apologetic in purpose. The purpose of an allegorical interpretation is to construct
a coherent referential subtext that will exist side-by-side with the ‘surface’ text
without destroying it, and that even ‘saves’ it.12 The Derveni author does exactly
the reverse: he systematically destroys myths. He does this not because he is an
unskilled or bad interpreter, but because this is the purpose of his work. He there-
fore is not an awkward allegorist, but an intelligent and skillful irreligious ration-
alist. His allegorical interpretation of the Orpheus’ theology, similar to the natu-
ralistic meteoroleschia in Aristophanes’ Clouds and the physical gods-elements
of the philosophers mocked by Epicharmus,13 belongs to the deconstructive type.
An example of deconstructive naturalistic allegoresis of the Orphic theogony is
provided by the sixth Homilia of the ps.Clementina.14 The Christian apologists
who reduced the Hellenic gods to the elements and natural phenomena did not
want ‘to save’ them; their purpose was to exterminate them, to dismiss them as
‘just a cloud.’ Their method was anticipated by Xenophanes.15 Heraclitus’ use of
11 According to West (1983) 190, the author’s interest in the Orphic text “is wholly philosophi-
cal, not philological.”
12 Brisson (2004).
13 Lebedev (2017d).
14 See test. 19 in § (III) below.
15 21 B 32 DK (= Xen 344 Strobel/Wöhrle): ἥν τ᾽ Iριν καλέουσι, νέφος καὶ τοῦτο πέφυκε,
/ πορφύρεον καὶ φοινίκεον καὶ χλωρὸν ἰδέσθαι. This comes from a series of demythologized
pseudo-gods of the poets.
498 Andrei Lebedev
in Herodorus of Heraclea;20 and, last but not least, with Orpheus as an ancient
philosopher and onomatothetes in Plato’s Cratylus who runs a philosophical
school of his own (οἱ περὶ Ὀρφέα). The attention to hyperbaton in the exegesis of
poets is a technique that Plato associates with Protagoras.21 The Derveni author
takes the Sophistic antithesis of nomos and physis for granted and he is appar-
ently a specialist in the linguistic science of ὀρθότης τῶν ὀνομάτων. Even his
physical doctrine is Sophistic: he makes use of Anaxagorean physics, as modi-
fied by Archelaus (and possibly Democritus), who may be considered the father
of the Kulturgeschichte. In his Περὶ φύσεως, Ionian cosmogony was for the first
time supplemented by an archaeologia that discussed the origin of nomoi and of
human language.22
The Derveni author’s theory of names is of primary importance for under-
standing his hermeneutical method and his theory of the origin of religion. It is
based on the distinction between τὰ ἴδια and τὰ κοινὰ ὀνόματα or ῥήματα (see
§ [IV] below). Orpheus, who clearly saw the philosophical truth, decided, for some
reason, not to reveal it to the polloi and therefore expressed it in enigmatic poetry
(αἰνι[γμ]ατώδης col. VII.5 and αἰνίζεται passim). Presumably, he did the same
when he established the sacred rites. Instead of using plain words in common
language – the κοινὰ ὀνόματα – Orpheus obscured his message with ‘idiomatic’
or ‘peculiar’ words, τὰ ἴδια. The ‘peculiar’ words were partly invented by Orpheus
himself – these are the divine personal names. In some cases, however, Orpheus
used existing words of the current language of his time,23 but gave them unusual
meaning – these correspond to what we call ‘metaphors’. The noun μεταφορά in
a rhetorical sense is not attested before Isocrates and Aristotle; both the Derveni
author and Epigenes (who wrote on τὰ ἰδιάζοντα παρ᾽ Ὀρφεῖ, i.e. on metaphorical
or allegorical expressions) use a more archaic 5th-cent. terminology.24 The
author of Derv.T pretends to know the secret code for the correct reading of
this prototext of human civilization created by Orpheus col. ΙΧ.2–3: οἱ δὲ οὐ
γινώσκον[τες] | τὰ λεγό[μεν]α; col. XΧΙΙΙ.2: τοῖς δὲ ὀρθῶς γινώσκουσιν). His task is
to retranslate the “peculiar expessions into common,” τὰ ἴδια into τὰ κοινά: this
20 See the quotation from Clement in the previous footnote. Herodorus of Heraclea wrote τὴν
Ὀρφέως καὶ Μουσαίου ἱστορίαν (fr. 12 Fowler) and distinguished two Orpheuses and seven
Heracleses. According to this history, Orpheus was recommended to Jason by Cheiron (fr. 43
Fowler), whereas Heracles did not sail with the Argonauts at all (fr. 41 Fowler). Herodorus knew
Anaxagoras’ theory of the moon as a ‘celestial earth’ and used it in his science-fiction work about
Selenites (fr. 21 Fowler). Can he be the author of Cheiron the astronomer story as well?
21 Pl. Prt. 339a ff.
22 60 A 1; A 2; A 4.6 DK.
23 PDerv., col. XIX.9: ἐκ τῶν λεγομένων ὀνομάτων.
24 Cf. Clem. Al. Strom. 5.49 (= OF 407 + 1128).
500 Andrei Lebedev
The restricted use of etymology confirms our impression that the author is not an
allegorist in the usual sense of the term. He uses etymologies and some of them
are important for his argument, but more often he looks not for a phonetic corre-
spondence of the explanatory κοινόν with the ἴδιον, but for a functional equiva-
lence. Thus, αἰδοῖον is equated with the sun because their function is the same:
a generative principle. He explicitly states his ‘functionalist’ thesis as a general
principle of nomination in the following two passages:
a) PDerv., col. XIV.9–10: Κρόνον δὲ ὠνόμασεν ἀπὸ τοῦ | ἔ[ρ]γου αὐτὸν καὶ τἆλλα
κατὰ τ[ὸν αὐτὸν λ]όγον, “He named Kronos after his function, and all other
things (or gods) by the same principle” (i.e. “after the function of each thing”);
b) PDerv., col. XXII.1: πάν[τ᾽ οὖ]ν ὁμοίω[ς ὠ]νόμασεν ὡς κάλλιστα ἠ[δύ]νατο,
“And so, he named all things (or rather, gave all divine names) in the same
way as best as he could.” In the second passage, ὁμοίως exactly corresponds
to κατὰ τ[ὸν αὐτὸν λ]όγον in col. XX, i.e. it refers to the general principle of
the ‘functionalist’ semantics (as we will call it) and the theory of nomination
“after function” (ἀπὸ τοῦ | ἔ[ρ]γου).25
25 Therefore, the ingenious new reading πάν[τ᾽ ἀ]νομοίω[ς and interpretation proposed by Kot-
wick (2017) 94 and 302 cannot be correct. Kotwick takes ἀ]νομοίω[ς in the sense of “by different
names.” According to Kotwick, Orpheus gave many different names to the same god Air, knowing
that human nature and desire are never the same, etc. In such a case, Orpheus’ attitude towards
this variability and instabilty of human behavior and speech must be positive since he named
everything ἄριστα. But the following ll. 3–6 of col. XXII flatly contradict this conclusion: οὐδαμὰ
ταὐτά cannot be an example of ἄριστα. This lack of stability and consistency is perceived in
negative terms and even attributed to human πλεονεξία and ἀμαθία. The Derveni author con-
trasts human inconstancy and capricious wishfulness with Orpheus’ methodic exactness in
giving names to things and the gods always in accordance with the same ‘best’ principle, i.e.
‘after function.’ This principle is exemplified in the col. XXII.7–16 that follows after the moralistic
502 Andrei Lebedev
tirade: Meter was named from “giving birth” to all, Deo from “being ravaged” in congress, Rhea
from ἐκρέω, etc. In addition, to judge by the pl. 22 in KPT, three letters after παν fill the gap better
than two.
26 Cf. the list above, sub 1, 5, 11, 12, 13, 14, 21, 29, and 33.
27 Cf. Heraclit. 22 B 48 DK (= fr. 28 Lebedev): (…) ὄνομα βίος, ἔργον δὲ θάνατος; 22 B 23 DK
(= fr. 118 Lebedev): Δίκης ὄνομα vel ταῦτα (sc. ἄνομα ἔργα). In 22 B 15 DK (= fr. 148 Lebedev) the
ergon of Dionysos’ symbol (αἰδοῖον) is generation and life, but its name is death (Aides). Note
that unlike the Derveni author, Heraclitus regarded separate names of ordinary language as ‘syl-
lables’ of original natural names, i.e. of integrated pairs of opposite like life/death. For details
see Lebedev (2017a).
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 503
general utilitarian outlook: the value of something is determined only by its use,
and hence by its usefulness (τὸ ὠφέλιμον).
By translating χρῆσαι as ἀρκέσαι, the author eliminates mantic practices and
oracles (χρησμοί) as nonsense; the humorous interpretation of the oracular cave
of Night as a night-time (i.e. as a non-entity) in col. VII follows the same anti-
mantic line. By explaining the mythical Οὐρανός as the sun, and Olympus as time
(another non-entity),28 he intentionally deconstructs the divine world. The Hymn
to Zeus is a godsend for this purpose. Since Zeus is everything, and his name “for
those who understand correctly” (τοῖς ὀρθῶς γινώσκουσι) means “air,” all gods of
Greek religion are literally dissolved in the air. Air is the common referential sub-
strate of all conventional divine names (cf. Heraclit. 22 B 67 DK = fr. 43 Lebedev).
Hence the equations of the divine names in Derv.T are to be taken not as exam-
ples of mystical syncretism or sophisticated philosophical theology, but as inten-
tional deconstruction of divine personalities. The Succession myth, according to
the Derveni author, is nonsense since all its participants – Protogonos, Night,
Ouranos, Kronos, Zeus – are different names for the air, or for its constituents (hot
particles), or for the processes such as the separation of the sun. The translation
of Olympus as ‘time’ is connected with the reduction of the gods to processes:
the ‘gods’ exist not on Olympus, but ‘in time’; they are fluctuations of the air. The
conceptual framework for such etymologies is Heraclitus’ theory of the ‘univer-
sal flux’ and change of all things that Plato associates to the tandem Protagoras/
Heraclitus.
It follows that not only the mysteries, but also Greek religion as a whole is a
result of a misunderstanding, a kind of a linguistic mistake similar to a ‘disease of
language.’ The worship of the traditional gods is a result of the ignorant polloi’s
misreading of the proto-text. The referential meaning of the divine names is dif-
ferent from the meaning intended by the polloi. When they hear the name of Zeus,
they imagine the well-known anthropomorphic figure, but κατὰ φύσιν this name
refers to the air. Thus all ordinary Greeks are fools: they do not realize that they,
in fact, worship different forms of air, i.e. natural phenomena. A theory of the
original linguistic mistake of mortals that leads to even more catastrophic conse-
quences, i.e. to the origin of the phenomenal world of plurality, is attested in Par-
menides (28 B 8.53 DK).29 The Derveni author borrowed it from another source,
which he cites in col. IV. Heraclitus, along with his theory of the ambiguity of the
cosmic Logos, evidently gave the Derveni author the idea for the theory of the
linguistic mistake of mortals.30
31 See the lists in Rijlaarsdam (1978) 163–164, 236 ff., 257 ff., 271 ff., 295 ff.
32 On this point, see Baxter (1992) 62 ff., 76 ff., 167 ff.; Barney (2001) 83–98; Ademollo (2011)
278–280.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 505
37 This possibility is rightly rejected by Burkert (1968). Contra Kouremenos ap. KPT, 59.
38 Protagoras is cited nominatim together with ‘Orpheus’ and Heraclitus in Pl. Tht. 152e; the title
Περὶ τῶν οὐκ ὀρθῶς τοῖς ἀνθρώποις πρασσομένων (Diog. Laërt. 9.55) resembles the criticism of
the absurd practices and beliefs of hoi polloi in PDerv.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 507
on physics,39 his connections with Anaxagoras are well-attested,40 and his repu-
tation as an atheist was second to none:41 “This man has been corrupted either by
a book or by Prodicus.”42 After the trial of Anaxagoras and the psephisma of Dio-
peithes (432 BC), any Anaxagoreios in Athens may have looked suspicious to the
conservative public.43 His name is regularly included in the lists of atheists, and
it seems that he was a genuine philosophical atheist of the Protagorean (‘human-
ist’) extraction, but he is hardly as scandalous and iconoclastic as Diagoras in the
anecdotal tradition. In Plato’s Protagoras (315b–c) the description of Prodicus in
Callias’ house starts with a witty quotation from Homer’s Nekyia: καὶ μὲν δὴ καὶ
Τάνταλον γε εἰσεῖδον (...), “And, among others, I have noticed there Tantalos as
well (...).” In a very important and underestimated article, Charles Willink has
persuasively refuted the old interpretation (the sobriquet allegedly means “suf-
fering grievious pains” and alludes to the poor condition of Prodicus’ health)44
and explained it as a mythical paradigm of the “hybristic audacity” of a “cosmo-
logical blasphemer”45 like that of the meteorosophistai satirized in Aristophanes’
Clouds with Prodicus as their prince and arch-sophist.
The texts of Themistius and Aristophanes cited below leave no doubt that he
discussed in his works “the rituals of Orpheus” (Ὀρφέως τελεταί) and proposed a
‘meteorosophistic’ interpretation of the Orphic Theogony. Prodicus is the common
39 Test. 61–66 Mayhew. Note that Prodicus’ ‘physics’ pays attention to etymology and the ‘cor-
rectness of names’. Galen (test. 64–66 Mayhew) rebukes Prodicus for his deviation from the com-
mon usage and ‘innovations’ in the use of names (ἐν τοῖς ὀνόμασι [...] καινοτομίαν). Cf. § (B),
test. (T10) below. According to Aulus Gellius (15.20.4), Euripides was a pupil of Anaxagoras and
Prodicus.
40 Aeschin. Socr. (SSR VI A 73) ap. Ath. 5.62.220a–b (= Prodic. test. 30 Mayhew). Aeschines in
his Callias mocks Prodicus and Anaxagoras as ‘Sophists’ and immoral teachers corrupting the
young. It seems that Aeschines re-addresses the accusations of ‘atheism’ and corruption of the
young raised against Socrates to Prodicus and Anaxagoras.
41 See Henrichs (1975) 107 ff., a re-edition of the testimonium to Prodicus in Philodemus’ On
Piety, PHerc. 1428, (1976), and (1984a); Willink (1983) 25–27; Burkert (1985) 313–315; Scholten
(2003) 132 ff.; Mayhew (2011) xvii and 91; Bett (2013) 299–303; Roubekas (2017) 39–42. Reser-
vations about Prodicus’‘atheism’ have been recently expressed by Kouloumentas (2018) and
Vassallo (2018a); cf. also Sedley (2013) 141 and Winiarczyk (2016) 66, who ignore, however, the
‘Tantalos’ paradigm and the important work of Willink (1983). Prodicus did not begin to be re-
garded as an ‘atheist’ by the time of Cicero; he was nicknamed ‘Tantalos’ (= godless hybristes)
already by his contemporaries.
42 Ar. (Τηγανισταί) fr. 506 PCG (ex Schol. [VE] in Ar. Nub. 361a = Prodic. test. 5 Mayhew): τοῦτον
τὸν ἄνδρ’ ἢ βιβλίον διέφθορεν / ἢ Πρόδικος ἢ τῶν ἀδολεσχῶν εἷς γέ τις.
43 For doxographical testimonia to Anaxagoras’ alleged ‘atheism’ from papyri, see Vassallo’s
DAPR in this volume.
44 Willink (1983) 30.
45 Willink (1983) 31 ff.
508 Andrei Lebedev
source of the passages from Themistius, Aristophanes (Clouds and Birds), Plato’s
Cratylus, Euripides’ Bacchae, and other testimonia discussed below.
Testimonia (1) – (18) which support the attribution of PDerv. to Prodicus of Ceos
(T1) Plato [I]
46 See Rijlaarsdam (1978) 35 ff., 117 ff., 194 ff. The thesis οὐκ ἔστι ἀντιλέγειν (cf. Pl. Cra. 429d–e:
ἆρα ὅτι ψευδῆ λέγειν τὸ παράπαν οὐκ ἔστι, κτλ.) is explicitly ascribed to Prodicus by Didymus
the Blind: see Prodicus’ test. 60 Mayhew (with comm. by Mayhew [2013] 153–159); Binder/Liesen-
borghs (1976) 453–462.
47 Pl. Cra. 384b (= Prodic. test. 42 Mayhew).
48 Mansfeld (1983)’s identification of Plato’s source as Hippias cannot be correct since: Hippias
is the least philosophical of all the Sophists; the relativist theory of flux and sophisticated episte-
mology are a priori unlikely for him; in the parallel passages of Pl. Tht. 152e and 160d, Protagoras,
not Hippias, is mentioned. Protagoras was never associated with Hippias but was often connect-
ed with his disciple Prodicus. Mansfeld, however, rightly postulates a Sophistic source for the
‘Heraclitizing’ passages in Cratylus and Theaetetus. This source is most probably Prodicus and/
or Protagoras himself, who quoted Heraclitus with approval of his criticism of popular religion.
49 In Lebedev (2014) 22 the source of Plato is identified with Heraclitus and Pl. Cra. 408c2 (οἶσθα
ὅτι ὁ λόγος τὸ πᾶν σημαίνει κτλ.) is included in Probabilia, fr. 3 Lebedev. The fanciful etymology
of Pan may be Plato’s own, but the identification of Logos with the Universe is typically Heraclite-
an: it is based on Heraclitus’ metaphor of common logos or liber naturae in fr. 2 Lebedev (= 22 B 1
DK) and fr. 1 Lebedev (= 22 B 50 DK), on which see Lebedev (2017a).
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 509
(T2) Euripides
is the most plausible common source of Plato and Euripides. The cosmic αἰθήρ
(= air) in Euripides is always a reference to Anaxagoras’ cosmology; Zeus and
Hera in this passage are apparently allegorized as Air and Earth. In PDerv. Zeus is
air and Hera is earth (cf. cols. XVII.4 and XXII.7).
(T3) Themistius
εἰ δὲ καὶ Διόνυσον καλοῖμεν καὶ νύμφας καὶ Δήμητρος κόρην ὑέτιόν τε Δία καὶ Ποσειδῶνα
φυτάλμιον, πλησιάζομεν ἤδη ταῖς τελεταῖς καὶ τὴν Προδίκου σοφίαν τοῖς λόγοις ἐγκατα-
μίξομεν, ὃς ἱερουργίαν πᾶσαν ἀνθρώπων καὶ μυστήρια καὶ πανηγύρεις καὶ τελετὰς τῶν
γεωργίας καλῶν ἐξάπτει, νομίζων καὶ θεῶν ἔννοιαν ἐντεῦθεν εἰς ἀνθρώπους ἐλθεῖν καὶ
πᾶσαν εὐσέβειαν ἐγγυώμενος. οὐ μὴν οὐδὲ Ὀρφέως τελετάς τε καὶ ὄργια γεωργίας ἐκτὸς
συμβέβηκεν εἶναι, ἀλλὰ καὶ ὁ μῦθος τοῦτο αἰνίττεται, πάντα κηλεῖν τε καὶ θέλγειν τὸν Ὀρφέα
λέγων, ὑπὸ τῶν καρπῶν τῶν ἡμέρων ὧν γεωργία παρέχει πᾶσαν ἡμερῶσαι φύσιν καὶ θηρίων
δίαιταν, καὶ τὸ ἐν ταῖς ψυχαῖς θηριῶδες ἐκκόψαι καὶ ἡμερῶσαι. καὶ τὰ θηρία γὰρ τῷ μέλει
κηλεῖν κτλ.
Let the gods who oversee agriculture be summoned to help me with my oration (…) For
it is from the fruits of agriculture that they receive yearly recompense – drink-offerings,
sacrifices, banquets and all the Hours cause to spring up from the earth – and they receive
this recompense not only for helping mankind on oratory, but from everything that human
beings have from the high. If we should also summon Dionysos, the nymphs, Demeter’s
daughter (sc. Persephone), the rain-bringing Zeus and nourishing Poseidon, than we shall
be within short range of the rites and add a dose of Prodicus’ wisdom to our eloquence.
Prodicus makes all of mankind’s religious ceremonies, mysteries, festivals, and rites
dependent on the blessings of agriculture. He thinks that even the idea of gods came to
human beings from agriculture and he makes agriculture the guarantee of all piety. Not
even the rites and mystic ceremonies of Orpheus are unconnected with agriculture but the
myth about Orpheus also hints to this in enigmatic form, namely that it was through cul-
tivated fruits provided by agriculture that Orpheus tamed the whole nature and the diaita
(i.e. way of life and nutrition) of wild beasts and eradicated and tamed the bestial element
in the souls. Indeed, he was believed to enchant wild beasts by his music conducting all
sacrifices and rites in honor of the gods using the fruits of agriculture.55
After this passage, Themistius presents Orpheus as the greatest culture hero
who taught the art of agriculture to all nations of οἰκουμένη, and in turn, this
development triggered the transition to sedentary life, the rise of civilization, the
emergence of laws and justice, etc. Diels/Kranz print under Prodicus’ 84 B 5 DK
from Themistius only the words πλησιάζομεν (...) ἐγγυώμενος; Mayhew (test. 77)
expands the preceding context, but he also cuts the quotation at ἐγγυώμενος.
This emendation is based on the assumption that at this point Themistius stops
quoting “Prodicus’ wisdom,” i.e. his agricultural theory of the origin of religion,
and adduces a new piece of evidence, the myth of Orpheus the musician, unre-
lated with Prodicus. But in the preceding text, “Prodicus’ wisdom” is connected
with τελεταί, so in the text set in bold he rather states that what Prodicus explic-
itly said in his theory of the origin of religion is also in an enigmatic form “hinted
by” traditional myth (καὶ ὁ μῦθος), which means that Prodicus himself referred
to or discussed Orpheus’ teletai and Orphic mysteries as providing evidence in
support of his theory of religion.56 The identification of Dionysos with wine,
of Demeter with bread, of Poseidon with water are attested for Prodicus by the
consensus of Philodemus and Sextus (84 B 5 [I, III] DK).57 The reference to Dio-
nysos and Demeter in combination with mystery cults (μυστήρια) and initiations
(τελεταί) is sufficient to conclude that Prodicus discussed the Eleusinian and
Orphic (i.e. Bacchic) mysteries in his work on the origin of religion. If we accept
Henrichs’ reinterpretation of Philodemus, according to which Prodicus added
deified benefactors (πρῶτοι εὑρεταί) of the human race to “things beneficial for
human life” (τὰ ὀφελοῦντα τὸν βίον), the characterization of Orpheus as the first
agriculturalist in Themistius may also derive from Prodicus.58
Prodicus’ theory of the origin of religion from agriculture (and other “useful”
τέχναι) is directly attested in PDerv., col. XXIV, which comments on the Οrphic
verse about the moon (l. 3: “ἡ πολλοῖς φαίνει μερόπεσσι ἐπ᾽ ἀπείρονα γαῖαν”):
56 Mayhew’s skepticism about the authenticity of Themistius’ reference to mysteries, orgia, fes-
tivals, and teletai in Prodicus’ work is unjustified. The uniqueness of evidence may call for sus-
picion in the legal sphere, but not in the evaluation of historical or literary sources. Themistius’
reference is precise and concrete and is paralleled by a plausible reference to it in Plutarch’s De
Daedalibus Plataeensibus (frs. 157–158 Sandbach), see below. Incidentally, Greek agrarian festi-
vals (like those of Dionysos) or mysteries of Demeter provided more abundant and persuasive
evidence on the connection between religion and agriculture than, say, the Orphic theogony or
the poetic myth of Orpheus the singer. Even on a priori grounds, Prodicus could not miss such
opportunity. And this explains why it is Demeter and Dionysos who have a prominent place in
Prodicus’ theory of religion as cases at point.
57 Note the agriculturally relevant epikleseis of Zeus the Rain-giver (Hyetios) and Poseidon the
Nourishing (Phytalmios).
58 Nestle (1976) 439 compares Min. Fel. Oct. 2.21, errando (on ‘wandering’ benefactors), and
concludes that Orpheus was included in Prodicus’ list of deified inventors.
512 Andrei Lebedev
(…) he would not say “to many” (but to “all together”), i.e. to those who cultivate
the land and those who are engaged in navigation, [signalling] to them the hour
when the navigation starts. For if there were no moon, humans would have
discovered neither the number of the seasons nor the number of the winds (…)
nor all the rest (…)
The Derveni author starts col. XXIV with an interpretation of the epithet of the
moon ἰσομελής (hapax) that must have appeared in the verse from the Orphic
theogony quoted in the lost lower part of the preceding column, and he takes it in
the sense of “circular” on the grounds that only circular objects when “measured
from the center” (i.e., the distance to the periphery) have “equal limbs” on all
sides. Martin West suggests that the lost verse was similar to Parmenides’ 28 B
8.44 DK (μέσσοθεν ἰσοπαλές) and reads μέσσοθεν ἰσομελής. This reading remains
attractive, although it cannot be proved. In any case, the reference to the circu-
lar shape of the full moon is plausible. An objection against this interpretation
argues that adjectives ending with -μελής in Greek always refer to “stretched”
limbs. But this is untenable. In fact, in the poetic language, μέλη (plur.) can be
used as a pluralis poeticus for the whole body rather than for some “stretched”
parts of the body: cf. e.g. Parmenides’ 28 B 16.1 DK, where the expression κρᾶσιν
μελέων πολυπλάγκτων, “the mixture (i.e. composition) of much-wandering (i.e.
constantly changing) limbs (i.e. body),” refers to the condition of the body, not of
some limbs, and the Homeric epithet of Eros λυσιμελής, “relaxing limbs,” refers
to the relaxation of the whole body regardless of its shape.
The commentator also doubts the (rather obvious) meaning of the verse about
the moon that “shines,” i.e. is the source of light, “for many,” on the grounds
that in this case, one would expect “shines to all” rather than “to many.” Instead,
he interprets φαίνω as allegedly elliptical for φαίνειν τὴν ὥραν “to show (i.e. to
indicate) the appropriate hour” for starting various activities: that is, he tries to
connect it with the phases of the moon and the telling of time. The word “many”
59 We follow the subtle suggestion of Kotwick (2016) 3. The distinction between many and all
refers to τεχνίται, on the one hand, and to all humanity indiscriminately, on the other.
60 PDerv., col. XXIV.7–12.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 513
(T4) Aristophanes [I]
Cf. Ar. Nub. 828: Δῖνος βασιλεύει τὸν Δί’ ἐξεληλακώς. The text of PDerv., col.
XVIII.1–3 runs as follows:
(...) and the things that move down. By saying [“Moira” he means] the [vortex]
and all the rest in the air which is wind. It is this wind that Orpheus called Moira.
The supplement τήνδ[ε γῆν] in col. XVIII.1, proposed by KPT and accepted by
Bernabé, is unlikely. First, because teste TLG, all instances of this phrase in clas-
sical authors come from tragedy, there is not a single instance of ἥδε γῆ, τῆς δὲ
γῆς or τὴνδε γῆν in prose, either in classical or in late prose.63 Α possible phrase
for “this earth” in Greek prose would be τὴν γῆν τήνδε (τῆς γῆς τῆσδε)64 or τὴνδε
τὴν γῆν,65 but never τὴνδε γῆν which is an exclusively tragic idiom. And second,
in most cases, ἡ γῆ ἥδε means “this land” rather than “this earth” and refers
to the polis or region in which the speaker is located in drama, like Athens or
Corinth, but such a meaning does not fit the context of Derv.T at all. It is conceiv-
able that in astronomical and cosmological contexts, “this earth” might refer to
“our” planet earth as distinguished from another similar planet, but there is no
indication in the text of the papyrus that the Derveni author shared either Philo-
laus’ eccentric cosmology of two earths66 or the Ionian theory of innumerable
worlds in the infinite universe, each with its own earth, sun, moon, etc.67 The
most plausible reading that perfectly fits the context is τὴν δ[ίνην], the cosmogo-
nical vortex of the Anaxagorean (and Ionian in general) physics.68 Vortex is a
form of wind, and wind is air in motion, hence the mention of wind (πνεῦμα)
and air in the next l. 2.69 According to the Ionian mechanics of the vortex, heavy
63 For τήνδε γῆν TLG gives ten classical occurrences: seven from Euripides, two from Sophocles,
and one from Aeschylus. There are many more (50) instances of the genitive τῆσδε γῆς: 28 in
Euripides, 13 in Sophocles, nine in Aeschylus, and none from prose.
64 Hdt. 6.107.
65 Dem. 60.8.
66 Arist. fr. 204 Rose (= Simpl. In Cael. 511.25 Heiberg): μετὰ δὲ τῆν ἀντίχθονα ἡ γῆ ἥδε φερομένη
καὶ αὐτὴ περὶ τὸ μέσον, κτλ.
67 Theoretically, the Derveni author could share the latter theory since it is attested in Anaxago-
ras’ 59 B 4 DK, which describes extraterrestrials in a cosmos different from ours, apparently in
a distant part of the infinite universe. But the cosmogonical context in PDerv., col. XVIII in any
case has nothing to do with the theory of innumerable worlds. In late prose (Dionysius of Hali-
carnassus, Cassius Dio, Flavius Josephus, and others), the expression “this earth” is used as a
synonym of οἰκουμένη, without antithesis to “another earth,” but these contexts are historical,
geographical, and ethnographical, and cannot be compared with col. XVIII.
68 I have proposed this supplement in my 1993 Princeton conference paper, and I am glad that
Walter Burkert and Richard Janko (ap. KPT, 227) arrived independently at the same conclusion.
In Janko (2001) 27, the reading is that of KPT. I am also glad that Piano (2016) 9 confirmed by au-
topsy the supplement κόσ]μου which I proposed behind the iron curtain in Lebedev (1989b) 39.
69 Betegh (2004)’s objection (p. 378) that a vortex cannot be “in the air” is futile. See e.g. Plut.
De Is. et Os. 373d4 ff.: αὐχμῶν δ᾽ ἐν ἀέρι καὶ πνευμάτων ἀτόπων, αὖθις τε πρηστήρων κτλ., “[Seth
is the cause] of droughts in the air, as well as enormous winds and hurricans (vel tornados)”;
Antiph. fr. 29 Pendrick (= 87 B 29 DK): ὅταν οὖν γένωνται ἐν τῷ ἀέρι ὄμβροι τε καὶ πνεύματα
ὑπεναντία ἀλλήλοις, τότε συστρέφεται τὸ ὕδωρ (...) καὶ συνεστράφη ὑπό τε τοῦ πνεύματος
εἰλλόμενον (...). Exactly as in PDerv., πνεῦμα in such contexts means “wind,” not “breath.” An-
tiphon explains the formation of hail (cf. Pendrick [2002] comm. ad loc.), but similar language
is used by the Hippocratic author of Aer. 8 in the explanation of the formation of rain (ὁκόταν δέ
κου ἀθροισθῇ καὶ ξυστραφῇ ἐς τὸ αὐτὸ ὑπὸ ἀνέμων κτλ.). It could be used in the description of
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 515
bodies move to the center of the vortex, and light ones move to the perifery: this
explanation fits perfectly with καὶ τὰ κάτω [φερό]μενα in l. 1. The conjunction
καί presupposes τὰ ἄνω φερόμενα in the preceding lines. In col. XVII, the author
interpreted the ‘Hymn to Zeus’ in terms of Anaxagorean cosmogony. In Anaxago-
ras’ cosmogony the operation of the Nous (identified by the Derveni author with
Zeus) produces a vortex.
We take πνεῦμα as “wind,” not as “breath” or “air” in general. The expres-
sion ἐν τῶι ἀέρι [πνε]ῦμα (XVIII.2) is a translation into κοινά of the ‘idiomatic’
expression μοῖρα Διός. The link between Μοῖραν | ἐπικλῶσαι (XVIII.3–4) and the
air-cosmogony is transparent: both κλώθω and δινέω mean “to spin”; the author
most likely interprets “the spinning of Moira” as “whirling of wind.” Moira and
ananke pertain to the same semantic field and are often associated with each
other (cf. PDerv., col. XXV.7). The identification of δίνη and μοῖρα may be com-
pared with Democritus ap. Diog. Laërt. 9.45: πάντα τε κατ’ ἀνάγκην γίνεσθαι,
τῆς δίνης αἰτίας οὔσης τῆς γενέσεως πάντων, ἣν ἀνάγκην λέγει.70 The concept of
Nous/Vortex determining the past, present, and future derives from Anaxagoras
(59 B 12 DK). It is obvious that δίνη is intended as an etymon of Δία. Taking into
account the uniqueness of this etymology, we can identify Ar. Nub. 380 and 828
as quotations from Derv.T.
PDerv., col. XVIII also contains a remarkable parallel to the ‘linguistic mistake’
theory of the origin of religion in Tiresias’ logos. According to the Derveni author,
when Orpheus said Ζεὺς ἐγένετο, “Zeus happened,” he meant that a cosmogon-
ical vortex started in the air; people misunderstood his words (οὐ γινώσκοντ]ες
τὰ λεγόμενα, XVIII.14) and decided that someone called “Zeus” was “born.” As
a result of this misunderstanding, an anthropomorphic pseudo-god Zeus is still
worshipped by the Greeks. In fact, they worship a cosmogonical vortex in the air
(which is identical with the cosmic mind, φρόνησις) and when they say Μοῖραν
ἐπικλῶσαι (XVΙΙI.4), they erroneously think of a mythical Moira, the spinner; the
original – and the correct – meaning (= whirlwind in the air) intended by Orpheus
has been forgotten, so they use the correct words without understanding their
meaning: λέγοντες μὲν ὀρθῶς, οὐκ εἰδότες δέ (XVIII.5).
the formation of world-masses with equal success. In his comment on Antiph. fr. 29 Pendrick,
Galen (in Epid. 3.33, p. 17a681 Kühn = pp. 128.5–9, 129.1–8 Wenkelbach) overstates his thesis that
εἰλούμενον means “is condensed” and nothing else. The verb συστρέφεσθαι makes it clear that
the connotation of “rolling” and “winding” is also present; on συστροφή “whirlwind,” see LSJ
s.v. II, 3.
70 = 68 A 1 DK. Ἀνάγκη is a buzzword and a fundamental concept in Democritus’ cosmogony
and mechanics: see the texts 22–30 collected by Luria (1970) 33–35 under the heading Necessitas
naturalis.
516 Andrei Lebedev
(T5) Aristophanes [II]
There are more parallels between PDerv. and Aristophanes’ Clouds. See, first of all,
PDerv., col. XIX.14–15: ἀρχὸν δὲ [ἁπάντων ἔφη εἶναι α]ὐτὸν | [ὅτι πάντα ἄρ]χεται
διὰ [τοῦτον κτλ. This is one of the earliest attestations of what has become later
the standard philosophical etymology of the name of Zeus Δία = διά: Zeus is a
universal causa activa that determines everything.
The cosmogonical motif of the “vortex” reappears twice in col. XXIII.11:
“ἶνας δ᾽ ἐγκατ[έλε]ξ᾽ Ἀχελωΐου ἀργυ[ρ]οδίνε[ω.”] | τῶ[ι] ὕδα[τι] ὅλ[ως τίθη]σι
Ἀχελῶιον ὄνομ[α. ὅ]τι δὲ | τὰ[ς] δίνα[ς ἐγκαταλ]έξαι ἐστ[ι ]δε ἐγκατῶ[σ]αι .
The commentator takes Achelous as a general term for the element of water and
reinterprets ἐγκαταλ]έξαι71 “built in” as ἐγκατῶσαι “threw down,” i.e. Zeus/Air
“pushed down water by vortex.” This is a plausible source of Ar. Nub. 376–381:
ΣΩ. ὅταν ἐμπλησθῶσ᾽ ὕδατος πολλοῦ κἀναγκασθῶσι φέρεσθαι (sc. Νεφέλαι) /
κατακριμνάμεναι πλήρεις ὄμβρου δι᾽ ἀνάγκην, εἶτα βαρεῖαι / εἰς ἀλλήλας
ἐμπίπτουσαι ῥήγνυνται καὶ παταγοῦσιν. / ΣΤ. ὁ δ᾽ ἀναγκάζων ἐστὶ τίς αὐτάς – οὐχ
ὁ Ζεύς; – ὥστε φέρεσθαι; / ΣΩ. ἥκιστ᾽, ἀλλ᾽ αἰθέριος Δῖνος. ΣΤ. Δῖνος; τουτί μ᾽
ἐλελήθει, / ὁ Ζεὺς οὐκ ὤν, ἀλλ᾽ ἀντ᾽ αὐτοῦ Δῖνος νυνὶ βασιλεύων.
There can be little doubt that Dinos/Zeus derives from the same Sophistic
source as ἀμέτρητ’ Ἀήρ (v. 264) and the whole ‘atheistic’ meteoroleschia of the
Clouds. This source is almost certainly Prodicus of Ceos who is mentioned by name
in v. 361 as a king of meteorosophistai second only to Socrates.72 Nephelai would
not believe any other meteorosophistes except Prodicus because he surpasses all
other sophists in wisdom and judgement: οὐ γὰρ ἂν ἄλλῳ γ᾽ ὑπακούσαιμεν τῶν
νῦν μετεωροσοφιστῶν / πλὴν ἢ Προδίκῳ, τῷ μὲν σοφίας καὶ γνώμης οὕνεκα, κτλ.
(vv. 360–361).
It has been thought by some that the cryptic allusions to mysteries and
initiation in the text of the comedy are connected with the Eleusinian myster-
ies.73 However, we should rule out a limine the possibility that Aristophanes is
mocking the Eleusinian mysteries. The language of mysteries and initiation in
Aristophanes is a metaphorical code that exclusively belongs to the iconic, and
not to the referential, level of text.74 On the referential level, we have the target
of these allusions: Socrates and Prodicus, who represent all sophists and the
new education perceived as a danger to traditional religion and morality. The
75 This is a unique metaphor in Aristophanes: cf. Taillardat (1962) 287 and 507.
76 Ar. Nub. 331 ff. This is an exact parallel to the birds, the new gods in Aristophanes’ Birds, who
claim to be the source of beneficial things for humans.
77 Ar. frs. 583–584 PCG. Cf. Mayhew (2011) 247–248.
78 On this point, see Reesor (1983).
79 Dover (1968) xlix ff.
80 Contra Janko (2001) 13, who tries to revive the implausible hypothesis of Winspear/Silverberg
(1960) 11 ff.
81 This was corrected by Willink (1983) 26: “(…) the arch-sophistic ‘Socrates’ satirised in the play
is in several features (e.g. fee-taking, philological quibbling, heretical cosmology) specifically
modelled on what we may take as to have been the popular view of arch-sophist Prodikos.”
518 Andrei Lebedev
“grotesque anticlimax” (vv. 359–363),82 the Clouds assure Socrates that they
would not listen to any other “meteorosophist” except Prodicus and Socrates,
the former because of his wisdom and judgment, and the latter because of his
meaningless wanderings barefoot through the streets as he endured all kinds of
discomfort. Prima facie this anticlimax looks like a comical absurdity, but behind
it lurks Aristophanes’ excuse for ascribing the cosmological ‘wisdom’ of Prodicus
to Socrates. It is Prodicus who has knowledge of this science and is the leading
‘meteorosophist’; Socrates is just an uneducated and wretched vagabond. The
image of an ἄστεγος vagabond enduring evils (κακά) is an allusion to the popular
Socratic motif of καρτερία, i.e. to Socrates’ ethics, and not to a physical doctrine
he never held, whereas the alleged ‘ignorance’ of Socrates may be Aristophanes’
mocking parody of Socrates’ thesis ἓν οἶδα ὅτι οὐδὲν οἶδα.
(T6) Aristophanes [III]
690 ἵν᾽ ἀκούσαντες πάντα παρ᾽ ἡμῶν ὀρθῶς περὶ τῶν μετεώρων,
φύσιν οἰωνῶν γένεσίν τε θεῶν ποταμῶν τ᾽ Ἐρέβους τε Χάους τε
εἰδότες ὀρθῶς, παρ’ ἐμοῦ Προδίκῳ κλάειν εἴπητε τὸ λοιπόν.
(...) you (= humans) will hear from us everything in the correct way about celestial
things, / the nature of birds, the origin of gods, as well as of rivers, of the Chaos
and Erebos, / and once you know all this correctly, you may tell Prodicus to weep
for the rest of his life.
The Birds’ cosmogony is with good reason included in the editions of Orphica
as early evidence of the Attic version of the Orphic theogony with the primeval
Nyx (rather than Kronos as in the Rhapsodies), who produces the world-egg from
which the firstborn god (Eros) comes out. But it would be preposterous to take
this text as a parody of ‘Orpheus’ theogony’ itself. First, mocking a Hieros logos
in Athens after the psephisma of Diopeithes was a risky enterprise, and second,
the emphatic mention of Prodicus from the start is left unaccounted for and
unintelligible. Since we know now that Prodicus wrote an allegorical naturalistic
interpretation of Orphic theogony, we must admit that the target of Aristophanes’
agonistic mockery is Prodicus’ allegorical interpretation of the Orphic theogony
rather than the Orphic theogony itself.83 It is hard to imagine that a rather tra-
ditional poet could mock a Hieros logos in his system of values. And it is only
natural that he ridicules an ‘atheistic’ interpretation of a Hieros logos.
The birds’ version of the origin of the world and their ‘ornithological’ explana-
tion of the origin of gods (agonistically counterposed to Prodicus’ ‘meteorosophis-
tic’ version) and of the meaning of the Orphic cosmic ‘egg’ will surpass Prodicus in
their alleged “correct understanding” (ὀρθῶς εἰδέναι). Thus, one may forget about
Prodicus’ history of the human race and his theory of the origin of religion allegedly
supported by the ‘evidence’ of the ‘ancient poetry’ of Orpheus. The adverb ὀρθῶς,
correctly, is emphatically repeated twice; it alludes to Prodicus’ terminology and
his claims of correctness, ὀρθότης: the phrase εἰδότες ὀρθῶς in Av. 692 looks like
a quotation of ὀρθῶς γινώσκουσιν in PDerv., col. XXIII.2. Aristophanes knew and
perfectly understood that Prodicus’ playful interpretation of Orphic theogony as
an alleged ancient proof of Anaxagoras’ physiologia was a hoax and a mockery of
religious conservatives like Diopeithes. In this case, the purpose of his mock cos-
mogony was to surpass Prodicus in mockery and to ridicule the Sophistic Kultur
geschichte, thus defending the traditional values of an ordinary Athenian. Mayhew,
with a very good reason, criticizes DK for underestimating the importance of the
chorus’ parabasis in Birds as evidence for Prodicus’ doctrines. Therefore, he prints
under test. 69 the vv. 685–725 that expand the cosmogony in a narrow sense by
preceding vv. 585–589 (the original miserable condition of humanity) and fol-
lowing Prodicus’ appearance in vv. 693–722 that, apart from theogony, contain a
parody of Prodicus’ ‘utilitarian’ theory of religion. We understand these verses as
follows: after you hear our Theogony, you may say goodbye to Prodicus’ version.
Prodicus’ Horai are parodied in the context of Ar. Av. 708 ff.:
And the greatest things for mortals are from us, the birds. / First, we make known
the seasons: spring, winter, and summer; / when migrating to Libya, the crane
cries “Sow your seeds” / – and tells the shipowner “Time to hang up your rudder
and sleep” – etc.84
The “greatest things” (τὰ μέγιστα) in this context are synonymous with the
“most useful things.” According to Prodicus’ theory of the origin of religion,
humans first deified τὰ ὠφελοῦντα, things beneficial for the human race; the
elements, the sun and the moon, which are indispensable for agriculture. PDerv.,
col. XXIV describes the usefulness of the moon for telling time and recognizing
the seasons: without the moon, agriculture and navigation would be impossi-
ble. The choir of the birds, after announcing a competition with Prodicus, claims
that thumans have been taught by the ‘signals’ that the birds sent to them to
recognize the seasons; without birds, there would be no agriculture and naviga-
tion. Exactly the same crafts are mentioned in exactly the same order in PDerv.,
col. XXIV.8–9. The hyponoia of this in Aristophanes’ Birds is: the utility of birds
for the human race far surpasses that of the traditional gods and of Prodicus’
“useful things,” therefore the birds win the agon with Prodicus, and they should
be deified for their utility and proclaimed new gods. A number of other useful
crafts accomplished by birds’ signals is adduced in the following lines: the crane
signals when to weave (ὑφαίνειν) a winter cloak, “the kite appears after this to
make known the change of season (ἑτέραν ὥραν), / when it’s the season to shear
(πεκτεῖν) the sheep’s wool, in spring; then the swallow / appears when it’s nec-
essary to exchange (πωλεῖν) the winter cloak and buy (πρίασθαι) some summer
clothes.”85 The birds are equally indispensable for trade, for acquiring the means
to live, and for man’s marriage.86 None of these crafts (except agriculture and
navigation) is attested nominatim either in Prodicus or in PDerv., but this may
be due to chance and the fragmentary state of our sources. Themistius’ enco-
mium of agriculture ascribes the theory that agriculture is the cradle of religion,
civilization, and all human crafts to Prodicus. It is hardly accidental that in the
birds’ competition with Prodicus, different crafts are correlated with different
“Seasons” (Ὧραι).
The protogonos Eros “similar to the windy whirlwinds” (εἰκὼς ἀνεμώκεσι
δίναις) in v. 697 alludes to the cosmogonical vortex and connects the ‘ornithogony’
of the Birds with the ‘cosmology’ of the Clouds.
(T7) Aristophanes [IV]
The very idea of ‘surpassing’ Prodicus’ allegorical cosmogony in the comical agon
in Aves by substituting the natural elements with the image of ‘birds,’ the new
gods of the dream city of eternal happiness, more powerful and more ‘beneficial’
for the human race than Zeus and the Olympians, seems to have been suggested
to Aristophanes by another passage of Derv.T (Prodicus), i.e. col. II in which we
propose some new readings:
And besides that (sc. besides honouring Erinyes), one should offer exceptional
honours to Metis and burn something avian. And he (sc. Orpheus) added hymns
[or poems] that suit the music, but their meaning escapes (sc. those who lack
understanding) etc.
The reading τ[ῆι Εὐμεν]ίδι at the beginning of l. 7 proposed by KPT is unlikely for
two reasons. First, such a “collective singular” (KPT, 144) is unlikely as such and
is nowhere attested. Second, honouring Erinyes has already been mentioned in
the preceding lines, and this fact makes ἔτι, “and besides that,” pointless. In ll.
6–7, the author adds to the honouring of Erinyes the honouring of yet another
(ἔτι ~ καί) daimon and the requirement of avian offerings to all daimones (i.e. not
only Erinyes/Eumenides). It is hard to find a more plausible name of a daimon
ending on -ιδι in the dative than Metis attested in col. XV.13: Μῆτιν κάπ[πιεν ἠδὲ
λάβ]εν88 βασιληίδα τιμ[ήν], “[Zeus] swallowed Wisdom (Metis) and received the
royal honor.”
The author of the Derveni theogony (Onomacritus, according to Aristotle)
borrowed from Hesiod the epithet of Zeus μητίετα which is attested in PDerv.,
col. XV.6 and 11. It is hard to see why he could not borrow the kataposis of Metis
in Hes. Theog. 886–900 as well. The phrase βασιληίδα τιμ[ήν (XV.13) quotes Hes.
Theog. 892.89 He adapts it to the Orphic narrative: Zeus follows the prophecy of
Night and Kronos rather than that of Ouranos and Gaia, and Metis is not just a
personification of Wisdom and not Zeus’ “first wife” (Rhea/Demeter in col. XXII),
but one of the names of the daimon Protogonos.
87 The supplements κ[αὶ τῆι Μήτ]ιδι in l. 7 and ἔλαθε το]ὺς in l. 9 are ours, the rest by KPT.
88 κάπ[πιεν Kotwick (2017) 324 : κάπ[πινεν Santamaría (2012) 71 : ἠδὲ λάβ]εν vel ἠδ᾽ ἔλαβ]εν
temptavi.
89 Contra KPT, 213, who are on this point vague and indecisive.
522 Andrei Lebedev
It is tempting to take ὀρνίθ ειόν τι in col. II.7 as a reference to the egg.90 The
Derveni author must have discussed the cosmogonical egg from which Protogonos
“sprouted first” in the lost parts of the papyrus. It has been preserved in Aristo-
phanes’ ornithogony:91 the Derveni author may have allegorically interpreted it
as an Anaxagorean mixture of various ‘seeds’ of all things (a similar naturalistic
interpretation of the Orphic egg can be found in the ps.Clementina).92
Avian offerings are for the second time mentioned in col. VI.8–11: “Mystai
perform preliminary sacrifice (προθύουσι) to Eumenides in the same way
as magoi, for Eumenides are souls (ψυχα[ὶ). For this reason (vel therefore, ὧν
ἕνεκ[εν) one who is going to sacrifice to gods [would] first offer something avian
(ὀ[ρ]νίθ[ε]ιον) etc.” Why is the identification of Eumenides/Erinyes with the souls
presented as a necessary reason to sacrifice first “something avian”? This prima
facie strange inference can be explained only on the grounds of the allegorical
interpretation of the Eumenides-souls as ‘air.’ In Greek popular ‘folk-zoology’
and in Empedocles, the three elements (world-masses) of earth, sea, and air (sky)
were correlated with three kinds of animals: terrestrial animals, fishes, and birds.
The Derveni author is not a priest and he does not give in these lines ritual pre-
scriptions: he ‘decodes’ in the teletai established by Orpheus the same ‘ancient
wisdom’ as in his poetry. The commentator assumes that first offerings are due to
the first gods. Both magoi and mystai converge in that they first make offerings to
the souls that, like birds, reside in the air and (according to the commentator) are
nothing but air.93 It follows that ancient religion accords with modern science:
both in Orpheus and in the Anaxagorean physics, ‘air’ is the original source of
everything.94 Once we admit that PDerv. is a work of Prodicus parodied by Aristo-
phanes in the Birds, it is reasonable to conclude that the choice of ‘birds’ as ‘new
gods,’ more ‘ancient’ than Olympians, was also suggested to Aristophanes by the
same work on the origin of religion and was intended as a mocking parody of it.
(T8) Aristophanes [V]
(T9) Plutarch [I]
95 Parts of this text in OF 671 (= Diag. fr. 94 Winiarczyk = FGrHist 800 T 9).
524 Andrei Lebedev
τὰς τελετὰς ὀργιασμοὶ καὶ τὰ δρώμενα συμβολικῶς ἐν ταῖς ἱερουργίαις τὴν τῶν
παλαιῶν ἐμφαίνει διάνοιαν. κτλ.
“Take up Plutarch of Chaeronea and read his statements about our subject,
statements in which he majestically converts the myths into what he says are
‘mystic theologies’; purporting to reveal these, he says that Dionysos is intox-
ication (...) and Hera the married life of husband and wife. Then, as if he has
forgotten this interpretation, he tacks on directly afterwards a different account:
contrary to his previous view he now calls Hera the earth, and Leto forgetfulness
and night. Then again he says that Hera and Leto are identical; next on top of this
Zeus is introduced, allegorized into the power of aether. Why should I anticipate
all this, when we can listen to the fellow himself? In the work he entitles On the
Festival of Images at Plataea he discloses what most men are unaware of in the
secret natural science that attaches to the gods, and does so as follows.
Ancient natural science, among both Greek and foreign nations, took the
form of a scientific account hidden in mythology, veiled for the most part in
riddles and hints, or of a theology as is found in mystery-ceremonies: in it what
is spoken is less clear to the masses that what is unsaid, and what is unsaid gives
more speculation than what is said. This is evident from the Orphic poems and
the Egyptian and Phrygian doctrines. But nothing does more to reveal what was
in the mind of the ancients than the rites of initiation and the ritual acts that are
performed in religious services with symbolical intent.”96
Note the following similarities of Plutarch’s source with the Derveni treatise.
The enigmatic Orphic poetry and mysteries are taken as remnants of the ancient
physiologia, and alternative rationalistic interpretations confuse the reader: the
equation of gods Ge = Hera = Leto is stated; Zeus is an airy substance; Hera is
also ἀνδρὸς καὶ γυναικὸς γαμήλιος συμβίωσις; Leto is night and a shadow of the
earth that eclipses the sun. The identification of Hera with Ge is found in PDerv.,
col. XXII.7. Dionysos’ association with wine is attested for Prodicus in test. 71, 74,
and 76 Mayhew and in the passage of Themistius quoted above (test. 77 Mayhew).
Λητώ = λήθη is found in Pl. Cra. 406a8. The etymology of the name of Apollo in
Plutarch’s fr. 157 Sandbach (§ 5: [...] Ἀπόλλων δ’ ὡς ‘ἀπαλλάττων’ καὶ ‘ἀπολύων’
τῶν περὶ σῶμα νοσηματικῶν παθῶν τὸν ἄνθρωπον. κτλ.) is paralleled in Pl. Cra.
405b9–c1 (κατὰ μὲν τοίνυν τὰς ἀπολύσεις τε καὶ ἀπολούσεις, ὡς ἰατρὸς ὢν τῶν
τοιούτων, “Ἀπολούων” ἂν ὀρθῶς καλοίτο). The common source must be Prodi-
cus/the Derveni author.
(T10) Plutarch [II]
Plut. De Pyth orac. 407b5 ff.: Ὀνομάκριτοι δ᾽ ἐκεῖνοι καὶ Πρόδικοι (Botzon :
προδόται MSS) καὶ Κιναίθωνες (Botzon : κινέσωνες MSS) κτλ. Bernabé identi-
fies the Plutarchean Prodicus with Prodicus Φωκαεύς, the alleged author of the
Minyas (test. 3, PEG I, 137). However, Plutarch gives a list not of epic poets qua
poets, but of χρησμολόγοι and (from his point of view) pretentious charlatans
who discredited oracles with their theatrical grandeur (τραγῳδία καὶ ὄγκος),
which he contrasts with the simple style of the genuine oracles of the Pythia.
The Rhapsodic Theogony was not a literary ‘poem’ composed by an ordinary
poet: Ἱεροὶ λόγοι means that it was conceived and presented as divine word, as
a kind of χρησμός inspired by Apollo, with Orpheus as his prophet. It is possible
therefore that Ὀνομάκριτοι (...) καὶ Πρόδικοι in Plutarch is a kind of ‘hendiadys’
that refers both to the bombastic Theogony of ps.-Orpheus falsified by Onoma-
critus and its disreputable and scandalous (in Plutarch’s opinion) interpreter
Prodicus.97
(T11) Epiphanius
Apart from the sun and the moon, Epiphanius also includes the four elements
in the list of the deified ‘beneficial’ things from Prodicus’ theory of religion:
Πρόδικος τὰ τέσσαρα στοιχεῖα θεοὺς καλεῖ, εἶτα ἥλιον καὶ σελήνην· ἐκ γὰρ τούτων
πᾶσι τὸ ζωτικὸν ἔλεγεν ὑπάρχειν,98 “Prodicus calls ‘gods’ the four elements, and
then the sun and the moon, for it is from them, in his opinion, that all men get
their means of living.” All six are attested in the allegoresis of PDerv. as ‘real’
referential meanings of the mythical names: according to the Derveni author, air
(and mind) was deified as ‘Zeus,’ fire and sun as Protogonos, the water element
as Achelous, earth (Ge) as Demeter, the moon as Selene. A very similar natu-
ralistic interpretation of Greek mythology was parodied as ‘atheistic’ already by
Epicharmus.99
97 Clem. Al. Strom. 1.131.3 (= OF 707) attributes Orpheus’ ‘Descent to Hades’ to a certain Prodi-
cus of Samos: (...) τήν τε εἰς Ἅιδου κατάβασιν Προδίκου (τοῦ Σαμίου sc. εἶναι λέγουσι); Suda s.v.
Ὀρφεύς (= OF 709) has Προδίκου τοῦ Περινθίου.
98 Epiph. Exp. fid. 9.25, p. 507 Holl (= Prodic. test. 78 Mayhew). Cf. Cole (1990) 156.
99 Epich. fr. 199 PCG. For a detailed comparison with PDerv., see Lebedev (2017d) 19–22.
526 Andrei Lebedev
100 OF 856.
101 Cf. Sider (1997) 138.
102 Metrod. Lamps. 61 A 3 DK (= Tatian. Ad Gr. 21).
103 Kern explained it as a poetic equivalent of the epiklesis Ἐργάνη. It does not mean “hard-
working” as in Nicander (Ther. 4: πολύεργος ἀροτρεύς), but rather “master of many works,”
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 527
chance: authors who connect the verse with “hands” prefer “one of many works,”
whereas the authors who cite it in support of the allegorical interpretation of
another famous mythical trickster, Prometheus, prefer “one of great prudence.”
It is striking that both the etymology of χεῖρες and the allegorical interpretation
of the name Prometheus seem to be related with Prodicus’ ‘utilitarian’ theory of
the origin of religion: χρῆσις, χρήσιμον is a synonym of ὠφέλιμον, ‘useful,’ and
both Athena and Prometheus fit perfectly into the category of πρῶτοι εὑρεταί
that played an important role in Prodicus’ second stage. Since the interpretation
of Zeus as ‘mind’ is attested in PDerv., chances are that Athena and Prometheus
were mentioned in the lost parts of the papyrus.
Τhe myth about Prometheus moulding (πλάττειν) man from clay is
explained in Syncellus’ source as an allegory of forming man by knowledge
and reshaping him from apaideusia state to the state of paideia. Both Syncellus
and a scholiast on Aesch. PV 120.17 add to this allegory a quotation from the
Σοφισταί of Plato Comicus (fr. 145 PCG): προμηθία γάρ ἐστιν ἀνθρώποις ὁ νοῦς.
Some have thought that the title Sophists refers to tragic poets and musicians
only, but the evidence for this is weak.104 The group of Sophistai mocked in the
comedy may well have included both poets and sophists in the familiar sense,
like Prodicus.
One puzzle remains unsolved. The verse about Athena as a “master of many
works,” i.e. τέχναι, is very different from the verses of Orphic theogony quoted in
PDerv.: it looks like a gnome or a verse from elegy rather than a fragment of epic
mythical narrative. It is hard to imagine what its original context in a theogony
might have been. And even more puzzling is the fact that the author of this verse
seems to share Prodicus’ somewhat unholy explanation of traditional gods as
personifications of ‘useful’ τέχναι. Can it be a playful fabrication of Prodicus
himself?
Philochorus has been plausibly identified as the source of these quotations.105
Dirk Obbink, on independent grounds, has convincingly argued that Philochorus
quoted the Derveni Papyrus.106 Objections to Obbink’s thesis (e.g., Philochorus
i.e. presiding over different crafts (τέχναι). Πολύτεχνος is the epithet of Athena (and Hephaestus)
in Solon’s fr. 13.49 West.
104 The scholiast on Ar. Nub. 331a (= Plato Com. fr. 149 PCG) commenting on σοφισταί tells
us that the word is applied not only to those who study celestial phenomena, but – improperly
(καταχρηστικῶς) – also to specialists in all kinds of knowledge, even to a flute player Bacchylides
in Plato Comicus’s Sophistai. He does not tell that all Sophistai in this play were musicians like
Bacchylides: on the contrary, he quotes Bacchylides as an extraordinary case.
105 Hussey (1999) 315.
106 Obbink (1994) 110–135. FGrHist 328 F 185 is to be compared with Phld. De piet., PHerc.1428,
col. 6.16–26 Henrichs (= Chrysipp. SVF II 1078).
528 Andrei Lebedev
and the Derveni author may quote the same source independently)107 do not take
into account Philochorus’ general predilection for rationalistic and ‘euhemeristic’
interpretations of myth which can be best explained by the influence exerted on
him by Prodicus’ work on religion and Orphic theogony.108 Philochorus wrote a
Περὶ μυστηρίων and a Περὶ μαντικῆς in which he mentioned Orpheus and quoted
two Orphic verses on prophecies.109 Therefore, he may well have consulted the
influential work of Prodicus on the same subject. Furthermore, neither ἡ αὐτή (sc.
ἐστίν) in PDerv., col. XXII.7 nor τὴν αὐτὴν εἶναι in Philodemus’ On Piety (PHerc.
1428, col. 5.3 Henrichs) is a part of the verse, i.e. of the supposed ‘common source.’
Unlike the names of the gods, it is in both cases a piece of the commentary or a
paraphrase and therefore reflects the commentator’s linguistic preference (which
is the same). It is hard to imagine that the identities of the three goddesses were
stated in a hymn in such plain, prosaic language. Expressions like ἥν τε καὶ Γῆν
καλέουσι are conceivable or, alternatively, the same goddess was called by three
different names in the invocation.
A striking sample of ‘linguistic archaeology’ reminiscent of PDerv. is pro-
vided by Philochorus’ rationalistic and naturalistic explanation of the names Tri-
topatores and Apollo. Cf. FGrHist 328 F 182 (verbatim quotation in Harpocration):
Φιλόχορος δὲ τοὺς Τριτοπάτορας πάντων γεγονέναι πρώτους· “τὴν μὲν γὰρ Γῆν
καὶ τὸν Ἥλιον (φησίν), ὃν καὶ Ἀπόλλωνα τότε110 καλεῖν, γονεῖς αὑτῶν ἠπίσταντο
οἱ τότε ἀνθρωποι, τοὺς δὲ ἐκ τούτων τρίτους πατέρας.” Prehistoric men spoke an
original, natural language not yet corrupted by misunderstanding and correctly
applied the name ‘Apollo’ to the sun.111
(T13) Philodemus
107 Betegh (2006) 98–99 n. 20; Bremmer (2014) 65 n. 60; Vassallo (2015b) 98.
108 Chances are that the collection of hymns quoted by Prodicus was no longer extant or avail-
able some 150 years after Philochorus.
109 FGrHist 328 F 77 (= OF 810). The fragment is odd: Orpheus speaks in the first person and
boasts that his prophecies are infallible. Is it a proem to a collection of χρησμοί?
110 For no good reason Jacoby deletes τότε.
111 On Orphic Physica and Tritopatores see Gagné (2007) 1–24 and Bremmer (2014) 62 ff.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 529
alter letters” (with a connotation of “to distort,” “to falsify,” by analogy with
παραχαράττειν), not “to rearrange.”112 The reference is apparently to the rational-
istic etymologies based on assonance between the divine name and its supposed
etymon. Examples of this technique are found in PDerv., cols. XIV.7 (Κρόνος =
κρούων νοῦς) and XXII.9–10 (Δημήτηρ by change of letter δ to γ becomes Γῆ
Μήτηρ). The Derveni author (Prodicus) himself uses a similar expression in col.
XXVI.11, γράμματα παρακλίνοντα, to describe the possible change of μητρὸς ἐᾶς
to μητρὸς ἑοῖο. The phrase μικρὸν παρακλίνω “alter slightly,” exactly with the
same meaning, occurs in Pl. Cra. 400c (the change of only one letter in Orphic
etymology σῶμα/σῆμα) and 410a (the Phrygian pronunciation of the word πῦρ
that “slightly deviates” from the Greek).113 Most of the etymologies of the divine
names in Plato’s Cratylus are based on assonance between the name of a god
and its etymon.
(T14) Galen
On several occasions (in four different treatises!) Galen angrily rebukes Prodicus
for using the term for phlegm (φλέγμα) not in its commonly accepted sense of a
cold and dense liquid in the body, but in the unusual sense of something “burnt”
on the ground of its etymological derivation from φλέγω, “to burn.”114 Cf. De
nat. fac. 2.130.5 ff. Kühn: Πρόδικος δ’ ἐν τῷ περὶ φύσεως ἀνθρώπου γράμματι τὸ
συγκεκαυμένον καὶ οἷον ὑπερωπτημένον ἐν τοῖς χυμοῖς ὀνομάζων φλέγμα παρὰ τὸ
πεφλέχθαι (…). ἀλλὰ τοῦτό γε τὸ πρὸς ἁπάντων ἀνθρώπων ὀνομαζόμενον φλέγμα
τὸ λευκὸν τὴν χρόαν, ὃ βλένναν ὀνομάζει Πρόδικος, ὁ ψυχρὸς καὶ ὑγρὸς χυμός
ἐστιν κτλ. The unusual periphrastic expression “as it is called by all men” instead
of “common name,” according to a whole corpus TLG search, does not occur else-
where, except in another passage of Galen (De loc. aff. 8.74 Kühn), but it strikingly
resembles the distinction between the ‘peculiar’ expressions of Orpheus and the
‘spoken names,’ “which have been called by all men” (PDerv., col. XVIII.8–9: ἐξ
ὧν ἅπαντες ἄνθρωποι | ὠνόμασαν).
(T15) Plato [II]
Another common feature of Prodicus and the Derveni author is the attention to
synonyms and similar phraseology in semantic analysis. It might seem prima facie
that they follow different or even contrasting procedures: Prodicus was renowned
for his subtle distinctions of words (ἀκριβολογία) with similar meanings, the
Derveni author, in contrast, emphasizes “the same meaning” (ταὐτὸ δύναται, cf.
cols. X.3, 8; XI.5). But there can be little doubt that Prodicus mastered his teacher
Protagoras’ art of arguing both ways: (...) Πρόδικος διῃρεῖτο τὰς ἡδονὰς εἰς χαρὰν
καὶ τέρψιν καὶ εὐφροσύνην· ταῦτα γὰρ πάντα τοῦ αὐτοῦ, τῆς ἡδονῆς, ὀνόματά
ἐστιν. (...), “(...) Prodicus divided pleasures into joy, merriment and delight, for all
these names denote the same, namely of pleasure.”115 Compare this triad of names
with the triad γινώσκειν/μανθάνειν/πιστεύειν in PDerv., col. V.9–12 and λέγειν/
φωνεῖν/διδάσκειν in col. X.1–3. Although the author asserts ad hoc the semantic
identity of the three words (ταὐτὸ δύναται), this passage betrays a professional
knowledge of synonyms. The two different procedures are best explained by his
two different goals: in his teaching of general rhetoric, Prodicus aimed to teach
students orthoepeia, the correct use of names based on subtle semantic distinc-
tions between synonyms. In his allegorical interpretation of divine names, his
aim was exactly the reverse: naturalistic monism (“everything is air”) imposed an
emphasis on “the same meaning.” Prodicus’ terminology of the semantical analy-
sis (διαίρεσις) imitated in Pl. Prt. 340a8 ff. (= Prod. test. 50 Mayhew) is very similar
to the terminology we find in PDerv.: (...), ᾗ τό τε βούλεσθαι καὶ ἐπιθυμεῖν διαιρεῖς
ὡς οὐ ταὐτὸν ὄν, (...) ταὐτόν σοι δοκεῖ εἶναι τὸ γενέσθαι καὶ τὸ εἶναι, ἢ ἄλλο; κτλ.
(T16) Plato [III]
῾Υπερβατόν occurs in PDerv twice: in col. IV.10 in the authorial comments on Her-
aclitus’ quotation, and in col. VIII.6 applied to the verses of Orpheus (τ]αῦτα τὰ
ἔπη ὑπερβατὰ ἐό[ν]τα λανθάν[ει). In both cases, it is a rhetorical and grammatical
term for irregular word order: see § (IV) below for details. In both cases, it is used
to reveal the cause of the ambiguity of the text and the reason behind its mis-
readings. A third mention of hyperbaton is probably found in col. VII.3–4: [κ]αὶ
εἰπεῖν οὐχ οἷόν τ[ε τὴν τῶν ὀ]νομάτων | [θέ]σιν, “and it is impossible to determine
the position of names.”116 “Position” here means the syntactical position, i.e. πῶς
κεῖται τὸ ὄνομα, i.e. whether it should be taken with what precedes or with what
follows, as in the case of the word αἰδοῖον. Hyperbaton is an exegetical tool which
Protagoras, the teacher and friend of Prodicus, used in his interpretation of poetic
texts (Pl. Prt. 343e3: ὑπερβατὸν δεῖ θεῖναι ἐν τῷ ᾄσματι τὸ ἀλαθέως). This word is a
hapax in Plato, and since Plato puts it into the mouth of Protagoras, it may well be
an authentic term of Sophistic hermeneutics. Plato probably regarded this tech-
nique with suspicion since it could easily be used for ‘sophistry’: the substitution
of a “penis” for a “venerable god” in PDerv., col. VIII.6 by admitting a hyperbaton
is a case in point.
(T17)
In the Ionian dialect of Ceos (group of the Central Ionian) Atticisms are attested
in the last quarter of the 5th cent. BC.117 This perfectly agrees with the dialect of
PDerv. which Tsantsanoglou describes as “an Ionic text liberally sprinkled with
Attic features,” and Willi characterizes as “a curious mixture of Attic and Ionic.”118
(T18)
We do not rule out that one of the sources of the physical allegoresis of Orphic
theogony in [Clem. Rom.] Recogn. 6 may be PDerv., especially in regard to the
reduction of Olympian gods to different forms of air in 6.8–9: Zeus is θερμότατος
and καθαρώτατος αἰθήρ; Hera is the sublunar ἀήρ which is not so clean, and
her ability to beget refers to the εὐκρασία ἀέρων; Athena is very hot air (ἄκρως
θερμόν), which is unable to generate anything, hence the myth that she is a
virgin; and Artemis is the lowest part of the air that is extremely cold, hence the
similar myth of virginity. The name of Dionysos refers to the exhalations upwards
and downwards (a ‘Heraclitizing’ tenet!). In 6.9.5 can be read: Αφροδίτην εἰς μῖξιν
καὶ γένεσιν. Orpheus is one of τῶν πάλαι ἀνδρῶν σοφώτατοι who concealed true
knowledge of the divine from the unworthy in the form of myth: Kronos never cas-
trated Ouranos, and Zeus never seized royal power from Kronos, never swallowed
LSJ II, 4 (f). But this does not fit the context because asyndeton is always obvious. Demetrius
(Eloc. 191), following Aristotle, explained the obscurity of Heraclitus by lysis.
117 See the burial law ap. SGDI III.2, 5398.27 (ταύταις)
118 KPT, 11–14; similarly West (1983) 77 and n. 11; Willi (2010) 114. On the dialect see also Brem-
mer (2014) 64. On the alleged Doric νιν see § (VII) below (on Diagoras).
532 Andrei Lebedev
Metis, and never gave birth to Athena from his head and Dionysos from his thigh
(6.2). All mythology is a result of a misreading of Orpheus’ text.
(T19)
= App. (3).
119 This section supersedes the text and interpretation in Lebedev (1989b), although the basic
approach to koina/idia and to the general meaning of Heraclitus’ fragment remains the same.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 533
with an article are not typical for Heraclitus’ archaic and poetic prose. Even on
formal linguistic grounds, such language is unlikely in Heraclitus: he uses an
article only in rare cases, and he regularly omits it when he speaks about phe-
nomenal opposites.120 3) Such terminology in Heraclitus is unlikely not only on
linguistic, but also on philosophical grounds: plur. τὰ κοινά in an epistemologi-
cal or ontological sense is ruled out in Heraclitus’ work since τὸ ξυνόν (22 B 114
DK = fr. 133 Lebedev) means ‘one’ by definition and is opposed to ‘many.’ Ξυνὸς
λόγος is the only one true logos and is opposed to many false logoi of poets and
other philosophers. Sound mind (τὸ φρονεῖν) is also one and the same for all: it
is “common to all” (ξυνὸν πᾶσι) and opposed to the plurality of imaginary worlds
of dreamers and poets. Heraclitus’ authentic word for “false beliefs” or subjective
opinions is δοκέοντα (22 B 28 DK = fr. 138 Lebedev), without an article, not τὰ ἴδια.
Following this false assumption, KPT try to supplement verbs that would reflect
Heraclitus’ rejection of ‘private’ (IV.3: σίνεται; IV.6: κατ[αστρέ]φει τὰ ἴδ[ι]α) and
approval of ‘common’ (IV.5: μα[ρτυρόμενος] τὰ κοινά), but this attempt results in
strange and artificial Greek. The verb καταστρέφει to my ears sounds like modern
Greek. In modern Greek, this (very popular) verb can be used in a wide variety of
contexts not confined to physical destruction (e.g. καταστρέφει τὴν ὁμορφιά, τὸ
νόημα, etc.), but in classical Greek it is used predominantly in military contexts
and literally means “ruining,” or “destroying,” or “setting upside down” (a city).
We could not find in lexica or TLG a single instance of this verb in a grammatical
or rhetorical context: it simply does not convey the notion of “rejection,” “avoid-
ing,” etc. The same a fortiori can be said about the verb σίνεται, which is used
exclusively for physical violence, looting, plundering, damaging property, etc.
Such verbs could not be used by a literary critic in a stylistic analysis and could
not be used by a commentator as descriptions of what Heraclitus was doing either
in his life or in his philosophy. For example, σίνεται could be appropriately used
when Herostratus set the Artemision on fire. The only possibility of making sense
of this opposition in col. IV is to admit that τὰ κοινά and τὰ ἴδια, “common and
peculiar names,” are rhetorical terms of the Derveni commentator himself with
ὀνόματα or ῥήματα implied: the “common names” are plain words of ordinary
language which are in common usage and have a transparent meaning intelli-
gible to everybody; they are the same as the “names used by all men” in col.
XVIII.8–9 and the “spoken and (commonly) recognized words” in col. XXIII.8.
The “peculiar” names are poetic metaphors and divine names whose meaning
escapes the understanding of hoi polloi and requires the Sophistic art of inter-
pretation. Common words existed in the beginning before the “peculiar” ones;
peculiar words seem to be a later invention of poets like Orpheus. This can be
inferred from col. XVIII, according to which Orpheus metaphorically applied an
already existing common name, μοῖρα (“part”), both to the wind (of cosmogonical
vortex, l. 2) and to the intelligence (φρόνησις) of the god (ll. 7–9). The opposition of
κοινά/ἴδια ὀνόματα in col. IV corresponds to the opposition ἄνθρωποι ὠνόμασαν/
Ὀρφεὺς ὠνόμασεν in col. XVIII. Furthermore, the distinction between earlier
“common names” and later “peculiar names” recalls the distinction between
“first” and “second” names in Plato’s Cratylus (see § [II] above). Plato may have
borrowed this distinction from Prodicus. The time when only “common” names
were in use probably corresponds to the original phase of civilization discussed
in Protagoras’ Περὶ τῆς ἐν ἀρχῇ καταστάσεως. The worship of anthropomorphic
gods of official Greek religion at that time could not exist since the names of the
gods had not yet been invented by poets. Humans living at that time either were
natural atheists or worshipped natural phenomena, “things that really exist” (τὰ
ἐόντα, τὰ πράγματα), like the stars and the elements, and, first of all, things that
were useful for human life (τὰ ὠφελοῦντα τοὺς ἀνθρώπους), like the sun and
the moon. The false mythological religion of poets was the result of the subse-
quent ‘disease of language,’ of the misreading and misunderstanding of Orpheus’
poetic cosmogony by the ignorant polloi.
Both Orpheus and Heraclitus, according to the Derveni author, use idiomatic
cryptic language to convey to “those who understand correctly” similar philo-
sophical ideas (in this case on the cosmic mind producing cosmic order) and at
the same time to conceal these ideas from “the many.” It becomes clear that in
this case the subject of μεταθέμενος is also Heraclitus (and not Zeus or the cosmic
mind) and that the object of this verb is again ὀνόματα.
The term μεταφορά for what we call a metaphor is not attested in poetics
and rhetoric before Isocrates, Anaximenes of Lampsacus, and Aristotle in the 4th
cent. BC. But words and concepts are not the same thing, so it does not follow that
5th-cent. BC Sophists had no concept of metaphorical language. We have good
reason to suppose that ἴδιον ὄνομα or τὰ ἰδιάζοντα was one of the early (5th-cent.
BC) terms for the metaphor.121 The 5th-cent. BC usage was still followed by
121 This usage is semantically related to the grammatical term ἰδίωμα (peculiarities of style,
idiomatic expressions, LSJ s.v. II) and the common grammatical phrases ἰδίως λέγεσθαι, ἰδίως
λεγόμενα (or κοινῶς λέγεσθαι), but should be distinguished from ἴδια ὀνόματα “specific, i.e. ap-
propriate” words in Plato (Resp. 9.580e) and Aristotle (Rhet. 3.5.1407a31), as well as from the
logical term τὸ ἴδιον to mean “specific or essential feature” in Aristotle and the Stoics, on which
see Reesor (1983). An exact parallel to the usage in PDerv. is found in Antiphan. Com. fr. 207.1–3
PCG: πολύ γ᾽ ἐστὶ πάντων τῶν ποιητῶν διάφορος / ὁ Φιλόξενος. πρώτιστα μὲν γὰρ ὀνόμασιν /
ἰδίοισι καὶ καινοῖσι χρῆται πανταχοῦ.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 535
Epigenes (ap. Clem. Al. Strom. 5.49) in his allegorical interpretations of Orpheus’
poetry: οὐχὶ καὶ Ἐπιγένης ἐν τῷ Περὶ τῆς Ὀρφέως ποιήσεως τὰ ἰδιάζοντα παρ᾽
Ὀρφεῖ ἐκτιθέμενός φησι (...)· “μῖτον” δὲ τὸ σπέρμα ἀλληγορεῖσθαι, και “δάκρυα
Διὸς” τὸν ὄμβρον δηλοῦν, “Μοῖρας” τε αὖ τὰ μέρη τῆς σελήνης, τριακάδα καὶ
πεντεκαιδεκάτην καὶ νουμηνίαν· διὸ καὶ “λευκοστόλους” αὐτὰς καλεῖν τὸν Ορφέα
φωτὸς οὔσας μέρη. κτλ. The term τὰ ἰδιάζοντα, “peculiar expressions,” for poetic
metaphors is not a part of Clement’s own lexicon. It occurs only once in a quota-
tion from Epigenes and therefore most probably belongs to Epigenes. The Derveni
author also conveys the concept of metaphorical language by the participles of
the verb εἰκάζω: Orpheus compared time to snow (XII.11), the sun to the phallus
(XIII.9), and Zeus to a king (XIX.8). A common name becomes metaphorical
(“peculiar”) by re-attaching it (προσφέρειν) to a different object. The term προσ-
φέρειν will be changed in the 4th cent. BC to μετα-φέρειν.
Scholars who attempted to restore the text of the Heraclitus quotation have
often been misguided by the long ago antiquated physicalist approach to Hera-
clitus’ philosophy in the tradition of Kirk and Marcovich that derives from Burnet
and Reinhardt. Scholars of this trend dogmatically denied the authenticity of the
world-conflagration (ekpyrosis) in Heraclitus, regarding it as a Stoic distortion
of the alleged theory of “cosmic measures” which, as we said, emphasized sta-
bility rather than change: Heraclitus’ dynamic cosmic cycle, unanimously rec-
ognized by all ancient readers of his book, has been replaced by trivial ‘mete-
orological’ changes on a regular basis (like day and night) in a stable, eternal
cosmos. Since the cyclical cosmogony is firmly linked with the notions of Time
and Fate, they rejected the ‘universal flux’ as Plato’s invention (another imag-
inary ‘projection’) and interpreted the image of the cosmogonical god of Time
(Aion) as a trivial saying about human fortune. Diels had already wrongly rele-
gated authentic verbatim fragment of Heraclitus on Fate to Spuria.122 The days
when such an approach to Heraclitus was dominant have passed. Charles Kahn
was right when he remarked that “the Stoics were the Heracliteans of the ancient
world” and when he emphasized in his criticism of Burnet, that if there was any
theory of cosmic ‘measures’ in Heraclitus, it was a theory of “measure or equality
122 22 B 137 DK (= fr. 53 Lebedev). We defend its authenticity in the commentary to our edition
(Lebedev [2014] 362–364) and restore the text as follows: ἔστι γὰρ εἱμαρμένα <πάντα> πάντως,
“all things (or events) are in all ways determined by fate.” Stobaeus is an excellent and trustwor-
thy source; γράφει indicates a verbatim quotation. Diels dismissed it with a surprising dogmatic
verdict: “Zitate Heraklits gibt es in Placita nicht.” The Derveni Papyrus demonstrates how wrong
Diels was: the doxa on the size of the sun is a verbatim quotation with a transposition of only
one word (εἱμαρμένα is found already in Thgn. 1.1033 and need not be a ‘projection’ of Stoic
εἱμαρμένη).
536 Andrei Lebedev
123 See Kahn (1981) 147–153 (Excursus I: On the traditional interpretations of the cosmic cycle).
124 See Lebedev (1985b), (2014), and (2017a).
125 We argue for this in extenso in Lebedev (2014) 59–90.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 537
(from which the sacral metaphor of πῦρ ἀείζωον derives), cosmos as a stadion
with a cosmic race (ἐναντιοδρομία) of opposite forces, cosmos as a battlefield in
which the four world masses (Pyr, Prester = Wind/Air, Sea, and Earth) are engaged
(22 B 31 DK = frs. 44–45 Lebedev), winning and losing in turn at predestinated
periods of time ‘measured’ by fate, cosmic cycle as a pesseia game conducted by
the divine child Aion (22 B 52 DK = fr. 33 Lebedev), etc. Most of these metaphorical
models present a diachronically, and not spatially (i.e. geometrically) structured
pattern of the “road up and down” (ὁδὸς ἄνω κάτω) by which all things travel.
All cosmic phenomena, including the elements and stars, incessantly move from
a minimum to a maximum (“way up”) and backwards (“way down”), in a kind of
swaying motion, like a pendulum. It is from this section of Heraclitus’ book, from
a series of empirical “proofs” (tekmeria) of the universal “divine law” of regular
“reversals” (tropai, amoibai) of opposite forces that the Derveni fragment of Hera-
clitus about the sun derives. 22 B 120 DK (= fr. 55 Lebedev), which in our edition
immediately precedes the Derveni quotation from Heraclitus (fr. 56 Lebedev),
speaks about the “turning posts” (τέρματα) of the Morning and Evening and
identifies one of these points with οὖρος αἰθρίου Διός, “the limit of (the period)
of clear Zeus = Sky,” i.e. “with the autumnal equinox.”126 And the Oxyrhynchus
fragment on the moon (fr. 60 Lebedev) that follows soon after the Derveni frag-
ment speaks about the number of days (fourteen), i.e. again about the time, not
about size. The Hippocratic author of De diaeta 1 summarizes Heraclitus’ theory
of cosmic change with more precision and accuracy than Plato in his passages
on the ‘universal flux’ in Theaetetus and Cratylus.127 It is to these temporal limits
and “turning points” of the “way up and down” (increase and diminution), and
not to the size of the stars and material masses that Heraclitus applies the term
ὅροι (synonymous with τέρματα “turning posts”), τροπαί (“turns” like those of a
wheel), ἀμοιβαὶ ἀναγκαῖαι (“fated changes”), and παλίντροπος (“turning back”)
in the extant authentic fragments. Therefore, in the quotation in PDerv., col. IV,
ὅρους refers to the “fixed terms” of the year-cycle, i.e. to the summer and winter
solstices (τροπαὶ ἡλίου) which the sun will “never exceed.” The mention of the
“fixed month” (μηνὶ τακ[τῶι) in col. IV.13 makes this interpretation certain (see our
commentary on this line below). The regular change (increase and diminution) of
all cosmic phenomena is not due to chance: the temporal “limits” are set by a
divine Supervisοr and Umpire (ἐπιστάτης καὶ βραβεύς), the supreme ruler of the
universe represented in the current cosmological phase by the sun, the remnant
of the original pyr aeizoon. In Heraclitus’ mythopoetical universe, the sun is not
a celestial body like the “ignited lump” of iron in Anaxagoras: it is a living god
imbued with a mind and probably identified with Apollo.128 “Being the size of
a human foot” is a rhetorical phrase that emphasizes the modesty of the ideal
monarch: the sun is ‘tiny’ in size when compared with the huge masses of the Air
(Prester), the Sea, and the Earth, and yet he rules over all of them because he is
the mind of the universe. The supreme cosmic god is the size of man’s foot: this
is political and theological rhetoric, and not physical science.129 The rule of “one
the best” (εἷς ἄριστος) over many kakoi is “according to nature” (κατὰ φύσιν). He
is the παράδειγμα of the best ruler, because he strictly obeys the θεῖος νόμος of 22
B 114 DK (= fr. 131 Lebedev). According to Diodotus, Heraclitus’ book was not περὶ
φύσεως, but περὶ πολιτείας, τὰ δὲ περὶ φύσεως ἐν παραδείγματος εἴδει κεῖσθαι
(Diog. Laërt. 9.15). Heraclitus points to the ‘paradigmatic’ form of government in
the polis of Zeus (monarchy of the sun) in order to demonstrate that popular rule
(the rule of ‘many’) is unnatural. And the law-abiding monarch is, at the same
time, juxtaposed with the tyrant.130 The clause on Erinyes in Heraclitus’ fragment
is a rhetorical circumlocution (imitating the style of Loxias’ oracles) “because the
sun is bound by the unbreakable horkos,” where horkos is an archaic metaphor
for the law of the cosmos, viz. the ‘divine law’ of the universe in B 114. The pecu-
liar function of the Erinyes was to punish those who commit perjury (ἐπιόρκους).
Therefore oaths may have been ‘sealed’ by a potential curse: “if I break the oath,
let the Erinyes, ministers of Justice, find me out and seize me!” See, on this regard,
the “decree of Ananke sealed by wide oaths (ὅρκοις),” i.e. the divine law of trans-
migration in Empedocles’ 31 B 115 DK. As in Heraclitus, cosmic ‘oaths’ determine
fixed periods of time. Additional confirmation seems to be provided by §9 of
Janko’s text of PDerv., where ὅρκοι μεγάλοι are associated with δίκης ὑπερήται (=
Δίκης ἐπίκουροι).
Having these considerations in mind, we propose the following reconstruc-
tion of the text of col. IV:
PDerv., col. IV
[names?] of gods (...) “(...) he (sc. Orpheus) changes the established names (...) [the
name of Zeus] rather alludes to the mind since it would be impossible to under-
stand [the origin of the cosmos] as something due to chance. Isn’t the cosmos set in
order by the mind? In accord with Orpheus, Heraclitus [also] changes the common
names and uses in his writings peculiar expressions. Speaking similarly to the
author of Hieros logos, he says: ‘the sun is the mind of the cosmos by nature, being
one man’s foot in width and not exceeding the set limits. For if he does exceed the
appropriate limits, Erinyes, the ministers of Justice will find him out.’ He said so in
order to make his speech obscure and based on inverse word order (hyperbaton)
(…) justice (…) the sun makes reversals (i.e. solstices) in a fixed month.”
Commentary
Col. IV.2: The subject of μεταθ [ έμενος (or any other verb with similar semantics)
is Heraclitus, not a mysterious “one of the gods” (pace KPT, 129) or Nous (in the
commentary). The participle κείμ[ενα] (something already “set” and “established”)
cannot refer to the primordial mixture of chaotic matter, and μεταθ [ έμενος vel sim.
540 Andrei Lebedev
Col. IV.3: LSJ s.v. τείνω A, I, 4: “aim at, direct upon a point,” explained as a meta-
phor: originally, “to stretch, i.e. to point a bow at someone” (cf. Pl. Phd. 63a7–8:
εἰς σὲ τείνειν τὸν λόγον). It is also used in commentaries and scholia (not in LSJ):
Eust. In Il. 4.955.22 (τὸ δὲ “οὐδ’ αὐτὸν” ὡς πρὸς τὸν Ἕκτορα τείνεται); Ar. Plut. 379
(τὸ στόμ’ ἐπιβύσας κέρμασιν τῶν ῥητόρων).
Col. IV.4: We agree with KPT, 153 that εἴ[η is an impersonal optative potential
without ἄν as in col. XXV.8, but the verb has nothing to do with cosmogonical
processes. Like κείμ[ενα] μεταθ[έμενος in l. 2, τ]είνεται is a grammatical term,
which means “to take in a certain sense,” “to interpret” (LSJ s.v. λαμβάνω, I, 9,
b–c; cf. ἐκλαμβάνω, V). The perfect-tense verb τέτακται (with an allusion to cos-
mogony) goes better with διὰ τόνδε than the present tense τάξιν έχει. Cf. Dem.
4.36.1–2: ἅπαντα νόμῳ τέτακται. Α striking parallel from Aristotle’s Metaphysics
Λ, ch. 10 in a ‘Heraclitizing’ context: in the universe (ἡ τοῦ ὅλου φύσις) the good
(τὸ ἀγαθόν) exists both as something separate (like a general of the army) and as
something immanent (the order, τάξις in the army): πάντα δὲ συντέτακταί πως,
(...). πρὸς μὲν γὰρ ἓν ἅπαντα συντέτακται, ἀλλ᾽ ὥσπερ ἐν οἰκίᾳ τοῖς ἐλευθέροις
ἥκιστα ἔξεστιν ὅ τι ἔτυχε ποιεῖν, ἀλλὰ πάντα ἢ τὰ πλεῖστα τέτακται, κτλ. (1075a16
ff.). It is emphasized that order in the army exists because of the general, but
not vice versa: 1075a15, οὐ γὰρ οὗτος διὰ τὴν τάξιν ἀλλ᾽ ἐκείνη διὰ τοῦτον ἐστιν.
Τhis imposed order, as in col. IV under discussion, and does not leave things up
to chance (ἔτυχε). The analogy between strategos/army on the iconic level and
god/universe on the referential level looks Heraclitean: in Heraclitus, Polemos
(= Zeus) is the supreme commander in the cosmic war of elements, and god is
conceived as νοῦς (= γνώμη in the Ionian dialect of Heraclitus).
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 541
Col. IV.5–7: The reading [ἀστρο]λόγωι proposed in KPT is unlikely. In its early usage,
ἀστρολόγος could only mean “astronomer,” but astronomers do not speak about
Erinyes: mythical language is appropriate for a ἱερολόγος. According to the Derveni
author, Heraclitus, like Orpheus, uses mythical names to describe cosmic processes
and cosmic order, not in the sense intended by hoi polloi: in Heraclitus, Erinyes are
not terrible mythical creatures, but physical forces that sustain the cosmic order.
These are “peculiar names” (ἴδια ὀνόματα), the meaning of which is accessible only
to “those who understand correctly” (οἱ ὀρθῶς γινώσκοντες). What we expect at the
end of l. 6 is either a verb meaning “to rule,” “set in order,” on which the genitive
[κόσ]μου depends (e.g. ἄρχει κόσμου), or a noun meaning something like “mind”
(νόος or φρήν) or “ruler” (e.g. ἄναξ, if ἀρχός and βασιλεύς are too long). If these
supplements are too long, we should postulate a lacuna between ll. 6 and 7, since
ἥλιος cannot stand on its own without a verb or a nominal predicate. A nominal
clause [νόος] | ἥλιος [κόσ]μου with asyndeton and hyperbaton, instead of the ordi-
nary ἥλιός ἐστιν νόος τοῦ κόσμου, is both possible and quite likely in Heraclitus:
the omission of articles and nominal clauses with asyndeton is well attested in the
verbatim fragments of Heraclitus: ἄνθρωπος ἐν εὐφρόνῃ φάος (22 B 26 DK = fr. 75
Lebedev); ὁ θεὸς ἡμέρη εὐφρόνη (22 B 67 DK = fr. 43 Lebedev); νέκυες γὰρ κοπρίων
ἐλβλητότεροι (22 B 96 DK = fr. 143 Lebedev); αὔη ψυχὴ σοφωτάτη (22 B 118 DK =
fr. 73 Lebedev); ἠοῦς καὶ ἑσπέρας τέρματα ἡ Ἄρκτος (22 B 120 DK = fr. 55 Lebedev);
etc. Cleanthes’ identification of the sun with the “heart of the cosmos,” the seat of
the cosmic mind, and the “ruling principle” (τὸ ἡγεμονικόν) of the cosmos131 has
ancient roots and can be traced back to Heraclitus. It is attested both in a verbatim
quotation from Heraclitus and by a remarkable convergence of several independent
testimonia in the Heraclitean tradition. In Heraclitus’ 22 B 100 DK (= fr. 57 Lebedev),
the sun is ἐπιστάτης καὶ σκοπός who supervises the cosmic agon of the seasons
(Homeric σκοπός is Heraclitus’ authentic word, ἐπιστάτης seems to be Plutarch’s
gloss of it). Cf. Hippoc. De diaet. 1.10.17: ἐν τούτωι (= ἡλίωι) ψυχή, νόος, φρόνησις,
κτλ.; ps.-Heraclit. Ep. 5.1.8–11 Tarán: ἐγὼ εἰ οἶδα κόσμου φύσιν, (...), μιμήσομαι θεόν,
ὃς κόσμου ἀμετρίας ἐπανισοῖ ἡλίῳ ἐπιτάττων; Macrob. In Somn. Scip. 1.20.3 (sol
dux, princeps et moderator reliquorum) hunc ducem et principem quem Heraclitus
fontem caelestis lucis apellat; Pl. Cra. 413b4–5 (= Heraclit. fr. 81 [b] Marcovich): (ety-
mology of δίκαιον) τὸν ἥλιον· (...) ἐπιτροπεύειν τὰ ὄντα; Scythinus of Teos, fr. 1
West ap. Plut. De Pyth. or. 402a (= Heraclit. fr. probab. 13 Lebedev).
Col. IV.8–9: cf. οὐχ ὑπερβήσεται μέτρα in Plutarch’s quotation De exil. 604a; for the
phrase τὸ μ[έτριο]ν οὐχ ὑπερβάλλων, cf. Democrit. 68 B 233 DK: εἴ τις ὑπερβάλλοι
τὸ μέτριον; [Pl.] Def. 415e9–10: ἕξις (...) ὑπερβάλλουσα τὸ μέτριον; Dion. Hal.
Ant. Rom. 5.74.3.8–9: κἀν ταῖς ὑπερβαλλούσαις τὸ μέτριον εὐτυχίαις. The reading
μ[έγεθο]ς (KPT) should be ruled out for several reasons: a) it is an Attic and koine
form: Herodotus has only μέγαθος; b) it is pleonastic and duplicates εὖρος; c) it is
imposed by the mistaken ‘quantitative’ interpretation of cosmic ‘measures’ in Hera-
clitus; d) in restoring the original text of Heraclitus’ fragments, we adhere to the
general rule that a verbatim quotation in Ionian dialect should not be ‘emended’
on the basis of a doxographical paraphrase. But τὸ μέγεθος is not even a part of
paraphrase. Περὶ μεγέθους ἡλίου in ps.-Plutarch’s Placita is a heading of a chapter
in a handbook of physics of imperial times.132 Heraclitus was an ethico-religious
and political thinker, not a physical scientist like Anaxagoras or Democritus. The
‘size’ of the heavenly bodies was the last thing in which he was interested; for him,
as later for Socrates, πολυμάθεια was worthless. In his politico-theological ‘cos-
mology,’ he was primarily interested in the regularity of the cosmic cycles of alter-
nating opposites (day/night, summer/winter, koros and chresmosyne of the Megas
eniautos), which is directly linked with his theory of the natural law (‘cosmic
justice’). In his ethico-political discourse, τὸ μέτριον is often associated with τὸ
μέσον and τὸ δίκαιον, similarly to Plato in the Politicus and the Laws and Aristotle
in the Nichomachean Ethics. Already Democritus anticipates Aristotle by equating
the best disposition of the soul (εὐθυμίη) with a μέσον between ὑπερβολή and
ἔλλειψις. The sun god in the polis of Zeus sustains the perfect balance of opposite
forces in the cosmos by alternating periods of heat (summer) and cold (winter).133
The verbs ὑπερβάλλω (in the papyrus) and ὑπερβαίνω (in two Plutarch’s quota-
tions) are roughly synonymous, but the former is more often used in the sense of
“exceeding” a term (like the dates of τροπαί) or a period of time (cf. LSJ A II, 2), a
context very similar to Heraclitus’ Oxyrhynchus fragment about the phases of the
moon (ἐν ἡμέραις τεσσαρακαίδεκα).134 The reading οὔ]ρους ἐ[οικότας is strongly
supported by προσήκοντας ὅρους in Plut. De Is. et Os. 370d6–7, since the two words
are synonymous. Cf. also Gorg. 82 B 11a.28 DK: εἰκότα, (...) προσήκοντα; Pl. Resp.
2.362c5: προσήκειν ἐκ τῶν εἰκότων; Dem. 18.69.4: εἰκότως καὶ προσηκόντως.
Col. IV.10: When reconstructing and interpreting a defective text, one should care-
fully study the usage of the given author and take it into account, as well as always
respect Greek grammar and morphology. Those who mistranslate ὑπερβ]ατόν
132 On the origin of the doxographical tradition of Placita philosophorum see Lebedev (2016).
133 Cf. Alcmaeon’s concept of isonomia: in Lebedev (2017c) we have argued that Heraclitus may
have used the term ἰσονομία in his cosmological historiosophy.
134 POxy. LIII 3710, col. II.43–47 (= Heraclit. fr. 60 Lebedev). Cf. also Hippoc. De hebd. 26.10–12 Ro-
scher: ὅταν δὲ τούτους τοὺς ἀριθμοὺς ὑπερβάλλῃ, χρονίη ἤδη γίνεται ἡ κατάστασις τῶν πυρετῶν.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 543
135 Laks/Most (1997) 11; Sider (1997) 141 (in an otherwise excellent study full of fine observa-
tions); Betegh (2004) 11; Janko (2001) 19 (“surpassing”).
136 The original source of this mistranslation seems to be Mouraviev (1985) 131. We pointed to
this already in Lebedev (1989b) 39 and n. 1.
137 Betegh (2004). On hyperbaton, see Kühner/Gerth (1982), II/2, 600, § 607; Devine/Stephens (2000).
138 Lebedev (2014) 48–49.
139 Hyperbaton type Y1, according to Devine/Stephens (2000) 31 and 33 ff.; Denniston (1952) 47:
“emphatic word placed early in violation of natural word order”.
140 Stob. Ecl. 1.25 (= Heraclit. 22 B 3 DK = fr. 56 [b] Lebedev). We do not quote ‘Aëtius,’ one of the
many distortions of pagan names in Theodoret. For a detailed criticism of Diels’ mistaken attri-
bution and of the neo-Dielsian doxographical theory of Mansfeld and Runia, see Lebedev (2016).
544 Andrei Lebedev
Col. IV.12–13: This is an excellent and virtually certain supplement of KPT. The
“fixed month” is a month of the solstice: June for the summer solstice and Decem-
ber for the winter solstice. Solstices (τροπαὶ ἡλίου) were of greatest importance in
Heraclitus’ theory of cosmic justice, and δίκη is mentioned in l. 12. If ὑπερβατόν
is a rhetorical term of the commentator, then ll. 11–13 are not by Heraclitus, but
a part of the commentary. In any case, something like τροπὰς ποιεῖ (or ποιεῖται)
after μηνὶ τα[κτῶι seems very likely: a TLG proximity search for this phrase yields
60 instances (τροπὰς ποιεῖ or ποιεῖται) in astronomical texts: it was a fixed phrase
that was used with a dativus temporis specifying the month of the solstice. The
phrase occurs in the doxography of Anaximander (12 A 27 DK = Ar 8, 66 & 84
Wöhrle), Anaximenes (13 A 15 DK = As 40 & 125 Wöhrle), and Anaxagoras (59 A
42 DK); it is hard to imagine something very different from this in the original
Preplatonic texts. Nevertheless, it looks like an explanation of Heraclitus’ mytho-
poetic ‘peculiar’ expressions in plain ‘common words.’ Janko’s ἀμήνιτα (accepted
by Kotwick) is unfortunate: it is an archaic and poetic word (Archilochus, thrice
in Aeschylus) derived from the Homeric μῆνις, unknown in prose (with a single
exception, Hdt. 9.94) for more than 500 years until it resurfaces in Plutarch (10
instances), the lover of antiquarian lore. The probability of its occurrence in
5th-cent. BC Sophistic prose is close to zero. Furthermore, ἀμήνιτος is a charac-
teristic (ἀοργησία in classical philosophical prose) possessed by the gods and
the wise. The sing. neut. form τὸ ἀμήνιτον is conceivable and attested (once in
Plutarch), but the plur. neut. ἀμήνιτα is hard to imagine and unattested, just as τὸ
ἀόργητον (= ἀοργησία) is conceivable and attested, whereas the plural ἀόργητα
is not found. Therefore, Janko’s reading should be ruled out with certainty: there
is no alternative to μηνὶ τακ[τῶι of the KPT text.
Of all the candidates, the last one seems to be the most promising and better docu-
mented. Ὧραι or Seasons was considered already by Prodicus’ contemporaries as
his masterpiece. According to the scholiast, it contained the famous protreptic to
virtue, the story of Heracles. In earlier scholarship, the word Horai was understood
in a narrow sense as a reference to Heracles’ maturity.141 According to Wilhelm
Nestle, it was much broader in scope and consisted of three parts: a) praise of
agriculture, b) the origin of religion, and c) the story about Heracles.142 According
to Robert Mayhew’ ingenious reconstruction, Horai consisted of two parts: Part 1
on the early ‘seasons’ of the human race and Part 2 on the seasons of human life
(including the story of Heracles).143 The first part included: a) the miserable life
of the wretched primitive people alluded to in Aristophanes’ Birds (685–687); b)
the origin of religion, stage one: humans deify beneficial natural phenomena; c)
the origin of religion, stage two: humans deify the inventors of τέχναι with special
emphasis on agriculture and viticulture. In both stages, according to Mayhew,
“etymologically appropriate names are given” to the objects of deification. Our
reconstruction and reading of the Derveni treatise perfectly fits into Mayhew’s
Part 1. However, one difficulty remains: Prodicus was famous for his exquisite
style, and Heracles story (allegedly part of Horai) was praised by Xenophon as a
literary masterpiece. The style of the Derveni treatise is anything but Kunstprosa
(with the exception of cols. V, XX, and XXII, on which see § [X] below). To resolve
this difficulty, we must admit that the text of PDerv. is a Sophistic lecture based
on Horai. This hypothesis explains the sporadic change of style from simple to
exquisite one: it was recommended by Prodicus as a didactic device to keep his
listeners awake.144 Col. XX looks like an “insertion” (παρεμβολή) from the “fifty-
drachma” lecture.145 Pace Nestle and Mayhew, we have some doubts about the
possibility of integrating both Heracles’ choice and the treatise on the origin of
religion and civilization into one and the same work. The former has nothing to
do with agriculture and Kulturgeschichte; the latter has nothing to do with practi-
cal ethics. Stylistic differences alone make this integration unlikely.146 The choice
of Heracles is quoted by many authors, but it is cited under the somewhat surpris-
ing title Seasons only once in a scholium to Ar. Nub. 361. This section would fit
much better into a historical work in which agriculture was an important subject:
in Greek linguistic consciousness, the word ὧραι was closely associated with the
yearly agricultural cycle (ὧραι αἱ πάντα φέρουσι). The scholiast may have con-
flated Prodicus’ two most famous and influential works into one. Diels suggested
that Ὧραι was an artificial title like Ἡροδότου Μοῦσαι invented by the Alexandri-
ans.147 The alleged Muses of Herodotus refers to nine books, just as the Φιλολάου
Βάκχαι (a sculpture group of three bacchants) refers to the three books of Philo-
laus’ Περὶ φύσεως: in the same way, Prodicus’ Seasons might have been attached
by librarians to a collection of different speeches and works in four books. But
this is unlikely since the title Ὧραι is alluded to already in Aristophanes (both in
Birds and the neglected fragment from the Seasons) and in Xenophon (Mem. 4.4:
see App. [3] below). In Themistius, ὧραι are also associated with Prodicus’ theory
of religion, but not with Heracles’ choice. In the moral parable about virtue, Hera-
cles is a conventional literary fiction; in Prodicus’ history of religion, he would
have been presented as a deified king in the second stage.
The date. The relation of Derv.T to the psephisma of Diopeithes and to the
trial and death of Anaxagoras.
allusion to teletai in both comedies and possible quotations from Derv.T in Aris-
tophanes’ Clouds, the terminus ante quem should be pushed up to 420/417 (the
extant version of Clouds) or even 423 (the first version), since the image of Clouds
cannot be separated from the ‘air’ and the vortex cosmogony. A plausible termi
nus post quem is the psephisma of Diopeithes (433/432 BC)148 or rather the trial
(c. 430) or even death (428) of Anaxagoras, since the Derv.T looks like a ‘response’
to these events. Thus the Derveni treatise should be dated most likely between
432 and 423 BC. A date soon after the trial of death of Anaxagoras, i.e. the early
twenties, looks especially plausible. How do we know that the Derveni Treatise
was written after and in response to the psephisma of Diopeithes rather than
before it? Why not suppose that it was one of Diopeithes’ targets? The first possi-
bility better explains the extravagant figure of Orpheus the Anaxagorean. Before
the psephisma, any Anaxagorean or Sophist could express his views on nature,
the cosmos, and τὰ μετάρσια without fear. Now one had to be cautious to avoid the
charge of impiety. Orpheus the Anaxagorean was at the same time a parody (or a
polemical peritrope: see App. [2] below), a protective device against the charge of
impiety and an apology for Anaxagoras. The psephisma of Diopeithes introduced
the prosecution by eisangelia (i.e. as offenders against the state) of those who do
not recognize the traditional religion of the polis and teach astronomical theories
(logoi) that deny the divinity of heavens.149 The traditional views about the gods
and religious institutions were commonly referred to as τὰ πάτρια and πάτριοι
λόγοι. Just as the buzzwords of conservative political discourse were πάτριος
πολιτεία and πάτριοι νόμοι, the catchwords of the lexicon of religious conser-
vatives were πάτριος λόγος or νόμος.150 It is conceivable that in the original for-
mulation of the psephisma briefly paraphrased by Plutarch, πάτριοι λόγοι περὶ
θεῶν or μεταρσίων were opposed to conflicting “new doctrines,” the target being
Anaxagoras and the sophists who teach new astronomy and corrupt the young.
In any case, the author of the Derv.T could not be formally accused of rejecting the
148 On Pericles’ trial and Diopeithes’ psephisma, see Rubel (2014) ch. 2.5–6, who argues for a
date after 430. Contra Mansfeld (1980) 88, who proposes 438/437 BC. See the status quaetionis
accurately outlined by Vassallo’s paper in this volume.
149 Plut. Per. 32: (…), καὶ ψήφισμα Διοπείθης ἔγραψεν εἰσαγγέλλεσθαι τοὺς τὰ θεῖα μὴ νομίζοντας
ἢ λόγους περὶ τῶν μεταρσίων διδάσκοντας, κτλ.
150 Aristotle begins On Heaven’s Book 2 by prudently asserting that his views on the divinity
of the heavens are in perfect agreement with “ancestral doctrines” (De cael. 2.1.284a2 ff.: διόπερ
καλῶς ἔχει συμπείθειν ἑαυτὸν τοὺς ἀρχαίους καὶ μάλιστα πατρίους ἡμῶν ἀληθεῖς εἶναι λόγους,
ὡς ἔστι ἀθάνατόν τι καὶ θεῖον κτλ.). Cf. also ps.-Arist. Mund. 6.397b13–15: ἀρχαῖος μὲν οὖν τις
λόγος καὶ πάτριός ἐστι πᾶσιν ἀνθρώποις ὡς ἐκ θεοῦ πάντα καὶ διὰ θεὸν συνέστηκεν, κτλ. In Plut.
Cons. ad ux. 611d8–9, πάτριος λόγος is the doctrine of the immortality of the soul as taught in the
mysteries of Dionysos.
548 Andrei Lebedev
153 Contra Burkert (1980) 32; Kirk ap. KRS (1983) 32–33; Janko (2001) 24; Betegh (2004) 111 ff.;
Bernabé (2007) 107, and others. The correct view (αἰδοῖον masc. acc., “the reverend,” sc. Δαίμονα)
is that of West (1983) 84 ff., KPT, 133 and Sider (2014) 231, among others. Detailed and persuasive
refutation can be found in Santamaría (2016). Sider (2014) 241 has pointed out the important fact,
neglected by the supporters of the former view, that the sing. τὸ αἰδοῖον, “penis,” is a prosaic
form not attested before the late 5th cent. BC (Hippocrates, Herodotus) and therefore unlikely in
a 6th-cent. BC epic poem. In early 5th-cent. BC Ionian prose, we still find the epic plur. αἰδοίοισιν:
cf. Heraclit. 22 B 15 DK (= fr. 148 Lebedev). The masculine pronoun ὅς in PDerv., col. XIII.4 alone
makes it clear that αἰδοῖον is masc. acc. from the epithet αἰδοῖος applied to acc. δαίμον[α] κυδρόν
at the end of the preceding verse (col. VIII.5). If αἰδοῖον means “penis,” then Olympus means
“time,” Oceanus means “air,” Moira of Zeus means “vortex in the air,” and so on.
154 Diog. Laërt. 2.22 (= 22 A 4 [III] DK).
155 Lebedev (2014) 27–42.
156 Willink (1983) 33.
550 Andrei Lebedev
and was dismissed as a fake by Aristotle in his lost On Philosophy (frs. 25–26
Gigon). Chances are that already Herodotus and Ion of Chios in the 5th cent.
BC expressed doubts concerning its authenticity and attributed the Orphic doc-
trine to the Pythagoreans. We call it the ‘Attic version’ of the Orphic Theogony.
Its distinctive feature is the generation from Night as an initial stage rather than
from the ageless Kronos of the Rhapsodic Theogony known to the Neoplatonists.
According to the reliable (and for no good reason often neglected) evidence of
Aristotle, supported by such learned and discerning minds as Plutarch, Pausa-
nias, and Sextus, this ancient Attic version was composed in the late 6th cent. BC
by the professional mantis Onomacritus in Athens. Onomacritus may well have
been influenced by Pythagoras’ doctrine of the immortal soul as well as by the
authentic Theogony of Epimenides of Crete composed c. 600 BC in which: a) the
world originates from Night and a cosmic egg; b) the doctrine of reincarnation is
alluded to in Epimenides’ fr. 33 [I] Bernabé.157 According to Aristotle, Onomacri-
tus was “trained in the art of divination” in Crete, and the Cretan μαντικὴ τέχνη
was no doubt that of Epimenides. Pausanias’ report that Onomacritus invented
the myth of the sparagmos of Dionysos at the Titans’ hands look plausible, if not
strictly demonstrable.158 In a sense, Onomacritus was a sophos aner of a not so
distant past who invented a new religion for the masses: the ‘Orphic’ anthropo-
gony explaining the dualistic nature of man is a transparent popularization in
mythical terms of Pythagoras’ metaphysical dualism of peras and apeiron, the
same and the ‘other,’ the body as source of evil and the divine soul.159 A religion
157 We argue for the authenticity of Epimenides’ Theogony in Lebedev (2015) 555 ff., on the
Selene fragment and reincarnation 561 ff.
158 Contra Edmonds (1999) 43, who quotes in support of his hypercritical thesis Linforth (1941)
353: “No one else [sc. except Pausanias – A. L.] throughout antiquity quotes the works of Ono-
macritus or makes an allusion to them (…).” But this is blatantly wrong: Aristotle in his Περὶ
φιλοσοφίας, fr. 26 Gigon ascribes to Onomacritus the Orphic Theogony.
159 On ταὐτὸν καὶ ἄλλο as first principles of Pythagoras (sic) cf. Arist. fr. 152 Gigon. On Ar-
chytas see Lebedev (2017c) 242 ff. and (2017d) 23–24. We argue that, in Metaphysics Α, Aristotle
ascribes the table of 10 opposites to Pythagoras (sic) and 6th cent. BC Pythagoreans contempo-
rary with Alcmaeon and distinguishes this ancient group (oἱ πρὸ τούτων) from Philolaus and
5th-cent. BC Pythagoreans contemporary with Empedocles and Anaxagoras (οἱ ἐν τούτοις). In
this table, the corporeal changing substance (τὸ ἑτερόμηκες) is correlated with evil (τὸ κακόν)
and darkness (σκότος), and the immutable substance of the soul (τετράγωνον) with good (τὸ
ἀγαθόν) and light (φῶς). The square was a Pythagorean geometrical symbol of the immortal
self-identical soul. Cf. Lyd. Mens. 2.9 Wünsch: ψυχὰ γὰρ ἀνθρώπου, ὡς Πυθαγόρας ἔφη, ἔστι
τετράγωνον ὀρθoγώνιον (Archytas is a probable source). An unfinished square with two di-
agonals is pictured on the reverse side of the ‘Orphic’ bone plate (West [1983] 61 pl. 3) which
on the obverse has a graffito with the name of Dionysos and pairs of opposites σῶμα ψυχή,
ψεῦδος ἀλήθεια.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 551
of guilt is a godsend for tyrannical regimes, since it lowers man’s dignity and self-
esteem and makes him more submissive and easier to manipulate: the original
sin is perceived as a χρέος. Prodicus most likely knew that ‘Orpheus’ theogony’
was a fake. Orpheus was an exemplary mantis of the mythical past; Onomacritus
was a chresmologos and mantis who served the tyrannical regime of the Pisistrati-
dae and made the falsification of oracles his profession; Diopeithes and Lampon
were contemporary manteis who swore by the holy name of ‘Orpheus’ and fought
against Ionian natural science, which posed a threat to their profession. This
explains the freedom with which Prodicus, a leading representative of the ‘liberal
intelligentsia’ of his time, proposed fantastic fake interpretations of a fake ‘sacred
discourse.’
Now, as regards Prodicus’ (= the Derveni author’s) properly philosophical
sources, we should distinguish two areas: historical anthropology, origin of reli-
gion, philosophy of mythology, and philosophy of language on the one hand, and
physics and cosmology, on the other. In “human things” (τὰ ἀνθρώπινα) his main
sources of inspiration were Protagoras’ ‘Humanism’ and Sophistic Kulturgeschichte,
above all Protagoras’ On the Original Condition (sc. of the Human Race). In the phi-
losophy of religion and mythology, he combined the crypto-atheism of Protagoras’
On Gods with Heraclitus’ devastating criticism of theological anthropomorphism,
‘insane’ rituals, and mystery cults. The names of Protagoras and Heraclitus are
emphatically joined as two main representatives of the ‘universal flux’ school of
thought in Plato’s Theaetetus and Cratylus, in contexts that are at the same time
ontological and theological. If we translate Plato’s language into familiar modern
terminology, he regards (and ironically dismisses) them as knowledgeable of the
Ionian naturalistic pantheism, in which the divine is not separated from cosmic
processes and is conceived as constantly moving and changing. Plato himself sided
with Western Greek philosophical theology, the Pythagoreans and Eleatics, who
conceived god as set apart from matter and always ἀκίνητον. As a matter of fact,
historical Heraclitus was not an atheist like Prodicus: his cosmic god is a genuine
providential god, like the god of Stoics; his concept of the universal Logos paved
the way to the Stoic theological doctrine; and his archaic term for cosmic Ιntelli-
gence and Providential Will (Γνώμη) was ‘translated’ by the Stoics into familiar
Attic idiom as πρόνοια. Therefore, by joining Heraclitus with Protagoras and the
Sophists, Plato rather targeted the Sophistic reception of Heraclitus and may well
have had Prodicus in mind as well. In Plato’s Cratylus, the ancient inventors of
divine names like Rhea and Kronos are presented as prehistoric Heracliteans who
held the ‘universal flux’ doctrine. Whether Prodicus’ (Derveni author’s) theory of
the ‘agricultural’ origin of religion and deification of ‘beneficial things’ was antic-
ipated in Protagoras is difficult to determine, since too little is known about the
552 Andrei Lebedev
contents of Protagoras’ relevant treatises.160 The same holds true for the distinc-
tion between two successive stages in the parallel development of language and
religion: the original stage of simple and clear “common names” (κοινὰ, λεγόμενα
ὀνόματα) denoting “real things” (τὰ ἐόντα), and the later stage when “peculiar
names” (ἴδια ὀνόματα), like divine names, were invented by poets like Orpheus and
added to the common names. Those who spoke the original, simple language were
natural atheists: they venerated only real things (like the sun, the moon, the crops,
etc.) that were ‘useful’ for survival. The cult of the anthropomorphic gods of Greek
religion with strange and unintelligible (to hoi polloi) names appeared only at the
second stage as a result of the ‘linguistic mistake’ of mortals. In the Derveni treatise
(Prodicus), this mistake is attributed to the intentional ambiguity and enigmatic
character of “peculiar names” invented by Orpheus rather than to the spontane-
ous ‘disease of language’ posited by Max Müller. The anthropomorphic polytheism
of Greek mythology was dismissed as an invention of poets (Homer and Hesiod)
already by Xenophanes and Heraclitus in the late 6th to early 5th cent. BC. The
specific theory of the ‘linguistic mistake’ (a form of linguistic idealism) explaining
the origin of the mythopoetic gods was held by both Heraclitus (c. 490 BC) and
Parmenides (c. 480 BC). In Heraclitus the phenomenal world of plurality derives
from the wrong diairesis of the “common logos” (ξυνὸς λόγος) of the universe: the
meaningless ‘letters’ of the ‘book of nature’ were mistaken by the poets for names
that gave rise to imaginary individual objects and the plurality of gods; “wisdom
consists in knowing all things as one.”161 In Parmenides, the phenomenal world
of Doxa results from another linguistic mistake: one of the two names posited by
mortals for the supposed two primary elements (Light and Night = soul and body)
should not have been posited at all since Night is not a separate substance, but
just an absence of light, a non-entity.162 Parmenides’ influence on Prodicus and the
Sophists is ruled out: Gorgias’ parody of Parmenides makes it clear that the heirs of
Ionian ‘Enlightenment’ dismissed the idealist Eleatic ontology with a smile.
160 The lack of evidence on the contents of Protagoras’ Περὶ θεῶν (as compared with the rela-
tively abundant evidence on the analogous work of Prodicus) may be due to the fact that most
existing copies after his condemnation were confiscated and burned by the keryx on the agora:
Diog. Laërt. 9.52 (ἀναλεξάμενοι παρ᾽ ἑκάστου τῶν κεκτημένων). Prodicus’ work escaped this
fate because it was protected by his alleged respect for the ancient wisdom of Orpheus and the
ἀρχαῖαι δόξαι about gods. Prodicus could easily acquit himself of the charge of impiety by point-
ing out that the law, as formulated in the psephisma of Diopeithes, forbids teaching the new λόγοι
περὶ τῶν μεταρσίων, whereas he teaches the ancient doctrines.
161 Keeping the MSS’s correct reading εἰδέναι: Heraclit. 22 B 50 DK (= fr. 1 Lebedev: σοφόν ἐστιν
ἓν πάντα εἰδέναι).
162 Parmenid. 28 B 8.54 DK: τῶν μίαν οὐ χρεών ἐστιν – ἐν ὧι πεπλανημένοι εἰσιν. See Lebedev
(2017b) 512 ff.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 553
163 Heraclit. 22 B 15 DK (= fr. 147 Lebedev). For interpretation see Lebedev (2014) 449.
164 Theophr. Char. 16.10–11a Steinmetz. Pythagorean approval: Diog. Laërt. 8.13; Iambl. VP
11.54; 28.150.
165 Contra Janko (2016), followed by Kotwick (2017) 107–108. A reconstruction of Parmenides’
verse B 1.1 from a few letters seems too bold. See the criticism of Tsantsanoglou (2017) and (2018).
The attempt to connect Parmenides’ proem (interpreted as katabasis) with the oracle of Night in
PDerv. cannot hold out against criticism: in Parmenides, Night is the source of ignorance (B 8.59:
νύκτ’ ἀδαῆ), not of knowledge. In the opposition Light/Night of the Doxa, Night is axiologically
marked as a negative element, exactly as in the Pythagorean table of opposites where it is corre-
lated with κακόν, and Light with ἀγαθόν. The goal of kouros’ flight (sic) are the celestial gates (B
1.11–13: πύλαι [...] αἰθέριαι), and the revealing goddess is called in the neglected fragment νύμφη
ὑψιπύλη, the “maiden of the high gates.” She proclaims ‘Night’ (i.e. the corporeal substance)
an empty name, a linguistic mistake of mortals (B 8.54). Furthermore, in the geocentric cosmos
of Parmenides (who knew the cause of eclipses) there is no place for Hesiod’s Tartarus. In the
Pythagorean cosmos, Hades is the sublunar word, and we are dead now: for details see Lebedev
(2017b). A quotation from Parmenides is a priori unlikely: in the fight between the Anaxagoreioi
and Pythagoreioi, the Derveni author sides with the former, and Parmenides, ἀνὴρ Πυθαγόρειος
(Strabo), with the latter. If, by any chance, Janko nevertheless is right, we would suggest that the
reason for quoting Parmenides is, as in Heraclitus’ case, allegorical language: Sextus interpreted
the proem of Parmenides allegorically.
554 Andrei Lebedev
Leucippus probably was either Democritus’ pseudonym or a literary figure invented by Democri-
tus, presumably an “ancient sage” (sophos aner) whose logos or logoi were ‘cited’ in the Megas
Diakosmos and On Mind. The author of MXG 6.980a6–9, who does not depend on Epicurus, but
also doubts his authorship, cites “logoi that are said to be by Leucippus” (ἐν τοῖς Λευκίππου
καλουμένοις λόγοις): this language resembles quotations of Socrates’ logoi from Plato’s dia-
logues. Alternative hypothesis is as follows: the proem to the Megas Diakosmos contained a story
about the ‘discovery’ of Leucippus’ ancient doctrines (inscribed on tablets) in ancient grave or
some distant and mysterious place. Democritus may have intended the figure of ‘Leucippus’ as
an Ionian reply to the Pythagorean ‘Orpheus.’ The author of the Genealogies of Acusilaus (which
contained an Orpheus-style theogony) claimed, presumably in a proem, that the text is based on
ancient “bronze plates” (ἐκ δέλτων χαλκῶν) discovered by his father when he was digging in the
yard of his house (3 A 2 DK).
173 “I came to Athens and nobody knew me,” ἦλθον γὰρ εἰς Ἀθήνας καὶ οὔτις με ἔγνωκεν, quot-
ed by Demetrius of Magnesia ap. Diog. Laërt. 9.36 (= Democrit. fr. xxiv Luria = 68 B 116 DK).
174 Luria (1947) 134.
175 Lebedev (2014) 27–42.
176 Diog. Laërt. 9.34; cf. Democr. fr. xxiv Luria and, on Anaxagoras, Vassallo’s paper (§ 2) in
this volume.
177 Diog. Laërt. 9.34–35 (according to Favorinus) λέγειν Δημόκριτον περὶ Ἀναξαγόρου ὡς οὐκ
εἴησαν αὐτοῦ αἱ δόξαι αἵ τε περὶ ἡλίου καὶ σελήνης, ἀλλὰ ἀρχαῖαι, τὸν δὲ ὑφῃρῆσθαι. διασύρειν
τε αὐτοῦ τὰ περὶ τῆς διακοσμήσεως καὶ τοῦ νοῦ, κτλ., “Democritus said about Anaxagoras that
his views about the sun and moon were not his own, but ancient, and that he had stolen them.
Democritus also ridiculed Anaxagoras’ view on cosmogony and the mind, etc.”
556 Andrei Lebedev
the earliest evidence on the influence of Democritus in Athens in the late thirties
or twenties of the 5th cent. BC. Commentators have rightly drawn attention to
discernible terminological similarities in the cosmogony of PDerv. and the Atom-
ists: necessity (ἀνάγκη), collision of atoms (κρούεσθαι), separation of matter into
small bodies (κατὰ μικρὰ μεμερισμένα), etc. The atomistic theory of matter and
the corpuscular theory of matter are not the same thing: every atomistic theory is
a corpuscular theory, but not every corpuscular theory is atomistic. Both Anaxi-
mander and Anaxagoras spoke of particles of matter (σπέρματα, μοῖραι), but they
did not regard them as indivisible. Hence the difficult question of whether the
Derveni author speaking of “tiny bodies” and particles has Anaxagoras’ divisible
“molecules” or Democritus’ indivisible atoms in mind. The cosmogonic vortex
(δίνη) and the mechanistic motion according to necessity featured already in
Anaximander’s cosmogony and even the equation of dine with moira/ananke
may have been a part of a common Ionian heritage.178 But the ‘collision’ of par-
ticles looks like a typically atomistic terminology, to which we should add the
even more striking case of θόρνυσθαι in PDerv., col. XXI.2–4, where it describes
the chaotic pre-cosmic motion of small particles of matter: ἐν τῶι ἀέρι κατὰ μικρὰ
μεμερισμένα ἐκινεῖτο | καὶ ἐθόρνυτο, θορνύμενα δ’ ἕκα<σ>τα συνεστάθη | πρὸς
ἄλληλα. The original meaning of this verb is “to thrust out,” “to extrude,” to
eject and ejaculate, hence it is used of copulation, hence θορός (“sperm”) and
θόρνη (“copulation”), on which the Derveni author comments (XXI.1).179 In non-
biological contexts it was also used for ‘shoot-like’ swift motion, e.g. of arrows
in shooting or of beans in winnowing.180 When applied to the movement of par-
ticles of matter, it is semantically very close, if not identical with ἐκθλίβεσθαι,
an important concept in the atomistic mechanics of the vortex, denoting the
‘extrusion’ or ‘pressing out’ of light particles to the periphery of the vortex.181
Democritus also uses the very same verb θόρνυμι/θρῴσκω in his description of
the swift motion of εἴδωλα.182 Neither κρούεσθαι, θόρνυσθαι, nor their synonyms
occur in Anaxagoras’ fragments, and this is not due to chance: in Democritus this
concept emphasized that the motion of atoms is not spontaneous or resulting
from an inner vital force or psyche, but is produced by external mechanical force,
by πληγή and ἀνάγκη. Democritus rejected and ridiculed Anaxagoras’ teleologi-
cal concept of Mind,183 but the Derveni author does not care about such blatant
contradictions, since he is an amateur in physics and the aim of his work is not
to construct a consistent physical theory of matter and material change, but to
reconstruct the “ancient” physiologia of Orpheus and to demonstrate that Greek
anthromorophic religion is the result of “ignorance” (amathia) and the ‘disease
of language.’ In col. XIV.1, ἐ]κθόρηι refers to the “sprouting out” of Protogonos
and the formation of the sun. The Derveni author ‘detects’ a mechanistic concept
of the contemporary science in an epic word suitable for a pious description of
divine birth.
Epigenes
lectures. He cannot be the author of the Derveni treatise because his exegeti-
cal style is different and because he denied the authenticity of Orpheus’ poems
(ἀναφερομένης), whereas the Derveni author pretends to accept it. It is not nec-
essary to assume that he was as ‘atheistic’ and iconoclastic as Prodicus or the
Derveni author: he seems to be a genuine allegorist and more sympathetic to
myth and religion.
Euthyphron
From what has been said above, it becomes clear that the attribution of the
Derveni treatise to Euthyphron proposed by Boyancé and Kahn cannot be cor-
rect.187 As William D. Furley has convincingly demonstrated,188 Euthyphron was
not a religious innovator and ‘sectarian’ (Burnet), but a religious orthodox and
conservative. As a professional soothsayer, he must have opposed natural philos-
ophy of the Ionian type (and its Sophistic applications to the history of religion)
and approved of the psephisma of his colleague Diopeithes banning the teaching
of ‘meteorology’ in Athens. The Derveni author, in turn, almost certainly must
have classed people like Euthyphron with τέχνην ποιούμενοι τὰ ἱερά, whom he
sarcastically attacks in col. ΧΧ. If our attribution of the Derveni treatise to Prodi-
cus is correct, and if Euthyphron, as Wilamowitz suggested,189 wrote a book on the
etymology of divine names, the relationship between their works must have been
polemical. Euthyphron should most likely be credited with ‘pious’ and mystical
etymologies of divine names: Ἀθηνᾶ = ἁ θεονόα, “divine mind,” or Ἥφαιστος =
φάεος ἵστωρ, “knower of light,” cited by Plato in Cra. 407b5 and c4. The purpose
of these etymologies was apparently apologetic: to defend and to preserve the
traditional images and functions of the gods as divine personalities, in conscious
opposition to the rationalistic and naturalistic interpretations of the ‘Anaxagore-
ans’ and Prodicus. Plato was well aware of both trends, and he mentions them
explicitly in Cra. 397a1, εἴτε τῶν ἱερέων τις εἴτε τῶν σοφιστῶν, where “priests”
primarily refers to Euthyphron, and “Sophists” to Prodicus. It would be natural to
conclude that the two versions of the philosophy of Orpheus in Plato (as above)
correspond to the hermeneutical approaches of Prodicus (the Ionian ‘Orpheus’)
and Euthyphron (the Pythagorean ‘Orpheus’).
This attribution190 cannot be accepted for the following reasons: 1) Strictly speak-
ing, ἀρχὴν | (...) ἔ[λ]αβ[εν in PDerv., col. VIII.4–5 is determined by the Orphic
verse and does not constitute a linguistic preference of the Derveni author. Not
is only the combination of ἀρχήν/βασιλείαν with λαμβάνειν/ἀφαιρεῖν a are very
common expression (as Burkert recognized himself), but it is also attested in
similar mythographic contexts with no relation to Orphica or Stesimbrotos.191 2)
The succession Rhea/Zeus/Artemis/Athena in Stesimbrotos does not seem to be
‘Orphic’ and cannot be reconciled with the Derveni theogony; the similarities with
the Rhapsodies and especially the marriage of Zeus with Demeter/Rhea in col.
XXII point to Dionysos as the successor to Zeus. 3) Stesimbrotos was a rhapsode,
and his approach to myth in the extant fragments of Περὶ τελετῶν (FGrHist 107
F 12–20) is traditional and somewhat naïve, with no trace of philosophical inter-
est or allegorical interpretation. In the only extant sample of his etymology of a
divine name, Διόνυσος is derived from Διόνυξος, “piercing Zeus,” on the grounds
that when Dionysos was born, he was horned and therefore ‘pierced’ the thigh of
Zeus (FGrHist 107 F 13). Stesimbrotos’ method is exactly the reverse of the Derveni
author’s. He does not reduce the mythical to the rational and the commonsensi-
cal; he firmly believes in the traditional myth of Dionysos’ miraculous birth from
the thigh of Zeus. Leaving the myth as it is, he tries to bring the name of the god in
accord with it.192 He is a highly unphilosophical mind; therefore, his identity with
the Derveni author should be ruled out with certainty.
Diagoras of Melos
Richard Janko made a move in the right direction with his general view of PDerv.
as an ‘atheistic’ work rather than a piece of religious philosophy or a work by
an Orphic initiate. But the attribution to Diagoras of Melos he proposed193 lacks
documentary basis altogether and is utterly unlikely. Betegh and Winiarczyk
have submitted Janko’s hypothesis to devastating and well-argued criticism.194
We accept as valid all their arguments except those which are based on the false
assumption that the Derveni author was an ‘Orphic’ himself. The attribution of
PDerv. to Diagoras fails to meet the basic requirements for any reliable attribution
that we formulated above in the ‘Preliminary remarks’: nothing is known about
Diagoras’ philosophical views on religion (or any other subject), and this lack of
information is not surprising given that he was not a philosopher, but a dithyram-
bic poet; and there is not a single quotation (verbatim or not) from his works that
might be cited as proof of his authorship. Janko tries to support his thesis, inter
alia, by citing two instances of the pronoun νιν in PDerv. (IV.9 and XI.3), a ‘Doric’
form that allegedly points to the Doric island of Melos. The dialect of PDerv. is
Ionic with Atticisms (see test. [17] above): this combination fits Ceos with nearby
Athens much better than Melos. As regards the instance of νιν in PDerv., Nikolai
Kazansky, an expert in Greek dialectology, comments per litteras: “The form νιν
is regarded as being of later origin (μιν is attested already in Mycenean), but it is
essential that it occurs not only in the choral lyric, but also in tragedians outside
lyrical parts. Compared with the neutral αὐτόν, -ήν this form should point to the
tradition defined as literary Doric and typical for Epidaurus. I would not venture
to determine by this form someone’s local dialect. In Attic tragedy this form is
native, not epic. In Attic inscriptions it does not occur, but still it was in use, since
only in Sophocles it occurs 80 times, and in Euripides 260, and it does occur in
stichomythia. To try to determine by this form one’s local dialect seems to me
fundamentally wrong.” The form νιν is attested in an archaic inscription from
Amorgos, another island from the group speaking the ‘Central Ionic’ dialect, to
which Ceos also belongs.195
The Clouds provide no evidence whatsoever on any philosophical work of
Diagoras. As scholiasts saw, Μήλιος in v. 830 stands for ἄθεος. Aristophanes does
not ascribe the identification of Zeus with the vortex to Diagoras, but he quotes
Prodicus by name in v. 361 as the greatest meteorosophistes and eo ipso reveals
his source. As regards Athenagoras’ report that Diagoras “divulgated the Orphic
logos” and the Eleusinian mysteries,196 most other testimonia mention only Ele-
usinan mysteries, so the profanation of the Ὀρφικὸς λόγος in this context may be
explained by the popular Athenian belief that Orpheus was the founder of the
Eleusinian mysteries and by the existence in the late 5th cent. BC of a body of epic
poetry connected with Eleusinian cults. Fritz Graf has advanced and persuasingly
argued for this hypothesis.197 In PDerv. the ‘poetry’ of Orpheus is directly linked to
195 SGDI, II, 163. On ‘Central Ionic’ see Miller (2014) 161; cf. also EAGLL, II, passim.
196 Athenag. Pro Christ. 4 (= Diag. fr. 27 Winiarczyk).
197 Graf (1974) 22 ff.; see also Bremmer (2014). On the ‘Eleusinian connection’ of PDerv., col. II
(prothymata to Eumenides) see Henrichs (1984b) 266–268.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 561
his hierourgia, i.e. to teletai (col. VII.2–3). Once we admit the authorship of Prodi-
cus, who played an important role in the intellectual life of Athens in the last third
of the 5th cent. BC, the Derveni Papyrus brings support to and a confirmation
of Graf’s hypothesis. The discussion of the mysteries in the first columns is not
a separate subject. The Derveni author (Prodicus) shares (or pretends to share)
the late 5th-cent. BC belief of the Athenians that Orpheus was the founder of the
Eleusinian mysteries and, in accordance with his view that Orpheus encoded his
wisdom both in his poetry and in the sacred rites, applies the same allegorical
method to dromena and legomena. In a manner typical for the Sophistic age,
he also cites anthropological and ethnographical ‘parallels’ from the rituals of
the Persian Magi that allegedly support his thesis.198 The main reason for doing
so was probably his conviction that the barbarians (at least some of them) were
closer to the primitive men from the Sophistic Kulturgeschichte and therefore may
have preserved some archaic features that have been lost in Greek culture. Cf.
Porph. Quaest. Hom. ad Il. 10.153, p. 285 MacPhail: ἦν δὲ τοιαῦτα τὰ παλαιὰ οἷαπερ
καὶ νῦν ἐν τοῖς βαρβάροις, “ancient beliefs were like those which still exist among
the barbarians.”199 (Incidentally this Sophistic anthropological doctrine was
‘rediscovered’ by Edward B. Tylor in his influential essay Primitive Culture that
appeared in 1870, including the theory of ‘survivals.’) In the early Greek tradition
on the Persian Magi, it is noted as a peculiar feature that they have no temples
and venerate the elements. From the similarity of the ritual performed by the
Magi with that of the Eleusinian mysteries (a τεκμήριον), the author infers that
Erinyes and Eumenides was the original name for air (ψυχαὶ = ἀήρ), like almost
all other mythological names. It is probably no accident that Aristophanes chose
the Persian cock for his parody of Prodicus’ ‘linguistic archaeology’ (see § [IX]
below).
198 Ahmadi (2014) has persuasively demonstrated that the magoi in col. VI are genuine Iranian
Magi, and not Greek charlatans.
199 Cf. Arist. Poet. 25.1461a3–4: οὕτω γὰρ τότ᾽ ἐνόμιζον, ὥσπερ καὶ νῦν Ἰλλυριοί.
200 See DAPR, T7.
562 Andrei Lebedev
on Anaxagoras’ trial, namely the reference to torture not attested elsewhere, and
secondly, it provides a clue for the elucidation of two very ‘tantalizingly’ obscure
passages in Euripides’ Orestes.
Philodemus uses the trial of Anaxagoras as a case in point in a list of misfor-
tunes of philosophers who failed to persuade judges or their fellow citizens and
therefore did not escape the death penalty or exile. Two other cases in the pre-
served portion of the list are those of Pythagoras and Socrates. Nobody has ever
doubted that Socrates indeed failed to persuade the judges in his apology and
was executed, and nobody doubts the general credibility of the ancient tradition
on Cylon’s uprising against Pythagoras and on the pogroms of the Pythagorean
synedria. Therefore, there is no reason whatsoever to doubt that Anaxagoras was
flogged (μασ]|τιγωθεὶς ) during the investigation and showed the stigmata201 to
the judges at his trial (μώλω|πας ἐπεδείκνυεν | τοῖς δικασταῖς): we should accept
this as historical fact. The language of Philodemus’s source is well illustrated
in the forensic speeches of classical orators. The phrase ἐπιδείκνυμι τεκμηρίωι
(-οις), “to demonstrate by proofs (facts),” or ἐπιδείκνυμι τεκμήρια, “to present
the proofs,” occurs in Lysias, Isaeus, and Demosthenes. Anaxagoras’ stigmata
were exactly such “proof” (τεκμήριον) of his torture that he “demonstrated”
(ἐπεδείκνυεν) to the judges (presumably, showing them his back). In a speech of
Hyperides, someone refers to the stigmata on the back of one of his opponent’s
201 The noun “bruises” is too mild a translation of the Greek μώλωπες. In the lexicographers,
it is a synonym of τραῦμα, πληγή, ἕλκος (Ael. Herod. De orthogr. 3.2, GG III.2.1, p. 593 Lentz). It
is regularly and specifically associated with flogging and scourge: in Theophrastus’ Physics (fr.
176 FHS&G), it illustrates a special kind of causation, scourge being the cause, and molops the
effect ([...] ἢ τρίτον ὑπὸ ἐντελεχείᾳ ὅλως ὄντος, ὡς καὶ ὁ μώλωψ· ὑπὸ γὰρ ἐντελεχείᾳ οὔσης τῆς
μάστιγος γίνεται, [...]). The μώλωπες bleed (πορφύρεοι, ἐρυθροί, φοινικοί) and may be the cause
of death (Luc. Philops. 20). As scars, they last for a long time: Plut. Aem. 19.9; Epict. Diss. 2.18.12
speaks of μώλωπες in the soul caused by the passions, which, unless completely wiped out from
the soul, become permanent scars and after the next emotional ‘flogging’ turn into open wounds
(ἕλκη). Showing one’s μώλωπες causes compassion. Lucian (Somn. 4), after his brother beat him
with a club, shows the stigmata to his mother and accuses him of “extreme cruelty” (πολλὴν
ὠμότητα); his mother becomes outraged, etc. In Machon Com. fr. 16.285–289 Gow, the hetaera
Gnathaina, after noticing οn the back of her lover μαστιγίας μώλωπας, exclaims: τάλαν, τάλαν,
ἄνερ, πόθεν ἔχεις ταῦτ᾽, ἔφη, τὰ τραύματα;, “Oh my poor, poor boy! From where have you gotten
these wounds?” In the New Testament, μώλωψ occurs once with a reference to the “healing
wound” of Christ the Saviour (Ep. Petr. 1 2.24); St. Paul (Ep. ad Gal. 6.17) speaks of στίγματα τοῦ
Ἰησοῦ and this expression becomes standard in Patristics. The distinction between μώλωψ as ἐκ
πολέμου γινομένη πληγή and στίγμα as a wound from flogging in the grammarian Ptolemaeus
(De diff. vocab., lett. μ, 99) is not supported by the early usage.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 563
slaves to prove that he was tortured: κρεμάσας ἐκ τοῦ κίονος ἐξέδειρεν, ὅθεν καὶ
μωλώπων ἔτι νῦν τὸ δέρμα μεστὸν ἔχει.202
The torture (βάσανοι) of Athenian citizens was forbidden by law, but free aliens
were not exempt from it.203 Classical orators attest to a number of cases in which
a free alien accused of a serious offence was tortured, either to extract a confes-
sion or as a punishment.204 In other words, in some cases, they were treated like
slaves, and that was the case of Anaxagoras. Physical pain aside, imagine how
unbearable the ‘Tantalic’ torture of the humiliation that deprived him the dignity
of eleutheros must have been for Anaxagoras. What kind of confession might the
interrogators of Anaxagoras have tried to extract from him? Since according to
Diodorus/Ephorus and Plutarch, the trial targeted Pericles, it is conceivable that
in addition to the confession of his own intentional asebeia, they were looking
for accomplices and threads leading to the ‘Olympian’ himself. Anaxagoras most
likely expounded his theory on the nature of the sun and the moon in his Peri
physeos published some 20 years before the trial. In Plato’s Apology, Socrates
asserts that it could be bought by anyone for one drachma from a bookstall in the
agora.205 The word μύδρος, “nugget,” that occurs in the reports about the prose-
cution is a rare and technical term (unlike the common πέτρος or βῶλος); there-
fore it looks like a verbatim quotation from his Peri physeos that probably figured
in the accusation. This word was enough for the accusation of disrespect towards
the νομιζόμενα of the polis, but to make their case even stronger, the investigators
probably were looking for tekmeria that the asebeia of Anaxagoras and his disci-
ples did not stop there, but went even further, i.e. that after rejecting traditional
beliefs they “introduced new gods” and new cults such as the ‘meteorosophistic’
initiations satirized in Aristophanes’ Clouds. The surprising accusation of Anaxa-
goras in medismos that presented him as an undercover Persian agent in Athens
was probably based on the alleged similarity between the non-anthropomorphic
‘naturalistic’ religion of the Persian Magoi (as perceived in early Greek tradition)
and the Anaxagorean physical allegoresis of traditional Greek mythology.
Keeping these considerations in mind, let us now turn to Euripides’ Orestes.
In vv. 4–10 the “blessed” (μακάριος) Tantalos “flies in the air fearing the rock that
rises over his head”; he “pays this penalty” for his “licentious tongue” (v. 10:
202 Hyp. fr. 200 Kenyon (= Poll. Onom. 3.79.6–7). Pollux remarks that ἐκδέρω, properly “to strip
the skin from somebody” in this passage is catachrestic. It should be taken as a rhetorical hyper
bole: he whipped the slave so fiercely that it was like stripping the skin from him.
203 See MacDowell (1978) 246–247.
204 See the list in Macdowell (1978) 274 n. 562.
205 Pl. Ap. 26e1.
564 Andrei Lebedev
ἀκόλαστον ἔσχε γλῶσσαν, αἰσχίστην νόσον).206 In vv. 982 ff., again in connection
with Tantalos, Electra mentions “a rock suspended by golden chains between
heaven and earth, a lump from Olympus carried by whirlwinds (δίναισι).” A lump
or nugget (βῶλος) is a metallurgical term, with which Euripides renders Anaxa-
goras’ μύδρος with exactly the same meaning. In both cases, the ‘rock’ of the
Tantalos myth is identified with the sun. This, combined with the Anaxagorean
motif of the ‘vortex,’ leaves no doubt that Euripides blends together the Homeric
golden chain and Anaxagoras’ astrophysics. Some modern interpreters suggest
that these passages rely on a rationalistic interpretation of the Tantalos myth that
derives from an Anaxagorean milieu.207 But it must be proved that Euripides here
relies on an intermediate source. Euripides himself was a distinguished repre-
sentative of the ‘Anaxagorean circles’ in Athens. He was a pupil and friend of
Anaxagoras, he knew his doctrines from the original source, he was a creative
poet, not a compilator, and he could freely use the doctrines of Anaxagoras in his
tragedies. Thus in Melanippe the Wise, Melanippe (another ‘ancient physiologos’)
recounts the traditional myth of the marriage of Heaven and Earth in the terms
of Anaxagorean cosmogony.208 She attributes it to “her mother,” i.e. Hippo, the
daughter of Cheiron the wise, a great culture hero and the inventor of various
τέχναι. Therefore we should listen rather to the ancient interpreters of Orestes
who attribute the rationalistic myth to Euripides himself.209 To begin with, there
is no allegoresis in these passages. The identification of the sun with an ‘ignited
lump’ was a scientific theory of Anaxagoras, and not an allegorical interpreta-
tion of a myth. In both passages, we are dealing with a parable rather than alle-
goresis, a parable about crime and punishment. Tantalos, like Melanippe, was an
ancient sage and a physiologos who held210 that the sun was a flying rock or lump
driven by a vortex (δίναισι). For this cosmological blasphemy, for his ἀκόλαστος
γλῶσσα (v. 10), he was punished by Zeus. The hyponoia for those who under-
stand ‘correctly’ is this: that is what happened in our days to Anaxagoras and
this will happen to any intellectual who dares to undermine traditional beliefs
by his ‘licentious tongue.’ The frightening ‘rock’ over the head of any physiologos
206 Eur. Or. 4 ff.: ὁ γὰρ μακάριος (κοὐκ ὀνειδίζω τύχας) / Διὸς πεφυκώς, ὡς λέγουσι, Τάνταλος /
κορυφῆς ὑπερτέλλοντα δειμαίνων πέτρον / ἀέρι ποτᾶται· κτλ. Cf. LSJ s.v. ὑπερτέλλω incorrectly
renders ὑπερτέλλω πέτρον as a rock “hanging over” Tantalos’ head. This verb is regularly ap-
plied to the rising sun, and it retains this meaning here.
207 Di Benedetto (1965) 7. Willink (1983) 32 n. 47 agrees and suggests Metrodorus of Lampsacus
as a possible source.
208 Eur. fr. 484 TrGF (Kannicht).
209 Diog. Laërt. 2.8; Schol. in Pind. Ol. 1.91 Drachmann (= Anaxag. 59 A 20 DK); Eust. In Od.
1700.60.
210 Or discovered a secret hidden by the gods from mortals?
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 565
is the permanent threat of the γραφὴ περὶ ἀσεβείας and the psephisma of Dio-
peithes, the servant of Zeus. Willink compares the “licentious tongue” with the
ἀδολεσχία of the meteorosophists like Prodicus in the Clouds, where ἀδολεσχία
is virtually a synonym of atheism (asebeia). Euripides, no doubt, shared Anaxa-
goras’ cosmological ‘blasphemy,’ but he could not acknowledge this openly:
hence the characterization of free speech as αἰσχίστη νόσος. Note, however, that
this condemnation is phrased as a common perception placed in oratio obliqua
which quotes what people say about Tantalos; Euripides distances himself from
people’s accusations (ὡς μὲν λέγουσιν) and delicately alludes to his compassion
(οὐκ ὀνειδίζω τύχας). The second crime of Tantalos, according to people’s accu-
sations, was his desire to be a commensal of the gods, and thus to be equal with
gods. This is probably a hint to the motif of the apotheosis of the philosopher
widespread in early Greek thought and attested both in the mystical apotheo
sis and deification in the Pythagorean tradition, and in the rather metaphorical
‘equation with the gods’ of a sophos in the Ionian humanist tradition: it is no
accident that the saying ὁ γὰρ νοῦς ἐν ἡμῖν θεός is attributed to Anaxagoras.211 In
both passages, Euripides speaks about ‘Tantalos’ with sympathy and compassion
for his tortures. If Anaxagoras indeed was tortured before the trial (as we believe
he was), Euripides must have known this fact. On these grounds, we venture to
propose a hypothesis that vv. 4–10 (coupled with 982 ff.) of Euripides’ Orestes are
a cryptic makarismos of Anaxagoras under the allusive name of Tantalos as an
innocent and heroic martyr of Greek ‘Enlightenment’ (cf. μακάριος in v. 4). Like
the mythical Tantalos, Anaxagoras endured unbearable tortures for revealing
the true nature of the heavenly bodies and the origin of the universe to human-
ity. The date of the production of Orestes is 408 BC: Euripides, quite probably,
commemorates the tragic fate of his teacher and friend on the occasion of the
20th anniversary of Anaxagoras’ death (428 BC). A similar makarismos of a man
who dedicated his life to the study of the laws of nature is found in Euripides’
fr. 910 Kannicht: ὄλβιος ὅστις τῆς ἱστορίας / ἔσχε μάθησιν, / κτλ. The adjectives
μακάριος and ὄλβιος are synonymous: in both passages, alluding to Anaxagoras,
they assert that the philosophical life is incompatible with the violation of law
(ἄδικοι πράξεις) and “nasty deeds” (αἰσχρὰ ἔργα); this looks like an apology of
Anaxagoras and a refutation of the false accusations against him in asebeia.212
(occurrences of the verb αἰωρέομαι). Willink (1983) ibid. compares ἀκόλαστος γλῶσσα with the
ἀδολεσχία of meteorosophistai like Prodicus mocked in the Clouds. But this would not affect our
interpretation of the Tantalos paradigm in Orestes.
213 For the distinction between metaphorical and natural analogy see Lebedev (2017a) 233–235.
214 Macdowell (1978) 201.
215 Macdowell (1978) 201; Garland (1992) 145.
216 Dressler (2014) 242.
217 Contra Dressler (2014) 241, who underestimates both the applicability and the impact of the
decree. See also Yunis (1988) 68 ff. and Rubel (2014) 35–37.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 567
Both (1) and (3) appear more likely than (2), but in the absence of definitive evi-
dence, we would rather leave this question open for further discussion. One
practical recommendation that follows from this investigation is that the Derveni
220 A comic word (Ar. Nub. 398) appropriated by the Epicureans as invective against Plato’s
doctrine of the divine Nous/Demiourgos: cf. ps.-Plut. Plac. 881a.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 569
The two lines apparently come from a dialogue scene in an unknown comedy.
The ‘loud-voiced’ bird is no doubt a cock. Cocks normally signal the morning hour
outside the house. The speaker who presumably wakes up at night after a crow
of a cock, whether real or imitated by someone, is indignant and demands expla-
nation by pointing to the absurdity of the situation. The suspect who ‘persuaded’
the cock to crow at night must be a Sophist or a rhetorician: it is a comic allu-
sion to Gorgias’ famous definition of rhetoric as a “maker of persuasion” (πειθοῦς
δημιουργός: Pl. Grg. 453a, 455a = 82 A 28 DK). Sophistic rhetoric can perform
wonders, even to ‘persuade’ a cock to crow at night! If so, the ‘house’ that pro-
vides the setting of the comedy seems to be a meeting place of Sophists like the
house of Callias, a favourite target of mockery in ancient comedy. The speaker
has an ‘Ionian accent’: εὐφρόνη is a poetic and Ionian word, inconceivable in
colloquial Attic. The only Sophist in the extant sources whose name is associated
with the very rare verb ὡρολογεῖν is Prodicus of Ceos. In his Lampoons (Silloi),
Timon of Phlius calls Prodicus λαβάργυρος ὡρολογητής, viz. “money-grasping
speaker-about-the-horai.” This phrase is part of a hexameter and therefore a ver
batim quotation from the Silloi.222 The noun ὡρολογητής is an absolute hapax,
most probably a neologism coined by Timon like his numerous other bombastic
words of abuse;223 μεγιστόφωνος is also hapax.224 But the verb ὡρολογέω from
which the nickname derives was in common use: this is proved by the fragment
from comedy and by an epigram of Posidippus.225 The sobriquet ὡρολογητής is
intentionally ambiguous: it alludes at the same time to the title of Prodicus’ work
221 We take τὴν εὐφρόνην adverbially, as acc. temporis (as it is used in Hdt. 7.188), not as direct
object of ὡρολογεῖν. Note that the preceding lemma in Suda (3811) illustrates the same meaning
of εὐφρόνη by quoting (also anonymously) exactly this passage of Herodotus: ταύτην μὲν τὴν
εὐφρόνην οὕτω ἔμεινον, ἅμα δὲ ὄρθρῳ κτλ. This fact alone leads us to expect in 3812 a quotation
from a classical author.
222 Ath. 9.71.406d–e (= Tim. fr. 18 Di Marco = fr. 792 Lloyd-Jones/Parsons = Prodic. test. 9 May-
hew).
223 More than 40 new formations in 135 fragments, according to Clayman (2009) 131.
224 It cannot be found either in LSJ or in the Supplement. TLG search yields, in addition to the
Suda passage, only one instance in Tzetz. Chil. 4.4.859, where it is used for the characterization
of a proverbial ‘fool’ who all the day ‘crowed’ “alpha, beta, gamma” like another fool who could
count only up to 3, and then started again “one, two, three,” etc. The source of Tzetzes is most
likely our passage in Suda: the verb ἀνέκραζε that he uses alludes to the cock’s ‘crow’: cf. Jo.
Chrys. HEph. 4.12.3 Montfaucon (PG 62.92).
225 Posidipp. fr. 52 Austin/Bastiniani.
570 Andrei Lebedev
Ὧραι and to his provebial philargyria: he charged for his lectures “by hour.”226
Ambrose and Mayhew have advanced a plausible hypothesis that the lost comedy
Ὧραι of Aristophanes was related to Prodicus’ work with the same title; accord-
ing to Mayhew, Aristophanes’ Seasons may have been a ‘reply’ to Prodicus’ work
of the same title or contained a parody of it.227 It is hard to imagine a more appro-
priate source for our fragment than a comedy with a title Ὧραι. In Aristophanes’
Seasons, Callias indeed was mentioned; he was described as “wealthy, pathicus,
ruined by prostitues, and feeding parasites (flatterers).”228 Socrates’ associate
Chaerephon was probably one of these κόλακες. It is tempting to suggest that
the speaker in our fragment is Prodicus (or a caricature of him under a different
name) and that the comic poet puts the verb ὡρολογεῖν (along with the Ionian
word for night) into his mouth as a distinctive feature of his discourse. But even
without this suggestion, ὡρολογητής is likely to be a mocking parody of Pro-
dicus’ terminology.229 An important question that is not so easy to answer with
certainty is this: can we explain the verbal coincidence of the comedy fragment
and Timon’s Silloi by the common source (i.e. Prodicus’ Horai) or by Timon’s ‘quo-
tation’ of Aristophanes’ Horai?230 Even if Timon depends on the comedy, we lose
nothing, since in this case he explicitly identifies the speaker in the Suda frag-
ment as Prodicus.
We know from Cicero that Aristophanes “attacked new gods and the nocturnal
vigils that accompany their worship, so that in his play Sabazios and certain other
immigrant gods are expelled from the city after a trial.”231 It is probably from the
final expulsion scene that the fr. 578 PCG comes: τὸν Φρύγα, τὸν αὐλητῆρα, τὸν
Σαβάζιον. Fr. 581, the most significant of the remaining fragments, is a dialogue
226 So in the Epitome of Ath. 5.2.2 (p. 22) and Eust. In Il. 4.901.3–4 (λαβάργυρον ἔφη ὡς ἐπὶ μισθῷ
ὡρολογοῦντα) in his quotation of the Athenaeus passage: cf. Mayhew (2011) 81.
227 Ambrose (1983) 137 ff.; Mayhew (2011) App. 4, 247–248.
228 Schol. (VΔ) in Luc. Iov. trag. 48, p. 83.16 Rabe (= Ar. [Horai] fr. 583 PCG).
229 In Posidipp. fr. 52 Austin/Bastianini the verb means “to count” the days rather than “to tell”:
see the explanation of parthenos as caryatis in Fain (2010) 105. In the derivatives ὡρολογεῖον
(later ὡρολόγιον), “clocks” (used both of sun dial and klepsydra), the second element of the
compound, also means “to measure, to count,” not “to speak.” Cf. Orion Theb. Etymol., lett. Ω,
170.26–28 Sturz: Ὡρολογεῖον· λέγειν τὸ μετρεῖν. ὡρολογεῖον οὖν, ἐν ᾧ τὰς ὥρας μετροῦμεν. οὕτως
Ἀπολλώνιος ἐν Γλώσσαις Ἡροδότου.
230 On the influence of Greek comedy and especially of Aristophanes on Timon’s Silloi, see Clay-
man (2009) 124–130.
231 Cic. Leg. 2.37 (= Ar. [Horai], PCG III.2, 296, test. *ii): novos vero deos et in his colendis noc
turnas pervigilationes sic Aristophanes, facetissimus poeta veteris comoediae, vexat, ut apud eum
Sabazius et quidam alii dei peregrini iudicati e civitate eiciantur (transl. by J. Henderson). The
expression nocturnas pervigilationes suggests νυκτιπολεῖν, νυκτιπόλοι in the original Greek, and
the last words καταδικασθέντες ἐκβάλλονται ἐκ τῆς πόλεως.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 571
between two unnamed characters: (A) is a god who promises to turn the market of
Athens into a miraculous cornucopia of all kind of fruits, vegetables, poultry, etc.
available throughout the year, even in midwinter, as a reward “for honouring the
gods” (v. 13: ἐπειδὴ τοὺς θεοὺς σέβουσιν).232 His opponent (B) is a commonsensi-
cal skeptic: he does not believe in such miracles (instead of summer fruits in mid-
winter he expects rather to see a blinding dust-wind (v. 2) and warns that seeing
gourds (a summer vegetable) in midwinter would confuse people about the time
of the year (vv. 6–7), i.e. there will be confusion in telling time (sc. ὡρολογεῖν). In
the end, the skeptic (B) accuses (A) with indignation: “you have turned Athens
into Egypt!” (v. 15: Αἴγυπτον αὐτῶν τὴν πόλιν πεποίηκας ἀντ’ Ἀθηνῶν). In earlier
scholarship, (A) has been erroneously identified as Athena. Olson is right when
he points out that the choir of Seasons would sympathize with (B) since (A) is
their enemy who wishes to abolish seasons altogether. Olson also correctly asso-
ciates the speaker (A) with the new gods and (B) with the traditional ones. The
appearance of Egypt cannot be chalked up only to the stereotype of it as the land
without seasons (Hdt. 2.77.3); according to Olson’s penetrating suggestion, “the
more substantial point is that the city has no need of Egypt’s plethora of absurd
deities.”233 While accepting Olson’s general approach, we would venture to make
a further step in the same direction by specifying precisely both the identities of
the two speakers and of the “absurd deities” of Egypt. In later authors, Sabazios
was identified with the “chthonian Dionysos,” the son of Zeus and Persephone
distinguished from the traditional Greek Dionysos, the son of Semele. This Dio-
nysos was already in 5th cent. BC associated with Orpheus’ theogony (Hieros
logos) and the myth of sparagmos of the divine child by the evil Titans: in the
so-called ‘Orphic graffiti’ from Olbia dating from the second half of the 5th cent.
BC, he is named Διόνυσος Ὀρφικός.234 The dialogue in fr. 581 is between the ‘old
good’ Dionysos of Greek myth (in whose theatre the comedy was performed) and
232 Note that ἐπειδὴ τοὺς θεοὺς σέβουσιν is not a condition, but a statement of fact.
233 Olson (2007) 107.
234 We take ΟΡΦΙΚŌΙ as dat. sing., not as nom. plur.: Διο[νύσοι] Ὀρφικοί is a prescription to
sacrifice to Dionysos Orphikos, i.e. to Dionysos of Orpheus’ Theogony, the son of Persephone,
not the son of Semele. The ugly plate cannot be a dedication to Dionysos by a collegium of ‘Or-
phics.’ Ὀρφικοί is a late term: we know that the owners of the ‘Orphic’ lamellae called themselves
μύσται καὶ βάκχοι, and not Ὀρφικοί. According to our hypothesis, the Olbian bone plates were
kleromantic devices connected with astragalomanteia (7 astragaloi of Dionysos may be depicted
on one of the plates), ancient ancestors of the Tarot cards. Their owner was probably a “diviner of
Hermes” (θεοπρόπος Ἑρμοῦ) with a ‘royal’ Persian name Φαρνάβαζος known from other Olbian
graffiti. Pharnabazos either posed as a magos or was an Orpheotelestes, or both. He probably
had some competition with a rival street-diviner called Aristoteles: we interpret two ostraka pub-
lished by Rusyayeva and Vinogradov as an exchange of angry curse letters between them. He
572 Andrei Lebedev
the outlandish newcomer, his illegal half-brother who was worshipped at night.
Aristophanes portraits him as an impostor (probably targeting Orpheoletstai and
agyrtai) who deceives the would-be worshippers with false promises of material
paradise on earth and eternal bliss in heaven (μέθη αἰώνιος, in Plato’s words)
in order to gain profit. The agon between Dionysos and Sabazios recalls the
agon of Dikaios and Adikos logos in the Clouds. It was probably staged as a trial
with Athena presiding as a judge, who, after hearing the litigation, chooses the
worship of the traditional Dionysos in her city and condemns the alien god, “the
Phrygian, the flutist, Sabazios” to exile.235 Sabazios probably was wearing a Phry-
gian cap and pictured as a wandering agyrtes and flute-player (αὐλητήρ) with
vulgar manners; Dionysos must have been portrayed as a kompsos Athenian gen-
tleman with good manners. Such contrast is suggested by the dialogue between
the two. This reconstruction of the general plot can be supported by a roughly
contemporary parallel provided by Cratinus’ comedy with the same title Ὧραι.236
In this play, Dionysos figured in person; his mistress, although abandoned by him
(like Ariadne?), still loves him; the choir hails him as μακάριος τῶν παιδικῶν (fr.
278), a rare instance of τὰ παιδικά applied to a woman. Three fragments contain
legal terms. In fr. 279, someone (probably a demagogue or rhetor) is compared
with a “vociferous Persian cock who crows all the time”: ὥσπερ ὁ Περσικὸς ὥραν
πᾶσαν καναχῶν ὁλόφωνος ἀλέκτωρ.237 Already in the 5th cent. BC, the antiq-
uity of Orpheus’ theogony was doubted by some skeptics, Herodotus and Ion of
Chios among them. Herodotus ironically remarks that the “so-called Orphic and
Bacchic” rites are in fact Egyptian and Pythagorean implying that Pythagoras
imported them much later from Egypt.238 Heraclitus, in turn, accused Pythago-
ras of stealing his wisdom from the writings of Thoth.239 Aristophanes may have
worked in the agora of Olbia in the last quarter of the 5th cent. BC near the temple of Zeus where
he lost his cards. On Pharnabazos see Lebedev (1996).
235 Two out of the scanty 13 fragments are related with a trial. In fr. 579 PCG, διέφθορας τὸν
ὅρκον ἡμῶν (“you have violated our oath”), the reference must be to the Attic διωμοσία, the
“mutual oath” of both parties before ἀνάκρισις (ἡμῶν!). The oath must have been violated by the
bad guy Sabazios: hence Dionysos is speaking. In fr. 588 δικαστικὸν ~ τριώβολον is mentioned.
236 PCG IV, frs. 269–298.
237 We follow the traditional understanding of ὁλόφωνος “vox et praeterea nihil” (LSJ) rather
than from ὀλοός + φωνή, “killing with his voice” (Meineke) . Cf. Μεγιστόφωνος in Aristophanes’
Seasons.
238 Hdt. 2.81.5–7: ὁμολογέουσι δὲ ταῦτα τοῖσι Ὀρφικοῖσι καλεομένοισι καὶ Βακχικοῖσι, ἐοῦσι δὲ
αἰγυπτίοισι, καὶ <τοῖσι> Πυθαγορείοισι.
239 Heraclit. 22 B 129 DK, reading (= fr. 22 Lebedev) (…) καὶ ἐπιλεξάμενος Τααύτου τὰς συγγραφὰς
ἐποιήσατο κτλ. for ταύτας τὰς συγγραφάς, “and having read the writings of Taautos (= Thoth),
he claimed as his own wisdom what was (in fact) much learning and a con game.”
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 573
shared the skeptical view, according to which the myth of the chthonian Dionysos
and the Titans was invented by Onomacritus, who made an interpretatio Graeca
of the Egyptian myth of Isis and Osiris and expounded it in Homeric hexameters
as a Hieros logos of Orpheus.240 A second allusion to Sabazios’ connection with
Egypt is Dionysos’ remark about the danger of a “blinding dust-wind” in Athens
(κονιορτὸν ἐκτυφλοῦντα, fr. 581.2), a picture more reminiscent of a sandstorm in
the Egyptian desert rather than of the actual weather in winter Athens.
What was the relationship between the theme of alien gods and the mockery
of the Sophists in Callias’ house in the Seasons? The Clouds suggest an obvious
answer: the common denominator was the introduction of new gods that were
subversive to the religion and morality of the polis. Chaerephon, who seems to be
the acting director of Socrates’ phrontisterion in the Clouds, is called a “child of
the night” (παῖδα τῆς νυκτός) in the Seasons, and a ‘bat’ (νυκτερίς) in the Birds.241
These passages should be linked with the mysterious cock who awakes the inhab-
itants of Callias’ house at nighttime and with irrational Sabazios’ disrespect for
the rational Greek method of telling time in fr. 581. Do the inhabitants of Callias’
house wake up at night in order to participate in the nocturnae pervigilationes
of the worship of Sabazios? Did Aristophanes depict the nocturnal mysteries of
Sabazios as sexual orgies of Sophists and pornidia at Callias’ house? The scanty
remains of Aristophanes’ Seasons do not allow for a definite answer. We confine
ourselves to drawing attention to some details that might point in this direction.
Callias in the Seasons was depicted as πλούσιος καὶ πασχητιῶν καὶ ὑπὸ πορνιδίων
διαφορούμενος και κόλακας τρέφων (fr. 583). Hipponicus and Callias, the para-
digmatic father and son pair in the Seasons, mirror Strepsiades and Pheidippi-
des in the Clouds: an old-fashioned, but honest and hard-working father on the
one hand, and a morally corrupt and effeminate son, an akolastos dandy who
wastes the hard-earned fortune of his father, on the other. The only difference is
that Pheidippides wastes his father’s money on horses, and Callias on pornidia
and kolakes. The new ecstatic cult and the bohemian life-style of Callias’ salon
share one feature in common: excess in sexual activity and drinking.242 Callias
240 The Egyptian origin of the Orphica and Dionysos’ Orphikos (Sabazios, Zagreus etc.) was
recognised by both Orphic believers and non-believers: see OF 40–63. They only disagreed about
the date of this event: the believers attributed it to Orpheus himself (i.e. 14th cent. BC), and the
non-believers (Aristotle among them) to Onomacritus in the late 6th cent. BC. We side with Aris-
totle. Edmonds’ thesis of a much later ‘construction’ of Zagreus’ myth is hypercritical: the Orphic
myth of the diamelismos and Dionysos/Aides were known already to Heraclitus.
241 Ar. fr. 584 PCG; Av. 1296 and 1564.
242 Intoxication is a characteristic of the worship of Sabazios: in Ar. Vesp. 9–10 two drinking
slaves “worship the same god.” On the ecstatic mania of bacchic initiantions see Ustinova (2018)
115 ff., 124 (on Sabazios).
574 Andrei Lebedev
nist.250 The misogynism of Euripides’ Hippolytus (vv. 952 ff.) results from reading
too many Orphic books and chastising his body with a vegetarian diet. Inciden-
tally, Euripides was a friend and a pupil of Prodicus, and both of them were dis-
ciples of Anaxagoras and were therefore godless ‘Anaxagoreans’ in the eyes of
Diopeithes & Co. Euripides’ Hippolytus was produced in 428, in the first years
after the psephisma of Diopeithes and the trial of Anaxagoras, about the same
time as the PDerv (Prodicus’ Horai), and the very same year as Anaxagoras’ death
in Lampsacus. The chances are that the Aristophanes-style invective, unusual for
a tragedy, against an ‘Orphic’ Hippolytus with his anti-social sectarianism – along
with Theseus’, the father of the Athenian demos, egoistic obsession with personal
salvation and disrespect for Aphrodite, as well as the dismissal of Orpheus’ books
as nonsense (καπνός) – was Euripides’ message of solidarity to his Anaxagorean
friends, first of all to Prodicus and Protagoras. Alternatively, or at the same time,
it may have been a masked invective against Diopeithes & Co.: you swear by the
name of Orpheus who ἀσεβεῖ against τὰ πάτρια, as the religion of our forefathers
is based on animal sacrifice (θυσία), and not on a vegetarian diet (ἄψυχος βορά).
250 OF 1003–1004.
251 Th. Gelzer ap. RE, Suppl. XII, s.v. Aristophanes, 1408–1409. Similarly Ambrose (1983) 137.
576 Andrei Lebedev
turnal scenes following the crow of the cock alluded to the profanation of the
mysteries in a private house by means of a mocking reenactment of the Eleusin
ian ritual. One might conjecture, for instance, that Prodicus played the role (in
allusive form) of a hierophant (like Socrates in the Clouds), Callias the role of
a dadouchos, and Chaerephon the role of a keryx. The ‘booming’ bass of Prodi-
cus (Pl. Prot. 315d) may have been comically contrasted with the squeaky voice
of Chaerephon the Bat. Callias was a hereditary torch-bearer (dadouchos) in the
Eleusinian mysteries. Andocides (1.124) accuses him of illicit cohabitation in the
same house with the daughter of Ischomachos and her mother. He sarcastically
presents this as a blasphemous reenactment of his priestly duties to serve both
“Mother and Daughter” in the cult of Eleusinian Demeter: καὶ συνῴκει ὁ πάντων
σχετλιώτατος ἀνθρώπων τῇ μητρὶ καὶ τῇ θυγατρί, ἱερεὺς ὢν τῆς Μητρὸς καὶ τῆς
Θυγατρός, καὶ εἶχεν ἐν τῇ οἰκίᾳ ἀμφοτέρας. Iphicrates called Callias metragyrtes
rather than dadouchos (μητραγύρτην ἀλλ᾽ οὐ δᾳδοῦχον, Arist. Rhet. 3.2.1405a20);
this joke may be a reference to Aristophanes’ Seasons, in which Sabazios wor-
shipped in Callias’ house was portrayed as metragyrtes associated with the Great
Mother.252 After the Sicilian disaster (413), ‘bad omens’ preceding the expedition
of 415 were recalled (Plut. Nic. 18), especially the lamentations of the adoniazou
sai women and the cries Σαβάζιος (Ar. Lys. 388): thus in popular imagination,
Sabazios and other alien gods may have been blamed as scapegoats responsible
for the catastrophy. Therefore the most plausible date of the Seasons is one of
the nearest occasions after the fall of 413 BC (Lenaia 413?). The dialogue between
Sabazios and Dionysos in fr. 582 presupposes winter-time. The winter of 413/412
BC must have been one of the hardest in the history of Athens with the public
mood utterly depressed. According to Hansen’s estimate, in the Sicilian disaster
the Athenian army lost 3000 citizens, and the Athenian fleet 160 triremes each
with a crew of 200 or so, i.e. more than 30,000.253 Athens was literally depopu-
lated: the polis was turned into a desert. That is the meaning of Dionysos’ caustic
retort to Sabazios, “You have turned Athens into Egypt!” Sabazios was thought to
be the the same as Adonis (see supra), and in popular imagination, the laments
of adoniazousai women at the moment when the fleet was departing from Piraeus
may have been perceived not only as forecasting, but also as magically causing
the disaster.
252 According to Strab. 10.3.15 Sabazios is a child of the Great Mother (Meter), and Sabazia are
the same as Metroa (Strab. 10.3.18). The teletai of Aischines’ mother in Dem. 18.259–260 combine
peculiar features of Sabazios cult (cries εὐοὶ σαβοί, snakes) with what seems prima facie Bacchic
(νεβρίς, κρατηρίζω), Orphic (βίβλους), and metragyrtic (Kybele/Attis) elements. However, all
these belong to the same mystery initiation of Dionysos/Sabazios, the child of Meter, OF 577–578.
253 Hansen (1988) 15.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 577
euhemeristic second stage in Prodicus’ theory of the origin of religion. The theory
is “proved” (ἐπιδείξω) by empirical facts (τεκμήρια). Τεκμήρια were of primary
importance not only in the courts and in rhetoric, but also in Hippocratic medi-
cine and (pace Popper) in early Ionian Peri physeos historia.264 Like the Derveni
author and Prodicus, Peisthetairos resorts to ‘linguistic archaeology.’ The Derveni
author looks for the tekmeria that are ‘remnants’ of the beliefs of the ἀρχαῖοι not
only in ‘ancient poetry’ and in ritual, but also in proverbial expressions (φάτις)
like μοῖραν ἐπικλῶσαι or ἀφροδισιάζειν. Peisthetairos finds such a tekmerion in
the Greek name of the farmyard cock Περσικὸς ὄρνις. He indeed was an ancient
king of the Persians, “more ancient that Darius and Megabyzus,” as one may infer
(τεκμαίρεσθαι) from his upright comb (the upright cap was a privilege of the Great
King) and his royal power to wake up people of all professions. This may be com-
pared with the μεγιστόφωνος ὄρνις and ὡρολογεῖν in the comedy fragment cited
above. The list of craftsmen adduced as proof of the royal power of the cock looks
like a parody of Prodicus’ reference to τέχναι. Note that ἀλφιταμοιβοί are likely to
be the same as γεωργοί, for as Dunbar’s (1995) notes ad loc., in 5th-cent. Athens,
producers and sellers were as a rule the same.
264 On τεκμαίρεσθαι as empirical method in Alcmaeon and early Greek science, see Lebedev
(2017c).
265 ‘Gorgianic’ need not be restricted to Gorgias himself: on the influence of Heraclitus’ anti-
thetic style on Gorgias, Hippias, and Democritus, see Norden (19582) I, 18–23.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 579
266 Cfr. frs. 136–160 Lebedev; also theological Probabilia, frs. 10–15 Lebedev. The source of Dio-
genes Laërtius’ division of Heraclitus’ books into three logoi (9.5) is most probably Diodotus, as in
the description of its scope (9.15). We refute the mistaken view that this division is Stoic: in Stoic
thought, theology is a part of physics, and politics is a part of ethics. The differences do not stop
here: the first chapter Περὶ τοῦ παντός combines Logos theory and Fire cosmology, i.e. logic and
physics, and ethics is a part of politics in ch. 2. Cf. Lebedev (2014) 22–27.
580 Andrei Lebedev
of life and procreation, but in fact they worship the god of death, whose name
in hidden in αἰδοῖον, and “generate new deaths.” In other words, they commit a
ἁμαρτία. The chances are that the Derveni author’s interest in wineless libations
(ἄοινα) in the first columns of PDerv. is a reflection of Heraclitus’ anti-alcoholic
and anti-Bacchic exhortations.
From the convergence of Chalcidius’ evidence with the Hippocratic De diaeta
1, we can infer that Heraclitus admitted the possibility of divination and believed
in prophetic dreams.269 After Tsantsanoglou (1997), the author of PDerv., col.
V.4 (πάριμεν [εἰς τὸ μα]ντεῖον ἐπερ[ω]τήσ[οντες, “we enter an oracle in order to
ask a question”) has often been understood as a mantis or a religious specialist
himself,270 but this understanding is contradicted by the verb ἐπερ[ω]τήσ[οντες:
diviners do not ask questions, they answer them. We could not find a single
instance of ἕνεκα in the sense of “for the sake of others” using various whole
corpus proximity TLG searches for ἕνεκα with various verbs meaning “to ask an
oracle” and nouns meaning “oracular response.” In all instances we found, ἕνεκα
(or its synonym χάριν) in similar contexts refers to the purpose of consulting an
oracle (syn. περὶ ὧν), but never means “for the sake of somebody”271 The words
τῶν μαντευομένων ἕνεκα therefore mean “for the sake of prophecies,” and not
“for the sake of inquierers.”272 The “we” in the pluralis πάριμεν refers not to a
certain group or a corporation, but to general human habits. Greek philosophers,
especially moralists, use we when they speak about common habits, practices,
or experiences of people in general. Consider, for example, Heraclit. 22 B 21 DK
(= fr. 77 Lebedev): θάνατός ἐστιν ὁκόσα ἐγερθέντες ὁρέομεν, κτλ., “death is what
we see while being awake, (…),” and Arist. Εth. Νic. 2.3.1104b9: διὰ μὲν γὰρ τὴν
ἡδονὴν τὰ φαῦλα πράττομεν, διὰ δὲ τὴν λύπην τῶν καλῶν ἀπεχόμεθα. Examples
can be multiplied. In the latter quotation, the speaker probably does not even
include himself into his “we.” It would be preposterous to infer from this use of
“we” that Aristotle indulged in pleasures and abstained from noble behavior. The
sentence under discussion in PDerv., col. V.3–6 may well have been an interro-
gation (with an expected negative answer) in a series of rhetorical questions.273
From the moralistic condemnation of their ἁμαρτία and ἡδονή, one may
rather infer that he disapproved of their habit of consulting oracles. The Hippo-
cratic author of De diaeta admits that dreams may have prognostic value but dis-
courages his reader from going to interpreters of dreams because they often make
mistakes (ἁμαρτία). Instead, he advises the reader himself to interpret the signs of
health and disease in their dreams following his naturalistic guidelines.274 There
are reasons to suppose that Heraclitus also believed that he possessed an inter-
nal, personal Delphic oracle in his psyche: ἐδιζησάμην ἐμεωυτόν (B 101 = fr. 97
Lebedev). There are indications in the Heraclitean tradition that he interpreted
the most horrible of τὰ δεινά in Hades as an allegory of the actual moral condi-
tion of humanity, and the authors who quote this allegory repeatedly connect
the “filth” with ἡδονή and ὕες who βορβόρωι ἥδονται μᾶλλον ἢ καθαρῶι ὕδατι.275
In the Republic, Plato says that the dialectical method elevates the “eye of the
soul” buried in “barbaric filth” and raises it up: ἡ διαλεκτικὴ μέθοδος (...) τῷ ὄντι
ἐν βορβόρῳ βαρβαρικῷ τινι τὸ τῆς ψυχῆς ὄμμα κατορωρυγμένον ἠρέμα ἕλκει καὶ
ἀνάγει ἄνω, (...) (Resp. 7.533c7 ff.). Hermann Fränkel plausibly suggested that τῷ
ὄντι indicates a verbatim quotation (“indeed,” i.e. “as they say”) and identified
the source as Heraclitus.276 A striking parallel is provided by Plot. Enn. 1.6 (1).6.1
ff.: ἔστι γὰρ δή, ὡς ὁ παλαιὸς λόγος, καὶ ἡ σωφροσύνη καὶ ἡ ἀνδρία καὶ πᾶσα
ἀρετὴ κάθαρσις καὶ ἡ φρόνησις αὐτή. διὸ καὶ αἱ τελεταὶ ὀρθῶς αἰνίττονται τὸν μὴ
κεκαθαρμένον καὶ εἰς Ἅιδου κείσεσθαι ἐν βορβόρῳ, (...)· οἷα δὴ καὶ ὕες, οὐ καθαραὶ
τὸ σῶμα, χαίρουσι τῷ τοιούτῳ. κτλ. The “ancient logos” quoted by Plotinus is
almost certainly the word of Heraclitus. Since Heraclitus in B 14 (= frs. 146–147
Lebedev) condemns the mysteries accepted among men as unholy and threat-
ens the Bacchic initiates with punishment, it seems that he paradoxically rein-
terpreted the image of sinners “buried in filth” that refers to future punishment
as a moralistic allegory of the present condition of humanity. The ethical topos
characterizing a vicious person as a δοῦλος τῶν παθῶν is alluded to in PDerv., col.
273 E.g. ἆρα] (Lebedev) πόθωι (Janko) π[ερ]ὶ (Lebedev) | αὑτοῖς πάριμεν [εἰς το μα]ντεῖον
ἐπερ[ω]τήσ[οντες,] |5 τῶν μαντευομένων [ἕν]εκεν, εἰ θέμι[ς προσ]δοκᾶν (Piano) | ἐν Ἅιδου δεινά;
τί ἀπιστοῦσι; “Do we by regret [or “disquietude”] about ourselves ever consult an oracle for the
sake of prophecies, in order to ask whether it is righteous to expect the horrors in Hades? Why
do they do not believe?”
274 Hippoc. De diaet. 1.87–88.
275 Heraclit. 22 B 13 [II] DK (= fr. probab. 10 Lebedev).
276 Fränkel (1938) 311 ff.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 583
V.9 ([τ]ῆς ἄλλης ἡδον[ῆ]ς νενικημέν[οι). It fits perfectly with Heraclitus’ strongly
anti-hedonistic ethics of σωφρονεῖν, which is proclaimed the ἀρετὴ μεγίστη in B
112 (= fr. 100 Lebedev).
We encounter the same epistemological scale of cognitive faculties ἀκούειν
(ἰδεῖν)/μανθάνειν/γινώσκειν (i.e. sensation/experience/knowledge) in PDerv.,
col. XX. Rusten explained the paragraphos at XX.10 as a mark of the end of a
quotation (preceding ll. 1–10) from a prose writer.277 This remains a plausible sug-
gestion, or at least a serious possibility.278 Along with the ‘Gorgianic’ flavour of
the exquisite style of this column, this suggestion can be supported by the use of
the word γνώμη on col. XX.10 (καὶ τῆς γνώμης στερόμενοι πρὸς ἀπέρχονται). In
early Ionian prose (Hippocrates, Herodotus), γνώμη was often used in the sense
of “intelligence, mind” as distinguished from or opposed to the “body” or the
senses. This use of the word was well known to Galen, who comments on one
such instance in Hippocrates: τῶν αἰσθήσεων ἁπάσαις τὴν γνώμην ἐφεξῆς ἔταξεν,
ὅπερ ἐστὶ τὴν διάνοιαν, ἥν τε καὶ νοῦν καὶ φρένα καὶ λόγον κοινῶς οἱ ἄνθρωποι
καλοῦσιν.279 What was known to Galen has often been neglected by many inter-
preters of Heraclitus, who mistranslated this word280 in what is probably the most
important theological fragment of Heraclitus: “To recognize only one wise being
(= god): that Mind (Γνώμην) which alone steers the whole Universe.”281 In Attic
in the theory of names and his doctrine of the “common Logos,” which, due to
the poets’ misreading of it, resulted in the invention of polytheism.286 The verb
κρατιστεύειν, like its Homeric synonym ἀριστεύειν (αἰὲν ἀριστεύειν, Il. 6.208;
11.784), is often used in an agonistic context, therefore κρατιστεύοντες (...)
λέγουσι most likely refers to prize-winning poets like Homer and Archilochus who,
according to Heraclitus’ wish in 22 B 42 DK (= fr. 17 Lebedev), should be “thrown
out from competitions and flogged” (ἐκ τῶν ἀγώνων ἐκβάλλεσθαι καὶ ῥαπίζεσθαι).
In PDerv., col. XXII.1–6, the poets’ incorrect naming of the gods is contrasted with
Orpheus’ correct onomatothesia. The false naming results in “many names” of
different gods (i.e. polytheism), while the correct method recognizes one and the
same entity behind “many names” (i.e. monotheism): cf. Aesch. PV 210 (πολλῶν
ὀνομάτων μορφὴ μία) and Antisth. test. 179a Prince (= fr. 39a Decleva Caizzi ap.
Phld. De piet., PHerc. 1428, fr. 21.31–34 Schober: (...) λέγεται τὸ | κατὰ νόμον εἶναι |
πολλοὺς θεοὺς κα|τὰ δὲ φύσιν ἕν[α]). The “ignorance” (ἀμαθία) of poets concern-
ing “things divine” (τὰ θεῖα is the object of ἀπιστία in Heraclit. 22 B 86 DK = fr.
136 Lebedev) is a result of a fatal error (ἁμαρτ<ί>ης , col. V.8), which corresponds
exactly to what we have called the ‘linguistic mistake’ of mortals aka the ‘disease
of language.’ Orpheus’ onomatothesia is based on knowledge and understanding
(γινώσκων, col. XXII.2), whereas poetic discourse is based on emotion (θυμόν, col.
ΧΧΙΙ.5) and drinking too much: according to Heraclitus’ moral psychology, sex and
wine make the soul ‘wet’ and impair human intelligence (φρόνησις) and sound
judgement (γνώμας). Plutarch quotes Heraclitus’ dictum about ἀμαθία 4 times;
in two out of four quotations, ‘ignorance’ is linked with drinking wine (Quaest.
conv. 644a1, παρ’ οἶνον; fr. 129 Sandbach, ἐν οἴνῳ). It is by no means surprising
that an ‘atheistic’ declaration of such iconoclastic force, which proclaims that all
traditional gods of Greek religion are merely “empty names” and definitely liable
to γραφὴ ἀσεβείας, is veiled by cryptic language and disguised as innocent talk
about poetry. It seems that Heraclitus criticised not only Greek religion in ch. 3
and Greek politics in ch. 2, but also ordinary Greek language in ch. 1 of his poem.
He claims to speak κατὰ φύσιν, to reform ordinary language, e.g. by avoiding the
verb εἶναι when describing the phenomenal, and by omitting the conjunction καί
between opposites, etc. Chances are that when he refers to people whose logoi (cf.
λέγουσι in col. XXII.4) are various and wishful, the author means the poets who
created anthropomorphic polytheism; these poets are contrasted with Orpheus,
who named everything according to the same principle, κατὰ τὸν αὐτὸν λόγον.
However, this passage looks like a summary exposition of Heraclitus’ philosophy
of religion and language (with some authentic terms) rather than a verbatim
quotation. What about the ‘Heraclitizing’ passages in cols. V and XX? It is difficult
to decide between a verbatim quotation and a paraphrase. Both the paragraphos
in PDerv., col. XXII.11 and the vicinity of Heraclitus’ direct quotation in col. V make
the possibility of a verbatim quotation more likely than in the case of col. XXII. We
would not take the risk of including these three passages in the main corpus of
Heraclitus’ fragments. But they may and should be included in a separate section
of Fragmenta probabilia or at least under the heading ‘Imitations.’
epistomia, driven by grief and expressing thus their love towards the deceased,
decided to use a book from his library as a funeral torch and to place the remains
in the grave as a funerary offering. They most likely did not understand the philo-
sophical contents of the papyrus text, but the mere presence of Orpheus’ name in
it and quotations from Hieros logos were sufficient for their choice. (Incidentally,
if they did, they would have burnt it secretly and completely in the yard, so we
should be grateful to them for their mistake, since otherwise the papyrus would
not have been preserved.) The papyrus with Timotheus’ Persae dating from the
time of Alexander the Great, which has also been found in a grave at the Greek
necropolis in Abusir-Busiris, may have been a personal belonging of the dead, on
the assumption that he was a veteran of Alexander who received for his service a
kleros in the Busiris area; the patriotic poem may well have been a favorite book
of a man who fought against the Persians.287 According to Tsantsanoglou, the
spearheads, other weapons, and horse-gear found in the remains of the pyres
of the so-called ‘Derveni tombs’ “might identify the dead as warlords or royal
hetairoi of the Macedonian army.”288 A melopoios Eutychides, who ordered in his
will that he be cremated along with 12 cithars and 25 boxes of his compositions,
was considered eccentric and should not be compared with the Derveni case.289
A more ‘normal’ case, of the type that Jessica Hughes (2017) has labelled “sou-
venirs of the Self,” is the discovery of writing tablets with writing implements, a
papyrus, and musical instruments in the “Tomb of the Poet” in Dafni, personal
belongings of a young poet.290
If our attribution is correct (as we believe it is), the text known as the Derveni
Papyrus was most probably written in Ioulis on the island of Ceos, the birthplace
of Prodicus and two other 5th-cent. BC literary celebrities, Simonides and his
287 On palaeographical similarities between PDerv. and Timotheus’ Papyrus and the possibility
that they may have a “common Macedonian origin,” see Hordern (2002) 68. Hordern himself ad-
mits that the papyrus was “simply lost by accident” (p. 65). According to Wilamowitz, the scribe
of the Timotheus Papyrus must have been an Ionian. In this case, the owner of the papyrus may
have been of Macedonian origin himself.
288 K. Tsantsanoglou ap. KPT, 3. The most famous native of Lete who took part in Alexander’s
campaign was Nearchos (cf. Steph. Byz. Ethn. 11.49 [413.21–22] Meineke: οὕτως γὰρ ἱστορεῖται
Nέαρχος Ληταῖος, τῶν Ἀλεξάνδρῳ τῷ μεγάλῳ συστρατευσαμένων ὁ διασημότατος).
289 Satirized by the epigrammatist Lucillius (Anth. Pal. 11.133) and quoted by West (2013) as a
parallel to the Dafni trove. The epigram is a ‘warning’ to “those below” that Eutychides with 25
boxes of his poetry is coming: “Where can one go
in future, now that Eutychides is all over Hades
too?” (transl. by M. L. West).
290 On this see West (2013) who comments: “The instruments, at any rate, will surely have been
instruments that he or she played. The manuscripts will have contained texts that he or she
owned: perhaps read, perhaps copied, possibly composed.” (p. 85).
588 Andrei Lebedev
291 Simonides’ poetry held significant place in the lectures of Protagoras (Prodicus’ teacher and
close associate) on how to read poets; the emphasis on hyperbaton in his technique provides a
direct link with the Derveni Papyrus.
292 Scodel (2017) 37 ff. But we agree with the author that the war may have been another reason.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 589
293 Diog. Laërt. 9.55 (= Protag. 80 A 1 DK = Philochor. FGrHist 328 F 217 = Eur. Ixion test. [33] i
TrGF [Kannicht]).
294 Plut. De aud. poet. 19e (= Eur. Ixion test. [33] iii TrGF [Kannicht]).
295 Diog. Laërt. 9.54 (= Protag. 80 A 1 DK).
296 Cf. Suda ε 3695.8–10: (Euripides) ἐπὶ τραγῳδίαν δὲ ἐτράπη τὸν Ἀναξαγόραν ἰδὼν ὑποστάντα
κινδύνους δι᾽ ἅπερ εἰσῆξε δόγματα.
297 On Euripides’ library see test. G 49–50 TrGF (Kannicht).
590 Andrei Lebedev
roll.298 A copy of it may have been made for the royal library of Archelaus, a close
friend and admirer of Euripides. It is also conceivable that after Euripides’ death,
his library was incorporated (purchased or donated by relatives) into the royal
library in Pella. All further speculations on the fata libelli would be worthless.
We cannot absolutely rule out a coincidence, and we do not intend this section as
an argument in support of our attribution, which is rather based on quotations.
The question mark in the title of this section should be taken at face value, i.e.
as a question addressed by a historian of Greek philosophy to archaeologists and
papyrologists.
Appendix (1)
The Derveni Papyrus , Heraclitus, and the Stoics: A reply to Luc Brisson
Luc Brisson has challenged the communis opinio that dates the commentary of
PDerv. to the late 5th cent. BC and proposed to redate it c. 300 BC on the grounds
that it contains a Stoic physical allegoresis of myth.299 Both a Stoic influence and
a Hellenistic date for the Derv.T should be ruled out for the following reasons. 1)
The Ionian dialect started to fall out of use already in the 5th cent. BC under the
influence of the Attic dialect (we see this process in PDerv.). By 350 BC, it was
already dead in the main central and eastern Ionian regions; only the western
branch (Euboia) survived into the 3rd cent. BC. It not only disappeared by the
mid-4th cent. BC from inscriptions, i.e. ceased to be a spoken language, but it
also ceased to be the language of philosophy and science as it was in the 6th
and 5th cent. BC. We would like to see a single Greek philosophical text written
in a post-classical period in Ionian dialect. The Ionian dialect of any philosoph-
ical prose points to a pre-4th cent. BC date. 2) The pantheism of the Stoics and
of Heraclitus (like the pantheism of the Orphic Hymn to Zeus) belongs to the
ethico-religious type, while the ‘Anaxagorean’ pantheism of the Derveni author
(Prodicus) belongs to a different type, a naturalistic pantheism which is irreli-
gious and ethically irrelevant. The Stoics prayed to Zeus, but we doubt that the
Derveni author would pray to the cosmogonic Vortex: Aristophanes made fun of
this idea in the Clouds because he perfectly understood the irreligious character
of Prodicus’ pantheism. Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics unanimously dismissed
298 K. Tsantsanoglou ap. KPT, 9 dates 340–320 BC. Irigoin (1972) 543 admitted the first half of
the 4th cent. BC.
299 Brisson (2009). Cf. Betegh (2007).
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 591
304 Farinelli (2000).
305 Phld. De piet., PHerc. 1428, col. 6.16–26 Henrichs (on Chrysippus): ἐν δὲ τῶ[ι] δευ|τέρ[ωι] (sc.
Περὶ θεῶν) τά τε εἰς Ὀρφέ|α [καὶ] Μουσαῖον ἀνα|φερ[όμ]ενα καὶ τὰ | παρ᾽ [Ὁ]μήρωι καὶ Ἡ|σιόδω[ι]
καὶ Εὐριπί|δῃ καὶ ποιητα[ῖ]ς ἄλ|λοις [ὡ]ς καὶ Κλεάν|θης [πει]ρᾶται σ [υ]νοι|κειοῦ[ν] ταῖς δόξ[αι]ς |
αὐτῶ[ν]. Cf. Cic. Nat. D. 1.15.41. In the introduction to the sources, quoting this text in support,
Burnet (19714) 32 writes: “they [sc. the Stoics] seem really to have believed that the early poets and
thinkers taught doctrines hardly distinguishable from their own. The word συνοικειοῦν which
Cicero renders by accomodare, was used by Philodemus to denote this method of intetrpretation,
which has had serious results upon our tradition, especially in the case of Herakleitos.” [Italics
mine]. But: 1) the text of Philodemus is not a piece of objective historical evidence: it is polem-
ical, the term συνοικειοῦν is Philodemus’ own, not Chrysippus’, and it is here used ironically
(this is made explicit in Cicero). 2) Burnet cites this text to support his claim that the Stoics
misinterpreted “early poets and thinkers” [Italics mine], but there are no “thinkers” in Philode-
mus’ passage: it speaks about ancient poets only. It is obvious that συνοικειοῦν in Philodemus
refers to Stoic allegorical interpretations of the mythical theogonies of Orpheus, Hesiod, etc. How
can this passage of Philodemus be used as proof that the Stoics systematically misinterpreted
Heraclitus and that these distortions allegedly have heavily influenced the whole doxographical
tradition on Heraclitus? Heraclitus’ river fragment is cited and or/alluded to in dozens of sources
in a thousand years. The unique quotation that preserves the ipsissima verba of Heraclitus in its
intact form in Ionian dialect comes from the Stoic tradition of Zeno/Cleanthes/Arius Didymus: 22
B 12 DK (= fr. 67 Lebedev = fr. 40 Marcovich with testimonia). The context of this Stoic quotation
is also the only one that preserves the original psychological context of the simile. It contains an
example of the Stoic συνοικειοῦν, only in reverse order: Cleanthes assimilates Zeno’s theory of
ψυχή as sensory exhalation (ἀναθυμίασις) to Heraclitus’ view of the soul, i.e. Zeno’s doctrine is
derived from Heraclitus. There is no distortion in this assimilation: the Stoic archaic doctrine of
the soul as an exhalation from the blood indeed derives from Heraclitus.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 593
the existence of the physical allegory of the Homeric gods in 5th cent. BC is estab-
lished beyond any doubt by Metrodorus of Lampsacus and Euripides’ Bacchae.
Epigenes’ allegoresis of Orphic poetry is certainly pre-Stoic. Prodicus’ first stage
in the origin of religion (the veneration of the sun, the moon, and the seasons) is
based on a kind of physical allegoresis of the mythical gods. Some of the Pythago-
rean akousmata seem allegorical. Equating the gods with numbers and numbers
with the gods can also be viewed as a kind of mathematical allegoresis. Allegory
is used in Parmenides’ proem, and his Doxa contained, it seems, a complete alle-
gorical theogony of the gods of popular religion, which began with the creation
of Eros. Parmenides’ Aphrodite the demiourgos is akin to the Pythagorean Har
monia in Empedocles and Philolaus. The correlation of the four elements with
the four divine names in Empedocles cannot be separated from allegory: fire is
named ‘Zeus’ because the god Zeus of popular religion is κατὰ φύσιν celestial fire.
Chances are that the true father of Greek ‘physical’ philosophical allegoresis was
Heraclitus. In the third chapter of his work (λόγος θεολογικός), Heraclitus identi-
fied Zeus (Keraunos) with his “ever-living fire,”306 Apollo with the sun,307 Hades
with the sublunar air,308 etc. 8) Brisson’s thesis contradicts itself: if we admit that
the author of PDerv. is a Stoic, then we have Stoic evidence for pre-Stoic physical
allegoresis (Heraclitus).
Appendix (2)
Explanatory notice on the use of terms peritrope and ‘monism’/‘pluralism’
When we write in § (3) above about “the battle of ideas between Ionian natural-
ists (adept at naturalistic monism) and religiously minded dualists” in 5th-cent.
BC Athens, we use the term ‘monism’ in its traditional philosophical sense to
mean the metaphysical school of thought that recognizes only one kind of reality
and is opposed to metaphysical dualism that recognizes two kinds (corporeal
and incorporeal, god and matter, etc.). Metaphysical monism can be naturalis-
tic (only physis exists) and idealist, or mentalist (only Mind exists), also known
as immaterialist. Most Ionian physikoi and Ionian Sophists were naturalistic
monists; the Pythagoreans were dualists; Parmenides was an idealist monist or
immaterialist.311 Some scholars apply the term ‘monism’ to single-element theo-
ries of matter and counterpose the proponents of such theories (dubbed ‘monists,’
e.g. Anaximenes) to multiple-elements theories of matter held by ‘pluralists’
(such as Empedocles and Anaxagoras). This unphilosophical use of the terms
‘monism’/‘pluralism’ (which probably derives from some ancient doxographical
passages on the problem of ‘One’ and ‘Many’312) is potentially misleading and
can result in the confusion of the taxonomy of metaphysical theories of kinds
of reality and the taxonomy of physical theories of matter or physical elements.
Corpuscular theories of matter (such as those of Anaxagoras and Democritus)
should not be called ‘pluralist’ and should not be contrasted with ‘monistic’ the-
ories of a single material continuum. They should instead be called corpuscular
theories and contrasted with single-substrate or single-element theories of matter.
Corpuscular theories of matter may also be contrasted with single-substrate
theories of matter, and discrete theories of matter may be distinguished from
continualist theories. What matters in metaphysics and in the history of ancient
metaphysics is the perennial conflict between naturalistic monism and meta-
physical dualism of body and mind, god and matter, etc. Who the metaphysical
311 The doctrine of the identity of being and mind is directly stated by Parmenides in 28 B 3
DK. For a detailed refutation of the grammatically impossible interpretation of Burnet and his
followers see Lebedev (2017b).
312 Cf. Stokes (1971); Vassallo (2015a).
596 Andrei Lebedev
‘pluralists’ are, we do not know and would be grateful to anyone who would solve
this aporia for us. Aristotle’s four causes should not be cited as an example, since
these are not four substances, but aspects of ousia or explanatory approaches to
ousia. Perhaps the middle Platonic doxography of ‘three principles’ in Plato (god,
matter, ideas) could serve as an example? But the historical Plato was a ‘dualist.’
Democritus recognized an infinite number of atoms, but he regarded them all
as one (“as if each was a separate particle of gold”);313 he was a strict naturalis-
tic ‘monist’ who ridiculed Anaxagoras’ theory of the cosmic Mind as a conces-
sion to ‘creationism.’ The Derveni author (Prodicus) seems to follow Archelaus’
‘immanent’ version of the theory of the cosmic Mind and therefore seems like
a naturalistic ‘monist.’ Both Empedocles and Anaxagoras should be classed as
‘dualists’ (not as ‘pluralists’), though the precise nature of Anaxagoras’ Nous
remains uncertain and the subject of endless debates. We believe that the funda-
mental thesis of Greek philosophical theology, the identification of god with Mind
(Νοῦς), goes back to the 6th cent. BC and may be of Pythagorean origin. In the late
6th/early 5th cent. BC, this is attested in Epicharmus (in a parody of Pythagorean
theology), Xenophanes, and Parmenides (on Epicharmus see Lebedev [2017d],
with regard to Xenophanes’ 21 B 24–25 DK (= Xen 86 & 229 Strobel/Wöhrle), and
Lebedev [1985a]). If our reconstruction of the text of Heraclitus’ fr. 140 Lebedev
is correct (as we believe it is),314 the theory of the divine cosmic Mind existed
before Anaxagoras not only in the West, but also in the Ionian tradition itself. It
is therefore conceivable that Anaxagoras derived his concept of the cosmic Mind
from Heraclitus rather than from the Italian philosophers (however, the influence
of both traditions cannot be ruled out). Heraclitus’ teleological ‘cosmotheism’
was directed against Anaximander’s mechanistic theory of matter and ‘vortex’
cosmogony (cf. Lebedev [1988] and [2016] 597–598). Anaxagoras tried to recon-
cile and to synthesize these two conflicting theories and world views: he took the
mechanistic corpuscular theory of matter as ‘mixture’ from Anaximander and the
cosmic Mind from Heraclitus, and made the Mind trigger the ‘vortex’ mechanism
of ‘separation’ and world formation. The Western and the Heraclitean theories
of the divine cosmic Mind are based on different types of metaphysics: in the
dualist metaphysics of Magna Graecia, the God/Mind was ‘separated’ from matter
(corporeal substance) and opposed to it as a creative (demiurgic) element for a
formless and passive principle, while in Heraclitus’ strictly ‘monistic’ pantheism,
God and physis were identified, and the providential cosmic Intellect (Γνώμη)
or “the Wise Being” (τὸ Σοφόν) was conceived as immanent and inherent in the
313 Cf. Arist. Cael. 1.7.275b32–276a1 (= 67 A 19 [I] DK): τὴν δὲ φύσιν εἶναί φασιν αὐτῶν μίαν,
ὥσπερ ἂν εἰ χρυσὸς ἕκαστον εἴη κεχωρισμένον. The image seems to be authentic.
314 Heraclit. 22 B 41 DK (= fr. 140 Lebedev).
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 597
pyr aeizoon. It is conceivable, therefore, that in his theory of the cosmic Mind,
the Derveni author was influenced not only by Anaxagoras and Archelaus, but
also by Heraclitus. However, it should be stressed that Heraclitus’ cosmic God
is personal, providential, and relevant both ethically and religiously; the Stoics
were genuine Heracliteans in their pantheistic theology, as in their philosophy
of nature and ethics. To our knowledge, there is no indication in the sources that
Anaxagoras’ cosmic Nous was conceived as a providential personal God, who
cares for humans and with whom they can communicate through prayer and
worship. And Plato and Aristotle both dismissed this conception of Nous because
they sensed the artificial character of this synthesis and the ‘deistic’ character of
Anaxagoras’ Nous (never called θεός in the extant fragments). It remains unclear
whether the Derveni author understood the difference between Anaxagoras’ and
Heraclitus’ versions of the theory of cosmic Mind, e.g. when he quotes in col. IV
the sun fragment which proves the existence of the cosmic Mind by the regularity
of solstices.
Appendix (3)
A neglected reflection of Prodicus’ benefaction theory and PDerv., cols. IV and XXIV
in Xenophon’s Memorabilia
to us. This can be compared with PDerv., col. XXIV.7–11: (...) φαίνειν ~ τὴν ὥραν
~ σελήνη (...). Just as in this column of the Derveni Papyrus the telling of time
revealed by the moon serves the needs of agriculture and the production of food
“from earth”: the gods provided “appropriate hours” (4.3.5: ὥρας ἁρμοττούσας),
i.e. the seasons, for the agricultural ἔργα of men, and by adjusting the ὧραι to the
agricultural year cycle, they provided a water supply (rains) necessary for the cul-
tivation of plants (4.3.6). The greatest gift of the gods is fire, which helps humans
protect themselves against cold and darkness, and “helps in work towards any
skill and everything that humans contrive for the sake of utility” (4.3.7: συνεργὸν
δὲ πρὸς πᾶσαν τέχνην καὶ πάντα ὅσα ὠφελείας ἕνεκα ἄνθρωποι κατασκευάζονται);
“without fire men cannot contrive anything worth of mention out of things that
are useful for the human life,” οὐδὲν ἀξιόλογον ἄνευ πυρὸς ἄνθρωποι τῶν πρὸς
τὸν βίον χρησίμων κατασκευάζουσι (4.3.7). This looks like a verbatim quotation
from Prodicus. The following section (4.3.8) provides a remarkable parallel to
PDerv., col. IV: it refers to the winter and summer solstices (τροπαί) that save
us both from being frozen and being burnt to death: “Think again how the sun,
when past the winter solstice (ἐπειδὰν ἐν χεμῶνι τράπηται), approaches, ripening
some things and withering others, whose time is over; and having accomplished
this, approaches nο nearer, but turns away, careful not to harm us by excess of
heat (φυλαττόμενον μή τι ἡμᾶς μᾶλλον τοῦ δέοντος θερμαίνων βλάψῃ); and when
once again in his retreat he reaches the point where it is clear to ourselves, that if
he goes further away, we shall be frozen with the cold, back he turns once more
(πάλιν αὖ τρέπεσθαι) and draws near and revolves in that region on the heavens
where he can best serve us.”315
Xenophon was an admirer of both Socrates and Prodicus. He quotes his
version of Prodicus’ Heracles story in Book 2.316 The connection of Mem. 4.3 with
Prodicus’ Horai and the benefaction theory is palpable. But there is one signifi-
cant discrepancy, even a contradiction. The χρήσιμα and ὠφελοῦντα τὸν βίον are
the same as in Prodicus, but they have been reinterpreted as gifts of the gods, as a
result of which Prodicus’ ‘atheistic’ theory of religion has been transformed into
its ‘creationist’ opposite, the traditional popular belief in divine πρῶτοι εὑρεταί.
To resolve this contradiction, we must choose one of the following scenarios.
A) The conversation of Socrates and Euthydemus in Mem. 4.3 has been invented
by Xenophon. He took Prodicus’ benefaction theory, made a ‘pious’ version of
it, and put it into Socrates mouth as proof of his religiosity in order to defend
him against charges of asebeia. A similar ‘pious’ interpretation of Prodicus’
315 Transl. by E. C. Marchant.
316 Xen. Mem. 2.21–34 (= Prodic. test. 83 Mayhew).
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 599
benefaction theory was advanced later by Themistius (see § [3], test. 3 above).
B) The conversation is real, at least in substance. In this case the ‘pious’ version
of the benefaction theory was held by the historical Socrates. And if so, it might
derive from Socrates’ dispute with Prodicus and might be his (and not Xeno-
phon’s) dialectical peritrope of Prodicus’ Horai. The natural theology of Socrates’
speech in Mem. 4.3 has much in common with Heraclitus: Heraclitus’ fragment
on the τροπαί of the sun quoted in PDerv., col. IV was in its original context in
Heraclitus’ work a τεκμήριον of divine providence (Γνώμη). Socrates the reader
of Heraclitus may be something more than an anecdote: our reconstruction of the
‘technological’ section of Heraclitus’ second chapter (λόγος πολιτικός) indicates
that the use of τέχναι analogies in the Socratic dialogues may have been inspired
by Heraclitus. In other words, the historical Socrates may have relied on Heracli-
tus in his real debate with Prodicus. C) A ‘mixed’ scenario. Socrates indeed held
teleological and theological views similar to those ascribed to him by Xenophon,
but Xenophon freely used Prodicus’ benefaction theory in order to present them
in a more systematic and well-argued form.
We leave the matter undecided. The vexed question of Xenophon’s credibil-
ity as a source on Socrates’ philosophy should not concern us at present. In any
case, Xenophon’s passage brings an additional confirmation to our ascription of
the Derveni Papyrus to Prodicus and should be added to the testimonia collected
in § (III) above.
References
Adams (2017): Don Adams, Socrates mystagogos, London/New York.
Ademollo (2011): Francesco Ademollo, The Cratylus of Plato: A Commentary, Cambridge/New York.
Ahmadi (2014): Amir Ahmadi, “The Magoi and Daimones in Column VI of the Derveni Papyrus”,
in: Numen 61, 484–508.
Ambrose (1983): Z. Philip Ambrose, “Socrates and Prodicus in the Clouds”, in: John P. Anton
and Anthony Preus (eds.), Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, vol. 2, New York, 129–144.
Bergomi (2014): Mariapaola Bergomi, “Some Considerations on the Presence of Derveni
Allegory in Plato’s Cratylus”, in: Méthexis 27, 215–224.
Barney (2001): Rachel Barney, Names and Nature in Plato’s Cratylus, New York/London.
Baxter (1992): Timothy Baxter, The Cratylus: Plato’s Critique of Naming, Leiden/New York.
Bernabé (2007): Alberto Bernabé, “The Derveni Theogony: Many Questions and Some
Answers”, in: HSCPh 103, 99–133.
Betegh (2004): Gábor Betegh, The Derveni Papyrus: Cosmology, Theology and Interpretation,
Cambridge.
Betegh (2007): Gábor Betegh, “The Derveni Papyrus and Early Stoicism”, in: Rhizai 4, 133–152.
Bett (2013): Richard Bett, “Language, Gods, and Virtue: A Discussion of Robert Mayhew,
Prodicus the Sophist”, in: OSAPh 44, 279–311.
600 Andrei Lebedev
Binder/Liesenborghs (1976): Gerhard Binder and Leo Liesenborghs, “Eine Zuweisung der
Sentenz οὐκ ἔστι ἀντιλέγειν an Prodikos von Keos”, in: Classen, 453–462 [= Iid., in: MH 23
(1966) 37–43].
Boyancé (1974): Pierre Boyancé, “Remarques sur le Papyrus de Derveni”, in: REG 87, 90–110.
Bremmer (2014): Jan D. Bremmer, Initiation into the Mysteries of the Ancient World, Berlin/
Boston.
Brisson (2004): Luc Brisson, How Philosophers Saved Myths: Allegorical Interpretation and
Classical Mythology, Chicago.
Brisson (2009): Luc Brisson, “Zeus did not Commit Incest with his Mother: An Interpretation of
Column XXVI of the Derveni Papyrus”, in: ZPE 168, 27–39.
Burkert (1968): Walter Burkert, “Orpheus und die Vorsokratiker: Bemerkungen zum Derveni-
Papyrus und zur pythagoreischen Zahlenlehre”, in: A&A 14, 93–114 (= Id., Kleine Schriften
III: Mystica, Orphica, Pythagorica, ed. by Fritz Graf, Göttingen 2006, 62–94).
Burkert (1985): Walter Burkert, Greek Religion: Archaic and Classical, transl. by John Raffan,
Oxford.
Burkert (1986): Walter Burkert, “Der Autor von Derveni: Stesimbrotos Περὶ τελετῶν”, in: ZPE 62,
1–5.
Burnet (19714): John Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, London (1st ed. 1892).
Byl (1994): Simon Byl, “Les Mystères d’Eleusis dans les Nueés”, in: Simon Byl and Lambros
Couloubaritsis (eds.), Mythe et Philosophie dans les Nuées d’Aristophane, Bruxelles,
11–68.
Byl (2007): Simon Byl, Les Nuées d’Aristophane: Une initiation à Eleusis en 423 avant notre ère,
Paris.
Castagnoli (2010): Luca Castagnoli, Ancient Self-Refutation: The Logic and History of the
Self-Refutation Argument from Democritus to Augustine, Cambridge.
Classen (1976): Carl J. Classen (ed.), Sophistik, Darmstadt.
Clayman (2009): Dee L. Clayman, Timon of Phlius: Pyrrhonism into Poetry, Berlin/New York.
Cole (1990): Thomas Cole, Democritus and the Sources of Greek Anthropology, Atlanta.
Cosmopoulos (2015): Michael B. Cosmopoulos, Bronze Age and the Origins of the Eleusinian
Mysteries, Cambridge.
Csapo (2016): Eric Csapo, “The ‘Theology’of the Dionysia and Old Comedy”, in: Esther Eidinow,
Julia Kindt and Robin Osborne (eds.), Theologies of Ancient Greek Religion, Cambridge,
117–152.
Denniston (1952): John D. Denniston, Greek Prose Style, Oxford.
Devine/Stephens (2000): Andrew M. Devine and Laurence D. Stephens, Discontinuous Syntax:
Hyperbaton in Greek, New York/Oxford.
Di Benedetto (1965): Vincenzo Di Benedetto, Euripidis Orestes, Florence.
Dodds (1960): Eric Dodds, Euripides: Bacchae, Oxford.
Dover (1968): Kenneth J. Dover, Aristophanes: Clouds, Oxford.
Dressler (2014): Jan Dressler, Wortverdreher, Sonderlinge, Gottlose: Kritik an Philosophie und
Rhetorik im klassischen Athen, Berlin/Boston.
Dunbar (1995): Nan Dunbar, Aristophanes: Birds, Oxford.
Edmonds (1999): Radcliffe G. Edmonds III, “Tearing Apart the Zagreus Myth: A Few Disparaging
Remarks on Orphism and Original Sin”, in: ClAnt 18, 35–73.
Edmonds (2013): Radcliffe G. Edmonds III, Redefining Ancient Orphism: A Study in Greek
Religion, Cambridge.
Fain (2010): Gordon L. Fain, Ancient Greek Epigrams, Berkeley.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 601
Farinelli (2000): Caterina F. Farinelli, “Lobone di Argo ovvero la psicosi moderna del falso
antico”, in: Giovanni Cerri (ed.), La letteratura pseudepigrafa nella cultura greca e romana,
Naples, 367–379.
Ferrari (2007): Franco Ferrari, “Note al testo delle colonne II–VII del papiro di Derveni”,
in: ZPE 162, 203–211.
Fränkel (1938): Hermann Fränkel, “A Thought Pattern in Heraclitus”, in: AJPh 59, 309–337.
Furley (1985): William D. Furley, “The Figure of Euthyphro in Plato’s Dialogue”, in: Phronesis 30,
201–208.
Gagné (2007): Renaud Gagné, “Winds and Ancestors: The Physika of Orpheus”, in: HSCPh 103,
1–23.
Garland (1992): Robert Garland, Introducing New Gods: The Politics of Athenian Religion, Ithaca
(NY).
Graf (1974): Fritz Graf, Eleusis und die Orphische Dichtung Athens in vorhellenistischer Zeit,
Berlin.
Gray (2006): Vivienne Gray, “The Linguistic Philosophies of Prodicus in Xenophon’s ‘Choice of
Heracles’?”, in: CQ 56, 426–435.
Hansen (1988): Mogens H. Hansen, Three Studies in Athenian Demography, Copenhagen.
Henrichs (1968): Albert Henrichs, “Die ‘Erdmutter’ Demeter (P. Derveni und Eurip.
Bakch. 275 f.)”, in: ZPE 3, 111–112.
Henrichs (1975): Albert Henrichs, “Two Doxographical Notes: Democritus and Prodicus on
Religion”, in: HSCPh 79, 93–123.
Henrichs (1976): Albert Henrichs, “The Atheism of Prodicus”, in: CErc 6, 15–21.
Henrichs (1984a): Albert Henrichs, “The Sophists and Hellenistic Religion: Prodicus as the
Spiritual Father of the ISIS Aretalogies”, in: HSCPh 88, 139–158.
Henrichs (1984b): Albert Henrichs, “The Eumenids and Wineless Libations in the Derveni
Papyrus”, in: Atti del XVII Congresso Internazionale di Papirologia, 2 vols., Naples, II,
255–268.
Hughes (2017): Jessica Hughes, “‘Souvenirs of the Self’: Personal Belongings as Votive
Offerings in Ancient Religion”, in: Religion in the Roman Empire 3, 181–201.
Hordern (2002): James H. Hordern, The Fragments of Timotheus of Miletus, Oxford.
Hussey (1999): Edward Hussey, “The Enigmas of Derveni”, in: OSAPh 17, 303–324.
Irigoin (1972): Jean Irigoin, Les manuscripts grecs, II: Nouveaux recueils des fac-similés,
in: REG 85, 543–571.
Janko (1997): Richard Janko, “The Physicist as Hierophant: Aristophanes, Socrates and the
Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus”, in: ZPE 118, 61–94.
Janko (2001): Richard Janko, “The Derveni Papyrus (Diagoras of Melos, Apopyrgizontes Logoi?):
A New Translation”, in: CPh 96, 1–32.
Janko (2002): Richard Janko, “The Derveni Papyrus: An Interim Text”, in: ZPE 141, 1–62.
Janko (2016): Richard Janko, “Parmenides in the Derveni Papyrus: New Images for a New
Edition”, in: ZPE 193, 1–21.
Johnston (2014): Sarah I. Johnston, “Divination in the Derveni Papyrus”, in: Papadopoulou/
Muellner, 89–105.
Kahn (1981): Charles Kahn, The Art and Thought of Heraclitus, Cambridge.
Kahn (1997): Charles Kahn, “Was Euthyphro the Author of the Derveni Papyrus?”, in: Laks/
Most, 55–69.
Kapsomenos (1964): Stylianos G. Kapsomenos, “Ο Ορφικός πάπυρος της Θεσσαλονίκης”,
in: ArchDelt 19, 17–25.
602 Andrei Lebedev
Kilarski (2013): Marcin Kilarski, Nominal Classification: A History of its Study from the Classical
Period to the Present, Amsterdam/Philadelphia.
Konaris (2016): Michael D. Konaris, The Greek Gods in Modern Scholarship, Oxford.
Kotwick (2016): Mirjam E. Kotwick, “Notes on PDerveni cols. XV, XIX, XXII and XXIV”, in: ZPE 197,
1–4.
Kotwick (2017): Mirjam E. Kotwick, Der Papyrus von Derveni: Griechisch-deutsch, Eingeleitet,
übersetzt und kommentiert; basierend auf einem griechischen Text von Richard Janko,
Berlin/Boston.
Kouloumentas (2018): Stavros Kouloumentas, “Prodicus on the Rise of Civilization: Religion,
Agriculture, and Culture Heroes”, in: PhA 18, 127–152.
Laks/Most (1997): André Laks and Glenn W. Most (eds.), Studies on the Derveni Papyrus,
Oxford.
Lebedev (1978): Andrei Lebedev, “Τὸ ἄπειρον: Not Anaximander, but Plato and Aristotle”,
in: Vestnik Drevnei Istorii (A Journal of Ancient History) 1, 39–54.
Lebedev (1984): Andrei Lebedev, “‘Φύσις ταλαντέυουσα’: Neglected Fragments of Democritus
and Metrodorus of Chios”, in: Proceedings of the 1st International Congress on
Democritus, 2 vols., Xanthi, II, 13–25.
Lebedev (1985a): Andrei Lebedev, “A New Fragment of Xenophanes”, in: Mario Capasso, Francesco
de Martino and Pierpaolo Rosati (eds.), Studi di filosofia preplatonica, Naples, 13–15.
Lebedev (1985b): Andrei Lebedev, “The Cosmos as a Stadium: Agonistic Metaphors in
Heraclitus’ Cosmology”, in: Phronesis 33, 131–150.
Lebedev (1988): Andrei Lebedev, “Anaximander the Originator of the Mixis Theory of Matter and
the Founder of Mechanistic Physics”, in: 1st International Conference on Greek Philosophy:
Ionian Philosophy (Samos, 27–31 August 1988), Abstracts of papers, 56–57.
Lebedev (1989a): Andrei Lebedev, Fragmenty rannih grecheskih filosofov / The fragments of the
Early Greek Philosophers, Moscow.
Lebedev (1989b): Andrei Lebedev, “Heraclitus in the P.Derveni”, in: ZPE 79, 39–47.
Lebedev (1996): Andrei Lebedev, “Pharnabazos the Diviner of Hermes: Two Ostraka with
Curse-letters from Olbia”, in: ZPE 112, 268–278.
Lebedev (1998): Andrei Lebedev, “The Justice of Cheiron (Titanomachia fr. 6 and 11 B.)”,
in: Philologus 142, 3–10.
Lebedev (2010): Andrei Lebedev, “Western Greek Philosophical Poems and the Homeric
Tradition: Continuity or Rupture?”, in: Indo-Europen Linguistics and Classical Philology 14,
101–110.
Lebedev (2014): Andrei Lebedev, Logos Geraklita: Rekonstrukciia mysli i slova. S novym
kriticheskim izdaniem fragmentov / The Logos of Heraclitus: A Reconstruction of his
Thought and Word: With a New Critical Edition of the Fragments, St. Petersburg.
Lebedev (2015): Andrei Lebedev, “The Theogony of Epimenides of Crete and the Origin of the
Orphic-Pythagorean Doctrine of Reincarnation”, in: Indo-Europen Linguistics and Classical
Philology 19, 464–498 (in Russian with English summary).
Lebedev (2016): Andrei Lebedev, “The Origin and Transmission of the Doxographical Tradition
Placita Philosophorum (Arius Didymus, Ps.Plutarch, Stobaeus, Theodoret, Nemesius,
Porphyrius)”, in: Indo-European Linguistics and Classical Philology 20, 573–633.
Lebedev (2017a): Andrei Lebedev, “The Metaphor of Liber Naturae and the Alphabet Analogy in
Heraclitus’ Logos Fragments (With some Remarks on Plato’s Dream Theory and the Origin
of the Concept of Elements)”, in: Enrica Fantino, Ulrike Muss, Charlotte Schubert and Kurt
Sier (eds.), Heraklit im Kontext, Berlin/New York, 233–269.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 603
Obbink (1994): Dirk Obbink, “A Quotation of the Derveni Papyrus in Philodemus’ On Piety”,
in: CErc 24, 110–135.
Obbink (1996): Dirk Obbink, Philodemus: On Piety, Part 1: Critical Text with Commentary,
Oxford.
Obbink (1997): Dirk Obbink, “Cosmology as Initiation vs. the Critique of Orphic Mysteries”,
in: Laks/Most, 39–54.
Olson (2007): S. Douglas Olson, Broken Laughter: Select Fragments of Greek Comedy, Oxford.
Papadopoulou/Muellner (2014): Ioanna Papadopoulou and Leonard Muellner (eds.), Poetry as
Initiation: The Center for Hellenic Studies Symposium on the Derveni Papyrus,
Washington D.C.
Papageorgiou (2004): Nikolaos Papageorgiou, “Prodicus and the Agon of the Logoi in
Aristophanes’ Clouds”, in: QUCC n.s. 78, 61–69.
Pendrick (2002): Gerard J. Pendrick, Antiphon the Sophist: The Fragments, Cambridge.
Penella (2000): Robert J. Penella, The Private Orations of Themistius, Berkeley/Los Angeles/
London.
Piano (2016): Valeria Piano, “P.Derveni III–VI: Una riconsiderazione del testo”, in: ZPE 197,
5–16.
Reesor (1983): Margaret Reesor, “The Stoic Idion and Prodicus’ Near-Synonyms”, in: AJPh 104,
124–133.
Riedweg (1987): Christoph Riedweg, Mysterienterminologie bei Platon, Philon und Klemens von
Alexandrien, Berlin/New York.
Rijlaarsdam (1978): Jetske C. Rijlaarsdam, Platon über die Sprache: Ein Kommentar zum
Kratylos, Utrecht.
Rogers (1930): Benjamin B. Rogers, The Clouds of Aristophanes, London.
Roubekas (2017): Nickolas P. Roubekas, An Ancient Theory of Religion: Euhemerism from
Antiquity to the Present, London/New York.
Roux (1972): Jeanne Roux, Euripide: Les Bacchantes, II: Commentaire, Paris.
Rubel (2014): Alexander Rubel, Fear and Loathing in Ancient Athens: Religion and Politics
during the Peloponnesian War, transl. by Michael Vickers and Alina Piftor, London.
Rusten (1985): Jeffrey S. Rusten, “Interim Notes on the Papyrus from Derveni”, in: HSCPh 89,
121–140.
Sansone (2004): David Sansone, “Heracles at Y”, in: JHS 124, 125–142.
Santamaría (2012): Marco A. Santamaría, “Tiresias in Euripides’ Bacchae and the Author of
the Derveni Papyrus”, in: Paul Schubert (ed.), Actes du 26e Congrès international de
papyrologie, Genève, 677–684.
Santamaría (2016): Marco A. Santamaría, “A Phallus Hard to Swallow: The Meaning of
αἰδοῖος/-ον in the Derveni Papyrus”, in: CPh 111, 139–164.
Schober (1988): Adolf Schober, “Philodemi De pietate Pars prior”, in: CErc 18, 67–125
[= Id., Philodemi Περὶ εὐσεβείας libelli partem priorem restituit A. Schober, Diss. ined.
Königsberg 1923].
Scholten (2003): Helga Scholten, Die Sophistik: Eine Bedrohung für die Religion und Politik der
Polis?, Berlin.
Scodel (2017): Ruth Scodel, “The Euripidean Biography”, in: Laura K. McClure (ed.),
Blackwell Companion to Euripides, Chichester/Malden/Oxford, 27–41.
Sedley (2003): David N. Sedley, Plato’s Cratylus, Cambridge.
Sedley (2013): David N. Sedley, “From the Pre-Socratics to the Hellenistic Age”,
in: Steven Bullivant and Michael Ruse (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Atheism, Oxford.
17 The Authorship of the Derveni Papyrus 605
Sider (1997): David N. Sedley, “Heraclitus in the Derveni Papyrus”, in: Laks/Most, 129–148.
Sider (2014): David Sider, “The Orphic Poem of the Derveni Papyrus”, in: Papadopoulou/
Muellner, ch. 12.
Starkie (1911): William J. M. Starkie, The Clouds of Aristophanes, London (repr. Amsterdam
1966).
Stokes (1971): Michael C. Stokes, One and Many in Presocratic Philosophy, Washington D.C./
Cambridge (MA).
Taillardat (1962): Jean Taillardat, Les images d’Aristophane, Paris.
Tsantsanoglou (1997): Kyriakos Tsantsanoglou, “The First Columns of the Derveni Papyrus and
Their Religious Significance”, in: Laks/Most, 93–128.
Tsantsanoglou (2017): Kyriakos Tsantsanoglou, “Parmenides in the Derveni Papyrus?”,
in: ZPE 203, 24.
Tsantsanoglou (2018): Kyriakos Tsantsanoglou, “The Derveni Papyrus and Illusions”,
in: ZPE 205, 15–23.
Tzifopoulos (2014): Yannis Z. Tzifopoulos, “The Derveni Papyrus (PDerveni) and the
Bacchic-Orphic Epistomia”, in: Papadopoulou/Muellner, ch. 8 [= Id., in: TC 2 (2010)
31–63].
Ustinova (2018): Yulia Ustinova, Divine Mania: Alteration of Consciousness in Ancient Greece,
London.
Vassallo (2006): Christian Vassallo, “Sul concetto di speranza da Omero ad Eraclito”,
in: AAN 117, 5–39.
Vassallo (2015a): Christian Vassallo, “On the Supposed Monism of Thales in PHerc. 1788
(= VH2 VIII 60, fr. 6): Praesocratica Herculanensia I”, in: Hermes 143, 101–118.
Vassallo (2015b): Christian Vassallo, “Orpheus in the Herculaneum Papyri: Praesocratica
Herculanensia VI”, in: APF 61, 87–113.
Vassallo (2017a): Christian Vassallo, “Zeus unique, puissant, savant : Une note à Héraclite,
fr. 84–85 Marcovich (= DK 22 B 32 et 41)”, in: Philosophia 47, 17–20.
Vassallo (2017b): Christian Vassallo, “P.Herc. 1788 ([Philodemi] [Philosophorum historia?]):
Introduction, Edition, and Commentary”, in: AnPap 29, 7–56.
Vassallo (2018a): Christian Vassallo, “Persaeus on Prodicus on the Gods’ Existence and Nature:
Another Attempt Based on a New Reconstruction of Philodemus’ Account”, in: PhA 18,
153–168.
Vassallo (2018b): Christian Vassallo, “Feuer und göttliche Dialektik bei Heraklit: Neue Lesungen
in PHerc. 1428, Kol. 330 (olim Fr. 17): Praesocratica Herculanensia IX”, in: Mnemosyne 71,
717–732 (preprint BrillOnline.com, DOI: 10.1163/1568525X-12342391).
West (1983): Martin L. West, The Orphic Poems, Oxford.
West (2013): Martin L. West, “The Writing Tablets and Papyrus from Tomb II in Daphni”,
in: Greek and Roman Musical Studies 1, 73–92.
Wilamowitz (1919): Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Platon, 2 vols., Berlin.
Willi (2007): Andreas Willi, “Demeter, Gê, and the Indo-European Word(s) for ‘Earth’”,
in: HSF 120, 169–194.
Willi (2010): Andreas Willi, “Attic as the Language of the Classics”, in: Chrys C. Caragounis (ed.),
Greek: A Language in Evolution: Essays in Honour of Antonios N. Jannaris, Hildesheim/
Zurich/New York, 101–118.
Willink (1983): Charles W. Willink, “Prodicus, ‘Meteorosophists’ and the ‘Tantalus’ Paradigm”,
in: CQ n.s. 33, 25–33 (= Id., Collected Papers on Greek Tragedy, ed. by W. Benjamin Henry,
Leiden/Boston 2010, 81–94).
606 Andrei Lebedev