We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 423
AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY
COLLOQUIUM PUBLICATIONS
VOLUME XXV
LATTICE THEORY
BY
GARRETT BIRKHOFF
PUBLISHED BY THE
AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY
ProvipEnce, RuopE Isr4NpFirst Edition, 1940
Second (Revised) Edition, 1948
Third Edition, Second Printing, 1973
COPYRIGHT, 1940, 1948, 1967, BY THE
AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY
All Rights Reserved
No portion of this book may be reproduced
without the written permission of the publisher.
Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 66-23707
Printed in the United States of AmericaPREFACE TO THE THIRD EDITION
The purpose of this edition is threefold: to make the deeper ideas of lattice
theory accessible to mathematicians generally, to portray its structure, and to
indicate some of its most interesting applications. As in previous editions, an
attempt is made to include current developments, including various unpublished
ideas of my own; however, unlike previous editions, this edition contains only a
very incomplete bibliography.
Iam summarizing elsewhere} my ideas about the role played by lattice theory in
mathematics generally. I shal] therefore discuss below mainly its logical structure,
which I have attempted to reflect in my table of contents.
The beauty of lattice theory derives in part from the extreme simplicity of its
basic concepts: (partial) ordering, least upper and greatest lower bounds. In this
respect, it closely resembles group theory. These ideas are developed in Chapters
1-V below, where it is shown that their apparent simplicity conceals many subtle
variations including for example, the properties of modularity, semimodularity,
pseudo-complements and orthocomplements.
At this level, lattice-theoretic concepts pervade the whole of modern algebra,
though many textbooks on algebra fail to make this apparent. ‘Thus lattices and
groups provide two of the most basic tools of “ universal algebra”, and in particular
the structure of algebraic systems is usually most clearly revealed through the
analysis of appropriate lattices. Chapters VI and VII try to develop these
remarks, and to include enough technical applications to the theory of groups and
loops with operators to make them convincing.
A different aspect of lattice theory concerns the foundations of set theory
(including general topology) and real analysis. Here the use of various (partial)
orderings to justify transfinite inductions and other limiting processes involves
some of the most sophisticated constructions of all mathematics, some of which are
even questionable! Chapters VIIT—XII deseribe these processes from a lattice-
theoretic standpoint.
Finally, many of the deepest and most interesting applications of lattice theory
concern (partially) ordered mathematical structures having also a binary addition
or multiplication: lattice-ordered groups, monoids, vector spaces, rings, and fields
(like the real field). Chapters XIII-XVII describe the properties of such systems,
+G. Birkhoff, What can lattices do for you?, an article in Trends in Lattice Theory, James C.
Abbot, ed., Van Nostrand, Princeton, N.J., 1967.
iiiv PREFACE
and also those of positive linear operators on partially ordered vector spaces.
‘The theory of such systems, indeed, constitutes the most rapidly developing part
of lattice theory at the present time.
The labor of writing this book has been enormous, even though I have made no
attempt at completeness. I wish to express my deep appreciation to those many
colleagues and students who have criticized parts of my manuscript in various
stages of preparation. In particular, I owe a very real debt to the following:
Kirby Baker, Orrin Frink, George Gratzer, C. Grandjot, Alfred Hales, Paul
Halmos, Samuel H. Holland, M. F. Janowitz, Roger Lyndon, Donald MacLaren,
Richard 8. Pierce, George Raney, Arlan Ramsay, Gian-Carlo Rota, Walter Taylor,
and Alan G. Waterman.
My thanks are also due to the National Science Foundation for partial support
of research in this area and of the preparation of a preliminary edition of notes, and
to the Argonne National Laboratory and the Rand Corporation for support of
research into aspects of lattice theory of interest to members of their staffs.
Finally, I wish to thank Laura Scblesinger and Lorraine Doherty for their
skillful typing of the entire manuscript.TABLE OF CONTENTS
CHAPTER I
TYPES OF LATTICES
CHAPTER IT
POSTULATES FOR LATTICES .
CHAPTER IIT
STRUCTURE AND REPRESENTATION THEORY
CHAPTER IV
GEOMETRIC LATTICES . ‘ .
CHAPTER V
COMPLETE LATTICES
CHAPTER Vi
UNIVERSAL ALGEBRA
CHAPTER VII
APPLICATIONS TO ALGEBRA.
CHAPTER VIII
TRANSFINITE INDUCTION... : . .
CHAPTER IX
APPLICATIONS TO GENERAL TOPOLOGY . .
CHAPTER X
METRIC AND TOPOLOGICAL LATTICES.
CHAPTER XI
BOREL ALGEBRAS AND VON NEUMANN LATTICES
CHAPTER XII
APPLICATIONS TO LOGIC AND PROBABILITY
v
iu
132
169
180
2u1
230
254
277vi CONTENTS
CHAPTER XII
LATTICE-ORDERED GROUPS .
CHAPTER XIV
LATTICE-ORDERED MONOIDS
CHAPTER XV
VECTOR LATTICES .
CHAPTER XVI
POSITIVE LINEAR OPERATORS
CHAPTER XVII
LATTICE-ORDERED RINGS
BIBLIOGRAPHY
INDEX
287
319
347
380,
397
411CuarTzr 1
TYPES OF LATTICES
1. Posets; Chains
Pure lattice theory is concerned with the properties of a single undefined binary
relation <, to be read “is contained in”, “is a part of”, or “‘is less than or equal
to”. This relation is assumed to have certain properties, the most. basic of which
lead to the following concept of a “partially ordered set”, alias “partly ordered
set” or “ poset”.
Dermrmon. A poset is a set in which a binary relation x $ y is defined, which
satisfies for all x, y, z the following conditions:
Pl. Forallz,zSz. (Reflexive)
P2. Ife x. The above notation
and terminology are standard.
There are countless familiar examples of partly ordered sets—i.e., of mathe-
matical relations satisfying P1-P3. Three of the simplest are the following.
Example 1. Let D(I) consist of all subsets of any class I, including I itself and
the void class @; and let x < y mean x is a subset of y.
Example 2. Let Z* be the set of positive integers; and let x < y mean that x
divides y. ;
Example 3. Let F consist of all real single-valued functions f(z) defined on
-1S 2 ljand let f 2 g mean that f(x) 2 g(x) for every x with -1 SxS 1.
We now state without proof two familiar laws governing inclusion relations,
which follow from P1-P3.
Lemma 1. In any poset, x < x for no x, while x < y and y < z imply x < z.
Conversely, if a binary relation < satisfies the two preceding conditions, define x Sy
to mean that x < y or x = y; then the relation < satisfies P1-P3.
In other words, strict inclusion is characterized by the anti-reflexive and transi-
tive laws.
It is easily shown that a poset P can contain at most one element a which
satisfies a S x for all ze P. For if a and b are two such elements, then a @ from a poset P to a poset Q is called order-preserving or
isotone if it satisfies
a) 2S y implies (2) < Oy).§2 ISOMORPHISM; DUALITY 3
An isotone function which has an isotone two-sided inverse is called an isomorphism.
In other words, an isomorphism between two posets P and Q is a bijection which
satisfies (1) and also
a’) Oz) S Oy) implies x < y.
An isomorphism from a poset P to itself is called an automorphism.
‘Two posets P and @ are called isomorphic (in symbole, P ~ Q), if and only if
there exists an isomorphism between them.
The converse of a relation p is, by definition, the relation p such that xpy
(read, ‘‘ is in the relation 3 to y”) if and only if ypr. Thus the converse of the
relation ‘‘includes” is the relation “‘is included in”; the converse of “greater
than” is “less than”. It is obvious from inspection of conditions P1-P3 that
TuzoreM 2 (Duatary Princreue). The converse of any partial ordering is
iteelf a partial ordering.
Dermirion. The dual of a poset X is that poset X defined by the converse par-
tial ordering relation on the same elements.
Since X ~ X, this terminology is legitimate: the relation of duality is symmetric.
Dermrrion. A function 6: P — Q is antitone if and only if
(2) xy implies 6(z) = Oy),
(2') x) $ Hy) implies x2 y.
A bijection (one-one correspondence) which satisfies (2)-(2') is called a dual
We shall refer to systems isomorphic with X as “dual” to X. Obviously posets
are dual in pairs, whenever they are not self-dual. Similarly, definitions and
theorems about posets are dual in pairs whenever they are not self-dual; and if
any theorem is true for all posets, then so is its dual.
‘As we shall see later, this Duality Principle applies to algebra, to projective
geometry, and to logic.
Many important posets are self-dual (i.e., anti-isomorphic with themselves),
‘Thus Example 1 of §2 is self-dual; the correspondence which carries each subset
into its complement is one-to-one and inverts inclusion. Similarly the set of all
linear subspaces of n-dimensional Euclidean space which contains the origin is
self-dual: the correspondence carrying each subspace into its orthogonal comple-
ment is one-to-one and inverts inclusion.
In these cases the self.duality is of period two: the image (2’)' of the image 2’
ofany zisagaine. Such self-dualities (dual automorphisms) are called involutions.
Exercises for §§1-2:
1. Prove Lemma 1.
2. Prove Lemme 2,
3. Show that there are exactly three different ways of partly ordering a set of two elements.
4. (a) Show that there are just two nonisomorphic posets of two elements, both of which are
self-dual.4 TYPES OF LATTICES I
(b) Show that there are five nonisomorphie posets of three elements, throe of which are
self-dual.
+5. (a) Let Gin) donoto the number of nonisomorphic posets of 2 elements, Show that
G4) = 16, G(5) = 63, (6) = 318. (I. Rose - R. T. Sasaki)
(0) @*(n) denote the number of different partial orderings of n elements. Show G*(2)=3,
G*(3) = 19, G*(4) = 219, G*(5) = 4231, @*(6) = 130,023, G*(7) = 6,129,859.
(c) How many of the precoding give self-dual posets ?
(d) Is @*(n) odd for all nt? Justify.
3. Diagrams; Graded Posets
The notion of “immediate superior
poset, as follows.
Derinition. By “a covers 8” in a poset P, it is meant that a > 6, but that
a>x>bfornoze P.
By the order n(P) of a poset P is meant the (casdinal) number of its elements.
When this number is finite, P is called a “finite” poset. Using the covering
relation, one can obtain a graphical representation of any finite poset P as
follows.
Draw a small circle to represent each element of P, placing a higher than 6
whenever a > 6. Draw a straight segment from a to b whenever a covers b.
The resulting figure is called a diagram of P: examples are shown in Figures la—le
below.
Since a > 6 if and only if one can move from a to b downward along some
broken line, it is clear that any finite poset is defined up to isomorphism by its
diagram. It is also clear that the diagram of the dual P of a poset P is obtained
from that of P by turning the latter upside down.
in a hierarchy can be defined in any
(a) {by te) (d) (e)
Froure 1. Examples of diagrams
Dermrrox. By a least element of any subset X of P, we mean an element
aeX such that a < x for all xe X. By a greatest element of X, we mean an
element b eX such that b > x for all ze X.
‘The preceding concepts are not to be confused with the concepts of minimal
and maximal elements. A minimal element of a subset X of a partly ordered set
P is an element a such that a < z for no ze X; maximal elements are defined
dually. Clearly, a least element must be minimal and a greatest element maximal,
but the converse is not true.
Tarorem 3. Any finite nonempty subset X of a poset has minimal and maximal
members.§3 DIAGRAMS; GRADED POSETS 5
Proor. Let X consist of 2, -++,2,. Define m, = x, and m, asx, if, < my
and m,., otherwise. Then m, will be minimal. Similarly, X has a maximal
element.
TurorEm 4. In chains, the notions of minimal and least (maximal and greatest)
clement of @ subset are effectively equivalent. Hence any finite chain has a least
(first) and greatest (last) element.
Proor. If x < a for no xe X, then by P4 2 2 a for every re X.
Tunorem 5. Every finite chain of n elements is isomorphic with the ordinal
number n (the chain of integers 1, «++, 7).
That is, there is a bijection ¢ from the chain X onto {1, ---, n} such that x, < 2,
if and only if ¢(z1) S $(x2); finite chains are finite ordinal numbers.
Proor. Let ¢ map the least x X into 1, and the least of the remaining x ¢ X
into 2, ete,
‘The length of a finite chain n is defined to be » — 1 (see its diagram). More '
generally, the length UP) of a poset P is defined as the least upper bound of the
lengths of the chains in P. When [(P) is finite, P is said to be of finite length.
Any poset of finite length is defined up to isomorphism by its covering relation:
a>) if and only if a finite sequence x, 2, --+,2, exists, such that a = 2,
b = 2,, and %_, covers x fori = 1,+++,n.
The isomorphism or nonisomorphism of two finite posets can often be tested
most simply by drawing their diagrams. Any isomorphism must be one-to-one
onto between lowest elements, between next lowest elements, and so on. Corre-
sponding elements must be covered by equal numbers of elements, and the covering
elements must also correspond. These principles make it easy to enumerate the
different (i.e., nonisomorphic) posets having x = 4 elements (say); there are
exactly 16 of them.
In a poset P of finite length with O, the height or dimension h{[z] of an element
xe P is, by definition, the Lu.b. of the lengths of the chains 0 = x < a, <---
< 2, = between O and z. If P has a universal upper bound J, then clearly
HI] =P]. Clearly also, h[x] = 1 if and only if x covers 0; such elements are
called “atoms” or “points” of P.
‘The height function is especially important in graded poses. These are defined
as posets P with a function g: P > Z from P to the chain of all integers (in their
natural order), such that:
Gl. > y implies g[x] > gly] (strict isotonicity).
G2. If. covers y, then g[x] = gly] + 1.
Any graded poset satisfies the following
JORDAN-DEDEKIND CHAIN CONDITION. All maximal chains between the same
endpoints have the same finite length.
Lemma 1. Let P be any poset with O in which all chains are finite. Then P
satisfies the Jordan—Dedekind chain condition if and only tf it is graded by h{z].6 TYPES OF LATTICES I
Proor. If P is graded by Alz], then the Jordan-Dedekind chain condition
follows obviously: the length of any maximal chain joining the endpoints @ and
6 > ais h{b] — Ala]. Conversely, if the Jordan-Dedekind chain condition holds,
then A(z] is the length of every maximal chain from 0 to z, from which G1 and G2
follow immediately.
Exercises for §3:
1. (a) Show that the diagram of a poset is an oriented graph,t if we draw an arrow from x
to y if and only if x covers y. grea
_,(P) Show that finite oriented graph is associated with a poset if and only if apy, dy0ay “+
4,144 is incompatible with aoa,
{#c) Show that any oriented graph defines a quasi-ordered set, if ¢ 2 b is defined to mean
a = b, ab, or nace owt «++, a,b for suitable 4;,++ +, a.
2. Show that the “covering relations” of any poset form a new poset if ('‘z covers y”) >
{‘*u covers »”) means that y > w.
3. Show that any isotone transformation P — P, of one poset P onto another P, carries
connected components of the graph of P into connected components of the graph of Pi.
4. Which of the diagrams of Figure 1 represent self-dual posets 1 Define two new self-dual
posete by means of diagrams,
§. Show that a chain can be defined as a set of elements in which a transitive relation z > y
is defined, such that for any elements u, v, one and only one of the relations u > v, u = »,
v > uholds.
6. Show that chains are those posets, all of whose subsets are lattices.
7. Show that no finite poset of more than two elements is defined to within isomorphism
by its graph.
8. Lot P be. poset of finite length. Show that any two clements of P have an upper bound
if and only if P has a universal upper bound I.
9. Show that, in 9 poset P of finite length, a chain from a to 6 is maximal if end only if it is
‘connected in the graph of P.
4. Lattices
An upper bound of a subset X of a poset P is an element a € P containing every
xe X. The least upper bound is an upper bound contained in every other upper
bound; it is denoted l.u.b. X or sup X. By P2, sup X is unique if it exists. The
notions of lower bound of X and greatest lower bound (g.l.b. X or inf X) of X
are defined dually. Again by P2, inf X is unique if it exists.
Dzrrnrrion. A latticet is a poset P any two of whose elements have a g.l.b.
or “meet” denoted by x A y, and a.u.b. or “join” denoted byx v y. A lattice
L is complete when each of its subsets X has a 1.u.b. and a g.l.b. in L.
Setting X = L, we see that any nonvoid complete lattice contains a least element
Oand a greatest element J. Evidently, the dual of any lattice is a lattice, and the
dual of any complete lattice is a complete lattice, with meets and joins inter-
changed. Any finite lattice or lattice of finite length is complete. More sophisti-
{ For the concepts of graph and oriented graph (“digraph”), ef. O. Ore, Theory of graphs,
Amer. Math. Soc., 1962.
} The concept of a lattice (‘Dualgruppe”) was firet atudied in depth by Dedekind [1, pp.
113-14]. That of a complete lattice wes introduced by the author in [1, p. 442).
Edwin Hewitt, Kenneth A. Ross Hewitt and Ros Abstract Harmonic Analysis Volume II Structure and Analysis For Compact Groups Analysis On Locally Compact Abelian Groups
(Lecture Notes in Mathematics 1667) Jesús M. F. Castillo, Manuel González (Auth.) - Three-Space Problems in Banach Space Theory-Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg (1997) PDF