Hith 12154
Hith 12154
JUHAN HELLERMA1
ABSTRACT
In the scholarly reception of his work, Reinhart Koselleck’s notion of modernity and his
theory of multiple times have been cast as essentially at odds with each other. This article
argues that although these positions are valid, Koselleck’s writings can also accommo-
date an interpretation according to which the theory of multiple temporalities, or “layers
of time,” provides theoretical ground for the modern understanding of time and history.
Elaborating on this insight, the article shows the linkages sustaining the unity between
Koselleck’s formal theory of multiple times and his interpretation of modernity. To
that end, I outline the main premises of the temporalization thesis that lies at the heart
of Koselleck’s theory of modernity, scrutinize his notion of Historik within which the
framework “layers of time” belongs, and explore Niklas Olsen’s and Helge Jordheim’s
interpretive accounts on how to conceive of the relationship between the two strands in
Koselleck’s thought. Ultimately, I argue that “layers of time” entails the formal conditions
for historical acceleration, which is crucial for explaining the emergence of a specifically
modern temporality wherein experience and expectation increasingly grow apart.
This article will survey the relationship between Reinhart Koselleck’s account
of modernity and his theory of “layers of time” that is contained in his theory
of conditions of possible histories in his Historik. For Koselleck, the latter
notion indicates primarily his interest in various ontological and anthropological
conditions under which histories unfold, and is thus different from the concep-
tualization of the term handed down by Droysen that, foremost, engages with
the epistemological presuppositions of historical knowledge. Among commen-
tators, two strategies stand out with respect to how to conceive of the mutual
relationship between Koselleck’s account of modernity, on the one hand, and his
theory of multilayered history, on the other. According to the first interpretation,
Koselleck’s theoretical endeavors are a critical response to the singular notion of
history that, originating in the eighteenth century, eventually sustained violent
political regimes of the twentieth century (Niklas Olsen’s emphasis). On the
1. Research for this article was supported by the Dora Pluss Scholarship, funded by the European
Regional Development Fund, and the Kristjan Jaak Scholarship, funded by the Estonian Ministry of
Education and Research. In addition, the research is related to work done at the Centre of Excellence
in Estonian Studies (European Union, European Regional Development Fund) and research project
IUT20-5 (Estonian Ministry of Education and Research). I am also thankful for the Yale Baltic
Studies Program, which provided the conditions for completing the article.
KOSELLECK ON MODERNITY, HISTORIK, AND LAYERS OF TIME 189
second reading, the framework of “layers of time” is to be regarded as a form of
self-criticism by which Koselleck challenges the idea of distinct epochs, and his
own account of modernity in particular (Helge Jordheim’s point). In the face of
these two interpretations, I will suggest that Koselleck’s works include a third
dimension that enables depicting the framework of layers of time as accounting
for the individuality of what can be labeled as the modern age, thus giving rise
to an interpretation that views the relationship between the two frameworks not
necessarily in terms of opposition and exclusion, but rather as complementary.
I. MODERNITY AS TEMPORALIZATION
essays will constantly ask: how, in a given present, are the temporal dimensions of past
and future related?4
were created to describe them: “Experience and expectation have certainly been
increasingly growing apart since the Renaissance, but only in the term ‘progress’
is this distinction conceptualized.”11
Once the subjects of progress and history are universalized, the temporal
phenomena of the simultaneity of the nonsimultaneous (Gleichzeitigkeit des
Ungleichzeitigen) appears. In other words, when the totality of history is con-
ceived in terms of progress, the inequality of the progress achieved in different
parts of the world emerges, enabling a comparison of different rates of develop-
ment. In this sense, Kollektivsingular and Gleichzeitigkeit des Ungleichzeitigen
belong together.
11. Meier and Koselleck, “Fortschritt,” in Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe, II, 389: “Freilich haben
sich Erfahrung und Erwartung seit der Renaissance zunehmend differenziert: aber erst im ‘Fortschritt’
wird diese Differenz auf ihren Begriff gebracht.”
12. Koselleck, “Historical Criteria of the Modern Concept of Revolution” [1969], in Futures Past,
57.
KOSELLECK ON MODERNITY, HISTORIK, AND LAYERS OF TIME 193
clearly not capable of instructing in the same manner as history in the manner of
exemplary account.”13 Or: “History, processualized and temporalized to constant
singularity, could no longer be taught in an exemplary fashion.”14 In short, as
history turns into a singular process that consists of individual events, exemplary
stories of the past inevitably lose their credibility.
Furthermore, Koselleck also addresses the issue of how the change in tempo-
ral framework provokes the collapse of the premodern methodological model of
history.15 In particular, he shows that whereas in premodern historical discourse
the authenticity of a historical report was based on an immediate perception of a
given present (eyewitness), in the case of the modern historicist outlook the event
to be recorded loses its status as epistemologically feasible. Instead, the object
of historical research shifts from the recent past—retained in the memories of
eyewitnesses—to a distant past that lies beyond living memory and can be rep-
resented only by interpreting traces of the past. Hence the need for a historical
methodology radically different from the one characteristic of premodern histori-
cal discourse.
Over the course of several decades, alongside Koselleck’s account of the emer-
gence of the singular notion of history and the related ideas of temporalization
and historical time, he develops his own Historik, a theory of possible histories,
which he conceived of in terms of a historical anthropology that seeks to articu-
late the conditions under which history—or, more precisely, the plurality of his-
tories—unfold.16 Although Koselleck never presents a systematic account of the
different formal criteria belonging to his Historik, what connects his theory is
the attempt to clarify “historical-anthropological presuppositions . . . which give
rise to individual histories.”17 More specifically: “Rather, Historik is the theory
of the conditions of possible histories. It asks about the theoretically discernible
presuppositions that make conceivable why histories occur, how they unfold,
and, likewise, how and why they must be examined, represented, or narrated.”18
13. Koselleck, “Historia Magistra Vitae: The Dissolution of the Topos into the Perspective of a
Modernized Historical Process” [1967], in Futures Past, 32.
14. Koselleck, “‘Space of Experience’ and ‘Horizon of Expectation”: Two Historical Categories”
[1976], in Futures Past, 268.
15. Koselleck, “Neuzeit: Remarks on the Semantics of Modern Concepts of Movement,” 243.
16. See also Stefan-Ludwig Hoffmann, “Koselleck, Arendt, and the Anthropology of Historical
Experience,” History and Theory 49, no. 2 (2010), 214. On Koselleck’s Historik, see also Jacob
Taubes, “Geschichtsphilosophie und Historik: Bemerkungen zu Kosellecks Programm einer neuen
Historik,” in Geschichte—Ereignis und Erzählung, ed. Reinhart Koselleck and Wolf-Dieter Stempel
(Munich: Wilhelm Fink Verlag, 1973), 490-499. See also Koselleck, “Im Vorfeld einer neuen
Historik,” in Neue Politische Literatur 6 (1961), 577-588.
17. Koselleck, “Transformations of Experience and Methodological Change: A Historical-
Anthropological Essay,” in Koselleck, The Practice of Conceptual History: Timing History, Spacing
Concepts (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 50.
18. Koselleck, “Historik and Hermeneutics” [1987], in Koselleck, Sediments of Time: On Possible
Histories, transl. and ed. Sean Franzel and Stefan-Ludwig Hoffmann (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2018), 43.
194 JUHAN HELLERMA
24. Koselleck, “Structures of Repetition in Language and History” [2006], in Sediments of Time.
25. Sean Franzel, Stefan-Ludwig Hoffmann, “Introduction: Translating Koselleck,” in Sediments
of Time, xiv.
26. Ibid.
196 JUHAN HELLERMA
phenomena. In other words, he wanted to produce a theory that could account for
all possible durations and their respective modes of being. He found a common
denominator in the term “repetition,” which, for instance, he used to character-
ize both the recurring pattern of the movement of the sun, as well as the kind of
persistence that is characteristic of language and semantics.27
In the introduction to the collection of essays gathered under the title
Zeitschichten, Koselleck states that historical time should be distinguished from
natural time,28 and that both are in turn modifications of repetition.29 Koselleck’s
attempt to place the trope of repetition in the center of his theory is also evident in
his remark that Fernand Braudel’s distinctions with regard to different temporal
durations are reducible to a more universal phenomenon, that of repetition, which
in turn entails various layers.30 It is clear that a theory that aims to address such
a broad spectrum of phenomena must operate with a fluid definition of repeti-
tion. Indeed, Koselleck did not make his own definition of the term clear. This,
however, might not be a shortcoming considering that it is the very task of the
framework to inquire into various modes of repetition. Arguably, the key term
should be left open, since it is only then that it can perform its main function.
A second explanation might be that Koselleck wanted to achieve more con-
ceptual clarity across his different works. Since the term “historical time(s)” also
plays an important role in Koselleck’s elaborations on modernity and modern
temporal experience, it would be reasonable to establish a distinct theoretical
vocabulary within the boundaries of his own unique Historik. Even if Koselleck
did not intend this, it certainly helps to better structure the various parts of
Koselleck’s theorizing.
27. Koselleck’s later writing gives rise to an interpretation that the anthropological categories he
develops expanding on Heidegger—particularly insofar they represent specific conditions underlying
the occurence of concrete histories—likewise fall under the broadly conceived concept of structures
of repetition.
28. Koselleck, “Einleitung,” in Zeitschichten, 10: “One of my starting theses is that historical times
can be principally distinguished from times conditioned by nature, even though they interact with
each other in many ways.” Original: “Eine meiner Ausgangsthesen ist, dass sich historische Zeiten
von naturbedingten Zeiten grundsätzlich unterscheiden lassen, auch wenn sie -– auf sehr verschiedene
Weise—aufeinander einwirken.”
29. Koselleck, “Einleitung,” in Zeitschichten, 13: “Geographical and biological preconditions of
human histories cannot be completely controlled, even if this is increasingly the case in relation to the
advancements of natural sciences. Another mode of duration is animated by intentional and targeted
repetition. The latter is related to durability and stability of social behavior. Empirically, the border
between the natural and human-generated structures of repetition is fluid, but time-theoretically,
they should be kept strictly apart.” Original: “Geographische und biologische Vorbedingungen men-
schlicher Geschichten lassen sich nicht rundum beherrschen, auch wenn dies mit den Fortschritten
der Naturwissenschaften der Fall ist. Die andere Weise der Dauer lebt von gewollter und gezielter
Wiederholung. Sie verbürgt Dauerhaftigkeit und Stetigkeit gesellschaftlicher Verhaltensweisen.
Empirisch gehen die naturalen und die menschlich geregelten Wiederholungsstrukturen ineinander
über, aber zeittheoretisch müssen sie strikt voneinander getrennt werden.”
30. Koselleck, “Einleitung,” in Zeitschichten, 14: “Fernand Braudel’s methodological point of
departure is thus uncoupled from the parallel arrangement of long, short, and situational duration
and traced back to the common basic pattern that at the same time contains various layers of time.”
Original: “Der Methodische Ansatz von Fernand Braudel wird also aus der Parallelschaltung von
langer, kurzer und situativer Dauer herausgedreht und auf ein gemeinsames anthropologisches
Grundmuster zurückgeführt, das zugleich verschiedene Zeitschichten in sich birgt.”
KOSELLECK ON MODERNITY, HISTORIK, AND LAYERS OF TIME 197
A third reason that Koselleck opts to highlight the figure of repetition, as I
will later argue in more detail, is that, since it opens up the dynamic interplay
between repetition and innovation, it is more suited to accounting for the possibil-
ity of acceleration and delay in history than the conceptual toolbox suggested in
Koselleck’s earlier works.
Compare this with a modified version of the same passage found in the later essay
where the term “repetition” gains momentum: “
Let me mention some structures in this connection. Consider constitutional forms and
modes of power which are based on the repetition of well-known rules. Or take productive
forces and the relations of production, which change slowly, with sudden bursts at inter-
vals. Their effect derives from the repetition of certain procedures and from the rational
constancy of general market conditions.33
Transposing the term “repetition” from one context to another can also be seen as
illustrating that, over time, Koselleck’s interest shifted from the temporal break
occurring with the onset of modernity to a more formal theory of multiple times.
In the next section I will look at two interpretations—Niklas Olsen’s and Helge
Jordheim’s—of how Koselleck’s account of modernity and layers of time relate
to each other. I will argue that although both accounts point out valid perspec-
tives—indeed, their respective arguments can be made even stronger—there is a
further dimension that is not part of the main argument Olsen and Jordheim are
advocating.
genannt: Verfassungsformen und Herrschaftsweisen, die auf der Wiederholung eingespielter Regeln
beruhen. Oder die Produktivkräfte und die Produktionsverhältnisse, die sich nur langfristig, manchmal
schubweise wandeln. Aber ihre Wirkung beruht auf der Wiederholung bestimmter Verfahren und auf
der rationale Stetigkeit der allgemeinen Marktbedingungen.” (Koselleck, “Moderne Sozialgeschichte
und historische Zeiten” [1987], in Zeitschichten, 328-329.)
34. Niklas Olsen, History in the Plural: An Introduction to the Work of Reinhart Koselleck (New
York and Oxford: Berghahn Books, 2012), 44
35. Ibid., 42.
36. Ibid., 66.
37. Ibid.
KOSELLECK ON MODERNITY, HISTORIK, AND LAYERS OF TIME 199
can accommodate a plural notion of history. In other words, the idea of history
that unfolds on a multitude of intertwined but analytically distinct levels “became
a central discursive feature in the unifying pattern and the common objective in
Koselleck’s writings, as it served to substantiate his critique of notions of history
in the singular and as a very operational framework to thematize history in the
plural.”38 Furthermore, whereas the anthropological categories Koselleck devel-
oped, drawing upon Heidegger’s existential analyses of Dasein, were intended
primarily to deconstruct the singular notion of history, the framework of layers of
time provided a means to account for how history in the plural could be written
in practice.39
Olsen rightly points out that the notion of history as unfolding in layers pre
sents an alternative to the concept that depicts history as one-dimensional and
singular. However, he does not elaborate that Koselleck’s layers of time include
further resources that can make the position he is advocating for even stronger.
This can be achieved in reference to Koselleck’s analysis of structure and event,
wherein the two poles are viewed as interrelated but not linked causally. Even
though structures of repetition, as Koselleck notes, form the circumstances in
which individual events occur, they nevertheless do not entirely exhaust the
meaning of what unfolds, meaning essentially that there is no room for construct-
ing sequences that are based on necessity.
Our conceptual model aims at an aporia that opens up between the repeating conditions of
possible events and these events themselves, including their acting and enduring persons.
No event can be completely and sufficiently derived from synchronic conditions or from
diachronic preconditions, no matter whether these are economic, religious, political, psy-
chological, cultural, or whatever else.40
An event, therefore, is, on the one hand, inextricably tied to the structure, and,
on the other hand, remains relatively independent from that same structure. At
the same time an actual event manifests only one possibility that is enabled by
the structure that opens up a specific set of possibilities but does not necessitate
the occurrence of an individual event. Hence “the structures of repetition . . .
contain both more and less than what comes to light in the occurrences.”41 This
explanation serves to further substantiate Olsen’s argument that the framework
of layers of time calls into question the possibility of utopian visions of history,
particularly due to their deterministic commitments.
In Jordheim’s account, scholars in the Anglophone and German contexts have
viewed Koselleck’s theory of historical times predominantly as ultimately an
attempt to offer a periodization in which modernity as a particular epoch assumes
a central role.42 He writes that the theory of an “advent and specific temporal
qualities of the modern age, substantiated by his monumental endeavors in the
history of key concepts and social structures, has come to represent the main
focus of Koselleck’s work to the extent that other parts have been explicitly or
implicitly ignored.”43 In contrast to interpretations that regard Koselleck pri-
marily as an advocate of a theory of periodization, and modernity in particular,
Jordheim points to the existence of a separate temporal framework in Koselleck’s
works. Drawing on John Zammito’s review article of the 2004 essay collection
on Zeitschichten, Jordheim contends that Koselleck’s theory of historical times
is much more complex and comprehensive than previous commentators have
suggested. By way of disconnecting the theory of historical times from a theory
of modernity, Jordheim transposes it into the context of a theory of multiple
overlapping temporalities, arguing that the latter represents Koselleck’s “real
theory of historical times.”44 Moreover, he insists that Koselleck’s primary inter-
est was not developing a theory of modernity, but to engage with a more general
theory of multiple times that “is even constructed with the purpose of defying
periodization.”45
It is true that one of Koselleck’s programmatic aims in Historik is to disrupt
the traditional periodization schema that posits a succession of epochs. Moreover,
already in his 1971 essay “Wozu noch Historie?” Koselleck explicitly questions
his own analyses of the modern concept of history, arguing that the discipline of
history should be premised on multiple temporalities, which would naturally lead
to a renegotiation of the borders between the modern singular concept of history
and the earlier plural form. “In any case we need a theory of historical times when
we want to clarify the relationship between ‘history in itself’ and the endlessly
many histories in the plural.”46 Inquiring into temporal structures, Koselleck
furthermore argues, “opens a doorway for arranging the entire field of history
according to its immanent principles without having to resort to the chronological
triad and without stopping at the semantic threshold of experience established by
the notion of history as such around 1780.”47
In his 1973 essay “History, Histories, and Formal Time Structures,” Koselleck
picks up the question he had posed in the essay “Wozu noch Historie?” and offers
concrete examples as to how theoretical scrutiny can shed light on common fea-
tures between modern and premodern histories. Koselleck makes a similar point in
other writings as well, repeatedly stressing that in the face of structural continuities
the otherness of modernity should not be taken for granted. For example, consider
this passage:
There are repeatable constellations, long-term effects, contemporary manifestations of
archaic attitudes, regularities of sequences of events, and the contemporary historian can
inform himself about their actuality from history. . . . Only when we know what can repeat
itself at any time (though not always all at once) can we ascertain what is truly new in our
However, having demonstrated that despite the lack of the modern concept “his-
tory,” premodern histories exhibit temporal features similar to the ones found in
modernity, Koselleck flips his initial question, asking “by means of which cat-
egories can the specificity of modern history be distinguished from the regularity
of recurring sequences outlined above?”49 As a preliminary answer, he states:
“To deal with this, it is necessary to introduce into our hypothesis coefficients
of motion and acceleration which are no longer derivative of expectations of the
Last Judgment (as was the case earlier), but which instead remain adequate to the
empirical factors of a world increasingly technical in nature.”50
A similar pattern of argumentation occurs in his 1989 essay “Wie neu ist die
Neuzeit?,” where Koselleck initially questions whether the idea of modernity is
particularly different and new, but ultimately argues that modernity can neverthe-
less be distinguished from previous times because of the speed with which history
had changed over the previous two hundred years.51
In sum, Koselleck deploys his theoretical framework to argue against the
view of succession of distinct epochs, and modernity in particular, while at the
same time calling for a set of conceptual tools that accounts for different rates
of speed change. He thus reintroduces the idea of modernity as an era in its own
right insofar as it appears subject to unprecedented acceleration. It is the latter
perspective from which I propose to consider the significance of the framework
of layers of time.
Because different commentators set up the initial question regarding the rela-
tion between Koselleck’s notion of modernity and his account of layers of time
in diverging terms, we find variations in their respective points of emphasis.
Whereas Olsen emphasizes the critical potential of the notion of layers of time,
particularly as it opposes the singular concept of history, Jordheim has a differ-
ent point of departure, instead taking issue with the dominant vision of Koselleck
as an advocate of a periodization theory. In an attempt to show the limits of this
vision, Jordheim highlights Koselleck’s account of multiple temporalities, which
he argues facilitates a criticism of traditional periodization, and of modernity
in particular. I argue that we should not highlight the significance of layers of
time at the expense of downplaying the role of the specific shift in temporal
experience occurring in the eighteenth century, even if we have to admit that it is
problematic to accept it as a principle for periodization. By doing so, we would
not only be doing injustice to Koselleck’s entire oeuvre, as so many of his works
are concerned with the constitution and the origins of the modern world, but
most important, we would risk disregarding some of the key applications of the
framework of layers of time itself.
In contrast to approaches suggested by Olsen and Jordheim, who both depict
Koselleck’s account of modernity as being at odds with his theory of layers of
48. Koselleck, “Constancy and Change of All Contemporary Histories” [1988], in Sediments of
Time, 115-116.
49. Koselleck, “History, Histories, and Formal Time Structures” [1973], in Futures Past, 104.
50. Ibid.
51. Koselleck, “Wie neu ist die Neuzeit?” [1989], in Zeitschichten, 238.
202 JUHAN HELLERMA
time, I propose that the two frameworks are not necessarily opposed to each other
but can be brought into a productive dialogue. Specifically, I will illustrate that
the theory of layers of time offers tools that ground the definition of modernity as
an age of increasing acceleration, which in turn facilitates Koselleck’s thesis that
modernity is the growing-apart of experience and expectation.
One of the main functions that Koselleck attributes to his Historik is to clarify
theoretically the possibility of acceleration and deceleration. More specifically,
the theory of layers of time seeks to distinguish between the speed and pace of
change characteristic of different domains. Koselleck insists that even though
empirically different layers are intertwined, it is up to the theory to separate them
analytically and to determine their respective formal qualities.
One key distinction in Koselleck’s formal analyses is that between event and
structure repetition. Whereas the first is regarded as singular and unique, the other
forms the conditions in which events occur. “Within every singular action and
in every unique constellation that is performed or endured by similarly unique
human beings there are always repeatable layers of time. They make possible,
condition, and limit human possibilities for action as well as also set them free.”52
Events can be further analyzed by diachronic structures that repeat themselves
across various instances of a particular event (for example, revolutions), which,
as Koselleck stresses, does not affect their uniqueness. “Indeed, it may be surpris-
ing that events—which by definition presuppose or generate their own singularity
or even utter uniqueness—have repeatable regularities.”53
A model that combines singular events and recurring patterns also enables
Koselleck to make explicit the formal conditions for historical change. In so doing,
he seeks to discriminate between temporal schemas characteristic of different
structures of repetition. Ultimately, it is precisely the task of Historik to shed light
on the nature and speed of transformation within different layers, which in turn
makes it possible to illuminate tensions occurring between various layers.54
Furthermore, whereas events can be mapped onto a chronological scale, struc-
tures of repetition adhere to a different temporal logic that can be described with
the categories of acceleration (Beschleunigung) and delay (Verzögerung):
Acceleration would occur when, in a given set of cases, increasingly fewer cases were
found to repeat themselves and ever more innovations came about that departed from
52. Koselleck, “Einleitung,” in Zeitschichten, 13: “In jeder einmaligen Handlung und in jeder
einzigartigen Konstellation, die von ebenso einmaligen und einzigartigen Menschen jeweils vollzo-
gen wird oder ausgehalten wird, sind immer sich wiederholende Zeitschichten enthalten. Sie ermögli-
chen, bedingen und begrenzen die menschliche Handlungschancen und setzen sie zugleich frei.”
53. Koselleck, “Structures of Repetition in Language and History,” 168.
54. A good example in this regard is the debate on the formation of the new geological era, the
Anthropocene, which can be analyzed as an increasing intertwinement of ecological and geological
settings, on the one hand, and projects generated by modern society, on the other. Koselleck himself,
however, was interested primarily in tensions and interaction between human-generated patterns,
whereas Anthropocene discussion in contrast revolves around the impact of humans on the natural
environment eventually giving rise to the thesis about the collapse of the distinction between human
and nature.
KOSELLECK ON MODERNITY, HISTORIK, AND LAYERS OF TIME 203
the old preconditions. Delays would arise when traditional repetitions grind into place or
solidify in such a way that every form of change would be inhibited or even made impos-
sible.55
Hence, the theory of layers of time articulates the formal conditions for all pos-
sible accelerations and delays. Differentiating among various kinds of structures
of repetition with regard to their pace of change is thus one of the essential
tasks of the theory: “The advantage of a [theory of layers of time]56 lies in its
ability to measure different velocities—accelerations or decelerations—and to
thereby reveal different modes of historical change that indicate great temporal
complexity.”57 Hence, depending on how fast structures of repetition transform,
history either speeds up or slows down.
A further formal, universally applicable premise is that, no matter the actual
circumstances, every history can be analyzed as an interplay between duration
and innovation. “All actual changes, whether faster, slower, or in long periods
of time (to make Braudel’s categories more precise) thus remain tied back to the
variable interaction between repetition and singularity.”58 Therefore, whereas
the historical interrelationship between continuity and innovation changes, the
formal relationship between the two categories remains intact and hence forms
one of the cornerstones of the discipline of Historik: “Even if modern inventions
evoke truly new experiences, the tension between innovation and repetition will
never be done away with. Only the determination of their relation changes over
the course of history.”59 Faced with these formal conditions, it is possible to pro-
vide a definition of modernity. In other words, besides scrutinizing the conceptual
changes in which he grounds his temporalization thesis, Koselleck argues that
modernity can be distinguished from earlier times by virtue of the accelerating
pace of change occurring in areas such as social life, politics, and technology.
It is in this context that the theory of layers of time can become an explana-
tory model that accounts for the acceleration of history particular to modernity.
Following Koselleck, modernity represents a specific variation of the universal
interplay between repetition and innovation. In particular, with modernity, struc-
tural change unfolds with an unprecedented intensity, leading to Koselleck’s
diagnosis of modernity as an age of acceleration.60 Here, the term “acceleration”
as a characterization of a specific time period does not designate a formal pos-
sibility, as it did within the theory of layers of time, but instead refers to the
concrete instance of the formal possibility being realized. In this way, layers of
time as a theory makes possible an account of modernity as a period of intense
acceleration.
61. Koselleck, “Wie neu ist die Neuzeit?,” 238: “Einen solchen Strukturwandel unmittelbar wah-
rnehmen zu können, das zeichnet vermutlich die Neuzeit aus. Der Strukturwandel wird gleichsam
selbst zum Ereignis.”
62. “Zeit, Zeitlichkeit und Geschichte—Sperrige Reflexionen: Reinhart Koselleck im Gespräch
mit Wolf-Dieter Narr und Kari Palonen,” in Zeit, Geschichte und Politik: zum achtzigsten Geburtstag
von Reinhart Koselleck, ed. Jussi Kurunmäki and Kari Palonen (Jyväskylä, Finland: University of
Jyväskylä, 2003), 18-19: “Meine Hypothese lautet, dass der Anteil der stabilen Bedingungen, die sich
wiederholen, im Zuge der Neuzeit, der Industrialisierung, der Beschleunigung geringer geworden ist.”
63. Koselleck, “Time and History,” in Practice of Conceptual History, 113. This can be compared
with Hermann Lübbe’s notion of the contraction of the present [Gegenwartsschrumpfung].
64. “Histories in the Plural and the Theory of History: An Interview with Carsten Dutt” [2001],
in Sediments of Time, 265.
65. Koselleck, “Does History Accelerate?” [partially 1985], in Sediments of Time, 87, 93.
66. Ibid., 89.
67. Koselleck, “Zeitverkürzung und Beschleunigung. Eine Studie zur Säkularisation,” 184.
Original: “Denn wenn es eine weltimmanente, geschichtliche Zeiterfahrung gibt, die sich von den
naturgebundenen Zeitrhythmen unterscheidet, so ist es zweifellos die Erfahrung der Beschleunigung,
kraft derer sich die geschichtliche Zeit als spezifisch von Menschen produzierte Zeit qualifiziert.”
KOSELLECK ON MODERNITY, HISTORIK, AND LAYERS OF TIME 205
contrast, the structural notion of acceleration attends to conditions themselves—
political, technological, and otherwise—that in the context of modernity are
interrogated primarily with regard to their being more fluid and adaptable than in
previous times. Hence, what is ultimately at stake is real historical change and its
various intensities, on the one hand, and acceleration as a mode of consciousness
of time, on the other. Although interrelated, the two perspectives should neverthe-
less be considered distinct. Indeed, Koselleck explicitly argues that “real historical
acceleration” should be kept apart from “subjective attitudes of expectation and its
failed or fulfilled targets.”68
The structural notion of acceleration is nevertheless tied to the coming into
being of a specifically historical mode of experience that goes beyond naturalist
assumptions. In other words, the linkage between the two domains—structural
and experiential—occurs when structural change gains in intensity such that it
evokes a new experience of time. “Change, mutatio rerum, is reported in all his-
tories. However, the kind of change that calls forth a new experience of time—the
sense that everything is changing more quickly than one had expected or experi-
enced up to that point—is modern.”69
Hence we arrive at the link between increasing structural change and shifting
categories of experience and expectation. Unlike structural change, experience
and expectation are categories that specifically capture the actor’s attitudes
toward past and future and are hence cognitive in nature. Whereas the theory of
layers of time accounts for historical change, experience and expectation account
for the actor’s perception of past and future and their interrelationship. The ques-
tion, then, is how we correlate a metahistorical vocabulary that targets diverging
domains. In other words, how should we think of the interrelationship between
the categories of repetition and change central to the framework of layers of time,
on the one hand, and the anthropological categories of experience and expecta-
tions, on the other?
To flesh out the precise connection between the two, one can say that modern
temporal experience is defined by the shortening of the life span of structures of
repetition that in turn destabilize spaces of experience to the point that the present
recognizes itself as merely transitory, that is, as being on its way to a yet different
tomorrow. The faster structures change, the shorter the life span of the conditions
under which experience can unfold. But, more precisely, what constitutes the
modern experience of time is the awareness that lifeworld conditions are prone
to change. Modern acceleration is thus distinct insofar as it precipitates a change
in the experience of time.
Since not every perceived change is conducive to rupturing experience and
expectation, how much change is needed for the alteration of the perception of
time to proceed? Apparently, the minimal condition for that is the possibility of
experiencing structural change. Koselleck notes that structural changes are per-
ceptible “so long as their temporal span does not exceed the memory of contem-
porary generations,” adding that there are also structures “which are so enduring
that they remain for contemporaries part of the unconscious or the unknown, or
68. Koselleck, “Einleitung,” in Zeitschichten, 15-16.
69. Koselleck, “Does History Accelerate?,” 90.
206 JUHAN HELLERMA
Another passage similarly hints at the linkage under scrutiny: “For, where
formerly long-term processes became abbreviated through altering or even
accelerating speed, the spaces of experience were rejuvenated by the continual
requirement to adapt.”72 My general point, however, is that the concept of layers
of time can be construed as a theoretical framework, which permits an accounting
for the specificity of modernity by providing the formal conditions that underlie
a distinctively modern pace of acceleration. Furthermore, the acceleration thesis
can be connected to Koselleck’s earlier notion about modernity maintaining
increasingly divergent spaces of experience and horizons of expectations. In
other words, it is in light of Koselleck’s later elaborations of the framework of
layers of time that real historical change underlying the shift in the experience of
time can gain theoretical ground. This also shows that Koselleck operates with
two distinct but interrelated notions of modernity. From the perspective of lay-
ers of time, modernity is defined as an unprecedented pace of structural change.
As we recall, Koselleck suggests that every history is a version of a universal
interplay between repetition and innovation, and hence modernity viewed in this
context is nothing but a specific instantiation of this relationship. The second
definition regards modernity as a new experience of time where past and future
increasingly grow apart.
This idea that semantic changes testifying to the changed perception of time
reflect transformations occurring in the external world (but also facilitate them)
was present in Koselleck’s works from the very beginning. However, it is only
in light of the framework of layers of time that we can draw out the connection
in a more sophisticated fashion. To put it more schematically, given Koselleck’s
insights, one can analytically distinguish among three levels of analysis: the
objective level attending to the rates of transformation within different structures
of repetition; the level of analysis focused on the actor’s perception of time; and
the level of conceptual history that empirically validates transformations of tem-
poral experience.
In the light of what has been said, I briefly return to the discussion of the
translation of Zeitschichten. It seems that in the condition of modern fluctuations,
the rendering of Zeitschichten as “sediments” proves particularly problematic.
Hence, the idea of a multilayered history opens up the space for drawing analo-
gies from the past into the future by attending to structures rather than events.
75. Koselleck, “Was sich wiederholt,” Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung, no. 167 (July 21, 2005).
76. Koselleck, “Sediments of Time,” 5.
77. Koselleck, “Constancy and Change of All Contemporary Histories,” 114.
78. Koselleck, “Concepts of Historical Time and Social History,” 123. Compare Koselleck,
“‘Space of Experience’ and ‘Horizon of Expectation,’” 275.
79. Koselleck, “Representation, Event, and Structure,” 114.
KOSELLECK ON MODERNITY, HISTORIK, AND LAYERS OF TIME 209
Even though structures are also mutable, they nevertheless provide enough con-
sistency to delimit the potential boundaries for future action. In other words, the
framework of layers of time gives rise to a weaker a version of historia magistra
vitae that, consistent with the original thesis that events themselves have lost their
exemplary status, sheds light on various factors that condition the future space of
action. However, it remains unclear to what degree this modest optimism about
learning from history is compatible with Koselleck’s thesis on the modern insta-
bility of structures, since it is the persistence of structures that should serve as the
cornerstone of a more nuanced theory of historia magistra vitae.
CONCLUSION
University of Tartu,
Estonia