Kennedy-A Critique of Adjudication
Kennedy-A Critique of Adjudication
A CRITIQUE OF
ADJUDICATION
(fin de siècleì
Duncan Kennedy
KF8700.K46 1997
347.73dc21 96-4867!
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
i Introduction I
Notes 379
Index 4,5
I
Introduction
This essay proposes a theory of the political effects of the American social
practice of organizing law making through distinct adjudicative and leg-
islative institutions. It is a work of general social theory written from a
leftist and a modernist/postmodernist point of view. It represents adjudi-
cation and legislation as parts of political and cultural life, in the hope
that the picture presented will be both convincing and unsettling.
The main question addressed is the role of political ideology, in the
simple sense of, say, "liberalism" and "conservatism," or "states' rights"
and "abolitionism," in the part of judicial activity that is best described
as law making. ¡ argue that judicial law making has been the vehicle of
ideological projects of this familiar kind and of other kinds, but that ideo-
logically oriented legal work is different from ideologically oriented leg-
islative work. I address the grand question of the meaning and effects of
adjudication in society through the development of these differences.
The main vehicle of my analysis is a detailed account of adjudication
that employs a variety of methodologies. The law-making activity of
judges takes place in the context of a structure of legal rules, in the face
oía particular gap, conflict, or ambiguity in the structure. Judges resolve
interpretive questions through a form of work that consists in restating
some part of this structure and then deploying a repertoire of legal argu-
ments to justify their solutions. The most important mode of influence of
ideology in adjudication comes from the interpenetration of this specific,
technical rhetoric of legal justification and the general political rhetoric of
the time.
It is sometimes plain that judges experience themselves as constrained
by the materials to reach particular solutions, even if they work in a me-
dium saturated with ideology. But they always aim to generate a partic-
I
2 Introduction
ular rhetorical effect through this work: that of the legal necessity of their
solutions without regard to ideology. They work for this effect against
our knowledge of the ineradicable possibility of strategic behavior in in-
terpretation, by which I mean the externally motivated, ideological choice
to work to develop a particular restatement and a particular solution
rather than another. As a matter of fact, they seem often to engage in a
form of denial of their own strategic behavior that puts them in bad
faith.
On the basis of this model, I propose three answers to the question of
the effects of adjudication. First, we can at least guess at the difference it
makes to the total corpus of law that so much of it is made by judges
pursuing ideological projects under these peculiar interpretive constraints.
The diffusion of law-making power reduces the power of ideologically
organized majorities, whether liberal or conservative, to bring about sig-
nificant change in any subject-matter area heavily governed by law. It
empowers the legal fractions of intelligentsias to decide the outcomes of
ideological conflict among themselves, outside the legislative process. And
it increases the appearance of naturalness, necessity, and relative justice of
the status quo, whatever it may be, over what would prevail under a more
transparent regime. In each case, adjudication functions to secure both
particular ideological and general class interests of the intelligentsia in the
social and economic status quo.
A second way in which adjudication functions in our politics is
through its relationship to the general idea of rights. The belief that
rights exist is both sustained and threatened by their role in legal dis-
course. I will try to show, from my own "post-rights" perspective, how
the belief in rights has sustained belief in adjudication, and how the cri-
tique of adjudication has sometimes been implicated in the loss of faith
in rights.
Finally, our ambivalent belief in the possibility of legal rationality is
one of the models, along with scientific rationality, for the general insti-
tution of "rightness" in our society. At the most general level, the notion
that there are expert discourses to which a practitioner can pledge faith,
not just outside but against ideology, supports a multitude of depoliticiz-
ing practices oí role specialization. "It's not my job," and "don't politicize
your workplace," are maxims that make sense, at least in part, because
judges model neutrality for all of us. The concluding chapter teases out
some implications for workplace politics of the critique of adjudication
taking place in the distant realm of legal theory.
Introduction 3
iconology of constraint
Cls has existed for me in four quite distinct modes. First, there was once
a "movement" called cts; there still exist a cts "school" and a 'theory of
law" called cts; and there is from time to time a media "factoid" called cis.
By the "movement" I mean a "project" in just the sense I described
abovea goal-oriented practical activity of a loosely identifiable group
carried out in light of an analysis contained in a literature of shifting
content. The people in the cls project were overwhelmingly legal academ-
ics; the goals were contested within the group, but my version was that
we were trying to create a left legal academic intelligentsia as a new social
grouping that would influence both its own workplaces and the general
political culture.
Two practical activities were reforming law faculties, in a left/mpm
direction, and creating a legal academic literature that would develop left
ideas within legal scholarship. Cts was a movement rather than just a
project because the ideas of "change," "growth," and "opposition" were
built into it, in the sense of being conscious collective purposes. A third
practical activity was "building the movement" by recruiting new people,
doing public relations, and developing relationships on the inside. The
social/political/intellectual network that "was" cls in the late i 970S and
early 1980s came apart in the late 19805, for reasons I have tried to describe
elsewhere (including discipline and seduction by the mainstream, gender
and race politics, intergenerational tensions, the advent of postmodernism,
and, doubtless, failures of nerve and leadership).4 But there are various
successor networks that are as active as ever.
Cts as a school of thought is like the movement in that it is a project,
but it is the strictly academic project of developing a network of writers
and teachers who share a set of ideas, rather than the academic/political
project of transforming society by transforming legal education. The mem-
bers of the school share the goal of expanding its membership and influ-
ence, and they critique mainstream legal scholarship more or less aggres-
sively, but they do so without trying to challenge the rules of the game or
the balance of power in their institutions.
The social organization of the school is based on teacher-student and
mentor-mentee relations. Characteristic activities include recruiting and
then helping to advance careers to build the school, the organization of
scholarly events where the far-flung members of the network can exchange
ideas and build collegial relationships, and "representing" cts on academic
occasions when it is seemly that the different schools established in legal
thought should all be present.
io Introduction
The internal politics are generational and professional. They involve the
anxiety of influence as between and within generations, rivalry for the
ownership of ideas, and dramas of success and failure, heroism and oppor-
tunism, on the ladder of academic appointments. The school, unlike the
movement, is institutionalized at a small number of law faculties and
continues to reproduce itself socially and to develop intellectually over
time.
CIs as a theory of law exists in the very different form oía canon, a list
of texts that "are" cls, along with commentaries and critiques. You can be
the author of a canonical text without ever having participated in the
movement, and you can help define cls as a theory of law by producing an
interpretation that is influential mainly because it is discrediting. Like
many others, I tried to write articles that would constitute a cls canon and
that would "strengthen" it in its competitive relationship with other the-
ories. CIs as a theory of law is very much alive, "on the map" of generally
recognized rival theories, and it continues to develop as people write "cls
articles" and others comment on and critique "the" theory.
Now that a canon is constituted, I have to struggle like other authors
to get my current ideas included. Only texts and not people can be "in"
the canon, and a person's relationship to the historical movement or the
current successor networks doesn't guarantee, though, of course, it does
strongly affect his or her ability to get a new writing canonized. This book
is an attempt to add to the canon and thereby to change what the theory
"is," by developing it, strengthening it, and inflecting understanding of
it in the directions I favor. This implies critiquing and trying to displace
the many ideas found in canonical cls texts that I think are wrong.
Finally, cls existed recently, and may exist again, as a factoid, that is, as
an entity in the "spectacle" that the mass media provide for our amusement
and edification.' In the spectacle, cls "is" what journalists decide it is. A
network participant or theoretician of cls can affect what it is like and
what it does as a character in the spectacle only by meeting the rigid
criteria for what counts as a "story."
The elements in a story within the spectacle have to be both familiar
and simple, at the same time that the narrative as a whole has to be novel,
or at least interesting to the mass audience, and has to be edifying. So cls
could be "scanned" or "parsed" by the media as "sixties radicals at Harvard
in the eighties," for example, but not as "a few people interested in a
combination of New Left, neo-Marxist, cultural modernist, and feminist
ideas inspiring unease among liberal mainstream law professors" (not that
the latter would be "true").
Introduction ij
The notions of leftism and mpm are helpful in understanding many of the
debates that occurred within cls when it was a live movement and that
still arise about cls understood as a school and a theory of law. Attacks
from the left, internal and external, often focus on its mpm quality. "Being
right" in the rationalist sense has been a crucial part of leftism, and the
mpm strand in the project is hostile to rightness in all its forms. Other
critiques of the project from the left come from the demand that theory
contribute to a particular model of action in the world, whereas the dan-
dyish, aestheticist, politically quietist mpm strands rebel against that im-
age.
Many critiques of the project from the other direction come from mpm
maximalismfrom the demand to be right in the total rejection of right-
ness, and thereby justify quietism. The reaction is against the project's
apparent demand for commitment. Other mpm criticisms (revalidation of the
subject, failure to see that everything is already within a structure) are also
provoked by its leftism. In mpm, there is often a sense that critique should
be aimed at achieving negative liberty, against various kinds of bourgeois
moralism and hypocrisy. The left strand in the project seems as much of
a threat as the Right.
The reason for the chastened character of current American critical social
theory may be that within it mpm seems to have a "hypercritical" direction
that threatens to annihilate the left strand. Within critical legal studies,
in particular, the critique of adjudication has figured in a development of
ideas that paradoxically reverses its original function, turning it from a
workhorse obviously useful against Liberal legalism into a Trojan horse.
12 Introduction
Loosed from its host (adjudication), critique has spread through the proj-
ect, attacking all the "precritical" elements that seem necessary to give the
whole a left-wing character.
1 will try to show that there is still something both tenable and left
wing in critical legal theory, in spite of mpm critique, though the showing
requires abandoning or scaling down many left-tending claims that would
have seemed plausible a generation ago. The outcome, as I'm sure the
reader knows already, will be analysis that sometimes seems afraid of its
own implications. So, in Chapter 14, I'll let the left and mpm elements
clash head on. Working on the conflict between them involves changing
the traditional meanings of each, in the hope that the sacrifices will be
repaid in new energy (a typically modernist revivification project).
Subversion
Objeaivity
duce ecstasy in, inform, and perhaps change the audience without having
to be accepted as true in the mirror sense, indeed often by playing on the
limits of representation (that is, of methodology).
The representation as artifact in this modernist mode presupposes that
the audience and the object have their own relationshipthe audience has
its own access to the object (and maybe vice versa, if the object is someone's
behavior). The audience is trying to increase its own understanding, rather
than depending on the representation for everything. It's all in the trian-
gulation.
Contrast the traveler who wants to know when the train will leave and
has no way of knowing except through a schedule. The traveler cares only
whether the representation is true or false. The audience for the artifact,
by contrast, has its own version of the object to check against the repre-
sentation and, if the artifact "works" (big iO, understands itself to gain
rather than lose by radical disconrinuities as well as by striking similarities
between the two. (The artifact is in a metonymic relation to the object.)
Political/cultural impacts. My project for changing the world through
artifact production is left wing and culturally modernist/postmodernist. I
work on the assumption that the things that seem wrong and dead about
the social world are that way in spite of people's deep longing for justice
and liveliness. Also that belief systems constitute all of us in ways incon-
sistent with our own longings and impede our efforts to realize justice and
liveliness by falsely making it appear that they can't be realized or that
they have already been realized. My idea is to participate with others in
producing representations that will be inconsistent with these "legitimat-
ing" but also "constitutive" belief systems.
The test of this practice is whether the representations get appreciated
by an audience that incorporates them into left/mpm political and cul-
tural projects. This goal has a massive impact on the choice of what to
represent and how to do it, including on the choice of methodology. The
reason for this is the iron law of methodology: The more "hard" (capable of
being counted, highly verifiable and replicable, intersubjectively "valid"),
the more "nan'ow" (partial, fragmentary, meaningless). The things that in-
terest me are "broad," like justice and liveliness, so they can be grasped
in their totality only by means that are "soft" (contestable, subjective,
vague).
I think the way to respond to this dilemma is by using che hard/narrow
methods of representation strategically, in the interest of making the soft/
broad methods plausible, and in order to poke threatening holes in what
Introduction
It would be nice to begin (at last!) with a simple revelatory model along
the following lines. Imagine that all questions of law either have or do not
have a "determinate correct answer' when approached as questions of in-
terpretation. A question that does not have a determinate answer will be
decided, but the best way ro understand the outcome is as a choice by the
judge between rival ideological projects rather than between better and
worse interpretations. Then imagine that the participants in the system
believe in the naive rule-of-law theory, according to which judges apply
but do not make law.
What would be nice about this way of looking at it is that it would fit
in with the critical project of Ludwig Feuerbach7 and Karl Marx.8 In such
a critical project, we begin with supposedly conclusive demonstrations of
the internal incoherence of arguments for the existence of an omnipotent
God, or for the claim that the capitalist system operates through inexorable
laws to reward each participant according to his or her social contribution.
But people believe the oppositethat an omnipotent God does exist and
that the market distributes according to contributions. In each case, there
is a false appearance of determinacy in the social world, and the false
determinacy hides a true determination by human agency. In other words,
people "alienate their powers."
One then analyzes the consequences of belief in the false appearance of
determinacy secure in the knowledge that whatever may be going on it is
not what the participants think it is. The next move is to show that things
are really determined by something else. Thus determination by God's will
Introdkclioa ¡9
hides determination by, say, the need for food; determination by the market
hides determination by class power; determination by law hides deter-
mination by, say, ideology.
The illusion, and the alienation of human powers, contribute to or in-
fluence or partly cause the patterns of social life rather than just mystifying
them. The claim of the classical theories is that people would be less likely
to accept the patterns if they understood that the appearance of determi-
nation by God's will or the market is just a mask for determination by
human beings like themselves. Revealing that the apparent determination
is an illusion or fraud, and that an alternative determination (the need for
food, the logic of capital) is what is really going on, ipso facto discredits
the way things are.
The representation thus includes not only an alternative analysis of what
is really going on but also an appeal to an ethic that discredits what is
really going on. Communism as an affirmative ideal was cast as an appli-
cation of the reigning Judeo-Christian ethic to the world as it looked when
the precepts of classical political economy had been revealed as fraudulent.
The ethical move is thus a second determination: it correctly applies to
the world rendered transparent the principles that had functioned, in the
mystified world where people alienate their powers, as apology.
That left-wing project is the model for this one, in the following sense.
I argue that ideology influences adjudication, by structuring legal dis-
course and through strategic choice in interpretation. I argue that the
denial of the presence of ideology in adjudication leads to political results
different from those that would occur in a situation of transparency. And
I suggest that it would be in some sense "better" to determine our fates
without alienating our powers.
But my version of the critical project is modified in ways intended to
deprive it of pretensions to truth. The first modification is to get rid of
the idea that there is an objective boundary line we can draw between
questions of law that have correct determinate answers and questions that
can be resolved only through ideological choice. The second is to propose
an understanding of the rules that dispose ideological stakes as products
of the interaction between the legal materials, understood as a constraining
medium, and the ideological projects of judges. The rule choices that
emerge from the interaction should be understood neither as simply the
implications of authority nor as the implications of the ideological projects,
but as a compromise.
The third is to reject the idea of simple illusion, or false consciousness,
20 Introduction
in favor of the more complex idea that judges are in bad faith. They "deny"
their ideological projects rather than either putting them aside or lying
about them, so that there is a discontinuity between two levels of their
consciousness rather than between truth and illusion. The fourth is to
explore the ideological consequences of law making through adjudication
in bad faith, without proposing either a substitute determination of what
is 'really" going on or an ethical determination of how we must respond
to the revelation of error.
PART ONE
23
24 IDEOLOGICAL STAKES IN ADJUDICATION
There are two quite different conventional ways to state the idea that
appellate court discursive practices for choosing rules do or should exclude
ideology. These will figure heavily in the future discussion. One is to say
that the rule-making process is or ought to be "objective"; the other is to
say, much more modestly, that it ought not to be "personal."
Within legal culture, since the late nineteenth century, there has been
debate about the objectivity of the procedures that judges use in choosing
rules of law. For lawyers, J assert, the main thing at stake in these discus-
sions has been whether or not judges are, or have to be or ought to be,
ideological actors. To say that judicial law making produces rule choices
that are objectively correct s simply to say that it produces rule choices
that cannot be attributed to the ideological sympathies of the judges. It
is sometimes asserted that there are other stakes, like the nonpolitical value
of certainty as a facilitator of legal transactions, but these turn out to be
makeweights in the legal debate, though occasionally appealing to out-
siders.
An amusing sideshow to this debate has been staged by philosophers
(of many persuasions and ideologies) who have been interested in objec-
tivity "in general" and who address the question in law as an analogue to
the question as ir arises elsewhere. Often, they haven't understood the
lawyers' stakes, and so propose that law is objective according to an account
of objectivity that doesn't respond to the issue of the preclusion of ideo-
logical determination, thinking they are thereby clarifying things for us
philosophical illiterates! Because they miss the point, these interventions
don't usually get incorporated into the lawyers' debate.
Stanley Fish made the opposite mistake in his debate with Ronald
Dworkin.3 He seemed to think it should comfort us that, though law is
certainly not objective, there is no way for judges to escape control by
their context. But the mode of "always already constrained" that he pro-
posed was patently a constraint that couldn't exclude ideology.
The parallel debate about whether legal decision making is not or ought
not to be "personal" has the same stakes. Nonlawyers sometimes interpret
the exclusion of the personal as aimed at corruption, or at the random
preferences of judges, say, for litigants wearing blue shirts. But the only
real issue is the personal understood as the ideological. The following
passage is highly typical, not least in its equivocation as to whether judges
"really do not" decide on the basis of personal values, or are only "deterred"
from so doing, so that they can make "massive doctrinal shifts" only
"rarely."
The Distinction between Adjudication and Legislation 25
(Tihe fact that judges are protected in significant ways from the pop-
ular will . . . makeEs) it inappropriate for them to reach outcomes on
the basis of their personal (and possibly idiosyncratic) values. Despite
all the palaver that this is what judges really do, the truth is that they
really do no:. The institutional constraints I have already mentioned-
combined with the requirement of reasoned decision and a moral ob-
Ligation of candorare checks that deter the imposition of judges' per-
sonal values and that confine the courts to "molecular motions." Mas-
sive doctrinal shifts are rare. When they do occur, they are usually a long
time building, and, if they touch sensitive moral nerves, are at least as
long a time commanding the general acceptance needed to make them
effective.4
judge making any particular rule has an interest, an interest in his or her
rule prevailing, in presenting the rule choice as not judicial legislation.
Third, many particular claims of legal necessity in judicial opinions are
unconvincing on their face, and therefore raise the question of what is
"really" determining the outcome.
In stark contrast with the view that judges present in their opinions,
the standard practice of sophisticated journalism treats judges, at least of
the Supreme Court, as political actors whose views and alignments can be
analyzed through the conventional vocabulary of politics. Indeed, as in the
following quotation, the journalistic treatment of the Court uses the lan-
guage of ideology with more confidence than would a parallel treatment
of legislative disputes, given the prevailing sense that straightforward left-
right divisions only partially describe legislative politics. Linda Green-
house is describing the 1993 Supreme Court term for the Sunday New
York Times "News of the Week in Review":
A few months later, Vincent Blasi, also a law professor, reviewed a bi-
ography of Justice Lewis Powell in exactly the same vein:
In an age that generated fierce pressures to interpret the Constitution to
serve one or another partisan agenda, Lewis Powell probably did as much
as anyone to keep alive the ideal of judicial independence. Few Justices
in history have succeeded so well at separating their political predilec-
tions from their judgments regarding what the Constitution means.
Justice Powell's performance disappointed many conservatives . . . Be-
cause his view prevailed in a large number of closely contested decisions,
Justice Powell's independence had a major impact on the development
of the law.'°
A letter writer was concerned that the review might mislead the "ed-
ucated layman" into thinking that "independence" was rare rather than
the rule on the Supreme Court, but agreed that Powell's "ability to place
the law ahead of any ideological or political considerations is what made
him a noteworthy jurist."
Though in neither the reassuring nor the celebratory mode, this chapter
addresses the anxiety implicit in these reviewers' particular choice of praise.
If what makes a judge great is his ability to resist not only other people's
but also his own ideological predilections, then it seems to follow, as the
letter writer sees, that lesser judges dont manage this. In building their
The Distinction between Adjudication and Legislation 3I
ite positivist heritage by positing that there is a limit to the range of cases
that correspond to the method of coherence. The judges are obliged to
decide all cases that come before them, and some of these are beyond the
middle rangein other words, the law "runs out" and the judge must
legislate. Of course, he does so subject to the various constraints, such as
the requirement of a case or controversy, described above.
In this version, there are two forms of judicial legislation, only one of
which has a negative connotation. If, on the one hand, the judge fails to
perform his function of judicial law making according to the method of
coherence, and particularly if he makes a rule that corresponds to his leg-
islative preference rather than to the preference implicit in the legal ma-
terials, then the rule of law is in jeopardy. On the other hand, where the
law "runs out," he is simply the victim ola contradiction between the role
constraints proposed by popular political culture. He is supposed to decide
the case without judicial legislation, but this is impossible. Since not
deciding is also impossible (walking away means that the defendant wins),
the right thing for him to do is what he thinks is right, leaving it to the
legislature or (in the United States) to the constitutional amendment pro-
cess to correct him if he is wrong.
In the American version, the method of coherence will give a "right
answer" to any dispute over which the judge has jurisdiction. There may
be types of cases for which the adjudicative method is inappropriate
(Fuller,34 Hart and Sacks33), but legal doctrine itself defines these cases and
forbids the judge deciding them, rather than requiring him to do so. The
defendant wins "as a matter of law," rather than by refusal of justice. The
judge never has to legislate, and judicial legislation is always bad. The
conventional judicial rhetoric of constraint by law can be honored, rather
than treated in the positivist manner as a pious fraud. In this version, the
judge can do his job.
With the passage from Cardozo to Fuller and Liewellyn through Hart
and Sacks to Dworkin, there is a noticeable evolution of this position. It
moves in the direction of blurring the difference between the middle term
of coherence and judicial legislation, while at the same time vigorously
affirming its importance. Dworkin and many other modern American legal
theorists concede (even affirm) the political character of adjudication. They
affirm the possibility of "rightness" in even the "hardest" cases, while pro-
gressively abandoning any claim that this rightness is "objective," or de-
monstrable in the sense that any rational practitioner of legal reasoning
36 IDEOLOGICAL STAKES IN ADJUDICATION
would have to accept it, let alone noncontroversial within the canons of
good legal reasoning. They nonetheless retain a sharp distinction between
judging and legislating:
[Liegal practice is an exercise in interpretation not only when lawyers
interpret particular documents or statutes but generally. Law so conceived
is deeply and thoroughly political. Lawyers and judges cannot avoid poli-
tics in the broad sense of political theory. But law is not a matter of
personal or partisan politics, and a critique of law that does not under-
stand this difference will provide poor understanding and even poorer
guidance)6
For Dworkin, a hard case may require judgments of "political theory"
because there may be more than one solution that meets the requirement
of coherence or fit. Moreover, the operation of investigating whether a
proposed solution passes the initial test of fit will be influenced by the
same political theories that the judge appeals to if at the end of the day
he has to choose between outcomes that are equally coherent. There is no
metacriterion for choosing between political theories, or between versions
of coherence influenced by those theories, other than the judge's conviction
that a given theory is the best.
As Gerald Postema points out," this is an extreme "protestant' version
of "rightness" in interpretation. In hard cases, the judge cannot rely on
external authority or even on the idea of objectivity, and cannot hope to
compel the agreement of others; but he is never to succumb to doubt as
to whether the truth he seeks "really exists" outside himself. "[Jiudges
deciding difficult constitutional cases are [noti simply voting their per-
sonal political convictions as much as [sic) if they were legislators or del-
egates to a new constitutional convention."3S If the judge is doing "ordi-
nary politics n disguise," he is "incompetent or in bad faith."9
Contrast, finally, the civil law version of adjudication, a fifth strategy
that combines all of these elements in yet another way. On the Continent,
the official story is that the role of the judge is to apply the relevant Code
to the facts of the case using a presumption of gaplessness. If the case
cannot be resolved by semantic or deductive analysis of the meanings of
the terms in a validly enacted rule, the judge deploys interpretive tech-
niques based on the presumption that the Code is the coherent working
out of a particular conceptual structure. He does the best he can but does
not entertain the possibility that "there is no right answer." In the official
version, the judge can always do his job, though some cases are harder
than others. In this respect, Dworkin is a Continental.
The Distinction between Adjudication and Legislation 37
But the official version40 denies, first, that the judge will ever have to
go beyond coherence, or fit, into Dworkin's realm of personally held gen-
eral political theory, and, second, that these general theories legitimately
influence the operation of determining coherence in the first place. The
more radical Continental thinkers suggest that it may sometimes be nec-
essary for the judge to appeal beyond the conceptual form of coherence to
the notion of "progress" or "social evolution," but they underplay rather
than emphasize the controversial character of these ideas. Even the Con-
tinentals of the free law school took the convention of judicial necessity
far more seriously than does the current American academic mainstream.4
39
40 IDEOLOGICAL STAKES IN ADJUDICATION
The three concepts of groups, interests, and conflicts are not fully distinct
from one another. Groups are composed of people, and they are continuous
but not identical through time. The idea includes communities in the
strong sense but also groups that have only ideal interests in common-
such as civil libertarians. Interests are enduring orientations of groups to
outcomes for conflicts. The interest may be one held by all groups, some-
thing they compete over, like income or wealth or space; or it may be an
interest in doing something that another group doesn't want done, as
abortion. Ir may be a large or small aspect of group existence. Conflicts
are situations in which it looks as though interests are "at stake," rather
than just the object of discussion or disagreement.
Interests in common can bring people to consider themselves a group.
A group will enter into conflict with another group to protect its interest,
but a conflict between two individuals can cause others to redefine their
interests, or others to come into being as a group. There are no ontological
priorities among the concepts.
Rules of law play an important role in many different conflicts that people
conceive as "between groups." When these conflicts become lawsuits, the
plaintiff and defendant are understood to be stand-ins for groups, even if
ideological Conflict over the Definition of Legal Rk/es 4'
they themselves have no desire for this to be true and do their best to
avoid it. The group focuses not on the total complex of the parties' good
and bad behavior, extended back in time and implicating everything in
life, or on their guilt or innocence, but on a particular rule that has played
a role in the way the dispute evolved. This rule is a situational element,
quite possibly minor, in the dispute, but it is also part of the permanent
structure of group conflict. The choice of a definition or interpretation of
the rule may be insignificant for the parties, but because the rule appears
again in many other, distant contexts of similarly structured group conflict,
it is significant enough for the groups to fight about.
Ideologies exist not only in relation to group interests but also in relation
to other ideologies. A defining characteristic oí an ideology is that it is
"contested." This means that there is more going on in a debate than a
quarrel over the outcome of a particular interest conflict, and more also
than a focused disagreement in which it is clear to the parties exactly what
is at stake and how one might go about establishing the truth or falsity
of a position. In ideological conflict, it is common to hear things like, "I
disagree with everything you said; I disagree with your whole approach."
Often the two sides will propose different criteria of truth and falsehood
or of verification, so that it is hard to see how either side could possibly
convince the other.
Because the contest of ideologies is "deep" in this sense, we experience
it as interminable, at least in the sense that we think the opponents will
ideological Conflict over the Definition of Legal Rules 43
difference is that both sides expect that a decision will be madethe stakes
will be disposed, the rule defined one way or anotherbefore there is a
consensus on whose view of the truth of the matter is better. And each
party believes that, at the practical level of the stakes in question in each
particular dispute, its group's interests deserve protection whether or not it
is possible to achieve consensus on the truth before a decision is made.
Because the stakes will probably be disposed without agreement of all
affected, the ideological participants have an interest that is merely "stra-
tegic" from the point of view of the truth seeker. They enter in good faith
into the dialogue trying to persuade and open to being persuaded, but
they have to keep always in mind that they are responsible for the concrete
interests of the groups they are representing. They need to win even when
they can't persuade, rather than defining winning as persuading.
Ideological conflict shares with bargaining the situation of having to
decide one way or the other, whether or not the parties can achieve con-
sensus on what is right or fair, and therefore the element of the "strategic"
(versus the dialogic). But in contrast with arms-length bargaining, the
crucial fact of ideological conflict is the existence of neutrals and potential
converts, whether in the electorate, legislature, administrative agency, jury,
or judicial panel. The ideologists assume that over the long run the project
will succeed or fail according to its ability to affect these "swing" people.
In arms-length bargaining, we take it for granted that you know what
your interests are and I know what mine are; in ideological dispute, each
side tries to persuade some, "enough," of the others that what is involved
is a misunderstanding rather than a "true" conflict of interests.
The very universalizing of ideological intelligentsias presupposes that
something more than mere "settlement" is a possible outcome of the con-
flict. But it most definitely does not presuppose even the possibility of
consensus. Indeed, the most common structure for ideological conflict in
modern society seems to be that each side is internally heterogeneous, with
its members arrayed on a spectrum from "completely closed to persuasion
by the other side" to "practically no ideological loyalty at all," and that
there is in most disputes a significant "center" that defines itself as ideo-
logically neutral (of course, this turns out to be an ideology, too). Ideolog-
ical conflict presupposes the possibility of persuasion but also, typically,
the probability that when persuasion has proceeded a certain distance the
definition of the rule, or indeed the overall shape of society, will be decided
against the will of a large number of the participants in the society.
ideological Conflict over the Definition of Legal Rules 45
The subjects of ideologized group conflict over the definition of rules in our
particular society
A list of the stakes of ideologized group conflict in appellate courts is a
list of the claims of groups, cast in universal terms, that groups have tried
to get resolved in their favor in the courts. There is no list of issues that
are by their nature ideological or that are by their nature legal. The ten-
tative list below of issues that are understood and argued this way is the
product of the particular history of American society and American law.
Although I've organized it into a typology, I don't mean it to be exhaustive;
rather, it should be evocative of what "everyone" knows about American
politics.
definition isn't very helpfül for understanding these ideologies in the ap-
pellate courts, because the courts have relatively little to do with many
issues of governmental size that dominate in the legislatures, and because
the issues they do address evoke a much more complex set of liberal and
conservative positions.
American liberalism in the courts might be roughly defined as the proj-
ect of eliminating status-based inequality, both in formal legal treatment
and in private market treatment; promoting cultural pluralism (tolerance);
promoting legal rules that increase the relative shares going to workers,
other disfavored groups, consumers, and environment lovers, at the expense
of the owners of enterprises; promoting a participatory/therapeutic frame-
work for the exercise of legitimate authority; and promoting participatory
conceptions of democracy. Conservatism means arguing for preserving the
preliberal status distinctions, repressing various kinds of deviance, pre-
serving or increasing the relative shares of enterprise owners in their deal-
ings with workers, consumers, and environmentalists, defending authori-
tarian means in the exercise of authority, and resisting participatory
conceptions of democracy in favor of established institutions.
Both liberalism and conservatism are ideologies because these quite con-
crete positions in group conflicts are backed up by more or less elaborate
universalization projects, which allow advocates to claim that each of the
more particular positions is an instance of correct application of general
principles. The general theories can be roughly grouped as relying on
rights, morality, and social welfare, and what is most striking about lib-
eralism and conservatism is their virtually total agreement on what those
principles are. Both sides favor majority rule, individual rights, and the
rule of law; both embrace Judeo-Christian moral codes; both favor a reg-
ulated market economy with safety nets.
Both ideologies incorporate the same specific sets of standardized ar-
guments in each of these modes but apply them differently. Chapter 6
introduces the legal versions of these "flippable" arguments.
In each substantive area, there are familiar symmetrical tensions within
liberal and conservative positions:
The crucial part of the pyramid is the middle term. In disputes about
what rules are best, a surprisingly small set of arguments makes up the
whole lexicon, and these arguments get (a) used over and over again in
one context after another, and (b) switched back and forth between liberals
and conservatives. Of course, each particular rule conflict is different from
every other one. An enormous amount of the discourse is concerned with
figuring out just how this particularity should change the way the stereo-
typed argument comes out. But these very specific disputes, themselves
interminable, play out within a strikingly stable, simple, large ideological
framework.3
Ideological Conflict over the Definition of Legal Rukr 49
Other is terrifying because potentially evil (rather than someone who "just
doesn't get it"), and can't be dealt with in case of disagreement except by
force.
I don't think liberalism and conservatism are epistemes or paradigms,
because they have wanting, feeling, and solidarity dimensions. But these
are not outside discourse, and a good deal of ideologized group conflict
consists of appeals to wants, feelings, and solidarity on the other side.
We can also capture something of the experience through W. B. Gallie's
notion of a "contested concept" and Dworkin's reformulation of it as a
"conception" of a concept.6 The concepts include majority rule, rights, the
rule of law, equality of opportunity, Judeo-Christian morality, and a reg-
ulated market with a safety net. A large part of the discourse is easy to
interpret as conflict over how to interpret these abstractions, rather than
over what normative premises to adopt in the first place.
But neither "contested concept" nor "conception" adequately describes
ideology in the sense of liberalism and conservatism. First, they leave out
the things that are experienced as otherness in the interlocutorthe very
things grasped by the notion of an episteme or paradigm. Second, they are
no better than episteme or paradigm at grasping the noncognitive dimen-
sion of conflict. Indeed, Gallie and her followers, including Dworkin, often
seem to be attracted to the notion of the contested concept because it
allows us to understand ideological conflict as a philosophical discussion
(in the dialogue rather than the bargaining mode) gone wrong, rather than
as some other kind of conflict.
liberal point of view, all but abolished, conservatives draw back from the
abyss and adopt the very welfare state rhetoric they have been busily de-
nouncing as crypto-communist.
As a result, two kinds of potential incoherence constantly threaten each
camp: there is (a) the problem of reconciling positions in different domains
(for conservatives, their antipaternalist economic rhetoric with their pa-
ternalist social issue rhetoric), and (b) the problem of explaining, within
a given domain, why they draw a particular line rather than take the
position to its logical extreme" (for liberals, why they don't favor the
outright redistribution of wealth, for example).
For the observer/theorist (me) who wants to use liberalism and conser-
vatism as interpretive tools in constructing an account of how adjudication
works and what effects it has, the vulnerability of the two ideologies to
the charge of incoherence poses a classic methodological problem. One of
the meanings of mpm is a preference for one type of solution over another.
I doubt that there are "true," coherent versions of liberalism and con-
servatism for use in analyzing what lies "behind" the "objective" or "im-
personal" rhetoric of judges. While it is always possible that liberal and
conservative theorists will find (or have already found without my knowing
it) abstract formulations that would allow us to speak of the ideologies as
"requiring" this or that position on a particular issue, this seems highly
improbable to me. So how can I use liberalism and conservatism as ele-
ments, as conceptual tools for understanding adjudication, if my own view
is that each, when viewed as a "philosophy," is an internally contradictory
hodgepodge?
I am equally skeptical about coherent, operational definitions of liber-
alism and conservatism "from the outside," that is, using external factors,
like the supposed objective interests of particular groups or the supposed
rational implications of particular (coherent) premises. Such definitions
allow the outside observer to categorize motives or actions, for his or her
own purposes, as ideological or not, and then as liberal or conservative,
without referring to the contested dimension of internal coherence. But
an external definition is unlikely to be useful for our purposes because we
are interested in the very phenomena of self-consciousness, phenomena like
denial, that external definitions try to avoid.
To treat the ideologies as "projects" is to acknowledge or assert the
incoherence of their theory components, hoping that we will nonetheless
be able to distinguish liberalism and conservatism for our particular pur-
poses because there are factors other than internal coherence that "stabilize"
them. By a "stabilizer" I mean something that contributes to our sense
ideological Conflict over the Definition of Legal Rules 53
that we are talking meaningfully when we say that someone "is" a liberal,
or that a position "is" liberal, or that "liberals, but not conservatives, face
a hard choice on a particular issue." The basic idea is that the project is
an entity stable enough to be useful in analysis because it is more than a
theory: it is also a self-conscious group activity with a history and a prac-
tical dimension.
Some of the stabilizers that allow us to think we know what we are
talking about when we talk about liberalism and conservatism are the
following:
i. Self-conscious consensus: it's liberal to come out a particular way on
a new issue if liberals say it's liberal, and we are reassured if conser-
vatives say it's liberal too.
History: it's a liberal position if people who called themselves liberal
thought at some point in the past that it was entailed by liberal
premises and incorporated it into their program as such.
Structural position vis-à-vis alternatives: it's liberal if it is situated
between a well-defined conservative position and equally well de-
fined communist or anarchist positions; it's conservative if it is sit-
uated between a well-defined liberal position and fascist or ultra
free market positions.
Local coherence: it's liberal if it is so close to a lot of similar, well-
defined liberal positions that it would be bizarre to go the other way,
given how much is settled in the vicinity.
I hope it's obvious that I'm not claiming anything faintly "scientific"
or "objective" about this way of using the terms "ideology," "liberalism,"
and "conservatism." There will be plenty of room for disagreement, after
meticulous application of all the tests I've laid out, about whether any
particular person or position is one thing or the other. But I do want to
claim that the general notion of a project, and the particular elements I've
specified, fit the common usage of the three terms in present-day American
political culture.
More important, when members of the liberal and conservative ideo-
logical intelligentsias elaborate, to different ends, their common commit-
ment to the rule of law, they routinely contrast "legality," as a motive for
decision, with "ideology." When they do so, I think they mean ideology
in the sense I've been developing here. In other words, my claim is to have
given a kind of anthropologist's description of the typical usage of a cul-
turally significant term.
Finally, I think that liberalism and conservatism, so defined, are suffi-
54 IDEOLOGICAL STAKES IN ADJUDICATION
Ideological preferences
Liberalism capitalized
The abstract normative part of Liberalism capitalized, that is, of the larger
unit that includes liberalism and conservatism, is made up of the theo-
retical commitments that liberals and conservatives share, including
rights, majority rule, the rule of law, Judeo-Christian morality, and a reg-
ulated market economy with safety nets. But the Liberal center also defines
itself by semiotic contrast to its "opposite numbers," communism and
anarchism on the left and fascism and Manchesterism on the right.
We can and will look at the effects of the institution of adjudication
(judicial law making in a condition of contest about the role of ideology
in the process) on the political conflict between liberals and conservatives.
But the institution, thus contested, also has at least putative effects on the
conflict between the liberal/conservative "center," the larger party of Lib-
eralism, the party of "moderation" in the modern West, and the whole
spectrum of outlying, more radical, left and right ideologies.
I will not use the term "ideology" to describe Liberalism because I want
to reserve it for the more specific universalization projectsliberalism,
conservatism, communism, anarchism, fascism, Manchesterism, feminism,
and nationalismthat are commonly denoted by the term in American
political discourse. I am going to be arguing, first, that the central problem
ideological Conflict over the Definition of Legal Ru/es 57
laws about strikes, abortion, government support for the arts, and
thousands more issues this way. When the legal stakes in an appellate
lawsuit include the choice between definitions of a rule of law, and the
rule choice concerns behavior about whose value there is ideological dis-
agreement, then the legal stakes are also ideological stakes. I call these
stakes the "intrinsic" interest in the rules.
Second, the rules of law affect behavior in ways that in turn indirectly
affect the distribution of the good things of life other than compliance or
noncompliance with the rule in question, good things oí life whose distri-
bution is a matter of ideological dispute. The intelligentsias view rules
about, say, the regulation of truck weight on interstate highways as im-
portant because of their impact on the relations among different industries,
consumers, and taxpayers. We care about these rules less as "norms of
conduct" than as "rules of the game" of economic or gender or racial or
regional conflict. The rules affect outcomes that ideological intelligentsias
care about by changing the balance of power between groups, their ability
to get more or less for themselves in their relations of conflict and coop-
eration in the production of everything from steel to domestic life. I call
this set of concerns the "instrumental" interest in the rules»
These two ways of looking at rules are not mutually exclusive. One can
analyze the law of strikes from the point of view of the morality or im-
morality of striking or from the point of view of the effect of legalizing
strikes on the distribution of surplus between labor and capital. lt has been
common to classify rules according to whether they "are" afone or another
kindso that some crimes are malum in se, others malum prohibitum,
some rules are based on natural rights, others on what Blackstone called
"the convenience of civil society" and what today might be called "policy,"
some rules aim at compliance for its own sake (criminal and injunctive
sanctions), others merely attach legally defined prices to conduct (dam-
ages). I am proposing not a classification of rules but a classification of
ideological motives for interest in particular rules.
Sometimes it is clear that the actual motive of the rule maker was of
one type and not the other. Members oí parliament required the eating of
fish on Friday to promote the fishing industry, and indirectly Britain's
military sea power, rather than because they believed that it was intrin-
sically wrong to eat meat on that particular day. In the extreme case of
rules oía game, the definition of the rules has absolutely no intrinsic moral
or rights or utility significance: the height of the hoop in basketball,
whether a pawn can take diagonally. At the other extreme, we wouldn't
Ideological Conflict over the Definition of Legal Rukr 59
endorse the permission of murder even if it were shown that the murder
rate wouldn't change and that there would be a large, desirable increase
in the equality of the distribution of wealth.
This distinction between motives does not correspond to that between
utilitarianism and rights or morality as normative criteria. One can care
about a rule seen as a norm of conduct because one judges it bad according
to utilitarian ethics, and one can disapprove of the distributive conse-
quences of a rule seen as a "rule of the game" because, say, it leads to
homelessness, which violates people's right to shelter or is otherwise im-
moral social policy.2
When we look at legal rules intrinsically, it is natural to ask questions
about compliance and to see norms that achieve high levels as "more suc-
cessfùl" than ones that don't. When we look at legal rules as rules of the
game or instrumentally, we ask about how this definition of the rule, as
opposed to some variant, would affect the distribution of good things not
just between victim and violator, but among all the people who will be
affected overall by the change in behavior. We ask questions like, how will
deregulation affect airline prices and levels of service? The issue of com-
pliance comes up not ro measure the success of the rule but as part of the
calculus of effects. A littering prohibition that significantly reduces lit-
teringeven if it is obvious that people continue to litter all the time and
that an individual litterer doesn't see the legal prohibition as likely to ever
be applied to himcan be a big success.
ligentsias sometimes care about who wins a lawsuit because the lawsuit
itself, the final judgment, will dispose significant stakes. For example, a
single lawsuit that stops the construction ola nuclear power plant may be
important ideologically, even if the basis for stopping construction is so
idiosyncratic to the facts of the particular case that it is unlikely that any
rule laid down in the case will be important in any future environmental
conflict.
But I deal here with ideological interest in the way rules affect the
interests of groups. Who wins a particular lawsuit may be insignificant
from this point of view, even ¡f the parties are unquestionably members
of the groups in question, and even if the suit disposes important stakes
as between the parties. The lawsuit is of interest for my analysis only if it
is important beyond the interests of the parties, because in the course of
it a judge makes a decision defining a rule in a way that predictably affects
ideologized group conflict for the future.
It is often roughly accurate to distinguish between a rule and its appli-
cation, meaning by "application" the decision whether the factual predi-
cates in the rule that trigger the rule's sanction actually occurred. Did the
defendant strike the plaintiff, or was the defendant somewhere else at the
time? Where application means fact finding in this straightforward way,
application will have ideological significance only where the intelligentsias
anticipate that fact finding is a matter of choice, in the sense of being open
to ideological "bias." This is especially likely in cases with "mixed ques-
tions of law and fact" (was the defendant negligent?). Juries in rape trials
may tend over a large number of cases to reason along highly predictable
ideological lines in deciding whether there was "force" or "consent."
This book doesn't deal with the disposition of ideological stakes through
the application of valid, open textured standards of this kind. It is about
the ideologically motivated choice among standards, or the ideologically
motivated choice to modify an open textured standard like "consent" in
order to change outcomes in an ideologized group conflict, by presuming
force unless there has been an affirmative indication of consent, for ex-
ample. In other words, it is about adjudication of questions of law, under
the final authority of appellate courts.
When there are a number of possible legal rules that a court might
adopt to resolve an uncertainty in the law revealed in a particular case,
more than one of these may result in the particular defendant losing. From
the defendant's point of view, it makes no difference which of these turns
out to be valid law for the future. But from the point of view of the
62 IDEOLOGICAl. STAKES IN ADJUDICATION
I am worried that the reader may think that this approach to the ideolog-
ical stakes of law depends on a controversial definition of "law." I don't
think this is so. I would like my theory of ideology in adjudication, pre-
sented in Part Three, to be intensely controversial but effective in part
because constructed of commonplace plausible elements. To this end, let
me reiterate my definition of "validity." What I mean by a "legal rule" is
a rule that is "valid" in the very limited sense of being agreed by just about
everyone to be in force, meaning in force in the very limited sense of
expected by just about everyone to be applied by the top court in a juris-
diction when lawyers argue it to that court. I am quite sure that there are
such rules, as for example that in Massachusetts you can't vote until you
are eighteen (an easy case), and that past consideration is generally not
effective to make a promise binding (a harder case). This is just "what I
mean" by "legal rules," the delimitation of a field of study, rather than an
attempt to solve a problem of legal philosophy.
My notion is that if we restrict ourselves to rules that are pretty clearly
valid in this sense, we will have a large set with massive consequences,
and plenty to do without even considering situations in which it is not
clear what rule is validuntil, that is, we try to figure out how new rules
get validated ("made") in such situations. When we take up that question,
we will abandon prediction theories for the obvious reason that judges
don't decide what the rules are by predicting what they will decide the
rules are.!5
Normative effects
about the reality of the effects, it may be helpful to flesh out the hypothesis
of their existence in order to make it more plausible that they have been
a major factor, though only implicitly, in the discussion.
For some part of the audience, according to the common understanding,
the effects are independent of whatever is said in justification of the legal
result. They come just from reading about the outcome in the paper,
without knowing anything at all about how the court justified its decla-
ration of what the law is. A famous historical incident has been taken to
instantiate the obedience effect. In the Pullman strike of 1895, the railroad
obtained, in an atmosphere of intense polarization and potential violence,
a lower-court injunction against virtually all concerted activities the work-
men were carrying out. The workmen obeyed the injunction, without the
slightest knowledge of its (technically highly questionable) basis in legal
reasoning, and, to the astonishment and delight of conservative opinion,
simply "went home."
The conversion effect of validity is taken to operate, for part of the
audience, in the same "blind" waythat is, people come to believe in the
moral or political or social rightness of a norm just because it has been
promulgated as law, without regard to the reasons offered. But conversion
effects are less "all or nothing" than obedience effects. You either obey or
you don't, but you can disobey and still undergo the conversion effect. It
may still "work," even though the person in question is clear in his or her
mind that the new rule is wrong, by weakening that belief. The effect may
weaken belief simply by showing that what seemed obvious is in fact
controversial (the Supreme Court disagrees with me), or by making belief
more fragile (if the Supreme Court disagrees, maybe I'm wrong), or by
opening the way to a future change (flow I see what they were driving at),
and so on. Note that both obedience and conversion effects, as I've defined
them, are independent of what the judges say in explanation of their rule
choices.
dent on our hypotheses about the effects of the rule in question on conduct.
Rules affect conduct both by affecting prices for bad men working on a
prediction theory of law and by normative effects, which induce changes
in conduct by inducing blind obedience or blind normative conversion to
the rightness of the valid.
Before taking up ideological stakes in appellate adjudication as it func-
tions as a "forum" for ideological conflict, I want to contrast this more
positivist part of the theory with the "dispute-resolution" approach to the
sociology of law. It seems necessary to justify my focus on appellate ad-
judicationand I mean justify it rather than apologize for itbecause the
American tradition in the sociology of law has made it a point of pride to
downplay its significance in favor of what trial courts, juries, lawyers, and
private parties do as legal actors.17
least in common law countries (more on this later), affect ideologized group
conflict by producing rules that govern the conduct of people u'ho do not
engage in disputes.
In other words, these institutions perform a function" quite different
from the one allocated them by sociological theory, the function of pro-
ducing formal law, mainly through the appellate process. Judge-made for-
mal law is interesting for the same reason that law produced in legislatures
or administrative agencies or referendums is interesting. Formal law, it
seems reasonable ro assume, affects ideologized group conflict through the
mechanisms I have described: it disposes of ideological stakes, both in-
trinsic stakes in the content of norms and instrumental stakes in the dis-
tributive effects of rules. But it is interesting for another reason as well:
exactly because it differs from legislation in the particular that judges
operate under a duty of fidelity to the materials and make law in bad faith
(the hypothesis of alienated powers).
The U.S. Supreme Court's decision in Brown y. Board of Education is
of interest to a distributivist first of all because it was an attempt to use
the federal government to abolish school segregation. Of course, there was
a dispute in the case that was "resolved" in some sense. But it is more
important that the rule-making activity of a so-called dispute-resolution
institution that denies its own political role generated a whole generation's
worth of disputes (they still continue) about compliance with the rule
change and about what desegregation means. lt is still more important
that out of this series of disputes there emerged new norms of conduct
with respect to "discrimination" and a dramatic series of indirect effects
on the distribution of the good things of life between and within racial
groups.
Second, dispute-resolution institutions are important because they have
part of the responsibility for enforcing formal lawthat is, for making
sure that the prices law attaches to choices in order to influence the pre-
dictions of bad men and thereby influence their conduct will actually have
to be paid. The "lower" levels of the system do the actual enforcing, so
that the distributive approach suggests an interest in the way they translate
formal law into law in action, at the trial-court level and especially at the
level of "bargaining in the shadow of the law," in Robert Mnookin and
Lewis Kornhauser's phrase.2' But this is interest in a specific subset of
compliance issues: those in which there are ideological stakes.
What counts, if we are interested in dispute-resolution institutions from
the distributive point of view, is not whether the institutions successfully
68 IDEOLOGICAL STAKES IN ADJUDICATION
judges, and legal academics who participate in the organized legal dis-
course that explains the rules. Judges, advocates, and academics make lib-
eral arguments for liberal rules, and their counterparts make conservative
arguments for conservative rules. Neutrals and swing voting judges try to
decide between liberal and conservative arguments. Both sides constantly
position themselves vis-à-vis the distinction between law and politics, that
is, vis-à-vis the discursive convention that their ideological positions as
developed in law are not ideological.
Ideological conflict is a long-term, continuous discursive process inde-
pendent of the disposition of the stakes in any particular conflict, and it
has "dialogical" elements. Positions evolve in response to "external" events
but also in response to "moves" by the other side. We can ask, and the
sides themselves constantly do ask, how they are doing, seen as debating
teams, at the task of persuading judges to be, say, judicial liberals and
conservatives. We can ask how liberal and conservative judges are doing
at persuading the populace at large to be liberal or conservative.
A great deal of ideological dialogue and evolution of this kind in the
United States seem to take place in the forum of adjudication, particularly
at the state appellate and federal levels, and most obviously in the United
States Supreme Court. It seems to have a massive long-term influence on
the content of formal law.-on the legal rules that judges makeand so
to be an important factor in explaining how judges dispose ideological
stakes. Through the conversion effectthe ability of judges to validate
rules not just in the sense of making them but in that of inducing a change
in normative views or sentiments about themit arguably affects culture
more intimately and more pervasively than just by setting rules of the
game.
This combination of distributive significance with (denied) ideological
discursive content certainly seems more plausible as an explanation of the
intense intelligentsia interest in appellate adjudication than either the
coin-flip hypothesis or the idea that judges decide hard cases by a method
that is objective in the sense of demonstrable or algorithmic. "Taking
ideology seriously" in this sense is nonetheless counter, as we saw in the
last chapter, to the mainstream of modern American legal theory, one of
whose major preoccupations has been to show that judges are not or should
not be ideological actors, even though they are unquestionably law makers.
The next two chapters offer a historical/political explanation of this pre-
occupation.
PART TWO
lis chapter has two goals: first, to contribute to the comparative law
enterprise of distinguishing what I will call "American critical legalism,"
an odd combination of utter faith and utter distrust in law, from Western
European attitudes; second, to explain the difference by identifying the
"viral" strain of ideology-critique in American legal thought, the strain
whose relation to the "body" of thought is the theme of this whole book.
In Europe, until recently, the stakes in general ideological conflict have
been higher than in the United States. Liberals (social democrats) and
conservatives have defended the center against a communist left and a
fascist or authoritarian right that have actually held and have continuously
threatened to take power. In the United States, neither communist nor
fascist positions have been more than marginal to debate. On the other
hand, in the United States, the stakes of judicial law making have been
much higher than in Europe, because both in private and in constitutional
law the courts have played a major role in general political life. Both
liberals and conservatives have pursued major law-making projects
through the courts. A good part of the total corpus of law has no direct
legislative basis, and a good part of this law bears the unmistakable marks
of the liberal and conservative agendas.
A first consequence of this American context of centrist politics with
judicial importance is that disputes about the rule of law have been some-
what different in the two political cultures. Far more in Europe than in
the United States, the rule of law has been an important element in the
debate between the liberal/conservative center and the communist and
fascist extremes. The center has affirmed the rule of law as the heart of its
program, along with human rights and representative democracy based on
free elections. It has developed the legislation/adjudication dichotomy,
73
74 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
and Mitchel Lasser.6 For my purposes, it is enough to point out that neither
rule by judiciary nor critique is any more popular in England, the Great
Cybele of the common law, than it is in France or Germany. Perhaps we
can attribute the English positivist notion of the law "running out" to the
vagaries of common law, but beyond that English legal culture seems
neither judge-centric nor critical, but merely formalist. The distinction
between the code and the common law may be the starting point for our
comparison, but it certainly can't be the sole explanation of the American
paradox.
of American legal culture as well. For this reason, it is hard for American
legal theorists to imagine that if only Chief Justice Marshall had been
more responsive to "conventional legal thought in all countries," we could
have stayed out of trouble. Indeed, the American exceptionalist response
to Hart might be that these unusual cultural factors, along with the unusual
practice of judicial review, led to breakthroughs in legal thought, as well
as into the nihilist and romantic dead ends he identifies)°
To help explain the American case, we can add to common (as opposed
to civil) law the American experience of federalism. Until the rise of the
European Community, with its complex program of legal harmonization,
only a handful of European comparativists (for example, Rodolfo Sacco')
had worried about the existence oí conflicting judge-made rules derived
in different jurisdictions from identical code provisions. But every Ameri-
can state supreme court will at least cast a glance at solutions from beyond
its boundaries, and legal academics who want to write about any private
law subject have to be comparativists at least to the extent of "counting
the authorities."
A second consequence of federalism was that the federal courts had to
decide what role to play when called on to arbitrate state/federal conflicts.
lt is important to see how shallow Hart's view was: even if the U.S. Su-
preme Court had declined to strike down federal statutes as violative of
the federal constitution, it would have had to decide what to do about its
explicit jurisdiction to decide cases in which a state was a party, and about
conflicts between state and federal law. This kind of public law jurisdic-
tion, like that of the European Court today, involves questions that are
politically charged without there being any question of judges being asked
to apply "higher" law against legislative preference.
The sense that conflict and choice are pervasive and inescapable also
owes a lot to the historical circumstance that American jurisdictions im-
ported their law from England in the first part of the nineteenth century,
in an ideological context that emphasized the broadly "liberal" character
of American society, by way of contrast with the relatively "feudal" and
"technical" British regime. The experience of reception has been kept alive
through the present by the creation of new states, with local judiciaries
and no common law, as Europeans settled westward.
Another factor distinguishing the United States from Western Europe
(Hart's "all countries") is that beginning early in the nineteenth century
the legal profession, including the judiciary, was far more socially and
politically heterogeneous than in the Old World. When Alexis de Tocque-
The Paradox of American Critical Legalism 79
well as its detractors. In the liberal view, Brown y. Board was right not
because the judges had no choice but to legislate, so that whatever they
decided would be inescapably political in the sense of "raw legislative
preference," but because it was the legally correct outcome. We remain
participants in a familiar morality play in which the question is whether
the judges' personal ideology or "partisan politics" will overcome their
oaths to interpret the law rather than overthrow it.
What is most striking about American legal culture is not that court
decisions in politically charged cases produce these passionate arguments
about what the law "really" requires. It is that the context of controversy
has also produced, and here Hart was basically right, a particular, nation-
ally specific form of internal academic critique of legal reasoning. Whether
liberal or conservative, defenders of particular courses of decision against
the charge of judicial legislation have had to respond not just by explaining
that the decision was legally correct within the discourse of legality, but
also by explaining how adjudication in the abstract, or in the particular
case, can be different from legislation, even though it is interpretation
rather than mere application of legal norms.
At the turn of the century, the United States experienced a long period
of conservative judicial and liberal legislative control, one that looked as
though it might go on forever. Most liberals simply continued arguing
that each specific conservative judicial decision was judicial legislation
because there was a right legal answer that the court disregarded in favor
of its own subjective ideological preference. But some liberals "couldn't
take it anymore" and began to argue that the problem was that there were
no correct legal answers to these questions. This was the moment of the
American mutation, the "birth of the virus."
These liberals combined the positions of the German and French "free-
law" theorists with the English positivist position that judicial legislation
is inevitable when the law "runs out." It was particularly likely to run out
in the politically controversial cases that judges were then deciding in
what looked like blatantly conservative fashion. Whatever they said they
were doing, according to this new breed of critic, judges in these cases
made choices. Indeed, the general belief that there were correct answers
misled the judges themselves, forcing their biases to express themselves
"unconsciously."
82 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
CIs has had the project of resurrecting the critical strands in preWorid
War I legal progressive thought and in legal realism, so that we could
claim a tradition for our own highly controversial positions in domestic
legal academic debate, while at the same time finding a place in the larger
development. It is not my goal here to make this past "live again" in its
irreducible historical particularity, but I do want to clarify the present
situation by identifying a genealogy for particular elements in the modern
synthesis. I claim only that writers like Holmes, Wesley Hohfeld, Henry
Terry, Arthur Corbin, Walter Wheeler Cook, Felix Cohen, Robert Hale,
and Llewellyn invented the basic techniques and ground-level propositions
of today's practice.
Their attitudes toward these inventions, the way they fit them into their
more general legal and political and cultural postures, were various. None
of them seems at all similar, overall, to us, who claim to be their descen-
dants. In particular, none of them seems to have what we would now call
a critical project, as opposed to a critical practice. They often invented
critical techniques as part of ground-clearing operations for their "recon-
structive" efforts, their own ideas about how judges could escape the di-
lemma of being politically central without a respectably rational judicial
method. To this day, their posterity includes the scholar who develops an
elaborate critique of earlier attempts to rationalize a field, and then offers
his or her own alternative. The alternative sinks like a stone, but the cri-
tique not only effectively does in its object but survives as a model for
future destructive operations.'t
There are two parts to the realist heritage: the critique of the coherence
of the private law regime of contracts, property, and torts, and the critique
of the assumed ideological neutrality of judicial decision making in hard
cases. The critique of the coherence of private law doctrine was the outcome
The Paradox of American Critical Legalism 83
of the attempt to rationalize the common law, after the demise of the writ
system and in the light of the most sophisticated European thinking. It
had two strands, which we might call "nihilist" and "contradictionist."
The nihilist was best summed up by Terry, the most brilliant late-nine-
teenth-century tort theorist, who spent his life trying to figure out the
coherence of this new legal field. His last work on the subject was pub-
lished in 1903, and it provided a motto for all that followed (not to speak
of a prefiguration of Henry Hart's famous recession from his third Holmes
lecture):
There is no general rule for determining what legal duties exist, what
acts are commanded or forbidden by law. Much labor and ingenuity have
been expended in the attempt to find some general criterion of legal
right and wrong, some general basis of legal liability. But in vain; there
is none. Various acts are commanded or forbidden for various reasons,
generally on grounds of expediency; and they are different in different
places and periods. In this respect, the law presents irsell as having a
purely arbitrary or positive character, and the duties that exist in any
particular system of law must simply be separately learned.
But the absence of a "general rule" was not the end of the story. The
contradictionist side of the critique of doctrinal coherence started with the
proposition, implicit in nihilism as I just defined it, that the European
theorists of the codes were wrong and their critics were right. Neither
European nor American public or private law could be described as indi-
vidualist (or classically Liberal) in fact. Stronger yet, individualism as ap-
plied to law could not generate a coherent legal regime. The next move
seems never to have taken place in Europe, though this impression may
be wrong, and the move may in fact have been made but crushed by
resurgent orthodoxy and the political fears I described above.
This move was to assert that there was no way to resolve particular gaps,
conflicts, and ambiguities in the existing regime without resorting to "pol-
icy," that is, to a choice, in the particular context, between the conflicting
ideals of individualism and "interdependence" (or "collectivism," or "al-
truism") or, within individualism, between the ideal of private autonomy
and the ideal of state protection against fraud and coercion. As I will argue
at length in Chapter 7, "policy" turns out to be the vehicle for consciously
or unconsciously transposed versions of the general ideological debate be-
tween, for example, liberalism and conservatism. The much milder posi-
tion of the first generation of progressives was that the choice between
policies was "legislative."
84 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
So Terry was wrong when he asserted that "the law presents itself as
having a purely arbitrary or positive character, and the duties that exist in
any particular system of law must simply be separately learned." One
doesn't have to learn the rules separately, because in the contradictionist
view they are highly organized rather than purely arbitrary. It is just that
they have a dualist rather than a monistic logic. Here is a canonical ex-
ample:
The ethical problems involved in the law of contracts result as I see them
from four elementary ideas:
(z) The Tort Idea, i.e. that one ought to pay for injuries he does to
another. As applied to promises this means that one ought to pay for
losses which others suffer in reliance on his promises.
The Bargain Idea, i.e. that one who gets anything of value by
promising to pay an agreed price for it ought to pay the seller the price
he agreed.
The Promissory Idea, i.e. that promises are binding in their own
nature and ought to be kept in all cases.
The Quasi-Contractual Idea, i.e. that one who receives anything of
value from another ought to pay for it unless it came to him as a voluntary
gift.
These ideas, which at first seem trite and wholly harmonious, are in
fact profoundly in conflict. The first and fourth proceed from the premise
that justice is to be known after the event, and that it is the business of
the court to correct whatever consequences of voluntary intercourse be-
tween men may be found to have turned out unjustly. The second and
third proceed from the premise that justice is to be known before the
event in transactions voluntarily entered into, and that it is the parties'
business to settle the justice and injustice of the voluntary transactions
at the start. The conflict between these two standpoints is perennial; it
can be traced throughout the history of the law of contracts and noted
in nearly every debatable contract question; there is no reason to think
that it can ever be gotten rid of or to suppose that the present compro-
mises of the issue will be any more permanent than the other compro-
mises that have gone before.'6
the rule interpretation was required by the materials, or was the inter-
pretation that fit them best, or whatever.
But it is obvious that the choice between the two rules had a sig-
nificant effect on the outcome of an ideologized group conflict.
The only rational basis for making a decision seems to be to consider
and evaluate those effects on ideologized group conflict, and to choose
between the arguments of the two ideological camps present. The de-
cision is "inevitably" a question of "policy."
Because the choice is inadequately explained by the opinion, and
because the rational consideration of its effects inevitably involves "pol-
icy," and because policy issues are open to ideological controversy, it is
plausible that what the judge did in the case was to legislate his or her
ideological agenda (flot to be confused with agendas that are "personal"
in the sense of ice cream tastes or love of blue-shirted litigants).
My view is that there is an actual, dramatic historical moment when
this critical strategy was first formulated. lt occurred in 1894, when Oliver
Wendell Holmes published his article, "Privilege, Malice, and Intent."7
In discussing recent English and American labor and common law anti-
trust cases, he wrote this sentence: "The ground of decision really comes
down to a proposition of policy of rather a delicate nature concerning the
merit of the particular benefit to themselves intended by the defendant,
and suggests a doubt whether judges with different economic sympathies
might not decide such a case differently when brought face to face with
the issue."8 The rest is history.
Part a of this type of critique appeals to "universal" standards of con-
sistency that are supposed to be convincing to anyone and everyone, re-
gardless of context and commitment. It is an internal textual critique of
the particular opinion, exposing the chain of reasoning as internally flawed
in a way that nullifies its very particular claim of necessity. There is no
claim to have identified a "smoking gun" in the text that reveals the judge's
"bias." Indeed, the technique works best on opinions that present them-
selves as utterly outside ideological discourse.
For example, Holmes critiqued opinions that relied on the legal maxim
sic utere tuo ut alienum non ladas (use your property in such a way as not to
injure the property of others) as question begging.'9 The question to be
decided was which of two parties would be allowed to injure the other
without compensation. Hohfeld criticized a specific set of opinions about
labor/capital conflict on the ground that they falsely assumed that one
kind of right entailed a quite different one.2°
86 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
In every field of law we. . . find peculiar concepts which are not defined
either in terms of empirical fact or in terms of ethics but which are used
to answer empirical and ethical questions alike, and thus bar the way to
intelligent investigation of social fact and social policy. Corporate entity,
property rights, fair value, and due process are such concepts. So too are title,
contract, conspiracy, malice, proximate cause, and all the rest of the magic
"solving words" of traditional jurisprudence. Legal arguments couched
in these terms are necessarily circular, since these terms are themselves
creations of law, and such arguments add precisely as much to our knowl-
edge as Molière's physician's discovery that opium puts men to sleep
because it contains a dormitive principle.2'
renders the other, under the particular legal rights with which the law
endows him, and the legal restrictions which it places on others. To hold
unequal bargaining power economically justified, merely because each
party obtains the market value of what he sells, and no more and no less,
is to beg the question.22
Hale opened up a whole field of analysis, showing that the most appar-
ently unproblematic background rules of property, contract, and tort were
"really" sophisticated regulatory interventions through which the state
conditioned the outcomes of economic conflict.23 Since, according to the
hypothesis of contradictionism, this set of rules had no "logic," could not
be derived from a coherent theory of economic individualism, the way was
opened to choosing among possible interpretations with a view to these
distributive consequences. As with Cohen, there was a weaknessthe ab-
sence of a definition of unequal bargaining power.
The third step is the assertion that the issue in the particular case (not
in every case) "is inevitably one of policy." This means that the legal ma-
terials and legal reasoning could not resolve the question, could not con-
strain the judge, in a way that would permit him or her to decide without
reference to ideologically contested arguments.
This step is given credence by step a, in which it was demonstrated, by
appeal to widely or universally shared standards of rationality, that the
opinion failed to establish any kind of legal necessity. (It used a false
argument.) But the internal critique cannot, of course, establish that it
was impossible to write an opinion in the particular case that would indeed
have generated a sense of closure or constraint on the side of the actual
outcome.
The fourth step is no more than an assertion: Given that the judge
offered no convincing legal explanation, and that a rational ground of
decision would have had to take account oí the impact oí the rule on
ideologized group conflict, doesn't it make sense to think that ideology
played a part? The meaning of ideology in this context might be vulgar
and specificpro-labor judges make pro-labor decisionsor more refined.
And the critic might charge the judge with something like having an
ideological commitment, or merely with having what I called in the last
chapter an ideological "preference," as in Holmes's "economic sympathies,"
for example.
The turn-of-the-century critics were usually trying to persuade their
audience that particular pieces of controversial, conservative, judge-made
88 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
law were judicial legislation, and that they were wrong. They tended to
favor an attitude of judicial deference toward legislative majorities and a
frank consideration of the inevitable "legislative" factors by judges doing
common law judicial rule making. But they did not, contrary to the cur-
rent pop academic view of legal realism, equate the legislative with the
political. Their analyses of particular cases showed flaws in the reasoning
process, and strongly suggested ideological along with other "subjective"
influences, but offered some form of "policy analysis" as the alternative.
There was no assertion that adjudication was irredeemably ideological.24
This was true even of such notorious "bad boys" as Jerome Frank,2' Thur-
man Arnold,26 Joseph Hutcheson,27 and Max Radin,28 all of whom were
mainly debunkers of the "myth of certainty."
This position allowed an alliance with the liberal critics who believed
that there were correctliberalanswers to the hot legal questions of the
day but that conservative judges couldn't be expected to reach them. Over
the years, some members of both groups of critics supported proposals like
abolishing judicial review, codifying large areas of law, creating adminis-
trative agencies outside judicial control, electing judges to short terms,
and radically easing the constitutional amendment process.
But whether or not such changes occurred, success of the critique of
adjudication per se was quickly understood to threaten further conse-
quences. If judge-made law, at least in these controversial cases, is necessarily
based on legislative considerations, then it is arguably invalid, because it
is the legislature that should do legislation under the rules of majority
vote and democratic accountability. If many people regarded both the lib-
eral and the conservative law that judges have made in politically impor-
tant cases as presumptively invalid in this sense, this conclusion might
change our political culture.
The American mutation, the emergence of an internal critique of ad-
judication, is therefore an obviously dangerous fact. Both liberals and con-
servatives have an interest in legal authority in general, as part of the
general liberal/conservative commitment to the rule of law. And they have
had divergent particular interests in legal authority as a support for the
specific legal agendas they have pursued through adjudication when they
controlled the judiciary.
I think it quite common to see the history of American thought about
law in the twentieth century as a protracted debate about how to deal with
the "viral" tendency of internal critique, with the positions ranging from
flat rejection to compromise to flat endorsement. In the course of the
The Paradox of American Critical Legalism 89
debate, the practice of opinion writing, its defense as legitimate law mak-
ing. and the critique itself, have gone through many transformations and
elaborations.
The course of the debate has been powerfully influenced by its situation
as a distinct part of the general debate between left and right. The critique
has been an evolving part of the general left-wing attack on particular
rules and on the power of judges in general, and in itself logically uncon-
nected to leftism.
The first point is historical: the originators and developers of the critique
have used it over and over again against particular conservative victories
in the courts and generally against rule by judiciary. They have chosen
naturally enough to tailor the evolution of the critique, its defense and
development, to their left-wing projects. Almost all the classic instances
of internal critique, of assertion of the inevitability of "policy," and of
imputation of ideology are directed by liberals or radicals against conser-
vative rules and judges.
But there is a whole left-wing legal culture that rejects the strategy
represented by the critique, embracing the maximalist position that what
is wrong with judges is that they reach the wrong legal results. According
to this position, in one case or another the Constitution and statutes and
common law gave the victory to the left, but the judges snatched it away
through spurious legal argument.29 There is also a small part of the con-
servative legal culture that embraces the critique.° I don't think this
means they have "made a mistake" about the true implications of their
general ideological positions (more on this later). For the moment I simply
assert that there is nothing intrinsically liberal or conservative about the
critique.
There is an extension that we need on the table now. The realists and
their cls successors expanded opinion-critique beyond the demonstration
that there was a logical flaw. Even a judicial opinion that contains none of
the famous errors of formalism may be supremely unconvincing as a dem-
onstration of constraint. In particular, many opinions are unconvincing
because although of impeccable internal logic they don't confront obvious
responses to their arguments.
In The Bramble Bush3' and in his famous article "Canons on Statutes,"52
Llewellyn developed this notion through what I would call a "structuralist"
formalization of the arguments and counterarguments for broadening and
narrowing precedents and statutes. He summed up his theory of precedent
in language that applies, mutatis mutandis, following the progress of the
90 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
Comments: First, the formal and the social are opposed both to fascism
and to the Leninist theory of the dictatorship of the proletariatthey share
faith in rights, majority rule, and the rule of law. The advocates of the
social are no less committed to interpretive fidelity than the advocates of
the formal (in Italy, they appeal to the general clauses of the i 948 Con-
stitution affirming human rights and the protective role of the state).
Second, each side considers the existence of the other an imperfection-
each imagines that the incoherence of modern law, its patchwork corn-
94 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
bination of formal and social elements, could and should be cured by its
triumph over the other. The aspiration is for coherence, even if our fallen
state is incoherence. André-Jean Arnaud's wondethil Les juristes face à la
société is a lament for the suppression of the social in French Legal science,
rather than a critique of the dichotomy.4°
Third, as I noted above, the judicial role is unproblematic as long as it
is possible to situate each particular question within a subcategory of doc-
trine that is coherent according to one model or the other. Fourth, with
some Italian exceptions the major players in the battle between the formal
and the social are the intelligentsias of political parties, which try to im-
pose one vision or the other through legislation (rather than through
judge-made law), and legal academics, but not judges.
There is a strong resemblance between the Continental social current
and American liberal legalism. First, they are politically aligned and can
fruitfully borrow one another's doctrinal and institutional innovations. Sec-
ond, in each case, the practitioners take law seriously, in the sense of as-
piring to win their ideological battles by being legally correct. Third, ideas
like context and facts and a diffuse confidence that social science favors
progress are shared, as in Earl Warren's famous appeal to Kenneth Clark's
study of black schoolchildren to refute the idea that separate could be
equal.
The most important difference is that the social current is both more
and less critical than American liberal legalism. The social current is in a
continuing battle not just with conservatism but with a whole conservative
way of looking at law, the self-consciously formal. The formal doesn't exist
in the United States except as a form of reaction, because legal realism
killed it off and promoted a hybrid in which policy argument is included
as a supplement to deductive reasoning in both liberal and conservative
appellate opinions.
For this reason, European leftists can see the social as antagonistic to
the formal at many more levels than the merely doctrinal, whereas Ameri-
can liberals and conservatives mix and match the identical social and for-
mal elements in their legal writing and theory (Warren and his liberal
successors resort on a regular basis to civil libertarian formalism). Liberal
legalists differ from conservatives only in their preferred outcomes and in
their diffuse supralegal "vision of the good society" based more on "com-
passion," less on "self-reliance," and so forth.
But Continentals don't do the kind of internal critique and hopeful
reconstruction of judicial opinions that is the bread and butter of American
The Paradox of American Critical Legalism 95
the judge is willy-nilly a legislator when the "law runs out." It seems
obvious to me that the answer is that, given the viral strand in American
legal thought, the admission would threaten to delegitimate "too much"
of American law"too much" in the sense of too many doctrines, given
the critique of judicial law making in every field of law. And "too much"
in the sense of too important, because judges' decisions in hard cases settle
so many ideologized group conflicts in which liberals and conservatives
have big stakes. In other words, the stakes in the debate about judicial
method, loosely between the realists and their successors and all the gen-
erations of American reconstructors, from Cardozo to Liewellyn and Fuller
through Hart and Sacks to Dworkin, derive from the stakes of liberals and
conservatives in judicial law-making power.
5
97
98 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
doesn't settle the question of law, or (b) that the valid norm covering the
case requires the judge to consider nondeductive reasons for choosing one
subrule or another.
In case a, either the law "runs out," so that we have a "case of first
impression" or a "hard case," or there is an argument for letting policy
argument trump deduction, that is, an argument for overruling a prior
case. In case b, there are a number of possibilities. (i) The rule of law is
that the rule against perpetuities shall be "remorselessly applied," unless
there are "public policy reasons" for not applying it at all to the particular
type of interest in question.4 (2) A valid rule conditions an outcome on
"the equities," whose determination requires policy argument (see, for ex-
ample, the Restatement of Torts on what the judge is to consider in de-
ciding whether or not to grant an injunction).' ()"Standards" (negligence,
good faith, probable cause) require policy argument when we apply them
to particular facts or when we choose subrules that give the standard a
much more precise meaning for a subclass of cases (violation of a statute
is negligence per se).6
Second, the content of policy argumentwhat we do when we are not
arguing by deduction from valid rulesis argument about the desirability
of a subrule, in terms of some set of social or legal institutional values.
The social values are almost always one version or another of utility, ex-
tralegal rights, or morality. The legal institutional values are more nu-
merous, but some typical examples are considerations of judicial compe-
tence (judicial activism versus judicial passivism), administrability (clear
rules versus equitable standards), and federalism (virtues of centralization
versus virtues of decentralization). In the language of the realists, the dis-
cussion is "legislative," because legislators make these types of arguments
to one another when considering whether or not to pass a statute (raising
no constitutional issues).
Third, policy argument presupposes a "force field" model of the decision
process. The elements of the force field model are:
More than one policy is likely to apply to a question of law, and the
policies are perennially (though not necessarily) in conflict. In the utili-
tarian version, we have gains and losses to different parties whose in-
terests conflict; in rights argument, rights conflict; in arguments from
morality, there are conflicting moral principles.
Rules (subrules) represent compromises of conflicting policies,
"drawing a line" that "gives" more or less to each affected interest, right
or principle.
100 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
Under the first, deductions from the holdings of cases are legally valid,
and policy is only appropriate when deduction is impossible or the valid
rule requires it. Judges can make exceptions to valid holdings or overrule
cases altogether only when holdings or cases are contradictory, so that there
has to be a mistake somewhere. Under the second, we understand the
judges to have made rules all along to arbitrate between conflicting poli-
cies, and it is therefore legitimate for them to reject a deductively required
outcome in the name of the policies that underlay the original adoption
of the rule. In this theory, policy argument can trump deduction in com-
mon law cases (although not in statutory interpretation).7
There is an implicit lawyers' ontology of legal versus policy questions
that operates in both of these theories of precedent, and indeed throughout
American legal culture. By an "implicit ontology" I mean the never-artic-
ulated presuppositions of a discourse about what exists in the world in-
dependently of observers of the world. In this case, the implicit presup-
position is that it is possible to typologize legal questions, with some being
"by their nature" susceptible both to deductive and to policy resolution,
and others being "by their nature," that is, given the state of the legal
materials, susceptible to resolution only by appeal to policy.
The application of deduction or policy should depend on the nature of
the questionon something external to the judge. When a policy question
is resolved deductively, someone must have made a mistake, because, given
the nature of the question, it just wasn't possible to come up with a
deductively correct answer. This is the sense of the phrase "ir was inevitably
a question of policy." Conversely, when a question that is open both to
deductive and to policy resolution is resolved by an appeal to policy, the
judge has sinned because he or she should accept the deductive solution,
unless he or she can propose a theory of a legitimate nondeductive role for
judges (for example, Cardozo's theory that judges should evolve the law to
meet changed social circumstances).
fore Isentence you to life in prison." Because the fact has been found, the
consequences follow.
In Kelsen's sense, the judgment articulates a new norm (you are sen-
tenced to life imprisonment). But no subrule emerges from deductive rea-
soning starting from the valid rule; it is "merely applied." The case is just
an illustration of the "logic" of the rule, rather than the occasion for an
"interpretation" of it. This mode of deductive reasoning is pervasive but
of little interest for us. Nonetheless, it is reasoning, it is deductive, and it
can be extremely complicated.
A classic example is the rule against perperuities. It is common to pro-
duce elaborate reasoning chains from the definitions of the terms in the
rule (to be valid, an interest must vest, if at all, within twenty-one years
of the expiration of a life in being at the time of the creation of the interest)
and the particular facts oían inter vivos trust (from A to B in trust for A's
children, living and as yet unborn, to be distributed to each child on
attainment of the age of twenty-five). The process of rule application that
invalidates the interests of children born after the creation of the trust
seems to me well described as deductive.
A second classic example is consideration doctrine, once reduced to a
canonical formulation (a promise is nor binding unless there is something
"bargained for and given in exchange for the promise"). My uncle promises
me in writing to give me a sum of money for a trip to Europe, "in con-
sideration of" his "esteem and affection" for me; and unbeknownst to him
I buy a suit in preparation; he reneges. I need the doctrine of promissory
estoppel because there is no consideration for his promise.
In both of these cases, we understand the process as deductive in a very
strong sense: the facts are "data" fed into a system of categories that "pro-
duce" an answer. At each step, definitions do the work. There is no need
to elaborate a subrule that settles the question of interpretation of how
this rule will apply to a class of cases in which its meaning would otherwise
be in doubt. We are close to the civil law model of rule application, in
which we don't need precedent because the application of the rule is not
an interpretationit involves no choices that are "really" open (the choice
to make a logical error is not a choice), and we don't need to preserve it
as a precedent because if we have the same case later on we are confident
we'll do exactly the same thing even if we have no memory of the first
application.
The second form of deductive reasoning is much more important and
much more obscure. Lawyers propose two different interpretations of an
Policy and Coherence 103
tion of property, while at the same time giving its thoughts on the con-
sequences of one rule or another for "incentives," "trust" between spouses,
and the extralegal "rights" of the husband and wife to the rewards of their
enterprise. The judges debate the desirability of post-decree adjustments
of the valuation of a professional degree in terms of the consequent legal
uncertainty, the virtues of equitable flexibility, and so on.'5
Analogy plays an important role in this kind of argument, in two dif-
ferent ways. Sometimes it buttresses the deductive argument by showing
that the meaning proposed for a premise is adopted in other similar cases-
for example, that there are many nontransferable interests that are treated
as property, so that there is nothing anomalous about treating professional
licenses in this way. Sometimes, the role of the analogy is to show that the
conflict between policies present in this case has been resolved in other
cases similarly to the way it is proposed to resolve it herealimony de-
crees, after all, are subject to equitable revision in spite of the problem of
uncertainty, so why shouldn't we also allow revision of awards based on
the expected value of degrees?'6
What is formalism?
But if we still use deduction all the time in legal reasoning, what is for-
malism? Beginning with Ihering's "Heaven of Legal Concepts,"7 contin-
uing with Roscoe Pound's "Mechanical Jurisprudence,"8 and culminating
with Felix Cohen's "Transcendental Nonsense,"9 the critics of late-nine-
teenth-century legal thought characterized it as formalist in two quite
distinct ways that are now commonly confused. In one usage, formalism
is a "theory of law," though one invented by its adversaries rather than by
any known American proponents. Formalism in this sense is the theory
that all questions of law can be resolved by deduction, that is, without
resort to policy, except for questions arising under rules that explicitly
require policy argument.2°
Their critique of formalism in this sense was that it was possible to
maintain the idea that policy was never necessary only by making mistakes.
They supported their position by showing in particular cases that a par-
ticular analysis, supposed to resolve a legal question deductively, failed.
They critiqued not deduction in the abstract but particular deductions, in
order to show that formalism as a general theory was wrong. In American
legal thought, their critique fit with the pragmatist emphasis on the par-
ticular, on practice, on the specificity of the "facts."2' But, of course, at
io6 TI-lE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
the lower level, say of the definition of the expectancy, they used deduction
just as often and with just as much confidence as the next man.22
In the United States, their critique was successful in a very strong sense:
until recently, I had never met an American legal theorist or practitioner
who called him- or herself a formalist, except in jest.23 Liberals and con-
servatives agree that policy is sometimes necessary. Yet formalism is anything
but a dead issue, and charges of formalism are the bread and butter of legal
theoretical and doctrinal dispute. The reason for this is that the charge of
formalism has another meaning. In this second sense, it charges an adver-
sary either with making the mistake of thinking that a particular abstract
legal norm can generate a particular subrule, or with a general tendency
to overestimate the capacity of norms in general to generate subrules by
deduction.
In this sense, it makes sense to charge justice Rehnquist or justice Scalia
with formalism in a particular case or across the board, even though each
constantly and explicitly acknowledges that sometimes they have to resort
to balancing interests, or some other form of policy argument.24 A friend
recently lamented that the briefs before the South African Constitutional
Court in the Death Penalty Case were "formalist" because they tried to
answer the constitutional question, pro or con, by reference to the words
"right to life" in the South African constitution, without reference to the
history of apartheid.
The sociological jurisprudes and realists charged late-nineteenth-cen-
tury legal thought with formalism in this second as well as in the first
sense. Their message was that there was a systematic tendency to overes-
timate the extent to which the most abstract norms of the legal order
could generate the more particular norms needed to decide particular cases.
They tried to show that the governing abstractions lacked the operative
power that formalists attributed to them. They promoted an attitude:
"distrust of abstraction." They often argued in constitutional cases that
because deduction couldn't settle the question, and it was therefore inevi-
tably a question of policy, the Supreme Court should defer to the legislative
judgment. But in private law cases they simply insisted on an overt rather
than covert consideration of the legislative question that was "really" at
issue!'
In short, formalism in the second sense is a derogatory description of
your opponent's penchant to overestimate the powers of deduction, either
in general or in a particular case. Neither in the first nor the second sense
is formalism a method distinct from deduction. It can be invalidated as a
Policy and Coherence 107
The existence ola practice of charging formalism means that there is often
disagreement in particular cases about the boundary between questions
that "by their nature" can be resolved only by appeal to policy and ques-
tions that can be resolved by deduction. But it is not just that at a given
moment some think a given legal issue can be resolved deductively while
others think such a claim formalist. Over time, it appears that a whole
legal culture can shift its general attitude about the boundaries within the
implicit ontology oí types of questions, and, of course, different cultures
can differ along this dimension.
I mentioned a moment ago that the realists taught "distrust of abstrac-
tion." By this I mean that they had a general notion that the more abstract
the concepts that went into the definition of a legal norm, the more un-
likely that it could be elaborated by deduction to produce a subrule that
would resolve a particular case. Thus "contract protects the will of the
parties" was less likely to yield a valid, rather than a merely formalist,
deduction than "the rule is expectation damages."
One way to look at the history of American legal thought is in terms
of shifts over time in the level of abstraction at which it has seemed plau-
sible that legal concepts have the "operative" power to generate deductively
valid subrules. Before the Civil War, nondeductive argument was widely
deployed to resolve questions that got resolved deductively after that war,
and were then again put into the domain of policy by the sociological
jurisprudes and realists.26
As I've indicated several times already, your ordinary American lawyer
is likely to find European solutions to classic legal problems blatantly
formalist, in the sense of overestimating the power of deduction, and to
find European legal culture in general formalist in the same sense. When
Europeans protest that none of them think, or ever did think, that deduc-
tion could solve every legal problem, the American lawyer is likely to
think they have missed the point, which has to do with an attitude toward
abstraction rather than with a theory of law in the jurisprudential sense.
Proponents oí historical and comparative study are endlessly optimistic
about its capacity to undermine vulgar prejudice. But the modern Amer-
to8 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
¡can sense that the boundary between law and policy is 'out there" rather
than a cultural artifact, and that as a matter of "fact" policy comes into
play as soon as we rise above a low level of abstraction, easily survives
historical and comparative exposure. The history of American legal
thought has been written overwhelmingly by realists and by their main-
stream successors, who have had a passionate commitment to the ideas
that there was a misguided Formalist Period and that European legal
thought in general is prerealist. The ontology oí deductive and policy
questions survives unshaken because the views of other times and places
look just wrong.
The partial revival of deduction in American judicial opinions and schol-
arship after World War II might be another source for the idea that what
is a policy question and what is a deductive question is not a question of
fact. But the neoformalists of our time are, for the most part, either civil
libertarians or conservatives. In both cases, they interpret their own prac-
tice as simply reestablishing the force of first principles. Because both
groups seem blissfully ignorant of the realist critiques that killed off earlier
versions of their arguments, they come off as simple-minded rather than
as creative reconstructors, in the eyes of the older generation of pragma-
tists.
In short, the implicit lawyers' ontology of types of questions is alive
and well. The critique of formalism (in the sense of overestimation of the
power of abstractions) has reinforced it rather than undermined it.
The notion of policy was introduced into American legal thought during
the period of "reception" of English law as one of the two factors that
judges could and should use in deciding what rules to adopt, particularly
in situations in which there was an English rule that might or might not
be appropriate. There was a conventional distinction between "liberal" and
"technical" approaches to legal questions. The liberal approach was distin-
guished by willingness to consider, as legitimate elements in the inter-
pretive process, the purposes of rules, the intent of parties, and the equity
of solutions.
Within the liberal mode, policy (convenience, utility) was at first op-
posed to morality. The legal elite thought of morality in terms of a Prot-
estant Christian ethic of total duties of altruism, sharing, and self-sacrifice.
Policy was the countervailing prudential argument for limiting legal
Policy and Coherence 109
Policy is firmly within American law, but also firmly less than 'law" or
deduction or black letter or precedent or statutory authority. It is less
because it is understood as situated between the paradigmatically legal
appeal to authority and the paradigmatically extra- or nonlegal appeal to
"politics" or ideology. It is an intermediate term, partaking of some of the
elements of the extremes. Moreover, it is a "fudge word," meaning a word
that allows us to evade a problem that would be clear if we said what we
meant with more precision.
Because policy argument is unquestionably legal, to make policy ar-
110 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
guments is not to ask the judge to violate his role constraint by usurping
the legislative function. But it is more chan a matter of legal pedigree.
Policy arguers present it as different from pure politics, or ideology, be-
cause it appeals to universal rather than particular interests.29 Consequen-
nahst argument appeals to a notion of "social welfare" or "efficiency" or
"economic growth." Morality arguments deploy familiar general maxims,
like "no man should profit from his own wrong," "do unto others," "be
reasonable," and so on. Rights arguments (as we will see in great detail in
a later chapter) presuppose the universality as well as the facticicy of
rightseveryone has a right of free speech, to dispose of property, to
protection against fraud or duress, and so on.
Because policy argument deploys the full range of "social values" that
are conventionally understood to be relevant to choices among norms, it
will allow the judge to resolve any question of rule definition that litigants
may put. Policy is therefore a "mediator" of the contradiction in the def-
inition of the judicial role that requires the judge to decide only according
co law but also requires her to decide any question over which she has
jurisdiction. This means, as we will see, that policy plays the same role in
the conventional understanding that coherence plays in modern analytical
jurisprudence.
There is nonetheless a serious problem, one that "everyone" in American
legal culture is acutely aware of. Although policy argument formally ex-
cludes ideology, it is "soft" and so operates always under the suspicion of
permitting ideology to enter sub rosa. The formal exclusion oí ideology
means simply that it is "impermissible," it would be a legal "blunder," to
phrase a policy argument n explicitly distributive, or explicitly religious,
or explicitly "partisan" terms. Everyone has an interest in social welfare,
observance of conventional morality, and the protection of rights that ev-
eryone possesses. But people are sharply divided about whether it would
be desirable to redistribute wealth, to shift social power from men to
women and from black to white, to further the growth of the Catholic
Church, and so forth.
Even if everyone knows that a particular rights argument will effect
some redistribution (say, affirmative action, or the invalidation of a rent-
control statute), it is not permissible to give redistribution as the reason
for the rule change in question. The distributive consequences must be
presented as "side effects" of rights protection, or of a move that will
increase efficiency, or of insisting on moral acts by individuals or groups.
"Grammatical" policy argument never declares itself as simply "liberal" or
Policy and Coherence i i i
brethren for a "radical" attempt to argue "policy rather than law").3' The
rhetorical goal is to associate policy with the subjective, the political, the
ideological, and to extrude it from law, leaving only authority. The coun-
terbites denounce "legalism" or "sterile" or "bloodless" or "rigid" or "me-
chanical" or "arbitrary" deductive approaches, and emphasize the "inevi-
tability" of policy, as well as its "progressive" and "pragmatic" character.
Their goal is to tame deduction, to subordinare it to policy.
The social practice of policy argument in these forms, some of them as-
serting it as indistinguishable from law and others assimilating it to purely
political or ideological argument, is basic to American legal discourse. The
rhetorical tropes involved are prior to, rather than responsive to, the ju-
risprudential debate among American legal theorists about what adjudi-
cation "is." No formulation of the nature of adjudication that denies policy
argument as a fact, or that asserts that we should get rid of it as a normative
matter, can be plausible. The goal of legal theoretical discussion, since the
realists, has been to get beyond the mushy, self-contradictory quality of
the lawyers' usage to "firmer ground."
For the most part, the realists did not critique the implicit lawyer's
ontology of legal versus policy questions. What they tried to show was
that the English notion that the judge can reason deductively in most cases
but must occasionally act legislatively grossly underestimated the serious-
ness of the problem. Many, many questions that judges had purported to
resolve deductively were in fact policy questions. The failures of deduction
occurred not at the margins of the system but throughout. Given the
significant rule-making role of the judge, it was not possible to concede
the occasional need for legislative judgment and then get on with deduc-
tion, because that would leave a great deal of law if not illegitimate at
least ungrounded.
Much in the current state of legal theory in the United States is ex-
plained by the realists' choice to attempt to reground the rules of law in
a combination of fine-grained policy analysis and larger theories of coher-
ence. We can say of this enterprise, first, that it entailed the abandonment
of the critical, or viral, strand in their own project and, second, that it was
only partially successful.
The realists' critical project was aborted because they never extended
their successes in the critique of deduction, precedent, and statutory in-
Policy and Coherence ii 3
Crudely put, the liberal dilemma is as follows: The main vehicle of liberal
reform in the United States since World War II has been the judiciary,
and the judiciary, with the exception of a brief period in the mid-i 96os,
has consistently implemented reform against, rather than in collaboration
with, state and federal legislative majorities. It is not surprising that a
project of liberal (not Liberal) legal theory is to show that this judicial
contribution to the substance of both private and public law is democrat-
ically legitimate because it furthers the rule of law, rather than merely
legislating judicially.
But, as Gary Pelter and William Eskridge have suggested, the liberal
critique of conservative legal formalism, from Holmes through legal re-
alism, extended by critical legal studies, has dramatically undermined ac-
ademic faith in the possibility of judicial neutrality in hard cases.2 Indeed,
the postWorld War II liberal project is the lineal descendant oían exactly
opposite liberal project: that of showing that the enormous contribution
of a conservative judiciary to the shape of the prewar legal system was
democratically illegitimate.
The exit from the liberal dilemma has to be a theory of adjudication
that avoids the Scylla and Charybidis of formalism, in the sense of excessive
reliance on deduction, and nihilism. There are both existential and instru-
mental political dangers on each side. Antiformalism is a core element in
liberal legal identity because it reflects within this technical discipline the
general liberal resistance to rigidity, the doctrinaire, and the authoritarian,
all identified with nineteenth-century conservative ways of thinking and
¡14 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
rime or another played "brain trust" roles in national politics. Since then,
they have been mainly law professors in public law fields and jurisprudence
professors, writing primarily in specialized legal journals, some with hopes
of becoming judges. In the recent past the field of legal theory has emerged
outside the curricular categories to provide a common identity.
It is important that the recent participants have been neither conven-
tional political players (by contrast, European political parties often run
public law professors for national office), nor "just academics," interested
in adjudication in the abstract. They influence judges and elite lawyers,
who are also members of the political class, through legal education. Some
of them aspire to influence legal development directly through service in
liberal Democratic administrations or appointment to the bench. And they
suppose that they are part of a loosely articulated general intelligentsia
capable of translating technical or theoretical insights into the culture at
large through, for example, the New York Times Book Review, the New York
Review, and the New Republic, televised Supreme Court confirmation hear-
ings, and the occasional "appearance" on National Public Radio. They
think of themselves as players, but only over the long run and indirectly,
on the basis of this combination of technical and academic prestige with
"access."33
It has been obvious to liberal legal theorists, I speculate, that as present
and potential rulers through the courts, they have an interest in the ability
of the courts to command obedience and induce changes in moral senti-
ments. Any explanation of why the Warren Court did the right thing that
accepts a strong form of the realist and postrealist critique of judicial
legislation makes the people seem like dupes of legal mumbo jumbo that
is just a mask for the imposition of the liberal ideological agenda. Such
an explanation is not a good explanation. It is not good because it dele-
gitimates this form of liberal political power for the future, while unilat-
erally abandoning the demand for judicial neutrality as a means of keeping
todays conservative judges and left-fringe activists in check.
The instrumental stakes in liberal antiformalism are less obvious than
those in resisting nihilism. They have to do with this same struggle of
liberalism with resurgent conservatism, on one side, and diffuse rights-
oriented radicalism (rather than communism) on the other. The polariza-
tion of liberal courts against conservative legislatures gradually faded in
the 1970S and 198os, as conservative presidents partially remade the fed-
eral judiciary in their own image. There hasn't been another reversal, pit-
ring liberal legislatures against conservative judges in the mode of the
THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
long period between about 1870 and 1940. Conservative judges haven't
engaged in wholesale countermajoritarian initiatives (there has been no
need). But they haven't given up their major role in the management of
public life, as exemplified by the U.S. Supreme Court's sustained attack
on affirmative action programs.
To this purpose, they continuously redeploy all the formalist (that is,
implausibly deductive) legal gambits that they once used to block liberal
social legislation. The realist heritage of critique is kept alive in dissenting
opinions that carefully reveal the internally contradictory or inconclusive
character of the majority's syllogistic reasoning, thereby making way for a
liberal policy analysis that comes out the other way (classic examples are
Justice Brennan's dissent in the DeShaney" case and Justice Blackmun's
in Lucas").
At the same time, modern conservative law and economics theorists
claim that the goal of efficiency is the sole politically legitimate basis of
judicial law making and is sufficiently determinate to indicate a correct
answer to almost any question of regulatory law. They urge the judges to
adopt that solution, almost always in some sense "freeing" the market to
the detriment of economically weaker parties, more or less regardless of
what the common law precedents or prior statutory interpretations may
say. From the liberal point of view, this approach combines nihilism about
adjudication with formalism about economics, and it invites internal cri-
tique of the efficiency criterion to make room for "justice" concerns.
While there is no Marxist opposition, there has always been radical
pressure on the liberal left flank. A part of this pressure comes from lawyers
and legal academics influenced by the history of the critique of adjudica-
tion and forever impressed by the success oían earlier generation of liberals
in getting the courts to implement their program against legislative ma-
jorities. Their strategy is to claim that the Constitution requires, at an
abstract level, a regime of rights that corresponds to the radical multicul-
tural program that developed on the left of liberalism in the wake of the
civil rights, antiwar, and women's movements.
Left lawyers and academics of this persuasion continuously develop new
legal theories designed to mobilize the courts behind programs that have
no chance of being adopted by liberal legislative groups, let alone by
legislative majorities. Unemployment is an unconstitutional taking of
workers' property. The institutionalization of the mentally ill is unconsti-
tutional per se. The courts should guarantee a minimum level of subsis-
tence for welfare recipients, guarantee a right to decent housing, forbid
Policy and Coherence xi 7
The judge's job goes far beyond deduction. Process theorists distinguish
"kinds" of policy questions, namely, those that are and those that aren't
susceptible to "reasoned elaboration" (that is, nonideological resolution
through the method of coherence). There are two symmetrical sins in this
model: to ignore policy when the judge should consider it ("The Case of
the Spoiled Cantaloupes"),40 and to apply policy analysis to questions that
should be resolved "elsewhere" (Brown y. Board of Education, for Herbert
Wechsler).4'
The notion of "institutional competence" within the overall enterprise
of pursuing socially legitimate purposes solves the problem of judicial
legislation, permitting the judge to deploy policy argument and even to
reject deductive solutions on policy grounds, in some cases, while firmly
excluding the merely personal or ideological in cases where policy would
be a Trojan horse. As I pointed out in Chapter 2, when the question is not
one appropriate for "reasoned elaboration," the plaintiff loses for a good
legal reason (the coherence of a scheme of separation oí powers), rather
than through either denial of justice or judicial legislation.
The obvious problems are how to decide which questions have which
"natures," and what to do when the image of the division of labor within
a well-functioning bureaucracy is obviously unrealistic.42 The institu-
tional-competence notion worked well in retrospective 1950S liberal anal-
yses of conservative judicial overreaching up to the New Deal. But it
proved extremely difficult for its inventors (though not for its current
revivalists)43 to reconcile it with the activist role of liberal state and federal
courts after World War II. Writers like Hart and Wechsier, who had begun
their careers as liberal opponents of judicial activism,44 found themselves
unexpectedly the intellectual allies of conservative resistance to judicially
mandated racial integration.43
need to incorporate into coherence theory some attitude toward the judicial
activism of the Warren Court, the critique of American coherence theory
by British thinkers like Hart," Raz'2 and MacCormick,' and the rebirth
of the virus in critical legal studies. What follows is a cnt, left/mpm
reading of Dworkini as a contemporary.
First, Dworkin makes substantial concessions to the historical critique
of adjudication by affirming the political nature of legal interpretation, in
his early work, this legitimate political element, sharply contrasted with
"personal" or "partisan" politics, always turned out to be belief in rights
as opposed to one form or another of utilitarianism, in other words, al-
though the judge couldn't escape having a political theory, that theory was
just the opposite of "ideology." The theory constrained him because it was
an articulation of connections between general philosophical propositions
about the political good and particular instances; the judge who saw him-
self as a rule utilitarian couldn't switch ad hoc to a rights argument if he
didn't like a particular outcome.'4
In A Matter of Principle, Dworkin began to develop his own version of
liberalism as a political theory of just this type," contrasted it with con-
servative political theory, and quite abruptly affirmed that "we should
expect to find distinctly liberal or radical or conservative opinions" about
constitutional interpretation, and that "this is exactly what we do find."6
In Law's Empire, Dworkin acknowledges the common practice of analyzing
constitutional decision making through the lens of current ideology and
admits that even his own ideal judge may be well described in these terms
(providing we have enough data about his positions).'7 In other words,
liberalism and conservatism have crossed the line from the partisan or
merely personal into the realm of "theory." The choice among theories, as
we saw, may determine the content of judicial law making but can't be
justified as noncontroversial, demonstrably correct, or objective.
To this point, it is easy to see how Dworkin can fulfill the requirement
that a liberal legal theory provide a basis for attacking both conservative
judicial law making and left activist proposals as judicial legislation. In-
deed, Dworkin appears as the heir andin his own attacks on the semantic
view of law,'8 on oniginalism,'9 and on passivism60as the developer of
the legal realist tradition. But it is hard to see how he can avoid the English
positivist view that the judge is necessarily a legislator in hard cases, and
the corollary that the liberal activism of the Warren Court was no more
legitimate than the conservative activism it succeeded.
He turns this trick by characterizing his politicized version of adjudi-
122 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
cation as still very different from legislation. First, as we have seen already,
adjudication is properly the interpretation of the relevant legal materials,
with a view to understanding what they require if we imagine them to
express the views of a single communal person. This distinguishes the
judge from the legislator who is free to ignore the solution the materials
yield if he thinks he can do better. Dworkin swims with the tide of the
198os, in which the current of legal theory converged with that of her-
meneutics»
But within his version of the interpretive turn, fidelity to the materials
is more than a description of the typical judge's attitude that will help us
to understand what he does. Fidelity requires a commitment to finding
the "right" interpretation in every case, with rightness understood like the
judge's personal political theory as possibly controversial and in any case
nondemonstrable.62 The existence of controversial, nondemonstrable right
interpretations is attested by our collective practice of looking for them
and thinking we've found them. If the judge is committed to finding, and
if there always is, a right answer, then the law will never "run out." The
judge will never be in the English positivist position of having to legislate
no matter how much he would prefer to merely interpret.6
Second, in Dworkin's theory of interpretation, the requirement that a
solution "fir" with the body of legal materials, the requirement of coher-
ence, will often settle the case without controversy, and the judge will be
obviously distinct from the legislator. But where this is not the case, and
the judge must choose between competing versions of the coherent solu-
tion, the judge can deploy his personal political theory only under two
further constraints that don't apply to the legislator. The judge must be
able to defend his preferred political theory as offering the most coherent
explanation of the materials.b5 And he is supposed to apply it to the case
in hand. Together, these three constraints make him principled rather than
result-oriented.
The legislator can make law legitimately while disregarding all these
requirements. He can choose a rule that is blatantly inconsistent with the
larger regime of which it will become a part. He can choose it to further
his particular political philosophy even though that philosophy is totally
implausible as an explanation of the legal regime as a whole. And he can
choose a particular solution in spite of its being inconsistent with the
political philosophy he would apply in other similar cases. He can vote in
favor of an anomalous "anarchist" addition to a liberal legal regime, even
Policy and Coherence 123
this domain, even in common law cases, as well as failing to honor its own
historic mission oí protecting the individual against majority abuse. Here
Dworkin owes more than he has acknowledged to Hart and Sacks.
On the basis of these three claims about adjudication, Dworkin can
defend liberal judicial law making as democratically legitimate, not ju-
dicial legislation, not even activism, although as he recognizes the defense
has to be case by case, or "at retail."
Activism is a virulent form of legal pragmatism. An activist justice would
ignore the Constitution's text, the history of its enactment, prior deci-
sions of the Supreme Court interpreting it, and the long-standing
traditions of our political culture. He would ignore all these in order to
impose on other branches of government his own view of what justice
demands. Law as integrity condemns activism, and any practice of con-
stitutional adjudication close to it . . The alternative to passivism is not
a crude activism harnessed only to a judges sense of justice, but a more
fine-grained and discriminating judgment, case by case, that gives place
to many political virtues but, unlike either activism or passivism, gives
tyranny to none.69
For each case, the question is whether the judges reached the right
interpretation of the materials, one that respected the requirement of co-
herence, was principled rather than result-oriented, and eschewed reliance
on the judge's personal views of policy. Even if you agree that the judge's
rule making was thus constrained, you may well think the case came out
wrong, especially if you don't share the judge's political theory. But you
would be naive to expect anything else and foolish to prefer the legislative
process for hard cases. What makes law worthy of respect, what makes the
obedience and conversion effects tolerable in a democracy, is that adjudi-
cation "insures that the most frmndamental issues of political morality will
finally be set out and debated as issues of principle and not political power
alone, a transformation that cannot succeed, at least not fully, within the
legislature itself."7°
student of past and present American judicial opinions, it seems too ob-
vious to merit extended argument that judges constantly evoke, for and
against a given rule choice, the whole range of effects the rule will have
on people other than the parties, and evaluate those effects in terms of the
general goals of the community. Moreover, this practice is explicitly theo-
rized by so many judges with places in the American judicial pantheon
that it seems implausible to say the least to redefine it at this late date as
treason to the Empire. I offer just one example of my own.
In a famous hard case decided in 1842, Chief Justice Lemuel Shaw of
the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court held that Farwell, a worker,
could not recover damages from his employer to compensate an injury
caused by the negligence of a "fellow servant." His opinion clearly states
the common understanding of his time as to the role of policy in legal
reasoning:
argument not exactly "trivial," but rather useless for the purpose of de-
fending liberal judicial reform efforts without falling into either formalism
or nihilism.
Of course, Dworkin has had other agendas, indeed many other agendas
than that of responding to the dilemma of Warren-Court and Vietnam-
era American liberal legalism. Though he might not find the comparison
flattering, his early work resembles in many ways the project of Sir William
Blackstone, whose Commentaries undertook the "Herculean" task of show-
¡ng that the English common law of the late eighteenth century was best
understood as the working out into the details of legality of the rights of
Englishmen established in the Glorious Revolution.76 There is an echo of
this still unfulfilled program in Dworkin's gracious response to his mentor
Henry Hart's critique of the Noble Dream: "I hope to persuade lawyers to
lay the entire [positivist] picture of existing law aside in favour of a theory
of law that takes questions about kgal rights as special questions about
political rights, so that one may think a plaintiff has a certain legal right
without supposing that any rule or principle that already 'exists' provides
that right."77
As with Sir William, the larger Liberal project of reconciling rights,
majority rule, and the rule of law takes place in a much more specific
political context, for Dworkin the context of liberal/conservative ideolog-
ical conflict.
After explaining why Brown y. Board gave the "right" answer to the ques-
tion of de jure segregation, but should have demanded far more than "all
deliberate speed," and why racial quotas are constitutional, Dworkin asks
whether Hercules, his ideal judge, is "too conservative" or "too liberal."
He does not answer that Hercules is no more liberal or conservative than
he is activist or passivist. He says instead: "You cannot yet say, because
your judgment would depend on how closely your convictions matched
his across the wide spectrum of different kinds of convictions an interpre-
tation of constitutional practice engages."78
This answer makes me laugh. Over the course of his career, Dworkin
has endorsed as the legally "right answer" not just Brown without delay
and racial quotas, but civil disobedience,79 nonprosecution of draft card
burners,80 the explicit consideration of distributive consequences rather
than reliance on efficiency,8' judicial review of apportionment decisions,82
128 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
would not have joined the Lochner majority, for example, because he
would have rejected the principle of liberty the Supreme Court cited in
that case as plainly inconsistent with American practice and anyway
wrong and would have refused to reexamine the New York legislature's
judgment on the issues of policy that then remained.90
conservative whose goal has been to put a stop to the "eroding" or viral
progress of the critical project.
Stopping the virus doesn't mean rolling the clock back to I9oo; indeed,
it is hard to see how that could possibly work. Dworkin dispenses with
some of the dualities that initially both explained and justified the insti-
tution of professionally accountable courts specialized in adjudication.
Judges make as well as apply law; their law making is political; they arent
validated by objectivity. The tools of reconstruction are the interpretive
right answer, the notion of principle, and the distinction between rights
and policies. Through them, Dworkin reconstitutes the initial distinctions
in a modest mode: not law application but rightness in interpretation; nor
objectivity but principle; not law versus politics, but rights versus policies.
It is emblematic of American critical legalism that liberal legal theorists
attacked each of these attempts at regrounding, trying and to my mind
succeeding in showing that none could survive internal critique.93 It is
equally emblematic that they did this, one after another, in pursuance of
their own versions of the identical project of reconstruction. Some, for
example, take us back to the moderate English version in which legal
formalism radically restricts the nonetheless ineradicable moments of ju-
dicial legislation; others promise a return to objectivity, albeit in some
compromised form; maybe moral reasoning will turn out to have all the
qualities legal reasoning has lost; there are pragmatist options that fudge
even Dworkin's remaining distinctions.
My goal is to get out of this trap, to see what happens when one takes
not rights, and not critique, but their interaction seriously. It is quite
wrong to see Dworkin and cls, in the mode of pop jurisprudence, as "ap-
posites'he thinks there is always a right answer, we think there is never
onesince Dworkin takes critique much more seriously than his own
critics, and crits love determinacy, in its place, as much as the next person.
It is nonetheless a relief to say good-bye, for the time being, to all the
reconstructive projects, all so obviously based, at least to my jaundiced
eye, on making knowledge with a view to power, and power to serve the
holders of that very knowledge.
Some disclaimers. By saying that the liberal legal project has been to
defend the legality of the liberal judicial law making of the last fifty years,
while remaining true to the liberal critique of judicial legislation, I do not
mean to impute bad faith except of the existential type I want to impute
to judges as well. Contrast Dworkin's suggestion that some crits "may
want . . to move toward a new mystification in service of undisclosed
130 THE PROBLEM OF JUDICIAL LEGISLATION
political goals. " Nor am I arguing that the "pure" jurisprudential interest
in figuring out the "truth' about adjudication has been irrelevant. Far from
it. To say, for example, that Dworkin's theoretical work is incomprehen-
sible without the context of his personal political commitment to the
reforms of the Warren Court is not to say that he is dishonest, or not
"really" a scholar, or that his conclusions are "suspect" in a way that those
of more "disinterested" theorists are not.
Nonetheless, the liberal project inflects and also distorts the jurispru-
dential inquiry by influencing the choice of hypotheses, the choice between
equally plausible interpretations, and, above all, the investment of time
and energy in particular problems. In this case, time spent defending right-
ness, principle, and rights is time not spent on the left/mpm project of
unsettling those very ideas.
How does law making by adjudication in an ideologically divided so-
ciety alter the outcomes from those that would occur under a more trans-
parent process? Suppose that one or another theorist actually managed to
successfully answer the question of how a judge can be neutral. It would
still remain to be seen whether our actual judges try to be neutral in this
way, whether they succeed, and how their adoption of the stance inflects
rule making vis-à-vis the outcomes of, say, legislative supremacy.
The liberal legalist investment in Reason sometimes pays off in knowl-
edge that is useful beyond the project, that has as much "truth value" for
conservatives or radicals as for its liberal inventors. But the knowledge the
liberal legalist project produces is not much help with these questions.
We might define the project as a particular strategy for shoring up right-
ness, principle, and rights so that it will be unnecessary to answer them.
In short, the critique of ideologically oriented strategic behavior in judging
that I develop in the next three chapters applies to jurisprudence as well.
I propose to put my left/mpm questions, which are peripheral as long
as we are mainly concerned to defend the possibility of neutrality, in the
center of inquiry, by asking not how judges can be neutral but how they
can be ideological.
PART THREE
Ideology in Adjudication
6
The goal of this chapter is to flesh out the intuition that policy is a
potential Trojan horse for ideology. I begin by developing a simple model
of legal discourse in general, a model based on a sharp distinction between
legal norms and the reasons for adopting them. The model is designed not
to "explain" legal discourse but to provide a descriptive vocabulary in
which to argue three points.
First, legal discourse overlaps with, or interpenetrates, ideological dis-
course in a way that makes it hard to distinguish an ideological argument
from a "neutral" or "objective" or "impersonal" legal argument. Second,
over time the pursuit of ideological projects through law has "sedimented"
or structured legal discourse in such a way that it "guides" decision makers
into framing problems of rule choice in terms of familiar liberal and con-
servative ideological alternatives. Third, even a judge or lawyer with no
ideological project of her own will find that she is willy-nilly an ideological
performer, because she has to write her opinions in legal prose. The lin-
guistic units available in legal prose are loaded with ideological meanings.
The methodology through which I explore these asserted phenomena is
quite different from that of the last chapter, which purported simply to
state explicitly the presuppositions of "standard" American legal discourse
or of legal culture. While this chapter resembles the last in relying on no
more than "common knowledge" for data, it is "structuralist" in a much
more technical sense. It draws on Ferdinand de Saussure,' Claude Lévi-
Strauss,2 and Jean Piaget3 (though in the cannibalizing or "bricolage" mode
rather than in that of "application" of their theories) to represent the judge
as both liberated and constrained because her job requires her to speak, to
argue in, a particular language. Legal discourse is distinctive not just be-
cause it is "about law," but also because it is a "langue," or language, in
'33
134 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
i. Subject-matter structures
We organize the rules by subject matter. Some subject-matter dis-
tinctions are contracts, torts, procedure, the separation of powers,
federalism, evidence.
Within a subject matter, we can speak of the structure of a legal
field, the pattern of cases, statutes, and rules in a given area, distin-
guishing, for example, between fields that are well worked out, full
of "settled law," and fields that are chaotic or embryonic.
2. Horizontal structures
The rule-exception structure. If you took all the rules, you could
make thousands of subsystems by arranging them into rule-excep-
tion pairs. The logical status of rule and exception is complicated
and controversial, but that we tend to organize rules this way is
obvious. The "privilege of necessity" seems like an exception to the
doctrine of trespass.
The rule-counterrule structure. This differs from the rule-exception
structure because there is no defined hierarchy between the two
elements. The First Amendment, where it intersects the doctrine of
trespass in shopping-center speech or picketing cases, is a counter-
rule rather than an exception.
3. Vertical structures
The rule-instance structure. The point here is that the particular is
understood to follow from the general by deduction. If trespass to
land is voluntary physical invasion of real property, we are likely to
see "going hunting in your neighbor's woods" as just "what we
mean" by physical invasion.
The rule-specification structure. This is different because the par-
ticular is much more loosely derived from the general than in the
Policy and Ideology '37
other case. Specifications are further rules that fill in gaps, conflicts,
or ambiguities that may or may not be apparent on the face of the
more general rule. Is your invasion of your neighbor's land invol-
untary if you were ordered onto it at gun point, or only if you were
carried onto it? The issue has been decided by adding a subrule to
the doctrine of trespass through policy argument.
4. The rule-standard structure. This is a typology of rules distinguish-
ing them according to the extent they use, as triggers for official
conduct and definitions of that conduct, relatively particularized,
"objective" indicia like, say, age (in determining legal capacity) or
vaguer concepts like, say, "maturity" (for the same purpose).'
Although I think it's useful to distinguish the two structures (rules and
reasons for rules), the distinction is not a tight one, as the following cases
show. First, some standards and some rights are units in the system of
valid legal norms, of doctrine, and yet do provide their own justifications.
Second, sometimes we justify the choice of a rule neither by a policy
argument nor by deduction from a more abstract rule but by reference to
another rule, a rule of interpretation.
There are standards that appeal directly to one of the moral desiderata
of our culture, such as "good faith," "reasonableness," "unconscionability,"
"unfair trade practice." (Other standards refer to general descriptive cate-
gories understood to have little meaning until further specified, such as
"foreseeabiliry" or "restraint of trade." Unlike the first mentioned, these
provide no reasons for their adoption and get explained and interpreted
through policy discourse.)
Abstract but clearly legalized rights also violate my distinction between
rules and reasons for rules. For example, the constitution prohibits Con-
gress from "making any law abridging the freedom of speech," and refers
to the "right of the people to be secure in their houses, papers and effects."
Statutes and opinions may also declare rights (the right of privacy has been
declared as a matter of constitutional penumbra, as a statutory require-
ment, and as a common law rule).
There are two different ways in which rights can operate both in the
structure of rules and in that of reasons for rules. First, rights authorita-
tively declared at a high level of abstraction are self-justifping elements in
the rule structure, when we treat them as positivized natural rights, even
though it is not uncommon to offer nonrights-based reasons for them
("free speech helps the search for truth"). Second, it is standard practice to
invoke valid legal norms like the First Amendment as nondeductive policy
reasons for deciding cases, as in phrases like "First Amendment concerns
weigh heavily here" (as opposed to "the First Amendment requires . .
There are rules for the interpretation of rules, such as those of statutory
interpretation and those for the determination of the holdings of cases.
These are both rules and reasons for rules, and they constitute a "subdis-
140 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
course of authority." They are the first resort when there appears to be a
gap, conflict, or ambiguity. Like the other rules in the system, they may
generate an instant sense of legal obviousness that can be unsettled only
by sustained legal work. Thus they can function to eliminate the need to
resort to policy, or just defer it.
When we choose among them and interpret them in order to make
them applicable to specific questions about "primary" rules, we justify our
decisions through policy arguments ("it would cause hopeless confusion to
apply the maxim exciusio unius in this case"). This second-order policy
argument about how to apply rules of interpretation is like the first-order
policy argument about what rule to adopt. The units are internally struc-
tured, like both primary rules and policy argument-bites. For eirnple, in
the famous pieces already mentioned," Llewellyn analyzed the maxims
used in statutory interpretation, and in justifying the choices of "broad"
and "narrow" holdings for particular cases, into a set of rules and counter-
rules, which might just as easily be described as arguments and counter-
arguments.
So far, we have a static typology. But the rule structure is dynamic because
it contains rules for the generation of new rules, or operations.'2 And the
argument structure is a semiotic system, in the sense of a system of signs,
a system that people operate to generate new meanings out of a prestruc-
tured collection of elements.'3
The two operations that we perform on the rule structure are "constituting
the field" and "broadening and narrowing." Constituting the field means
deciding on a particular rule-exception or rule-counterrule structure as the
one within which to decide the case in hand. When striking bus drivers
lie down in front of the buses, we constitute the field when we decide that
the question" is whether their conduct fl1s on one side or another of a
line dividing "unjustified interference with the owner's property" from
"legitimate exercise of free-speech rights."
For a given controversy, there will typically be numerous different ways
to constitute the field. The First Amendment is one way to counteract the
Policy and Ideology I 4'
owner's property right, but another way would be to argue that what the
workers were doing was a public nuisance, so that there could be no private
action without "special" damage, which the owner failed to show here. Yet
another would be to argue that the workers were merely exercising self-
activity rights guaranteed by the National Labor Relations Act (NLRA).
My point is not that all these approaches are equally likely to generate
the experience of closure in favor of the plaintiffs or defendants. The point
is that there is a relatively formalized procedure, an "operation," of think-
ing up the various kinds of anti-owner or pro-worker rules that could
conceivably provide a basis for a pro-worker argument in this case.
Broadening and narrowing are operations we perform by restating a
rule-counterrule or a rule-exception structure so that conduct that at first
looked as though it was clearly within the scope of a particular rule now
appears to be within the scope of an exception or counterrule. Given a
side, that is, given a decision to argue for the plaintiff or the defendant,
there will be multiple possible rule restatements that will validate the
party's position. Here we are not talking about alternative constitutions
of the field (the choice between a First Amendment and an NLRA argu-
ment) but about the choice between "places to draw the line" within a
constituted field. The imagery is of degree, of more or less.
We generate the alternatives in this operation by "disaggregating" the
situations covered by a given formulation of rule and exception or rule and
counterrule. The imagery is of the rule as a formula composed of a set of
abstractions each of which covers a diversity of particular "real life" situ-
ations. The goal is to restate so that some of these situations no longer fall
within the rule's abstractions (narrowing) or so that they now include
situations to which they previously seemed not to apply (broadening).
The operations of field constitution and broadening/narrowing generate
a set of alternative rule formulations that will win for either side.
An example
This morning I woke up thinking about how to start this section and read
the Sunday newspaper.
Liability Waiver Barred
at N.Y.U. Dental Clinic
by Ronald Sullivan
Waivers that patients of the New York University Dental Center have
been required to sign before being treated by students at a reduced cost
are "against public policy" and cannot be enforced, an appellate court
ruled last week.
The waivers, similar to those used by other university-operated clinics,
seek to protect the institution from malpractice claims.
In a unanimous decision, the. . . Court. . condemned the use of the
.
waivers, which are generally not used by hospitals, medical clinics and
private physicians and dentists.
"We find that the exculpatory agreement sought to be enforced be-
tween a dental clinic and its patient implicates both the state's interest
in the health and welfare of its citizens as well as the special relationship
between physician and patient and that it would be against public policy
to uphold such an agreement," the court said in its ruling on Thursday.
"lt is clear that the state's substantial interest in protecting the welfare
of all its citizens, irrespective of economic status, extends to insuring that
they be provided with health care in a safe and professional manner," the
court said . .
The patient, Arthur Ash, a retired salesman, was referred to the clinic
in 1986 by his dentist, Dr. Charles Lennon, so that he could have about
$6,000 worth of dental care done for half the cost. In return for the
savings, the center required Mr. Ash to sign away any claim of liability.
144 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
According to the court, when Mr. Ash was treated by Dr. Lennon and
dental students at the center on Oct. 15, 1986, two gold crowns slipped
down his throat and lodged in his right lung and subsequently required
surgical removal
The court took note of the services that the dental center provided to
poor patients, but said that such services "cannot serve as a basis for
excusing such providers from complying with those minimum profes-
sional standards of care which the state has seen fit to establish."
Poor patients, the courts said, "cannot be considered to have freely
bargained for a sub-standard level of care for a financial savings."
1f dental centers were absolved of any liability, the court said, it would
create an "invidious" system in which "services received by the less afflu-
ent are permitted to be governed by lesser minimal standards of care and
skill than that received by other segments of society."
Generally, the courts have upheld agreements in which consumers
waive the right to sue for damages, provided that the consumers have
sufficient choices; that there is an "arm's length" distance between the
parties involved, such as in the case of owners and patrons of parking
lots; and provided that the agreements are specific on what they cover.
Howard R. Cohen, the lawyer for the dental center, said the ruling
would hurt poor patients by requiring the center to charge more for its
services in order to pay for malpractice insurance. He said the center had
not decided whether to appeal the ruling or to defend itself against Mr.
Ash's suit at trial.t4
loser. The opinion will look legal because it looks as though the judges
knew what rule applied and then applied it.
But the short opinion, in a case like this one, will also be unconvincing
to anyone skilled in legal argument, because it will provide no answers to
the whole complex of arguments that we can generate, without knowing
anything much about the details of the case, on the side of the clinic. In
the short opinion, the argument-bites that support the court's conclusion
are presented as disposirive in a way that we know, given readily available
formalized responses, just can't be the end of the story.
A longer, "better" opinion will get into the choices involved in field
constitution and narrowing/broadening, so that the reader has a sense of
the range of possible rule interpretations. It will also deploy a much fuller
repertory of argument-bites and provide a support system for each. The
two most familiar forms are the opinion that is like a brief for one side or
the other, and the opinion that carefully works out the arguments on each
side, and then abruptly resolves in a balancing test.
but tendencies defined in terms of one another: a person who draws the
line in one place is a liberal just because conservatives draw the line further
to the right.
Of course, in the next case the legal representatives of the liberal ideo-
logical intelligentsia may "go too far," and the same judge who enthusi-
astically endorsed their arguments the last time around will switch sides.
His opinion will sound conservative, as he cuts back products liability to
avoid "abuses" that "drive up prices." But this is just another instance of
the standard rhetorical structure of ideological debate in the United States,
where liberals and conservatives share identical major premises and switch
back and forth, as they draw lines, between identical intermediate-level
arguments.
The participants organize new legal conflicts into the existing /ega/ schemas
or structures that they have used to fight earlier ideological battles. When
presented with a new case, they do a kind of mental checklist to see if it
Policy and Ideology '53
fits into any of the well-known types of interest conflict that are ideolo-
gized.
If the case does fit in, it is possible to understand it as one of a series of
conflicts between two groups or interests, even if the parties don't think
of it that way. This will be easiest in the large class of cases that involve
resolving a relatively small gap, conflict, or ambiguity in a rule system
whose current state is understood to represent the outcome of earlier ideo-
logical conflict.
In these cases, the parties are likely to understand the issue as involving
the same contending group interests that settled the content of the general
rule whose interpretation is at issue here. In that initial dispute, we had
to decide whether there would be strict liability or negligence in defective-
products cases; the decision for strict liability left open the question
whether manufacturers can use an "assumption-of-risk" defense. When
that issue comes up, there will be little hesitation in organizing the case
so that we have yet another instance of ideological conflict between the
same strict liability and negligence forces that were arrayed in the decision
of the initial question.
Besides this "nesting" dynamic for "disputes within disputes," prior
ideological work provides analogies in cases of first impression. Let's sup-
pose that several generations of liberals imagining themselves to be the
intelligentsia of oppressed groups have developed a large number of pro-
posed compulsory terms in many different situations of alleged economic
inequality. Sometimes they have argued them to the legislature and some-
times to the courts. Solving a problem with a compulsory term is a familiar
liberal economic strategy.
Now suppose that within this general compulsory-terms project there
are already fifty cases identified as "about" the validity of seller disclaimers
of liability to buyers, in every kind of business from parking lots to legal
services, but there has never been a case about any kind of medical service.
This case involves a reduced-price university dental teaching clinic that
has injured a patient and disclaims liability. Lawyers and judges may pick
up on the presence of the disclaimer, and organize their arguments by
analogy to other compulsory-terms cases, as involving freedom of contract
versus the public interest in consumer welfare.
Rules, in short, have histories. If the history is understood by the par-
ticipants to be part oía general ideological conflict, then when a case comes
along that involves a disclaimer but also lots of other potentially important
facts, there is a ready-made, already ideologically organized, compulsory-
154 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
The work product of liberal and conservative lawyers and judges preserved
in briefs and opinions biases or skews the legal work that follows, because
it makes it easier to follow some lines of approach and harder to follow
others. On the basis of past work, the judge will be able with only minimal
new work to develop an interpretation of the facts that places the case in
one of the fields of ideological conflict between liberals and conservatives,
or between some other pair of opposed, universalized group interests.
If he or she accepts one of these ideological field constitutions, he or she
gets along with it a ready-to-wear set of policy arguments on each side.
One set of arguments supports rule interpretations that by degrees more
fully realize one interest, and the other set supports rule interpretations
pushing by degrees in favor of the opposing interest. He or she has only
to contextualize the formulas to fit the facts of the particular case. (J don't
mean to suggest that this is easy work.)
Because the materials are ideologically organized, the easiest thing for
the judge to do is to fit the case into one of the rule-conflict forms, and
then develop arguments from the justificarory forms. If he or she prefers
¡56 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
a rule that splits the difference between the positions of the two sides, it's
easy to justify the aspects of the outcome favorable to plaintiff's group
with one set of arguments and those favorable to defendant's group with
the other.
If the judge wants to do anything else but this, he or she has to set out
to do something to the language, rather than merely speaking it. He or
she has to be profoundly creative, somehow find time to make up new
arguments, arguments that are outside the organized system. Judges al-
most never do that. They are much more likely to create by developing
the stereotypical argument on one side or the other beyond its earlier state,
thereby permanently changing the store of bites, or to create more ephem-
erally in the work of contextualizing.
The judge who does set out to change the very terms of discussion is
likely to find his or her contribution instantly incorporated into the ex-
isting system of ideological conflict, but cannibalized by the parties for
their own ideologically organized purposes or, quite possibly, just ignored.
To be cannibalized is to change the discourse, though not the very terms
of discussion (to be ignored is just a warning to those who watched your
doomed effort).
The neutral judge is an ideological performer in this sense: he or she
develops the solution to a legal problem and then justifies it in a legal
language that is also ideological language. The outcome will be under-
stood, not always but often, to have favored a "side" defined ideologically.
The explanation offered will become a part of the materials available to
the winning and losing "sides" in future ideological conflicts. Attempts to
get out of this box sometimes succeed, producing true rupture or recon-
stitution of the system of ideological oppositions, but more often they are
cannibalized or ignored.
7
The question I have been posing is, How can the judge be ideological?
How can the judge be ideological, more specifically, if he accepts that he
is bound to be a faithful interpreter of the laws, bound to do law's bid-
ding" if it conflicts with his ideological preference? In the last chapter, I
asked why an informed observer might be suspicious of the claim that
legal discourse, and particularly legal policy argument, is autonomous from
ideological discourse. In this chapter, I attempt to reconstruct the situation
of the judge from the inside, so to speak, asking how the judge experiences
and responds to the body of legal materials when he has an ideological
preference for a particular rule choice.
To pose the question of how judges can be ideological is not to presup-
pose that all coherence theories are or must be wrong. But it is to take as
a point of departure, first, that none of these theories even suggests that
all, or most, American judges act according to their precepts and, second,
that a judge who accepts a coherence theory will often be uncertain how
to apply it. Even if one of the theories is right as a description of how
judges do and ought to reason to outcomes in ideologically charged cases,
it seems very likely, given the actual state of the bar and bench under-
standing of law, that judges constantly experience themselves as having to
make strategic choices.
In this chapter, the strategic choice involved is in deciding how to
deploy their resources for legal research and reasoning. Legal actors,
whether advocates or judges, can influence what the law "is" through legal
work. In generaL, legal practitioners don't have and don't feel a need for
strong theories of how the law requires one to choose a "direction" for this
work. If they are lawyers, they suppose that it is legitimate to deploy their
resources to shape law to favor their clients. Strategic behavior in choosing
'57
¡58 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
Work in a medium
The constraint we have been discussing so far is that the judge experiences
because he or she is personally committed to interpretive fidelityto do-
ing "what the law requires." But judges, as an empirical matter, as a matter
of plausible social fact, are also constrained by the reactions they anticipate
from their audience. In other words, judges, as fallen beings vis-à-vis their
oaths, want to appear ro be "following" rather than "making" law. What a
given judge will do in a case depends on what she thinks will "fly" as
"good legal argument" in the minds of others, as well as on what she
herself thinks about the matter.
The judge operates as a member oían interpretive community, more or
less reified in her mind, and this fact is a source of constraint, just as
writers like Owen Fiss claim.3 But it is a peculiar kind of constraint,
because the judge is a participant and can affect the community's reaction
to the interpretation in question, rather than having simply to register it
as an immovable, external fact.
The experience of "internal" constraint presupposes that the judge is
looking for a legal argument that looks good to her. "External" constraint
presupposes that the judge is looking for a legal argument that looks good
to the audience. We shift from investigating the way interpretive work
produces the subjective experience of constraint to investigating the way
the same work produces the effect of necessity, the experience of legal
compulsion, for the audience for the interpretation.
lowing and constraint by the text. "The law" does this because under the
norm of interpretive fidelity judges do things they would not do if they
were legislators. And I also affirm that judges are constrained by what they
think their audience will think of them.
But there is a limit to how much of legal reality we can understand this
way. As I said before, just about everyone now agrees that the naive version
of rule-of-law theory doesn't fully explain the role of judges. There are
many questions of law of which all or most or some observers and maybe
the judges themselves would say that the rule that emerges from the case
is a product of the judge's agency in a sense other than willingness to obey.
In these cases, the judge's activity, the judge's legal work, affects the out-
come, the rule choice, so that it is plausible that a different judge, or group
of judges, would have come up with a different rule.
A phenomenological account might look like this. We start from the
individual judge with ideological preferences.4 He is confronted with a
question of law posed by the advocates in the case. He has a sense of the
stakes for ideologized group conflict that will be disposed by his rule
choice. There is an "obvious" rule that seems to apply to the facts as they
have been presented at trial and summarized for appeal. What makes it
obvious is that some combination of argument from authority and policy
arguments seems to constrain him to apply it to these facts. The judges'
ideology appears to him to favor a rule other than this one that is "obvious."
The judge understands, as a participant in his legal culture, that he has
only a fragmentary knowledge oí all the authoritative materials and all the
modes of deductive and policy argument that might be mustered to resolve
the case. I mean, resolve it in a way that would fulfill his duty of inter-
pretive fidelity and his need to generate the effect of necessity for the
members of the interpretive community. He also knows that he will have
enough time to investigate only a part of this lost continent of possibilities
should he decide he wants to do more than just accept and reproduce the
"obvious" legal argument for the rule he thinks is unjust. In other words,
the judge knows that he is not Dworkin's Hercules, endowed with infinite
time and infinite legal skill.
He also feels obliged to do some legal work in spite of the apparent
obviousness of the binding rule, and he understands the interpretive com-
munity to expect this of him. American judges don't see themselves as
presiding over a beauty contest between the advocates, as in a moot court.
They regularly produce opinions that have only the most tangential rela-
tion to the briefs and to the points made in oral argument, using facts
from the record not even mentioned by counsel. The judges and their law
Ideologically Oriented Legal Work 163
clerks see themselves as required to do their own work to produce not only
the best outcome between the parties but also the best legal argument
they can muster in favor of the rule they decide should apply.
I believe that many judges are aware of the possibility, under these
circumstances, of undertaking an investigation of the legal universe with
the conscious strategic goal of unsettling the obvious solution. They also
have the goal of replacing it with a solution in favor of the 'just" rule,
supported by a legal argument that will appear, at the end of the work
process, to be "better" than the one that seemed initially obvious. "Better"
means that the new argument for the nonobvious just rule will seem to
the judge more consistent with his oath and will be more convincing to
the interpretive community.
The judge will also be aware that the undertaking of this strategic search
for a compelling legal argument for his ideologically preferred rule choice
is problematic from the point of view of the rule of law, and indeed of his
oath of interpretive fidelity. The reason for this is that the meaning of
strategic search is search that is "result-oriented," understanding this in
terms of rule choice rather than in terms of which party wins. It is a
strategy because it makes it more likely than would a random search that
he will "find" the result he wants, rather than confirmation of the obvious
rule he thinks is unjust.
Of course, what he is looking for is "inside" the law, since it is an
alternative that is more faithful to the materials than the one it may dis-
place. His search is guided by his prior knowledge of the materialshe
doesn't look where he doesn't expect to find. Of course, the search may
turn up nothing useful, from the point of view of the judge's ideological
preference, and thereby reinforce his initial experience of constraint by the
materials in the direction of the unjust rule. In that case, the judge is
committed by his oath to apply that rule.
The judge who operates in good faith as an ideologist has also to be
open to the possibility that the search process will change his view of what
was just in the first place. If that happens, he will have the option of
reorienting his work to reinforce the obvious, previously unjust rule by
showing that it is good against the counterarguments he himself has been
exploring.
Protestations of willingness to submit to the law whatever it may be at
the end of the search process, and of openness to the authority of law as a
counterweight to one's own ideologized sense of justice, may ease the
judge's sense of moral jeopardy. Rule-result-orientation is still problematic.
It is possible to understand the initial experience of certainty about the
164 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
Deductive work
will seem like authority in the case at hand only after the holdings have
been restated. It involves developing the definitions of the words in hold-
ings so that they have different implications for the facts presented than
they seemed to have at first. It involves restating the facts of the case in
hand to emphasize elements that would seem irrelevant if the obvious rule
applied, and restating the facts of precedents to distinguish some while
representing others as on point. In all these respects, deductive work is
the same as rather than the opposite of policy work.
Policy work
The paradigm case of policy work occurs when the parties and the judge
understand at the beginning that the question of rule definition is one of
"first impression,»' and the legal work they put in does not dispel this
sense. When the judge first reads the briefs, knowing that she will have
to "strike a balance" by choosing a rule, she may experience herself as fully
constrained, as having no choice given her particular understanding of how
policy argument is done, her theory of coherence. But she knows that she
has the option of developing one argument or the other, of working to make
it plausible in the circumstances.
Suppose the judge thinks the advocate for the liberal position, the ad-
vocate who makes the policy arguments that are part of the liberal project
of universalizing consumer interests, say, has done much better than the
conservative advocate. On the basis of what has been laid before her, she
would have to say that the balance favors a compulsory term in this class
of cases. Suppose that she is a conservative, and that her intuition, meaning
her informed impression based on her previous work as a judge, is that
the liberal legal argument is "actually" much weaker than the conservative
one. Suppose that the conservative advocate failed to mention, or to see
the relevance, of the argument that this term might make consumers worse
rather than better off.
Such a judge is likely to see herself as having a moral obligation to do
work on her own to explore the possibilities of developing the conservative
legal position, with the thought that when this work is done she may "see
her way clear" or "feel obliged" to come out for freedom of contract. The
type of work she will do is that which is inherent in the policy mode. First
of all, she will have to identify the range of rules that might apply in the
circumstances. Then she will have to adapt the policy argument-bites avail-
able to the particular facts and the particular rule.
i66 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
Lawyers conventionally distinguish hard and easy cases. We can use the
distinction to elaborate the paradigm of legal work. First of all, an easy
case ¡n the conventional sense is a hard case from the point of view of the
ideological strategist. What we mean by "easy" is that there is a rule that
obviously applies to the facts, given some explicit or implicit combination
of deductive and policy arguments. From the point of view of the person
whose ideological preference is for the obvious rule, the case is easy. From
the point of view of the person who thinks the rule unjust, this is a hard
case in the sense that it will be difficult, it may take a lot of work, and it
may be impossible to displace the obvious solution.
lt may be enough for the judge co turn an easy but unjust case into a
hard case, for which he offers, with much allusion to his internal struggle,
the best solution he can manage. But, of course, it would be better to turn
it into an easy case for his side, by supporting his preferred rule as both
deductively required and optimal as policy.
A hard case in terms of the lawyers' typology is an easy case for the
ideological strategist, since in a hard case there are two plausible rule
choices, rather than only one obvious one. A hard case is by definition one
in which the judge who prefers a particular rule choice won't have to
confront an initial probability oí failing to make a plausible legal argument
for itwhat makes it hard is that with minimum work or at first blush
it is obvious that there is no obvious answer.
lt may be enough for the judge if his work leaves the case a hard one,
as long as he can convince himself and his audience that interpretive fi-
delity favors his preferred outcome and can repel his adversaries' attempts
to convince the audience that the case was actually much easier than it
looked, and in the wrong direction. Of course, his ideal is to make a hard
case look easy, easily resolved on the side of his preferred rule choice.
might be the distance between the interpretation the judge favors and the
one that seems obvious to most members of the interpretive community.
On this basis, a mechanical but suggestive model of the charismatic econ-
omy might look like this.
Judges want to maximize their charismatic store. Charisma is generated
by having persuaded people in the past, as well as operating to add per-
suasive power to arguments in the present. The change in the store caused
by a particular performance depends on how much the judge has invested
in it, and on the "return" in charisma, which is a function both of the
distance the judge has moved the audience and of the importance or sa-
lience or visibility of the case.
On the basis of this mechanical model, the judge has to make a calcu-
lation in every case along these lines: (a) The obviousness gap is x. (b) My
arguments, from the base line of the zero-charisma judge, will get me
I/2X distance. (c) Adding my charisma has y% chance of overcoming the
obviousness gap, which would get me q of added charisma. (d) But there
is a too - y%, or z%, chance of falling short and losing p of charisma.
So the case has a "value" in terms of charisma of yq zp.
Of course, these are continuous functions rather than on/off choices. And
not all judges want to maximize their charisma, in the sense of ability to
generate the effect of necessity independently of the value of their argu-
ments. But I assert that some economy of this type significantly affects
some judges' decisions about how to deploy their legal resources.
ing case, for example. Sometimes, a judge working on such a question will
happily or reluctantly come to the conclusion that the question was not
really ideological after all, that the work of legal argument has generated
the experience of closure. But when this doesn't happen, and the question
still calls out for controversial choice even after the time for work is past,
this is not evidence that the question was inherently indeterminate. lt
might have been that a little more work, or work from the beginning
along a different path, would have produced experienced determinacy after
all.
If there is warrant neither in the experience of unselfconscious rule ap-
plication nor in that of constraint by the text for a conclusion that a given
question has or doesn't have a determinate answer, we can always look
elsewhere. I am not going to argue the proposition that there is no else-
where. It seems obvious to me. Try the thought experiment of the doctoral
candidate in legal sociology setting up his or her empirical study of de-
terminacy. What is the objective index against which to measure judicial
reactionsa panel of "control" judges? And what warrants the correctness
of their answers? And so on.
My approach in what follows neither answers nor rejects, but rather
defers or brackets, the question of what, if anything, lies behind ("in" the
legal materials) the experiences of openness and closure. ¡ think there is
quite a bit we can say about judicial law making without an answer to
this more ultimate question. We can explore the "surface," rather than
trying to penetrate the depths.
I am proposing to shift the investigation from the questions, "are judges
ever 'really' bound? and, if so, how often?" to the question, "what follows
from the fact that judges often experience themselves as bound?" The inquiry
into consequences of adjudication can go on because we can plausibly
describe an experience of boundness that affects behaviorby leading the
judge to actually do whatever he felt he was bound to do, even if he would
rather have done something else.
We ask what are the consequences for the political system if judges
sometimes experience the accessible surface as structured so as to determine
an outcome, and then bring about that outcome, either in the mode of
unselfconscious rule-following or in that of constraint. We ask what are
the consequences for the political system if judges often experience ques-
tions as open, and work to close them in one way or another, but also often
experience them as closed and work to open them, sometimes successfully,
sometimes not.
172 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
The question "Does the U.S. Constitution mandate federal judicial review
of state statutes?" is obviously a "bigger" or more abstract or less narrow
question than "Can a federal district court enjoin a state administrative
agency from enforcing a schedule of rates for rail shipment oí farm products
promulgated under a valid state regulatory statute requiring that rates be
'reasonable?' " Both the "initial" decision for judicial review and a long
sequence of cases fixing rules for narrower subquestions were obviously
"relevant," but they didn't settle in and of themselves this sub-subquestion.
Yet the ideological stakes in the little question were understood to be
large, certainly greater than those in many a local election, because of the
expectation that the state regulatory agency would decide the question of
reasonableness very differently than the federal court.
This is an example of high stakes because in long-run ideological con-
flict, "God is [ofteni in the details." Sometimes a small question involves
high stakes because the size of the wealth or resource transfer that will be
settled in the lawsuit is great, even though the question of law, the rule
choice, is unlikely ever to be relevant in a later case. The tenant farmers
under the "patroon" system of upstate New York litigated a case about
whether the form of tenure devised by the owners, which involved an
incorporeal hereditament called a "rent," was invalid because a restraint
on alienation.'0 When they won, they got a lot of land free and clear. The
rule choice had no significance beyond the case at hand, but the ideological
stakes were great.
But ir is conceding too much if I leave the impression that we are
speaking simply of a discontinuity between legal stakes and ideological
stakes. What the legal stakes in a case "are" depends on the work of ad-
vocates and judges. Legal work, in American history, has often, very often,
unsettled rules located way up in the pyramid: see Brown y. Board of
Education," Reynolds y. Sims,'2 Miranda y. Arizona» Dred Scott y. Sand-
ford,'1 Lochner y. New York," Escola y. Coca-Cola,'6 Javins y. First Na-
tional Realty.'7 Once we reject the ontology of determinacy and indeter-
minacy in favor of the notion of constraint as a function of legal work, it
is a question of fact, to be answered only through trial and error, whether
the optimal strategy of ideological work in law is to concentrate on little
Ideologically Oriented Legal Work '75
Nesting
How radical?
Is what I have been expounding no more than "the thesis that even the
best drawn laws or lines leave some penumbra of doubt, and this calls for
an exercise of a partly political discretion to settle the doubt?" lt really
doesn't seem that way to me. (Oh my God, am I really just a Hartian?)
First, that phrase answers the question "how can the judge be neutral?"
The answer is that he can't be, because "even the best drawn lines
My argument is that he can be ideological, not just because "the best drawn
lines . . ." but because the legal materials are lying there waiting for his
ideologically oriented work. Sometimes his "work in a medium" produces
convincing argument for his ideologically preferred outcome when work
in the other direction would have produced an ideologically contrary re-
sult.
Sometimes he can do much more than "exercise a partly political dis-
cretion" in a "penumbra of doubt." Sometimes he can generate a doubt in
the core of meaning; sometimes the field configuration invites him to settle
not doubt in a penumbra but raving contradiction across a doctrinal do-
main with high ideological stakes; sometimes the field is unrationalized
and he can have the thrill of explaining that its true spirit is libertarianism
in offer and acceptance. This is neither the Nightmare (the judge just does
ideology) nor the Noble Dream (there is a way to be right), but it is not,
I hope, hope, hope, just what the Brits have been saying all along.
If one sees law this way, it looks, as a whole, like the ossified record of
conflicting work projects. It is not just a list of rules, each with a penumbra
within which a little "partly political" discretion can be exercised. The
rules themselves have a new meaningthey are not just the command of
the sovereign, or what we get when we apply the rule of recognition, but
a ragged, contorted boundary trench that marks the outcomes of a thou-
sand sorties and countersorties. (Or maybe the line of scrimmage, just after
the snap . .
The parole evidence rule oía given jurisdiction looks like the particular
working out of the large conflict between a formalist and an antiformalist
version, plain meaning versus New Criticism. The next, sub-subquestion
about that rule looks like the latest incident in a perennial conflict, and,
¡78 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
if God is in the details, one camp or the other may win a major victory
even though it lost the last three battles. If God is in the details, the
reformulation of what it means for the burden of proof in employment
discrimination cases to shift after the making out of the prima facie case
may "gut the statute."
I am aware of a formulaic British response, first articulated, I think,
with supreme condescension by H. L. A. Hart, who claimed to be able to
catch "by a single glance from afar"2° what had been locally invisible before
his overflight. As he summarized the realists,
What did all this amount to? Seen from afar it appears to many English
jurists not to have advanced legal theory far or to have added much to
the stock of valuable jurisprudential ideas. But the virtues and beneficent
influence of the realist movement lay elsewhere . . For its main effect
was to convince many judges and lawyers, practical and academic, of two
things: first, that they should always suspect, although not always in the
end reject, any claim that existing legal rules or precedents were con-
straints strong and complete enough to determine what a court's decision
should be without other extra-legal considerations; secondly, that judges
should not seek to bootleg silently into the law their own conceptions
of the law's aims or justice or social policy or other extra-legal elements
required for decision, but should openly identify and discuss them.2'
Cis looks similar to realism in Scottish eyes:
As a heuristic device, it is, however, certainly good advice to scholars and
practitioners that they should always be ready to turn any question upside
down and to see whether underplayed principles cannot be played up to
create a seriously arguable counter to the view one has initially enter-
tained. The danger of mere dogmatism in legal dogmatics comes from a
failure to take seriously the possibility that another view might be argued
just as well as one's own initial one (mark you, this can be as true of
those who start with a view toward the political left as of those who start
from the political right; no party seems to have a monopoly on dogma-
tism). The uses of this heuristic are demonstrated in many excellent and
insightful CLS writings at the level of concrete doctrine rather than gen-
eral programmatics.22
All those modest studies (realist and cls alike) may have been instan-
tiating the liberal humanist virtues of skepticism about claims of authority,
candor, and antidogmatism, but they also claimed to be doing something
quite different. They also claimed to be showing that the actual outcome
of doctrinal debate, that is, the set of rules the judges chose, is much more
Ideologically Oriented Legal Work 179
intelligible (insert big German word) if you reject both the Hartian and the
American Noble Dream views, and adopt not the Nightmare but suitably
chastened ideology-critique.
In short, they were representing the actual content of doctrine as the
outcome of an argument between intelligible contending projects, or vi-
sions, with big stakes in view, rather than as either a struggle to "work
the law pute" or "mere personal preference" exercised in penumbras. The
plausibility of this project-to-show-the-projects-at-work does not depend
on a global internal critique, like Hart's, of the "inherent" limitations of
language. It depends on the plausibility of a minimalist internal critique
of the mainstream's attempt to show the coherence oía field, on the plau-
sibility of the restatement of the field as contradictory, and on the plau-
sibility of the formulation of conflicting blocks of implicitly ideological
legal argument to account for the cases that came out one way or the
other.23
The interest, as opposed to the plausibility, of the project depends on
an empirical proposition: that as a matter of fact, rather than of necessity,
very large ideological stakes have been disposed by the choice of rules in
cases in which ideologically oriented work of this kind made a difference.
This is the common sense of American lawyers and political commentators
with respect to American law/politics.
Perhaps it looks weird to English and Scottish commentators, for whom
judges exercise a "partly political discretion" in the "penumbras" that exist
in even the "best-drawn" rules, because as a matter of fact British judges
have not disposed large ideological stakes through ideologically oriented
work. Perhaps it seems positively deranged to Continentals because their
judges have disposed even less in the way of stakes than British judges,
who have to deal with the pesky indeterminacy oí the case method.
I have my doubts. But this is not the place to develop them into theories.
The next chapter takes up the metastrategies that American judges adopt
to deal with the anxiety of being strategists in a culture of critical legalism.
8
i 8o
Strategizing Strategic Behavior in Interpretation i8 t
lt was implicit in the discussion in the last chapter that it is always possib/e
for the judge to adopt a strategic attitude toward the materials, to try to
make them mean something other than what they at first appeared to
mean, or to give them a meaning to the exclusion of other initially possible
meanings. But it is never necessary that he do this, and never certain that he
will succeed if he tries. Finally, it is not usually possible to know whether a
particular decision came out differently, as a result of the judge adopting
a particular work strategy, than it would have come out if he had adopted
some other strategy.
It is always possible to behave strategically in the sense of trying to
make a particular rule interpretation look good. There is no definition of
the rule of law that could prevent judges from making this effort, and it
is plausible that the rule of law requires judges to make it, at least some
of the time.
A judge who habitually behaves strategically vis-à-vis the materials may
be insensitive to specifically ideological implications or work hard to ban-
ish them from her consciousness. She may have an agenda that we would
characterize as personal or idiosyncratic rather than ideological. Such a
judge has to use the discourse and listen to the arguments while somehow
not understanding the situation the way the others do, but things like
that happen all the time.
It isn't necessary to behave strategically at all. Many judges seem to
approach the materials with the belief that they must mean something,
and to have little talent or inclination for legal work. They may experience
closure at the end of a process that looks like random search, just grabbing
onto the feeling when it hits them. They may repress or never have ac-
quired the ability to strategize.
From our point of view, the input of these judges into judicial rule
making is uninteresting (though we might speculate about how their non-
strategic behavior will map in relation to the behavior of judges who are
political actors). It is quite important to distinguish this ideologically
random behavior both from unselfconscious rule-following and from con-
straint by the text. It is not unselfconscious rule-following because the
judge knows there is a question of law and is trying to find an answer. lt
is not constraint by the text because constraint means resistance to an
attempt to make the materials mean something in particular.
Even if you can always behave strategically, that doesn't mean you can
182 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
always modify the rule from what you at first thought it would be, or that
you can take what looks like an open question and show that the liberal
side was clearly right, or whatever. You can always work at manipulation,
but you may fail to achieve your objective.
It might be that there are no "real" opportunities for strategic behavior.
Maybe judges do as a matter of fact sometimes adopt the strategic attitude.
But whenever they do so they might be either deluded about what is really
going on, because the law guides them behind their backs, constraining
them in the end to the right answer, or in bad faith in the strong sense of
transgressing the role constraint of interpretive fidelity.
I don't think it possible to refute this possibility except by an appeal to
the history of critique and reconstruction. And this history, to my mind,
establishes only that it is plausible that ideologically focused work con-
stantly changes the meaning of the materialsthat successful instances of
strategic behavior are frequent. Judges often produce a convincing mean-
ing for the legal materials different from the convincing meaning a judge
with the opposite work agenda would have produced (or did produce in a
dissent). In what follows, I try to strengthen this hypothesis through a
description of three kinds of agenda that judges pursue strategically. I will
introduce my three typical characters first as they might be described by
someone interested only in predicting their behavior, someone using the
commonsense notion of an ideological "preference" I described in Chap-
ter 3.
This judge has no intention of disobeying the law. What makes her a
constrained activist is that she puts a great deal of time and energy into
working out a legal interpretation different from the one that first appeared
best. She does this in every case where the law seems "too liberal" to her.
Sometimes she is successful and sometimes not. When she fails, she un-
grudgingly chooses a rule that differs from her legislative preference. In
other words, whichever rule she finally chooses to apply to the case will
represent the best legal interpretation she can find for the materials. She
writes opinions that are formally "legal" and also reflect her honest belief
that the law "requires" the outcome she has reached.
I am calling this judge "activist" because she has an "extrajuridical"
motive, namely, the achievement of a just outcome, for preferring one
result to another across a wide range of cases, and works to make that
result law. Note that this form of activism is oriented to the legal rules. The
judge has a rule that she prefers to the one she thinks she may have to
apply, rather than just a party she wants to win.
In the course of her work, the judge goes back and forth between the
case for her new legal interpretation and the best case against it, in the
spirit of fidelity to the materials. But she is doing this with a goal: the
goal of establishing that her preferred legislative solution is the correct
legal solution. In pursuit of this goal, she has been anything but neutral
in her use of her resources. She has spent a lot of time inventing a strategy,
digging through the books, keeping an eye out all the rime for random
bits of stuff that might be useful in building her argument.
In developing the best argument against her position, her motive has
been defensive. That is, she has tried to think what someone who was as
determined to uphold the first impression as she is to upset it would say
to her alternative. When she is satisfied that she has a good answer to the
objections she can think of, she stops her inquiry and goes on with the
affirmative task of buttressing her own position, thinking up another ob-
jection to refute.
True, she has undergone in this process a good faith risk of being per-
suaded to the opposite side. She has really and truly opened herself to the
possibility that each argument for her first impression is right, and deter-
mined to give in to it if she can't answer it. But it is still the case that
she has an identifiable "project," a direction she is going in (to change the
unfair rule into a fair one). From her point of view, it will be a defeat if
(as often turns out) she just can't find a way around the unfair rule.
Now suppose the activist has a legislative sense of what would be best
but anticipates at the beginning of the interpretive process that there is
¡84 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
no clearly best answer from the internal perspective of fidelity to the ma-
terials. She works away at finding the interpretive strategy that will over-
come this first impression by establishing that fidelity requires the con-
servative outcome she chose on legislative grounds.
If she comes to the conclusion that the law requires the "wrong" inter-
pretation, she will struggle against the conclusion but submit to it if she
can't come up with a good legal argument to the contrary. If she ends up
with a sense that the arguments for alternative interpretations are evenly
enough balanced so that there is an element of choice in deciding between
them, she will decide according to her (predictably conservative) sense of
what is just in the circumstances and will write an opinion making the
best case she can that that result was legally required.
My claims here are, first, that many judges are constrained activists, and
they do a lot of important law making through adjudication. Second, the
results the conservative constrained activist judges come up with are dif-
ferent from those of the liberals with the same approach. It makes a big
difference how you deploy your resources among alternative work strategies
in response to your initial reaction to the materials. Liberal judges who
work hard and well will find good, even apparently (to them) conclusive
reasons for liberal solutions to questions of interpretation. Conservative
judges will come out the other way.
Third, if the conservative judge succeeds through work in making the
conservative outcome look required, we might say that she has changed
the rule of law from what it initially appeared to be. This change was
permitted by the materials, since otherwise the judge would not, at the end
of the process, be operating under the constraint of fidelity in interpreta-
tion. But it was not mandated or required by them. The law did seem to
speak to the judge, in the first instance, generating seemingly of its own
force an experience of certainty about what it required. But "it" didn't tell
the judge to change it or what ro change it into.
The bipolar judge combines traits from the other two. Sometimes, like a
constrained activist, he works hard to develop a strong liberal position on
an issue. But in the next case, he comes out just as strongly for a conser-
vative position, also like a constrained activist, but of the opposite com-
mitment. The outside observer understands him to have the project of
putting together a judicial career that splits the difference, rather than an
opinion in the particular case that does so.
¡86 IDEOLOGY IN ADJ UDICATION
His opinion in a given case will be hard to tell from what a constrained
activist judge on the same side would produce, except that it will not be
looking forward to promoting the libera! or conservative project over a
range of cases. (The bipolar judge, however, may well have made up his
mind on one side or the other for a whole field of law, and so work with
just as much sense of long-term strategy for that field as an activist col-
league.)
What makes this judge bipolar is that he has a consistent tendency to
alternate between the ideologies over time. At the most vulgar level, sup-
pose you are a practicing lawyer appearing before him with an ideologically
charged case at a moment when he has come out as a liberal several times
in a row. There is a much greater probability that he will go for a conser-
vative rule interpretation in your case than there would be if that very
same case had come before him at the end of a string of conservative
opinions-
There may be many particular aspects of the case that you can predict
will appeal to his particular judicial temperament or his previous pattern
of alternation between the sides. But it is also true that his judicial tem-
perament has a general structure independent of these particulars: he is
bipolar. He does not in fact belong to an ideological camp. But like the
difference splitter, we predict his behavior on the basis of our knowledge
of other people's ideological productions. The productions of others define
the alternatives between which he fluctuates. Unlike the difference splitter,
he "lets himself go" and participates actively in constructing the very
ideological positions of which he is at the same time "independent." His
liberal opinions influence the evolution of the liberal "side," just as his
conservative opinions influence conservatism. But having jumped in, he
backs off. Being independent turns out to be another form of compromise.
practically impossible to make the "just interpret" analysis unless one has
what we lack: some other criterion of legal correctness than the plausible
deployment of the argumentative tools that legal culture makes available
to judges trying to generate the effect of legal necessity. Lacking any in-
dependent criterion, I don't think it makes sense to ask how these judges'
outcomes differ from what they would have been had they "just inter-
preted" the law.
My plan is to use my three models of the judge as ideological strategizer
as elements in a theory of the difference it makes to liberal/conservative
conflict that so much of our law is made through an adjudicative process
within which liberalism and conservatism are not supposed to play a role.
The idea is to contrast the status quo, not with an imagined situation in
which judges "just interpret," but with an equally imaginary situation of
legislative supremacy.
With this in view, the rest of this chapter takes up two problematic
aspects of the description I've given of judicial strategy. The first question
is whether the idea of ideology as liberalism or conservatism can work as
an explanation of what judges do, and the second question is whether it
is possible to account for constrained activist, difference-splitting, and
bipolar activity without resorting either to the idea of conscious deceit or
to the idea of utter unconsciousness.
the case can go either way for a liberal, or a sense that any good liberal
has to support the regulations.
Of course, we could say that liberal ideology "really" required either one
result or the other. A judge might imagine that liberalism required regu-
lation of hate speech, but she would be wrong because liberalism prohibits
it. If we had a lot of confidence that the ideologies have this kind of bite
when correctly applied, we could use the notion of an ideological project
as an explanation of judicial outcomes even though we might have to
acknowledge that judges sometimes make mistakes.
The internal critic of this use of the notion of an ideological project may
not be able to "prove that it can't be done." But she will point persistently
to internal flaws in extant demonstrations of how liberal or conservative
principles apply in practice. Then there are all the cases in which suppos-
edly determinate liberal reasoning is unresponsive to alternative versions
of liberalism that have apparently equal claim to legitimacy.
Within the ideological "camps" there are diverse groups with different
positions, and even different "spbideologies." We sometimes see this in
terms of the underlying communities on which they draw. Liberal Repub-
licans of the old WASP gentry kind, with their progressivism on civil
rights and social issues combined with pro-business, antiregulatory sen-
timent, are very different from the libertarians, Jewish neoconservatives,
white middle-American social-issue fundamentalists, and black conserva-
tives. Feminists, rainbow coalitionists, civil libertarians, liberal union ac-
tivists, and environmentalists, to name a few, coexist within the liberal
camp.
My definition of an ideological project allows for conflict or incoherence
among the theoretical premises, and for inconsistency among practices and
between theory and practice. It also allows for fluid "membership" in the
project, and for disagreement about who is in and who is out. None of
this is inconsistent with the experience of closure, but it certainly makes
it implausible to claim that liberal or conservative ideology will yield a
tighter explanation of outcomes than neutral interpretation of the law.
Indeed, the parallel between ideology and legality suggests an inquiry
into how people's false belief in the determinacy of their own ideological
positions inflects the course oí democratic politics. And then we could go
behind ideology to try to find out how judges decide, for example, that
they "don't like" being opposed to regulation of campus hate speech, even
though it at first appears to them that their own liberalism requires that
opposition.
190 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
that wanted to be deceived, but it would then have the instability of any
conspiracy that involves many thousands oí people and has to constantly
renew itself by recruiting new Grand Inquisitors.
My way of looking at it is to start with the psychology of denial in an
individual judge, then suggest mechanisms by which the psychology of
the actor in the story gets adopted by the audience for the action. Judges
keep the secret, even from themselves, in part because participants in legal
culture and in the general political culture want them to. Everyone wants
it to be true that it is not only possible but common for judges to judge
nonideologically. But everyone is aware of the critique, and everyone knows
that the naive theory of the rule of law is a fairy tale, and those in the
know fear that the sophisticated versions of contemporary jurisprudence
aren't much better.
external facts about his or her situation, but in the special sense of
a "refusal to acknowledge," "refusal to recognize," "refusal to admit."
The denial requires something like "refusal," because it presupposes
that there is evidence for the thing denied, or an assertion of it by
someone in argument. When I say that judges "deny" the role of
ideology in their decisions, it is implicit that in my view it does play
a role in factthe denier is always wrong.
2. We agree about the misrepresentation that:
It is not merely conventional, as when you ask the terminally ill
patient, "how are you?" and he responds, "I'm fine, how are you?"
When judges write their opinions in the language of legal neces-
sity, this is just a convention; when we say that they are engaged
in denial, we mean that they at least partly believe the conven-
tion.
It is not a conscious, deliberate, strategic misrepresentation, not a
lie designed to deceive an audience without the speaker having any
belief at all in its truth (judges are not consciously trying to deceive
us about ideology in adjudication).
It is not a cognitive glitch or random error. For example, we have
more data than the statement itself, as in, "'I am not mad,' he
screamed, veins bulging." Or the speaker repeats the misrepresen-
tation after "dismissing" feedback or new data that the audience
believes would "normally" cause him to correct itnew data in the
form, for example, of a devastating critique of adjudication.
who deny do so all the time, or even that all judges are influenced by
ideology. As I said above, some judges are better understood as clueless,
or as devoted to agendas that aren't ideological at all in the sense in which
I've been using the term; and some judges are best understood as random,
or as operating on the basis of truly unconscious motives that are hopelessly
complex and also inaccessible. And in many, many cases, judges experience
themselves as constrained by the text, so that their liberal or conservative
or difference-splitting or bipolar strategic inclinations turn out to be ir-
relevant to the outcome, at least from their own point of view.
As long as we suppose that a significant number of judges are con-
strained activists, difference splitters, and bipolar judges, and that they
have made a lot of important law that is best accounted for by these
ideological postures, the analysis should be interesting. Even if you think
that there is always a legal right answer that is the same whatever your
"personal" ideological position, it should be interesting if you also think
that some judges some of the time behave in the ways described.
The constrained activist accepts the constraint of interpretive fidelity. But
when she thinks this obligation will require her to reach an unjust result,
or when she sees open texture, she works to change the meaning of the
materials in the direction of what we have decided is her own ideology.
When she writes her opinion, she obeys the convention that requires her
to present the outcome as fully determined by the materials and by her
reasoning. To the charge that the rule of law means no ideology in judging,
her reply is an opinion that denies that ideology had anything to do with
Strategizing Strategic Behavior in Interpretation '95
it. She offers no account of the role of ideological strategy in her work
process.
I've had conversations with three sophisticated constrained activist
judges, two liberal and one conservative, in "private," so ro speak. The two
liberals denied, in the mode of Cardozo, that ideology played any role at
all in their decisions, although they heartily agreed that technical reason-
ing was often indeterminate, that policy was a constant influence, that
they were perceived as judicial liberals and often as "partisan," and that
liberals but not conservatives had supported their most important judicial
initiatives.
They both said that they tried to shape the law "in response to the
development of the society." They thought liberal responses to socio-legal
problems, such as products liability or landlord/tenant, corresponded bet-
ter than conservative ones to the "needs" of society, and they therefore
chose those responses, with humble recognition that they might well be
wrong. This didn't make them ideological actors, in their own minds,
because they remained free agents, deciding each policy question on the
merits, without any loyalty or inner commitment to the ideology they
were implementing over time. The conservative judge was much more
"cynical." He saw his liberal brethren as unselfconscious or hypocritical,
and gave a sardonic but also uneasy description of his battles with them,
emphasizing that his own activism was strictly defensive.
The liberal constrained activists seem to me to be in denial or bad faith
because their explanation of how they are independent of ideology is an
evasion of rather than a response to the critique. Both liberals and conser-
vatives, like the activist judges, are formally committed to putting into
effect the rules that they respectively see as responding to the evolution of
society and meeting its needs. What divides them ideologically is that
they have sharply different interpretations of "society," "evolution," and
"needs." We don't hesitate to call a person a liberal or a conservative with
no more basis than that they consistently adopt the interpretation that one
or the other camp has evolved, over time, as an application of the shared
general principles (rights, majority rule and the rule of law, Judeo-Chris-
tian ethics, regulated market economy with safety nets) to each particular
question that implicates social need and development.
True, these judges could be ideological in a stronger sense. They might
"believe" in liberalism or conservatism as doctrines, and be committed to
working both to improve them and to ensure their practical triumph in
the world. It is fair for them to deny that they are ideologues or partisans
¡96 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
in this stronger sense. But the claim of the critique of adjudication is not
that judges are committed but merely that ideology influences adjudica-
tion.
If the judge admits that over time she has consistently found liberal
solutions to be more just than conservative ones, and consequently has
chosen to make them into law, she has admitted enough to validate the
critique. The bland persistence in affirming independence when one's vote
is highly predictable is a perfect example oí bad faith.
There are two kinds of difference splitters. One type is an ideological
moderate and splits the difference as a constrained (centrist) activist. This
judge's legislative preferences correspond to the results he works to bring
about through adjudication, and he is a denier and in bad faith to the
extent he claims that all he is doing is "calling them as he sees them,"
without any commitment to a camp. Again, what we mean by ideological
influence in adjudication is consistent orientation to a set of results, rather
than partisanship or true-believer-ism.
The more interesting type of difference splitter has internalized a strong
norm against activist behavior of any type. His idea of his role is that it
forbids acting like his colleague who is a "knee-jerk conservative" and also
like his colleague who is a knee-jerk centrist. He believes in one of the
various theories of his role that excludes an ideological motivation for the
work of legal reasoning, even if constrained. He may be a reasoned elab-
orator of the Hart and Sacks school, or a Dworkinian, or a positivist, or a
feminist pragmatist, or he may adhere to the view of the activists that the
judge should make law evolve to meet the "needs of society."
His practice does indeed represent a version of neutrality, since his "per-
sonal" or legislative politics, which may be liberal or conservative or cen-
trist, don't influence how he comes out. He splits the difference even when
he thinks that result monstrous and knows he would never vote for it if
he were a legislator. Ideology has no internal, commitment-based influence
on his behavior. It influences him only because he allows the ideological
positions of others to determine him by setting up the difference that he
splits.
But the theory of even the most revisionist advocates of the rule of law
is not that judges should consistently choose the path of ideological mod-
eration, against their intuitions of justice when necessary, but that they
should be in some sense nonideological. From the point of view of the
critique, ideology is no less an influence if it comes in only through the
back door, so to speak, by structuring his alternatives.
Srrategizing Strategic Behavior in interpretation '97
The bipolar judge, like the difference splitter, comes in two variants. He
may be an activist by personal or legislative commitment, first on one side
and then on the other. In this case he is, in pop psychological terms,
"schizophrenic." He is open to the critique that he is in bad faith on each
side of his split personality, because on each side he is an activist. Or he
may be best interpreted as acting on an implicit but untenable theory of
judicial neutrality, to wit, that as long as he isn't consistently liberal or
conservative, he isn't ideological.
Like the other two, he wants to be interpreted as doing just what he is
supposed to, that is, calling them as he sees them, without an ideological
commitment. He is exempt from the charge of having a commitment to
moderation because in any given case he can go all the way with the liberals
or the conservatives. The way he decides a particular case is to keep an
open mind as long as possible, listening attentively to the arguments on
both sides starting from his own understanding of himself as not a liberal
nor a conservative nor a moderare, but a "free agent."
This is his problem: He has a commitment to his idea of himself as a
free agent, but he would doubt that commitment in himself if he found
himself coming out too often on one side or the other. And since he is
proud of his independence and thinks others recognize it, he may be in-
fluenced not just by his own but by what he thinks his audience's ideas
are about what proportion of liberal and conservative decisions you need
in order to sustain the free-agent claim.
This type of bipolar judge differs from the constrained activist because
he doesn't start out asking whether he would favor the obvious interpre-
tation of the rule if he were a legislator. He doesn't see his role that way
at all. What he does is to listen to counsel or other judges putting forward
their arguments for ideologically organized alternatives and try to figure
out which one best "fits" the body of materials. He adopts first one point
of view and then the other. Finally, he commits himself. But the commit-
ment is ideologically patterned over time so as to keep him independent.
The nonactivist difference splitter as I have described him is an ideo-
logical moderate who believes that moderation is not ideology. The non-
activist bipolar judge calls them as he sees them, but turns out to see them
under the constraint that he must be able to appear to himself, over time,
as neither a liberal nor a conservative, no matter how he would react to
the merits without that constraint.
They are both classic bad-faith actors, because they deny both to them-
selves and to others something that they know perfectly well is going on.
198 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
is denial unconscious?
When you say "I'm not mad," or "my ideology had nothing to do with
it," and others think you're denying, rather than being polite, lying, or
making a random mistake, it's hard to decide what to call your relationship
to the true fact, your true intention, your true emotion.
When we are mistaken about the facts, in a random, unmotivated way,
we say that we are "not conscious" of the true facts. In lying, we are
"conscious" of the facts. In repression as it figures in Anna Freud, the
repressed impulses are really and truly "gone": "But the ego of the child
who has solved her conflicts by means of repression, with all its patholog-
ical sequels, is at peace."8 Denial is a much less drastic mode of defense,
which takes a less massive investment oí energy, and, like the other non-
repressive defense mechanisms has "to be brought into operation again
whenever there is an accession of instinctual energy."9 The judge has to
deny his ideological role every time someone asserts it, or evidence suggests
it; he cannot get rid of it once and for all by a single act of repression.
But it seems odd to apply the adjective "unconscious" to denial as l've
defined it. There is a problem in saying you're unconscious of a fact or of
an inner state when you muster a lot oí energy to "keep from knowing"
it. When we say that we are dealing with motivated error or wishful
thinking, we are saying that there is some part of the psyche that registers
the possibility of the unpleasant truth and then mobilizes to keep from
knowing it. The very thing we mean by denial in the psychological sense
is that what is involved is more than the mere speech act, and we interpret
this "more" as a strategy to deal with an anxiety-producing conflict. This
presupposes that the "strategist" in the story knows more than the obtuse
performer of the speech act of denial. As Sartre puts it:
To be sure, the one who practices bad faith is hiding a displeasing truth
or presenting as truth a pleasing untruth. Bad faith then has in appear-
ance the structure of falsehood. Only what changes everything is the fact
that in bad faith it is from myself that I am hiding the truth. Thus the
duality of the deceiver and the deceived does not exist here. Bad faith on
the contrary implies in essence the unity of a single consciousness.
It follows first that the one to whom the lie is told and the one
who lies are one and the same person, which means that I must know in
my capacity as deceiver the truth which is hidden from me in my capacity
as the one deceived. Better yet ¡ must know the truth very exactly in
order to conceal it more carefullyand this not at two different moments,
200 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
one of the early kings. The composition of the state, uniformly assumed
to be natural, was nevertheless known to be in great measure artificial.
This conflict between belief or theory and notorious fact is at first sight
extremely perplexing; but what it really illustrates is the efficiency with
which Legal Fictions do their work in the infancy of society. The earliest
and most extensively employed of legal fictions was that which permitted
family relations to be created artificially, and there is none to which I
conceive mankind to be more deeply indebted."
If many judges are denying the role of ideology in their decision pro-
cesses (and some of them are lying), it seems plausible to look for some-
thing common to their situation that produces a conflict, rather than a
million idiosyncratic versions of the Oedipus complex.
the guidance, no matter how difficult it may have been to figure out what
it was, or, on the contrary, took guidance from something else.
The alternative view, historically associated with British positivism and
radicalized in legal realism and cis, is that the judge faces not a conflict
between his role and his illegitimate desires but a genuine "role conflict."
There is a contradiction between the norms that are supposed to govern
his behavior. In this view, the motive for denial is not guilt at deviance
but the anxiety produced by the dilemma of not being able to do the right
thing no matter how hard you try, because you are being told to do two
opposite things at the same time. The denial of the ideological resolves
the conflict by making it appear that the role definition is coherent rather
than contradictory.
Again, I am not arguing that all judges decide ideologically, and I think
it likely that some judges have nothing to deny. These judges don't ex-
perience the conflict that my three types experience. My much more lim-
ited claim is that it is plausible that constrained activists, difference split-
ters, and bipolar judges experience role conflict, which motivates denial,
as well as or rather than a conflict between their will to ideological power
and their roles.
To say they experience role conflict is to say that it would be problematic
for them to exclude ideology because there is something in their under-
standing of the role of the judge that seems to push to include it. I think
that in fact judges, and actors in a range of similar positions, do often
experience a conflict of this kindroughly between the overarching gen-
eral goal or standard proposed to them and the particular rules that sup-
posedly further the goal but sometimes seem to conflict with it. For judges,
the goal is "justice under law," and the conflict is between that idea and
the categorical exclusion of the "personal,' in the sense of the ideological,
from the decision process.
For these judges, I imagine, it doesn't seem possible to say that justice
under law means no more than law application. First, they are very much
aware that their task is to decide "questions of law," meaning questions of
rule definition, and that these are questions of interpretation, rather than
of application of rules to disputed facts. Second, they are very much aware
that "the law" as it appears at the end oí the decision process is a function
of the work they do on the legal materials, and that different work strat-
egies are likely to produce different lawthat is, different legal rules-
with no intralegal criteria available to indicate which work strategy is
correct.
204 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
These judges, I imagine, feel that what they are supposed to do, what
their role requires them to do, when the law appears to depend on what
work strategy they pursue, is to consult their conception of justice, perhaps
concretized as rights, values, or needs. But, I imagine, they also feel that
they can't bring the idea of justice to bear on a dispute without allowing
ideology to enter the decision process. They don't want it to enter and
wish it couldn't; they may even believe that if only they could figure out
how, they could exclude ir. But as they experience it, the minute you start
talking of justice, you have a contested concept, and the contest is the
familiar one between liberal and conservative conceptions of just social
orderthat is, of just legal rules.
These judges are in a bind. Their sense of justice is inescapably an
ideological one, in the sense that an outside observer would easily cate-
gorize the judge as either a liberal or a conservative on the basis of his or
her answer to what justice required in the circumstances. The only alter-
native to ideological justice, once strategic behavior has become a possi-
bility, seems to be random decision. Random decision violates the role
definition of "justice under law" even more seriously, the judge might
suppose, than pursuing justice in the shadow of ideology.
In the description l've just given, my goal was to suggest what in fact
might motivate judges to deny the ideological in adjudication, rather than
"just saying no" and getting rid of it. It may be an accurate description of
what some judges experience, even if we conclude that there is in fact a
nonideological method for deciding questions of law. If this method exists,
judges ought to employ it, but they may be ignorant of it or unable to
make it work in particular cases.
In my view, a judge who experiences role conflict is "right," because
there really is a conflict built into her role, so that her only alternative to
denial is ro acknowledge that she can't do her job in the way she is sup-
posed to. The conflict is "real," in my view, because there is no extant
theory that plausibly explains how the judge can decide, once she is con-
scious of the possibility of strategic behavior in interpretation, in a way
that excludes ideology, supposing that her sense of justice is congruent
with an existing ideology.
Dworkin, for example, says two things to the judge: there are no criteria
outside legal argument for determining the rightness of rule choices,'4 and
the judge should deploy his own "political philosophy" (which may be
liberalism or conservatism)," both in the analysis that searches for legal
determinacy through fit, and in resolving gaps, conflicts, and ambiguities
Strategizing Strategic Behavior in Interpretation 205
So far, we have denial as a way to escape role conflict. But why doesn't the
judge respond by saying, "my role has an internal conflict, so it needs to
be redesigned"? Why don't academic critics help the judge off the hook
by suggesting that we are forcing her into hypocrisy? One way to extend
the analysis is to ask what reasons there are for people outside the role to
deny the ideological in judging, to act as codependents in the judge's
denial. The answer can't be role conflict for these outsiders, since they
aren't playing the rote.'7 But they can nonetheless have investments in the
nonconflictual character of the role, in the possibility of playing it without
ideology having a place in the decision process.
Two types of investment in the notion of judging without ideology
suggest themselves: (a) people may want to believe in it because not be-
lieving in it would induce anxieties based on the centrality of judges in
the political system, and (b) people may want to believe in it because belief
fulfills, at a distance, at a social remove, a pleasurable fantasy about the
possibilities of being in the world.
conservative, it is easy to deal with the idea that judges often allow ide-
ology in rather than just saying no to it. This insight simply requires us
to reform the judiciary, to get judges to obey role constraints that "every-
one" agrees are valid. Denouncing the tyranny of the judiciary can be a
staple of both liberal and conservative politics without threatening "the
system" in any way.
But if the critique is correct, this is shadow play, however satisfiing as
such, because there is no coherent account of how judges whose sense of
justice is ideologized can do what their role, defined as keeping ideology
out, requires them to do. And since it is hard to imagine how we could
exclude people who have this kind of "fallen" sense of justice from the
judiciary (especially if we have "fallen" ourselves), "the system" seems
flawed in a quite basic way, rather than just subject to the inevitable
corruption of judicial deviance.
In short, the viral critique arouses anxiety in part because it is delegit-
imating. lt undermines the broad Liberal consensus not just about how
society should be but about how it pretty much, with warts, is organized,
namely, in accord with the principles of individual rights, majority rule,
and the rule of law. lt suggests that, appearances to the contrary notwith-
standing, it isn't organized that way in fact, and won't be even after reform
of the judiciary. It couldn't be, given the empirical reality of strategic
behavior in interpretation and the difficulty of imagining how it could be
eliminated.
A second motive, a second kind of investment in the notion of the rule
of law as a guide rather than a mere constraint, derives from liberal and
conservative commitments to diverse, particular, judge-made legal rules.
The liberal stake in the nonideological character of adjudication might be
summed up by the question, "Don't you think Brown y. Board of Edu-
cation was legally as well as ideologically correct?" Liberals and conser-
vatives have many commitments of this kind to the specifically legal cor-
rectness of their favorite important judicial decisions. The news that Brown
was just a manifestation of liberal ideology, in the sense that it was no
more legally, as opposed to morally, correct than Plessy y. Ferguson, is bad
news for liberals, and the motive for denying it is obvious.
Yet another reason to deny viral critique is the fear that if it were valid,
and if judges fully understood it, they would tyrannize us worse than they
do already. This is the notion that belief in the rule of law as a guide,
rather than as a mere constraint, is a beneficent illusion, a myth with good
social consequences. I think Scott Altman, in his article preaching this
Strategizing Strategic Behavior in Interpretation 207
fear, is wrong to think that even the judge who fervently believes the myth
can unselfconsciously "follow the law," for the reasons already stated. But
I don't think the critique can deny that greater judicial sophistication might
(a) increase strategic behavior at the expense of ideologically random be-
havior, and (b) induce some judges to "cheat," by which I mean disregard
experienced constraint by the text.'8
I'm not going to pile speculation on speculation by trying to assess to
what extent these imagined dangers of the demystification of judging are
realistic. My intuition is that people who want to believe in rights and
the rule of law, and liberals who want to believe in the justice of deseg-
regation, will go on believing even if they accept the critique of judging,
and that greater sophistication on the part of judges would probably have
little effect on the content of judge-made law. But who knows? I assert
only that fear of the consequences motivates denial of viral critique.
Overcoming contradiction
ourselves. Trial judges who fear the anger of losing litigants, and appellate
judges who fear the anger of those who disagree with the rules they make,
have a motive to displace responsibility onto others, the legislature or prior
judges.22 To the extent they feel guilty about their ideological contribu-
tions to law making, they have a motive for the quite distinct operation
of projecting ideological intentions onto others.
As l've been arguing, judges find themselves willy-nilly participants in
the general cultural conception of judging as a situation of moral jeopardy
in which the chief danger is the introduction of ideology into the decision
process. It is not, I am supposing, psychologically tenable for judges and
their public to respond that there is role conflict here, rather than a moral
drama of corruption. They can't acknowledge that the rule of law is only
a constraint, and not a guide, and that some of the time, at some very
important times, it is a weak constraint, one that doesn't let them off the
hook represented by their ideologized, "fallen" conceptions of justice.
In this situation, the stability of the system of denial may get an im-
portant support from the projection of symmetrical ideological motives
onto one another by ideological opponents, followed by denunciation oí
those opponents for corruption. This "projective identification" involves a
self-reinforcing relationship with the person onto whom one has projected
a desire or a characteristic, rather than a mere externalization.23 The notion
seems to me helpful in interpreting the odd persistence in American legal
culture of obsessive concern with and equally obsessive denial of the ideo-
logical, what I called American critical legalism.
How could one "prove" a proposition like that of the last paragraph?
One couldn't. But consider the following letter to the editor of the Boston
Globe by a liberal participant in the intensely politicized battle over the
confirmation of a conservative Harvard Law School professor, Charles Fried,
to the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts. Because the letter quotes
Fried, as well as denouncing him, it allows a glimpse of the symmetrical
character of the projections, and it even contains a denunciation of the
very impulse to analyze judges ideologically that it itself perfectly exem-
plifies.
Fried has had a distinguished academic career, but I do not believe he is
an appropriate choice. He would bring an ideological predisposition and
potential divisiveness to a court that has been free of both.
Fried was a committed servant of the so-called "Reagan Revolution,"
an agenda that had as one of its main goals the dismantling of the legal
rights and remedies developed under Republican and Democratic ad-
ministrations for violations of Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.
Strategizing Strategic Behavior in Interpretation 2 II
The jealousy of the second layer, the projected, is derived in both men
and women either from their own actual unfaithfulness in real life or
from impulses towards it which have succumbed to repression. It is a
matter of everyday experience that fidelity, especially that degree of it
212 IDEOLOGY IN ADJUDICATION
Conclusion
Some judges some of the time pursue ideological strategies vis-à-vis the
materials rather than just accepting direction from them. The strategies
they choose have an impact on what law gets made in a given case. On
the one hand, this impact is not constrained by an electoral process, the
way it is when legislators bargain over the wording of legislation. In this
sense judges are freer than legislators.
On the other hand, the law constrains them in a way it doesn't constrain
legislators because they accept a duty of fidelity to the materials that rules
a lot of things out, even if it doesn't determine the choice between liberal
and conservative rule interpretations in many cases. In this sense they are
less free than legislators.
There is a discursive convention denying that judicial law makers are
engaged in an ideological practice. Most members of the intelligentsias
(including the judges themselves) believe that there is some truth to the
convention, that is, they deny the ideological in adjudication. They con-
sistently exaggerate the difference between what judges do when they
decide appellate questions of law in adjudication and what legislatures do
when they decide them by deliberating and then voting on statutes.
I am going to argue in the next part that the combination of the law-
making power of judges with the bad faith (mis)understanding of adju-
dication has consequences for ideologized group conflict.
PART FOUR
Consequences of A djudication
9
in most discussions of the rule of law, the implicit question is what would
happen if judges were "at large"? The quite different heuristic device em-
ployed here is to imagine a different system of governance than the one
we now have, one that would eliminate a crucial aspect of adjudication as
we currently understand it, and then speculate at length about what con-
sequences would follow for the political system. This method has the ad-
vantage of keeping the question of consequences relatively defined while
not suppressing the utterly conjectural character of the discussion.
What would happen if, in every case where appellate judges at the
highest level decided a question of law, there was an appeal to the legis-
lature, with a strong practice of the legislature considering and deciding
the question? There would be no written opinions in the legislature, but
there would be debate and legislative history. The legislature might use
more or less elaborate fact finding, just as it normally does. "Parties" could
submit whatever briefs they wanted to; there would be no rules limiting
"standing," once the question was in the legislature.
Imagine the abolition of final judicial review, in the sense that a final
adjudication of unconstitutionality of a statute could be appealed like any
other question of law to the legislature. Finally, imagine a general under-
standing that the legislature should approach questions from the courts
under decisional norms indistinguishable from those it observes in "ordi-
nary" legislation, including a norm of obedience to the state and federal
constitutions.
My claim is that the combination of our current practice of ad judication
with current understandings of that practice produces political results that
215
216 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
are different from those that would likely occur if we had this different
practice and different understanding. It would be a big change. But how
big? Your answer will depend on just what you think judges now do, and
on how you think people in various publics understand what judges do.
It is necessary to distinguish between these two questions because there is
so little consensus about the reality of the practice of adjudication. People
have widely varying views of the practice, and these affect both their par-
ticipation in it and their participation in legislation. Since it seems obvious
that the views contradict one another, in the sense that they can't all be
right, some substantial group seems probably to be misled.
In my hypothetical scenario, by contrast, there is a shared understanding
oí what is going on (though of course wide disagreement about what
should be done in particular cases and perhaps about the new system itself).
The question I want to pose is that of the impact on the political system
of doing law making through an adjudicative process subject to our par-
ticular multiplicity of understandings, including the widespread denial of
ideology in adjudication, rather than through a (relatively) transparent
legislative process.
Three hypothetical effects of our particular, and particularly misunder-
stood system of law making through adjudication, contrasted with my
counterfactual process, seem worth exploring. The first is the reduction of
the power of ideologically organized legislative majorities, and ideologi-
cally oriented high-court judges, whether liberal or conservative, to bring
about significant change in any subject-matter area heavily governed by
law. The second is the empowerment of the legal fractions of intelligentsias
to decide the legal outcome of ideological conflict among themselves, with
less control by the electoral process than would likely be the case under a
regime of legislative decision of appellate questions of law.
The third, which I take up in the next chapter, is a legitimation effect,
an increase in the appearance of naturalness, necessity, and relative justice
of the status quo, whatever it may be, over what would prevail under
legislative revision. All three effects presuppose that our society has a
particular main ideological division, liberalism versus conservatism. The
moderation and empowerment effects have to do with the fates of liber-
alism and conservatism under our own versus a different system. The le-
gitimation effect has to do with the question of how other ideologies, for
example radical leftism and radical rightism, are affected by the peculiar
phenomenon of practically or constitutionally final judicial law making
through adjudication.
The Moderation and Empowerment Effects 217
change. If she favors it, she will do something more than "implement" ir;
she will work to develop and entrench it, choosing among the possible
interpretations those that lead to a real shift in the balance of ideologized
group conflict.
If the constrained activist is on the losing ideological side, she will do
just the opposite, working to give the statute a minimal meaning, to fit
it into the great mass of rules in a way that will deprive it of ideological
bite. The difference splitter will position himself between these poles,
looking for "moderate" interpretations that can't be tarred with the brush
of partisanship. The bipolar judge will flip back and forth between vig-
orously extending the statute and equally vigorously cutting it back, main-
taining balance, but only over the long run.
All of this is happening in the context of constraint. But constraint just
means that sometimes each of these judges ends up choosing a rule inter-
pretation that he or she would not vote for as a legislator. Because oí
constraint, it may well be possible for the legislator to make a regime
change and implement it through the judiciary in a way that really does
shift the ideological balance. But there is nothing that guarantees that this
will happen.
The moderation hypothesis is based on a simple model: suppose that
the judges are divided up in a way that roughly reflects the ideological
divisions within the intelligentsia or political class, and that the legislature
also reflects the same division. It follows that a majority of the judges favor
the regime-changing statute and understand it as an ideological victory.
But some of them oppose it, and some don't feel strongly one way or
another. These underlying legislative preferences of the judges will be mod-
ified by the role constraint that forbids them to be ideological and drives
them into the three postures I've described. In this situation, only the
constrained activist judge who likes the statute will do what the majority
that enacted it would have done under a system of legislative revision.
The other judges will all, in some measure, work against che more
extreme possible meanings of the enactment, even though many of them,
as a matter of their "personal" legislative preference, would support those
meanings. The constrained activist on the losing side will be systematic
about it, doing as much "damage" (from the majority point of view) as is
consistent with her sense of constraint by the materials.
But the difference splitter will also systematically moderate the regime
change, choosing solutions that are plausibly nonideological because they
lie between the "extremes," even when he would have voted, as a legislator,
with the activist majority. The bipolar judge will sometimes do just what
The Moderation and Empowerment Effects 22!
the ideological majority would have done, and what he himself would have
done as a legislator, but sometimes the opposite, behaving like the anti-
statute constrained activist in spite of his legislative preference.
The role of constraint in all of this is complicated. At one level, there
will almost certainly be a range of possibilities that no judge would see as
consistent with interpretive fidelity. But after excluding these, the different
judges may have different reactions to particular cases. Conservative judges
who favor the regime change will feel constrained, after working hard to
extend the statute, to the extension their legal work has produced. Liberal
opponents who work equally hard to find narrowing interpretations will
feel equally constrained in the other direction.
The result is controversy, with each side claiming in good faith (but
more cosmically in bad faith) that the statute "requires" their particular
interpretation. The debate about interpretation that would have occurred
in an overtly ideologized language under a regime of legislative revision
occurs here inside a legal discourse that is also ideologized, but covertly
so. This is what Reich means when he says that the protestations about
Congress's intent are "for the cameras," and that "judges, motivated by
their own preconceptions of the public interest . . . will be making new
law.
Five complexities
First, constraint might come into play in the opposite way from that just
described. A conservative judge might feel more constrained to adopt an
"activist," but also self-defeating, interpretation of a liberal regime-chang-
ing statute than a liberal. She might see the statute as irrational to start
with but think its democratically elected authors entitled to make their
own mistakes. The liberal might feel more free to give an apparently
conservative, limiting interpretation that would save the liberal statute's
effectiveness, by compromising it in a way that would have surprised the
enacting majority.
Second, neither side in the judicial implementation process can afford
to drop the rhetoric of necessity unless the other side drops it as well. This
is the consequence of the (mis)understanding of the judicial role, main-
tained by judicial and popular knowing and denying, in bad faith, of the
shaping power of interpretation. As long as it is judges who are doing the
implementing work, each side has available the rhetorical resource of the
"rule of law," and each side must use it or lose.
Third, the need to maintain a rhetoric of judicial necessity "for the
222 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
cameras" masks the similarity between the judicial battle and the legis-
lative battle that preceded it. The practical effect of this is to empower
the opponents of the regime change in a way that would not occur under
legislative revision. In that process, they would appear as "the losers" trying
to snatch victory from the details, rather than as ideological neutrals trying
to puzzle out someone else's intention.
Fourth, the moderating effect is not a "distortion of the popular will,"
or of democracy, for three reasons. (i) Under the rule of law as I've defined
it, judges who experience interpretive fidelity as compelling a particular
result, against their legislative preference, go with the law and against the
preference. They must experience their moderating interpretations of the
regime change as permitted by the legal materials, or they don't adopt them.
Given the directed nature of the work process, they will often or perhaps
even usually experience them as required.
The moderation effect relies on a notion of constraint but not on any
particular or general theory of the "true," "correct," or "neutral" interpre-
tation of a particular statute or of statutes in general. The moderation is
in contrast with what would happen if the legislative majority could im-
plement its own regime change, rather than having to rely on a judiciary
that is both internally ideologically divided and motivated by role anxiety
not to appear ideological.
(2) It would be wrong to understand the legislative process as producing
meanings in isolation from the judicial process that implements those
meanings. Sophisticated legislators understand the moderation effect and
draft legislation with it in mind. For example, sometimes they draft what
looks like a regime change, with no expectation that it will be implemented.
Sometimes they exaggerate the degree of change in order to overbalance
the moderating effect and end up just where they want. The point is not
that there has been a distortion but that the medium through which the
legislature works has a particular molasses quality, which it might not
have under a different system.
() The alternative regime of legislative revision would have its own
distorting effect on the popular will. There would have to be a large in-
crease in the legislature's capacity to consider and enact statutes. However
this was organized, it would almost certainly change the balance of polit-
ical and bureaucratic power within the system as a whole, creating exten-
sive new opportunities for strategic behavior by litigants. And anyway,
why treat the existing balance of legislative power as legitimate, given all
its familiar distortions and corruptions?3
The Moderation and Empowerment Effects 223
with the same possibilities that exist for statutory change. The issues will
present themselves in the same nested pattern, with the ideological choices
supposedly settled at the high-court level re-presented in subsumed de-
cisions that have the potential of undoing the original scheme.
Fractions of the intelligentsia steadily develop programs for transfor-
mation of areas of life that are governed by the common law, such as, say,
spouse abuse or sexual harassment in the workplace. In the early stages, it
is difficult or impossible for them to muster legislative majorities or even
interest for their program. The judges may "adjust" earlier, gradually ab-
sorbing the new ideas as they work at splitting the difference between
what they see as the extant social visions.
Because judges have practically unreviewable law-making power in
common law and constitutional adjudication, fractions of the intelligentsia
can avoid the legislatures in bringing about policy change. As we will see
in the next section, the system operates more flexibly than it would if
adjudication were outside ideology in fact. But, at the same time, even
judicially initiated ideological change takes place in a muffled, compro-
mised way, rather than in the form of decisive action implemented across
the whole relevant range and with all the relevant detail questions resolved
in accord with a general plan.
Common law judicial initiatives oía similar type are the development
of labor torts around the turn of the century, the reform of the law of
business ethics through promissory estoppel and related doctrines, the
development of the modern law of consumer protection, the Tort Revo-
lution, the development of the modern law of land use restrictions oriented
to protecting subdivision development, the transformation of child cus-
tody doctrine, and the abolition of the causes of action (criminal conver-
sation, seduction, and so on) that once gave the marital relation a particular
legal structure.
In constitutional law, the epic judicial initiatives have been the attempt
to restrict social legislation under the Lochner Court and its successors,
and the judicial abolition of de jure racial segregation. But there are lots
and lots of less extreme cases, including the reapportionment, police mis-
conduct, and obscenity cases of the Warren Court, the abortion decision,
the neutralization of civil rights law during the 1970S and 198os, and on
and on indefinitely. The New Jersey Supreme Court's Mt. Laurel7 doctrine
is based on the clause in the New Jersey constitution to the effect that
legislation shall be "in the common interest."
My goal here is to give a political interpretation of this kind of judicial
law making through adjudication. The first question is how judicial as
opposed to legislative control modifies the outcomes of ideologized group
conflict. We need to make the general model a good deal more complicated
to make sense of this.
Let's look at the mass of legal rules from the perspective of an ideological
intelligentsia. Many of the rules are irrelevant to the kinds of group conflict
the intelligentsia is interested in. But some of the rules are very important.
Ifa group succeeds, through litigation or legislation, in getting these rules
to favor its interest, ir moves on to other legal or nonlegal concerns. It has
scored a victory and leaves it to the judges, constrained by the language
of precedents or statutes, to administer the new regime. Perhaps over time
the judges develop this body of law in the direction preferred by the
ideological intelligentsia, or perhaps it goes the other way.
A large number of particular rule systems have a history as objects of
ideological interest and controversy. Different subsystems, and different
particular rules within subsystems, are understood to be favorable or un-
favorable to particular interests. But the system as a whole has no single
226 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
This power goes beyond the ability to settle particular rules favorably to
one side in an ideologized group conflict. The judge deploys the mana,
the charisma, the concentrated authority that derives from our cultural
understanding of the Judge. The first, or elementary, importance of this
is that it allows the fraction to legitimate rules that favor it through
something more than mere state force. The judges who set the rules in
their favor also declare that these rules are required by "the statute" or "the
law," or by "the Constitution." This may make it more likely that people
will obey, accept, and eventually approve them.R
In so much as putting the charisma of the Judge behind the rule causes
people's views on the merits to change, judges form public opinion. They
are part of the political system not just as "appliers" of law made by
someone else, but also as formers of the sentiments that express themselves
in legislation. The most striking recent example of this is the judicial
contribution to gradual formation of a legislative consensus in favor of
desegregation. But John Marshall's contribution to the current consensus
on judicial review itself, and on the nature of federalism, shouldn't be
underestimated.
It is simplistic to denounce this process as "undemocratic." There is no
"private" sphere in which the will of the people could form without con-
tamination by all the various sources of authority in the society. The per-
suasive power of judges derives from what we might call the preliberal
consciousness of people, their attachment to ideas like God, the King,
Father, Doctor. There are numerous sources of authority of this kind. The
media filter what authorities say and do, but also amplifr and elaborate it,
drawing on their own sources of authority. Judges couldn't not exercise
this kind of mediated authority, unless they deliberately set out to dele-
gitimate themselves. If they did, others would take up what was ceded.
Empowerment is the ability of fractions of the ideological intelligentsia
to influence, according to their agendas, both the outcomes of conflict and
the formation of democratic majorities, by their privileged access to this
particular combination of state power, authority, and media.
It is equally simplistic to sanitize this authority through the theory that
228 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
judges "reflect" changing social ideas and customs. They do indeed reflect
them, but in their diversity, and above all in their contradictions. The way
the opposing views and habits of the population, their ideological divi-
sions, are represented in the judiciary, and then developed and pursued by
judges, affects the direction and speed of change of popular consciousness,
the emergence of new consensus. What judges do forms as much as it
reflects.
There is no popular will. There is a legislative process, and there is the
rule of law. Each is a component of the Liberal theory of democracy. The
structure that withdraws so much law making from the legislative process
and lodges it in a misunderstood judicial process influences what people
in general, and intelligentsias in particular, think about all kinds of policy
issues. It is difficult or impossible to know what public opinion expressed
through the legislative process would be if we did not entrust so much
law-making power to judges, and it is naive to think whatever that was
would be somehow purer.
Thus far, I have focused only on the way a shift toward legislative su-
premacy would threaten the current power of ideological fractions to col-
onize particular areas of law through sympathetic judges. The balance of
power in question is "horizontal": elites and their constituencies fare dif-
ferently in the judicial system than they would in the legislative. But the
empowerment effect empowers only those with access to the judiciary. The
next section explores the possibility that the privilege of the intelligentsia
in gaining this kind of access helps to explain the phenomenon of denial.
versy and critique have already thoroughly undermined belief in the pos-
sibility of objectivity, and even oí constrained interpretive fidelity in ad-
judication. What is left is no more than a convention, a fig leaf, a
performance "for the cameras."
I tried to respond to these views in the last chapter. Here I am going
to amplify the hypothesis that the intelligentsias of both ideological camps
have a common interest in mystified law making by adjudication. This
interest isn't the obvious one from the point of view of each fraction: the
ability to use the mana or charisma of the judge to enact and enforce their
particular policy preferences. Since the fractions have contradictory pref-
erences, and all have access to the Judge, the accesses cancel one another
out. A common interest means an interest in opposition to a common
danger.
I don't think the intelligentsia has a common material interest, in op-
position to the material interests of other social groups, that is strong
enough and dependent enough on access to judicial power to motivate
denial. Intelligentsia class privileges certainly depend on reverence for ed-
ucation, general belief in the power and validity of expertise, and respect
for "intelligence" in the abstract. But I don't think the knowledge classes
see their prosperity as depending particularly on special access to judges,
with accompanying mystic power, in anything like the way, for example,
that late-nineteenth-century big business did.
To make things even more complicated, there is an intelligentsia interest
in believing in law that has little to do with class conflict. Just about
everyone wants to believe in the success of their own ideological univer-
salization project. If they get their interests universalized in law, they
experience them as validated in a way that is not true for legislation. One
of the verses of "We Shall Overcome" that civil rights marchers sang at
the moment of laying their bodies in the way of police violence was, "God
is on our side." Civil libertarians are quite similar:
Pigeons were given a small but immediate food reinforcement for peck-
ing a certain key, and a larger but delayed reinforcement for not pecking.
Most of the pigeons tested pecked the key in over 95% of the trials . .
232 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
[Sol the experimenters offered the impulsive pigeons the option of peck-
ing a different colored key at an earlier time. Those pigeons that pecked
the different colored key found, upon waddling into the test chamber,
that the temptation of the small, immediate food reinforcement had been
removed. They were thereby forced to wait for the larger, delayed re-
wardsomething that over 95% of them could not bring themselves to
do when the temptation was immediately present. Significantly, 30% of
those same pigeons learned to peck the earlier key when it operated to
foreclose the later temptation. Even pigeons seem capable of learning to
bind their own future freedom of action in order to reap the rewards of
acting in ways that would elude them under the pressures of the mo-
ment.'2
These quotations are suggestions about the difference it would make if
we had just the same constitution we have now, but with the legislature
as the "final arbiter" of its meaning.
Judges doing final judicial review are not supposed to "enforce the Con-
stitution" against the legislature quite in the way the quotations suggest.
The role constraint on judges that is supposed to make their activity anal-
ogous to a "device" is interpretive fidelity to the whole corpus of consti-
tutional law, including past interpretations. The most we can hope for
from final judicial review is that we can use judges to "bind our own
freedom of action" according to their assessment of the meaning of the
Founders' text plus earlier judicial decisions.
Moreover, the authors of these two quotations do not believe even for a
minute in the naive rule-of-law theory. If the defects of majority rule are
in every child's commonplace book, every newspaper reader is used to neu's
stories (not editorials) that begin like this: "In the past month, the Supreme
Court's conservative majority has made clear that it now has the intention
and the votes to push criminal law sharply away from its liberal moorings
of a generation ago."3
Whether judicial review seems preferable to legislative revision should
depend on a complex calculus. You might believe that the pigeon idea is
powerful not because law is analogous to a machine that withdraws a
particular lever from the pigeon, physically preventing an error by the
pigeon, but because there are some clear constitutional directives that you
agree with, and judges are more likely to follow them than legislators.
You might concede that there will be many constitutional questions that
don't have clear answers but think that judges are not likely to do much
damage, however they decide them, as long as they hew to their task of
enforcing the good, clear mandates.
The Moderation and Empowerment Effecti 233
You might not like the text oí the Constitution, but like constitutional
law, seeing the judicial elaborations over the years as a valuable total cor-
pus. You might see the judicial technique of constrained activist fidelity
to the total corpus as a more reliable safeguard than the legislature will
ever be. And you might believe that even your own ideological camp, in
its legislative incarnation, is sorely in need of a safeguard.
But you might see the text as containing good and bad, and see judges
as having leeway to give good and bad meanings in accord with ideological
agendas you don't like. You might see our form of constirurionalism as
sanctifying, "enshrining," bad results and sapping legislative competence
and initiative.
People don't resolve themselves on this question behind a veil of ig-
norance, with no idea of what their particular interests and ideological
commitments will be in the regime chosen.'4 We can ask what conse-
quences we might anticipate for ideologized group conflict from switching
to the alternative. And there is no reason to think the consequences would
be the same regardless of the time at which one made the switch. Switching
today wouldn't be the same as never adopting Marbury y. Madison.
Constitutional law today is no more coherent than is the common law.
However the textual provisions may have seemed at the start, the process
of interpretation has turned them into a hodgepodge, with some built into
particular liberal or conservative agendas, others deployed in alternation
by liberals and conservatives, depending on which domain of ideological
controversy is in question. Some language switches its valence through
time, while other words and phrases have never been much use co either
side.
Liberals have been devoted to the equal protection clause, and to the
religion and speech clauses of the First Amendment, but speech issues are
more complex in the era of paranoia about political correctness; conser-
vatives like the just compensation clause of the Fifth Amendment, and the
contracts clause. Both sides like due process when it suits their interests
(that is, when they get to define liberty and property), and so on. There
have been activist liberal and conservative majorities of the U.S. Supreme
Court within recent memory, so that the body of materials taken as a whole
is quite representative of the ideological possibilities in the general polit-
ical culture.
I don't think that the commitment of the whole political spectrum to
judicial review is explained by the fact chat every part of the spectrum has
colonized some part of the corpus and wants to protect it against other
234 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
eral dangers of majority rule, dangers that everyone should fear. Then there
is what one might call constitutional wishful thinking, the conviction of
both liberals and conservatives that the corpus of constitutional law, cor-
rectly interpreted, protects them and their constituencies from their ene-
mies and their constituencies, while permitting their favorite (moderate)
reforms. Finally, there is the pervasive intelligentsia experience of living
on top ola disorganized, culturally disparate, ethnic, racial, class, regional,
religious stewpot, a stewpot that threatens periodically to boil over into
populist, racist, radical, or reactionary intolerance.
In this respect, the American intelligentsia is far more precarious in its
authority than the intelligentsias of the nations of Western Europe. Those
intelligentsias are by comparison "organic." Their authority is rooted in
the cultural and class and ethnic histories of relatively homogeneous soci-
eties.'6 But their history is also that of the guillotine and fascism and the
Holocaust and the gulag.
The American intelligentsia has a naive belief in constitutionalism: the
myth of the possibility and the reality of a national life organized in accord
with a set of founding principles, along with the myth that the Judge
presides "over" politics. But it also has a cynical conviction that it is best
for the masses to believe in law, in the Constitution, in the Judge, because
without them there is no telling what might happen.
In the absence of hierarchically structured community, which is the
(simultaneously secure and stultifying) condition of the Western Europe-
ans, any authority is better than no authority. And our extant constitu-
tional law, whatever its status in the Court of Reason, is, for both sides, a
lot better than just "any" authority. Experience formalized as critique
drives American liberals and conservatives into bad faith rather than apos-
tasy.
The Western European intelligentsia has no confidence in sacred polit-
ical texts whose mere interpretation guarantees legitimacy. It believes that
"anything can happen," whether or not you have judicial review. Law is
not at the center of politics, though I think it plays just as important a
role from the periphery, a role that is if possible even more thoroughly
mystified than in the United States.
Io
First, why assume that there would be rapid change? The legislature might
tend to approve the vast majority of common law rules, and even tend to
be more hostile to "reform" than the courts. Of course, the legislature
could reconsider whole common law schemes. It could decide that al-
though the common law had been clear, it should be scrapped, or an
exception added. There would be no issue oía duty of fidelity to precedent.
But in the debate about the modification or massive replacement of
common law regimes, we would expect legislators to put forward all the
arguments for stability in the law that we would hear in a discussion of
stare decisis. The advocates of change would in turn put forward ail the
familiar arguments that the "law evolves to meet new social conditions."
Legislatures might change common law rules more rapidly than courts
have changed them in the recent past, and the process might spin out of
control. But there isn't a powerful theory that indicates that would happen,
so let's suppose it doesn't.
The stricture of the distinction between the common law and legislation
Why do people see judge-made common law as less political than statutory
law? At an elementary level, we have a cultural belief in the distinctions
The Legitimation Effect 24!
between law application and law making, between adjudication and leg-
islation, and between judicial resolution of controversial questions of rule
interpretation and legislative resolution of equivalent questions.
People have associations with law, and its development through adju-
dication, that connect to the "natural, necessary, just" pole of the duality,
with legislation associated with the traits at the other end. The figure of
the Judge is a real one in the imaginations of all classes of people, and it
is quite a different figure from that of the Congressman or the Senator.
This belief operates in different ways at different levels of the class and
gender and race systems. For example, in popular consciousness, the courts
may be strongly associated with the repression of deviance and the settle-
ment of disputes according to widely shared social norms.' The legislature
is there to take care of problems, to make changes in response to new forms
of deviance or to the deterioration of systems. At the other pole, the spe-
cifically legal intelligentsias have a clear conception of courts as resolvers
of ideologized group conflict according to an often indeterminate method.
For different people, the belief that there is a fundamental distinction
goes along with different kinds of critique and cynicism about the judicial
role. These views may dovetail only on the proposition that it is not "all
politics," though politics has a lot to do with it. The different strata can
and do disagree on exactly how or why it is not all politics, without
undermining the basic structure, as long as circumstances don't force their
(mis)understandi ngs into actual conflict.
In what follows, ¡ am concerned with the way the conservative and
liberal intelligentsias, and their specifically legal subparts, (mis)understand
the distinction, and with the consequences. In the (mis)understanding of
the intelligentsia, there are three structural aspects of the relationship
between judge-made common law and legislation that are politically im-
portant.
i. The common law is a background, a complete or potentially complete
system that is there waiting to dispose of any new case, and does in fact
dispose in a routine way of the overwhelming mass of legal business. Leg-
islation is a foreground, a more or less striking intervention that makes
things different than they were before, but does this only to a small piece
of the total system and does it episodically. Contrast an understanding in
which "the Code" is the background on which judges do foreground in-
terpretation, with the legislature occasionally "fine tuning" its own prior
work.
2. The common law is, roughly, "commutative," concerned with "right-
ing wrongs" within a well-defined system of individual and collective
242 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
rifice could abolish it, because its roots are in human nature and the ne-
cessities of social life, and besides there s nothing wrong with it.
With respect to the level of inequality in society as it exists right now,
there is a related spectrum of attitudes. The current level might be intol-
erably and unnaturally and unnecessarily large, or far too small to be con-
sistent with ethics and rationality, or it might be just about right. The
argument is that how you see the common law will influence where you
stand on this spectrum.
Suppose the choice is between seeing the common law as a nonpolitical
background institution whose practices are governed by technical require-
ments (the interstate highway system) and seeing it as a part of the political
system that resolves issues of ideologized group conflict. The claim is that
the more you see it as political (in the sense of ideologically disputed choice
that increases or lessens inequality), the less likely you are to see the current
level of inequality as natural and necessary, and the more complex your
argument that it is just. In short, the withdrawal of the common law from
politics favors the status quo. Why should this be so?
or charisma of the judiciary that established it. To mess with this rule will
be understood as messing with one of the set whose derivation is outside
the political process but also in a domain of authority.
The analogy is to arguing, for example, that bridges should be built
differently in order to make it easier for poor people to cross them. Such
a proposal comes up against the notion that the authorities "know what
they're doing." lithe Engineer says it should be built in a particular way,
then we ought to do what he says.
But it is not just a matter of floating, prerational charismatic power.
Like the Engineer, the Judge has her reasons. There is an apolitical logic
of bridge building, based on factors like cost and safety. There is also an
apolitical logic to the common law definition of fraud (false statement,
made with knowledge of falsity, that reasonably induced reasonable reli-
ance by the addressee, to his or her detriment).
At least it is the burden of the legal opinions that lay down the rules,
and of the academic literature that compiles and comments on them, that
there is such a logic. This body of texts is "apologetic," in the sense that
it argues, under the convention of necessity, that the rules are as they
should be, or that the rules should be marginally modified in a conservative
or liberal direction. In other words, we withdraw the common law from
politics into a domain in which there are apolitical ethical and instrumental
and purely "technical" justifications for what the judges have done.
The notion that law is apolitical has both a positive and a negative
meaning. The positive meaning is that there is a judicial method, that the
method is that of fidelity to the materials (to the past, to the previously
agreed on), and that the method is, in some sense, to a large degree, ideolog-
ically "neutral." The negative is the absence, from judicial or academic
justifications for rule interpretations, of the kinds of reasons that are cul-
turally identified with the ideological.
These include preference for egalitarian or unequal income distribution,
for a particular religious vision, for a controversial version of sexuality, or
for the promotion of racial, as opposed to individual or "American," iden-
tity. Ideological preferences are present as a matter of fact, as I argued
above, built into the universalistic discourse of "policy," and worked out
by restrained activist, difference splitting, and bipolar judges. But they
are present denied, as the stain of bad faith.
The point is not that the rules thus justified have a liberal or a conser-
vative "tilt." Within the domain of law making by adjudication, the dif-
ferent ideological fractions vigorously pursue their different agendas. Their
246 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
success varies with time and the process of judicial appointment, subject
to the vagaries of the moderation and empowerment effects.
The point is rather that a cost of movement toward greater equality or
greater inequality appears to be the "abandonment" of law. It means chal-
lenging authority; it means renouncing the security of understanding this
part of social order as "necessary" (in the sense that legal outcomes are
necessary rather than contingent), in favor of flux. It means finding a way
to answer the web of legal argument that asserts the fairness, rightness,
usefulness of the judge-made rules, and their transcendence of narrow ideo-
logical considerations.
In short, our current understanding, however qualified by cynicism,
withdraws these legal rules into a domain in which a whole knowledge
industry has worked for generations to justify them, subject again to mod-
erate reformist and reactionary critiques. The legitimation hypothesis is
that this limitation of the political imagination is good for the status quo.
Disclaimers
An analogy
law, local government law, race law, the law oí the First Amendment, and
gender law. My presentation becomes more schematic as it goes along and
in every case neglects the richness of context and the major differences
between the different authors, within as well as among fields.
Labor law
Labor and capital are each organized, with individual workers and unions
on one side and capitalist enterprises of different sizes and structures on
the other. There are elaborate rules of the game about how the entities can
be constituted (bargaining unit definition, union democracy rules, corpo-
rate and antitrust law) and about what they can do to each other (covering
activities like trespass, picketing, strikes, secondary boycotts, discharge,
lockouts, blacklists, and so forth). The outcome of conflict and cooperation
is a distribution between the underlying groups behind the legal entities.
In the foreground, the outcomes are determined by "bargaining power," a
black box that includes the value at the margin of contributions to the
productive process, but also strategy, group cohesion, resources, and so
forth, of capital and labor.9
The first version of labor law delegitimation was that of the progressives
up to the passage of the Wagner Act. In the United States the two main
movements of opposition to the status quo in the late nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries were the agrarian movement and the labor movement.
The law of legal personality, especially corporate law, and tort law were
focal points. In particular, labor cases put common law judges in the po-
sition of deciding issues that were ideologically contested with large stakes.
Both labor and capital defined the issue in terms of "unbiased" rules of
the game.
The legal representatives of capital developed a version of property
rights that conservative judges accepted in many cases.'° The labor move-
ment developed a symmetrical populist position based on the right of the
individual to dispose of his labor and to make agreements with others
parallel to those among employers. Outside the milieu of socialism, the
demand was for a "fair shake" or for preservation of traditional forms of
worker collectivity, rather than for, say, worker control." Labor advocates
argued that the conservatives were distorting the true logic of a system of
individual rights in order to protect their interests. But their supporters
in the progressive intelligentsia had a much more sophisticated notion of
what law was and what it could achieve.
250 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
the 19405 and 19505 had chosen a particular interpretation of the NLRA,
one that was required neither by the principles of statutory interpretation
nor by a compelling theory of the background legal context, but rather by
a "deradicalizing," moderate liberal ideology. These acts of interpretation
by a labor intelligentsia empowered through adjudication created a legal
regime that naturalized a particular vision of collective bargaining.
It created a legal context that was systematically hostile to labor mili-
tancy, whether at the level of union activity or at that of the rank and file.
The promotion of arbitration, enforcement of no-strike clauses, insulation
of unions from effective fair-representation suits, constriction of subjects
of compulsory bargaining, narrow interpretation of the duty to bargain in
good faith, and many other doctrines represented ideologically motivated
choices with massive but largely invisible consequences. What came to be
regarded by both labor and management intelligentsias as the beneficent
logic of the collective-bargaining "system" created by the statute func-
tioned in fact to demobilize workers and then "administer" them.
The obvious difference between the earlier and later critiques is that the
first was liberal and the second radical, oriented to worker control, work-
erist, hostile to what Kathy Stone called "industrial pluralism."4 Another
important difference is that the cis critiques emphasize the reproduction
within the antiformalist, policy-driven liberal labor law regime of "social
conceptualist" legal reasoning techniques." As we saw in Chapter 5, the
realists didn't come close to solving the problem of the coexistence of
deductive with policy reasoning, and this made their work vulnerable to
a critique analogous to that they had leveled against formalism.
A third equally important difference is that the critical analysis em-
phasizes the way the labor law regime and its analogues actually constitute
the "subjects" they regulate. In addition to distributing surplus by influ-
encing bargaining power, the labor law regime favors the "social construc-
tion" of passive workers and then purports to give them what they want
through freedom of contract.'6 The progressives tended to take the "sub-
jects" of the conservative regime as given outside the legal analysis, thereby
avoiding difficult political questions of "false consciousness" but also un-
derestimating the stakes of law.'7
Federalism
More or less at the same time that they were critiquing tort law in the
labor context, the progressives applied the same tactic to the law of fed-
eralism. Liberal/conservative conflict takes place within a public law struc-
252 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
tute that allocates some powers to the federal and some to the state gov-
ernments. At any given moment, in the foreground of political conflict,
liberals and conservatives compete in elections for control of governments
at both levels. The choice of policies with distributive consequences for
their constituencies depends on how they do.
But once liberals or conservatives gain power, what they can do at the
level they control is conditioned by the rules of federalism. If you control
the federal but not the stare level, you get only federal powers. If you
control at the state but nor the federal level, you may be legally blocked
by the law of federalism and practically blocked by deregulatory compe-
tition among the states.
Again, the progressive motive for critique was conservative judicial in-
terpretation, in this case of the commerce clause and the Tenth Amend-
ment. The federal government had no power to regulate activities whose
effects on interstate commerce were merely "indirect"; manufacturing was
"not commerce"; the states could not supplement weak federal regulation
where Congress had "occupied the field"; the states were prohibited from
regulating in some areas even if Congress had not done so.
lt is easy to see this doctrinal development in terms of the empowerment
effect: conservative political groups achieved results that they might not
have been able to achieve through national and state legislatures. The
legitimation effect was the "withdrawal" of the issue of the allocation of
state and federal power from the political discussion of how to deal with
monopolies, child labor, and so forth, because it appeared that federalism
was just a neutral framework for the democratic process, rather than a
framework shaped by the very interests that were contending within it.
The progressives responded by developing the same force field model
for federalism that they had worked out for private law conflict.'8 They
attacked all the conservative on/off distinctions as hiding questions of de-
gree that couldn't be decided without reference to policy.
(r) Within the general framework of the Constitution, there are vast
leeways in deciding the particular rules of federalism, because terms like
"power," "commerce," and "tax" are too vague to preclude setting the rules
so as to further the substantive liberal or conservative policies you favor.
(2) The choice of a particular specification of the idea of federalism will
have large consequences, much larger than appear if you focus on the
foreground of state and federal electoral politics. () Our specific set of
rules is the product of conservative judges empowered through adjudica-
tion, legitimated through legal reasoning, and much worse for liberal re-
The Legitimation Effect 253
ways in defining sovereignty, which is, like property, best seen as a bundle
of rights and powers and which lacks, like property, an internal logic that
would make it sensible to oppose any desirable solution for an international
problem on the ground that it is "incompatible with sovereignty." (2) The
choice of a specification of the concept has much larger consequences than
people preoccupied with the foreground of military, diplomatic, and eco-
nomic conflict within the rules imagine. (3) The preWorld War I rules
were put in effect by leaders of a small group of dominant imperialist early
modern states and then frozen through legal reasoning as necessary im-
plications of basic concepts.() It was urgent to revise the state system by
reconfiguring sovereignty and building new institutions, in the interests
of the victims, whether those who die in wars, the colonized peoples, or
minorities within existing states.22
The interwar thinkers, like the progressive critics of labor law and the
law of federalism, were successful in the sense that their ideas became a
kind of orthodoxy in the era of the United Nations. But as orthodoxy the
critique became itself a part oí the background, this time for a disinte-
grated pragmatic policy discourse within the larger structure of Cold War
stalemate.
I would cannibalize the work of cis post-Vietnam critics for use in my
schema as follows. They hoist the antiformalist liberals on their own petard
by pointing out the residual power of a formalist concept of sovereignty
within a discourse that claimed to have superseded any such primitive
notion. They pointed out the tension between the claim to have superseded
formalism and heavy reliance on the notion of expertise to legitimate suc-
cessive New World Order projects. As had the labor lawyers, they em-
phasized the subject-constituting effects of legal discourse but included
the decision makers themselves as products of their own policy speech.
Along with other second- and third-generation crits, they developed a
postmodern methodology that had not previously been tried in law. They
eschewed programmatic radicalism and replaced analysis in terms of rela-
tively coherent visions with a combination of cultural critique and the
kind of semiotic analysis described in Chapter 6.23
I think there is a good case for describing local government law as defining
a field like those above. Rich and poor and black and white compete in
markets, which are a foreground for the exercise of bargaining power,
The Legitimation Effect 255
against not one but two backgrounds. The first is that of the rules regu-
lating the interactions of labor and capital as bearers of "legal personality,"
developed in labor and corporate law. But these same groups also pursue
their interests within local government law, a "state system" analogous to
the international and federal systems.
Groups can homogeneously control their own city, town, or county
governments, exist as minorities within them, find themselves "balkan-
ized" or "ghettoized" by the local government system, and so forth. Legal
rules govern the formation and dissolution of such governments, and what
they can do in competition with one another through their tax, zoning,
and voting policies, and legal rules also allocate powers between state and
local government. The relative wealth and poverty of groups, as well as
their opportunities for consumption of housing and community charac-
teristics like slum conditions and racial segregation, depend on this struc-
ture.
There does not seem to have been a progressive critique in this area
parallel to those in labor, federalism, and international law. As I read it,
the cls version24 was originally quite close to the early labor law model
but built on the realist critique of federalism that was still an important
part of the law school curriculum in the late 1950S and early 19605. Local
government law was also one of the locales for the shift to postmodernism.
I would appropriate some of its elements for purposes of my schema as
follows.
(t) Within the general structure of local government law, neither the
public/private distinction nor concepts like plenary state power over mu-
nicipal corporations and home rule are any more determinate as guides
than property, states' rights, or sovereignty. Doctrine develops through
opposed rhetorical modes (for example, picturing space as naturally divided
or as featureless). There is no reason not to take our substantive views
about rich/poor, black/white conflict into account in designing this struc-
ture. (2) Its distributive effecton urban wealth and poverty, for example,
or on the national pattern of racial segregation in housing, schools, and
jobsis vastly greater than appears when we focus on the foreground of
city budget crises, desegregation decrees, urban riots, or white flight.
() The extant rules were frozen in place by nineteenth- and twentieth-
century judges with various agendas and naturalized through legal reason-
ing. They function today to generate outcomes much less favorable to
cities, the poor, and people of color than might occur under a different set
of rules. () We should change the rules to change both distributive out-
256 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
Race law
The legitimation critiques in the areas of race, the First Amendment, and
gender law differ from those in the above areas because they do not have
progressive forebears. Indeed, First Amendment, and race and gender equal
protection law, as developed from the 1930S through the 1970s, represent
the main alternative to legal realist policy analysis and interest balancing,
namely, the appropriation by liberals of what had been a right-wing rheto-
ric of individual constitutional rights. In these areas, the liberals were
antimajoritarian and therefore concerned to build up, rather than under-
mine, judicial authority.
As I see it, the analysis in the race area had two stages. Derrick Bell
showed how the development of supposedly color-blind, individual legal
rights against discrimination in the school desegregation context could
have large negative consequences for their supposed beneficiaries.26 Liberal
victories sometimes turned out to undermine black community resources
and institutions and to promote the polarization of the black community
along class lines. The judiciary, and white elites in general, were at best
only ambivalently committed to racial justice. Rather than pushing for-
ward to deal with the unintended consequences oî reform, they pulled
back from confrontation with the white working and lower-middle classes,
and compromised or gutted the set of legal doctrines that had promised
to transform the legal structure oí black-white relations.27
The legitimation critique in the area of race law was of the way in which
the prestige of the judiciary, the mana of the Judge, deployed from the
1950S through the early 1970S by liberals against racial oppression, turned
against the cause of racial justice when conservatives got control of the
courts and switched from the "victim" to the "perpetrator" perspective.
Alan Freeman's brilliant analysis28 was thus parallel in its radical intentions
to the critiques of liberal policy analysis in labor law and international
law, but he aimed at a different mode of judicial legitimation of the status
quo. His work, and some of critical race theory, fits the more general cis
schema as follows.
(i) The legal concepts, like equal protection, discrimination, and eq-
The Legitimation Effea 257
It is easy to see how one can mechanically apply my schema to the law of
gender.
(i) The regime of legal rules that constitutes men and women and gays
and straights as legal subjects, and then structures their competitive and
cooperative interactions, has no more coherence than the others described
above. (2) Its effects are great, potentially far more important than those
of the foreground dramas provided by the prosecution of cases of alleged
abuse, the battle over affirmative action for women, or the gender wars
beloved of the media. (3) It was put in effect by conservative and liberal
judges who thought they could derive it from their (conflicting) ideas
about the natures of men and women, gays and straights, and naturalized
as background through legal reasoning. (j) We should change it in the
direction of radically egalitarian, anti-essentialist gender liberation.
But this is no more than a form. To give it content is to illustrate again
that there is no general theorem of the legitimating effect of adjudication,
only a series of historically specific examples. In this case, the crucial moves
were those that allowed the extension of the labor law model to gender
but in the process transformed the schema. The extension was difficult
because there are many ways in which we conceive issues of gender law as
arising in a context so different from that of labor law that they are irrel-
evant to one another.
To begin with, labor law is the place where the distributive focus, which
The Legitimation Effect 259
frankly asks how law affects the division of the fruits of cooperation be-
tween participants, is most developed and has been most developed for the
longest time. The law of gender, by contrast, seems mainly preoccupied
with two quite different kinds of issues: first, with defining the limits of
formal legal inequality between the sexes and, second, with the enforce-
ment of norms thought of as unproblematic, like the prohibition of do-
mestic violence.
In labor law, issues of formal inequality were worked out over the eigh-
teenth and the first half of the nineteenth centuries," so that the preoc-
cupation of theorists of the field, whether Marxist, progressive, or conser-
vative, was how to analyze and respond to the tendencies coward inequality
within a regime of formally equally legal rights. The cls critique was, in
a sense, third generation, following first the Liberal critique of formal labor
hierarchy and, second, the liberal critique of the conservative version of
equal rights for labor and capital.
Feminist reformers through the 1970S initially focused on completing
the Liberal critique of de jure gender inequality. They had to work out a
liberal feminist approach to issues like special treatment for women as
child bearers within an only recently established regime of formal equality,
and devise new practical remedies for male abuse of women. The radical
feminist approaches to legal issues I am about to describe, like the post
civil rights movement race critiques, can be seen as responses to the re-
alization that neither the establishment of formal legal equality, nor its
fine tuning, nor supplementing it with affirmative action would "solve"
the problem of gender oppression.
The competitive and cooperative relations between men and women
occur in a variety of domains, each with its own sociology and its own set
of legal background rules. There are the domestic sector, the "street," and
the workplace, to name just three. The "stakes" in the domains are dif-
ferentpower over household decisions, the division of housework, and
sexual conflict and cooperation differ markedly from competition for jobs
and salaries in the marketplace. But power translates or transfers from one
domain to another, as when the restriction of employment opportunities
reduces women's bargaining power in the home.
The distributive conflicts between men and women are played out be-
tween individuals, rather than between legally structured organizations
like labor unions, corporations, sovereign states, federal and local govern-
ments, and media "speakers." Far more than in economic relations between
social classes, we habitually attribute what happens in these face-to-face
260 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
legal regime itself are far less visible than in the labor law area, because
of the widespread conceptualization of male-female interaction as "pri-
vate." Olsen's critique39 was that this notion has the double consequence
of making law more invisible than it ought to be and of rationalizing an
antiregulatory attitude on those occasions when the background is noticed
and it seems plausible to modify it to favor women.
The trick here is analogous to, and a complex extension of, the way the
public/private distinction has functioned in the labor area. First, just as
the economy is private in relation to the state, the family is private in
relation to the economy. Second, just as the privateness of the economy
vis-à-vis the state justifies leaving worker-employer bargains to the out-
comes conditioned by the invisible background rules, so the privateness
of the family vis-à-vis the market justifies leaving male-female bargaining
to the outcomes conditioned by the even less egalitarian background re-
gime of gender law.
On the basis of this figure/ground reversal, combined with the legal
realist/institutionalist analysis of the economy, the gender critique devel-
oped the notion that the legal regime constitutes the subjects who bargain
and consent within it. The regime (along with myriad other cultural prac-
tices) creates them as people who will consent to the reproduction of me-
galitarian relations that it seems merely to reflect.4° Just as liberal labor
law after the NLRA developed in directions that made workers passive,
according to the cls critique, the actual administration of the background
rules governing violence against women, and the property regime that
keeps them economically weak, has the effect of forming them as characters
who will accept and even embrace subordinate status. The rules push them
to understand themselves to be heterosexual, monogamous, and maternal
beings, as a consequence of the very nature of womanhood)1
With some notable exceptions, doctrinal analysisthe demonstration
of the incoherence of legal conceptions like marriage, custody, and con-
sentplays a less important role in this critique than in that of labor law,
internacional law, or First Amendment law.2 I think it plausible that, as
a matter of fact, the (mis)understanding of adjudication and legal correct-
ness, the denial of the ideological in legal work, play less important roles
in the reproduction of gender oppression than in other kinds of oppression.
It was rather the critique of rights43 (the subject of the next chapter) and
of identity,44 both important parallels to the critique of adjudication, that
developed here with particular clarity, as did the technique of analyzing
opinions as texts promoting or instantiating cultural conceptions.4S
262 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
The development of parallel critiques in field after field went along with
the development of a large number of concrete proposals for judicial or
legislative change in the particular legal rules that made up the structures
we were critiquing. We were influenced (although not at all required) by
our mode of critique to make policy proposals with a particular kind of
structure. I would describe it as follows. Many cts proposals focused on
changing the background rules so as to change the distribution of power,
as a means to redistributing the good things of life. By contrast, the main-
stream liberal emphasis tended to be more on regulating unequal rela-
tionships by the two techniques of prohibiting discrimination and requir-
ing particular substantive contents.
Typical "empowering" as opposed to "regulating" solutions are the crea-
tion of limited equity cooperative housing,48 liberalizing the battered
woman's right of self-defense49 and establishing a community-based shelter
system,'° changing labor law rules to promote worker self-organization,
worker participation in management decisions, and worker ownership,I
creating new tort remedies for sexual and racial harassment and hate
speech'2 and for employer abuse in the workplace," and modifying home
rule to give inner cities a voice in suburban decision making.4 But the
line is not a clear one. In the many cases where the critics favored regu-
lation, it was often, as in the case of the warranty of habitability," with a
view to the local, strategic use of new legal tools to pursue distributive
ends.
Shifting power balances by changing background rules also fit well with
the project, inherited from 196os radicalism, of equalizing distribution
among groups, conceived as crosscutting and intersectional, rather than
of, say, guaranteeing equality of opportunity to individuals without regard
to their race or class or gender. Typical policy proposals were "race con-
scious" or "gender conscious," or "class conscious," at the same time that
The Legitimation Effect 263
There were many other differences between the cls style of delegitimating
critique of liberalism and the progressive-era style directed against con-
servatism. I've already mentioned the contrast between radical and liberal
reformist political motivations, the different methodologies of internal cri-
tique, and the emphasis on the social construction of identity through law.
CIs has been committed to appropriating whatever is useful in neo-Marx-
ism, particularly its Gramscian strand, and aims to synthesize it with the
progressive/realist tradition of legal analysis that had treated the more
orthodox Marxism of its time as an "other." The various non-Marxist Con-
tinental European intellectual currents that influenced the progressives,
from structuralism/poststructuralism through psychoanalysis, had evolved
a long way in a generally irrationalist direction by the time the crits tapped
into them.
But perhaps more striking than any of these is the contrast between the
relatively unified progressive commitment to reconstruction by the appli-
cation of pragmatism to law and the wild diversity of attitudes toward
reconstruction within cis, within critical race theory, and within feminist
legal theory. My summaries above suppressed these differences of sub-
stance, strategy, and tone. The remaining chapters of this book bring them
to the fore.
II
Adjudication in Social Theory
since the turn of the century. And the grand tradition imagines legal
regulation as institutionally effective in a manner belied by realist skep-
ticism about the correspondence between the law in books and the law in
action.
The grand tradition's alleged misappreciation of law seems important
because law is such an important element in the tradition. But it is still
an open question how the incorporation of one or another version of post-
realism might alter the Weberian and Marxist theories. And it is another
open question to what extent we can usefully deploy elements from those
theories to explain judicial behavior and assess its effects, once judging is
seen as underdetermined by logic and incoherent as policy.
The approach I've outlined, looked at as postrealist social theory, has
three components: the distributivist analysis of the ideological stakes of
formal law making, the notion that adjudication is a forum of ideology,
and the theory of denied strategic behavior in legal interpretation. The
moderation, empowerment, and legitimation effects of adjudication are
supposed to be plausible consequences flowing from the combination of
these elements in the context of an ideologically divided society.
What shall I call this theory? Not the "cnt" theory, because although I
tried in the last chapter to assimilate a large amount of cnt work to it
(and could have assimilated a lot more in similar fashion), there is no
consensus on these issues, as we'll see in this chapter, among people who
have identified themselves as cnits. It is, likewise, only one among a num-
ber of possible left/modernist-postmodernist theories. I'll call it the "Pink
Theory," or PT.
The PT developed in the face of and in continuous response to two
critiques. The first, the "skeptic's critique," has been that the PT overes-
timates the social significance of appellate adjudication. The second, the
"systematizer's critique," is that the PT underestimates its significance.
Both skeptics and systematizers draw on elements from legal realism, em-
pirical and functionalist sociology, neo-Marxism, American populism, crit-
ical theory, and other elements too numerous to figure out.
The skeptic's critique is that the Pink Theory overestimates the signif-
icance of appellate opinions, because the formal law they produce has little
practical importance and their ideological productionshave little audience.
The systematizer's critique is that the theory underestimates the extent to
which the specifics of judge-made formal law can be explained as respon-
sive to and legitimating of either the needs of a market system or the
structural requirements of particular stages of capitalist development.
266 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
In the 1980s, American legal sociologists who had long since abandoned
dispute-resolution functionalism had a biting critique of the cls preoccu-
pation with appellate opinions and other "mandarin materials." This attack
came first from older "law and society" mainstreamers, like Lawrence Fried-
man, and then from the Amherst Seminar, which loosely grouped left "law
and society" people, left legal anthropologists, and sociologists working in
the European critical tradition.
Both critiques had a strong tone of disciplinary ressentiment (even the
sociological mainstreamers seemed emotionally invested in seeing them-
selves as marginal and disrespected both in legal academia and in academic
sociology). The mainstreamers claimed that if you didn't do empirical
research, and do it in something more recognizably "the field" than a law
library, you certainly weren't a sociologist, or a "real" progressive, and most
likely were engaged in reasserting the social power of "law professors"
(sneer quotes) through Byzantine doctrinal discussions that we all know
have nothing to do with what happens in the real world.
The leftists, by contrast, had neither a scientistic idea of the empirical
nor a prejudice against the discursive in general. But they were very much
in agreement that the sociology of law should focus on what happens in
the field, defined as lower-level, "action-end" dispute resolution insti-
tutions. They also agreed with the mainstreamers that, as Susan Silbey
put it,
Remember that the Pink Theory is committed to the idea that judges
dispose important stakes of ideologized group conflict through choices of
interpretation of many different kinds of rules, ranging from the regulation
of abortion to the regulation of truck weight on interstate highways. It
makes no more sense to ignore them as rule makers, on the ground that
particular rules they make don't get enforced, than it would to ignore the
legislative process because the same is true of statutes.
The claim that the rules made by appellate courts are more rather than
less important than people think is based on the idea that people often
fail to advert, in ideological conflicts, to the ways legal rules function as
rules of the game, more or less effectively but invisibly altering the out-
comes from those that would occur if different rules were in force. The
point is not that the rules are more widely effective on conduct than you
would think. It is that the legal background rules, to whatever degree they
may be effective, are habitually left out of our causal hypotheses about
hierarchy and alienationthis is the whole point of the figure/ground
reversals I described in the last chapter.
Perhaps the rub is there. If the sociologists were claiming that the rules
are so thoroughly ineffective that they cannot be attributed causal force in
constituting the relative bargaining power of competing groups, then they
would be striking to the heart of the PT. But it turns out on closer ex-
amination that they never go that far, though their traditional rhetoric
sometimes suggests they'd like to. Here, for example, is a summary of the
enormously valuable work of the Wisconsin school on contract law in
action:
[The] focus on business behavior quickly reveals an important insight-
that contract law doctrine worked out by appellate courts is insignificant
in its impact for many reasons, among them: the sanctions provided by
contract law are too weak to deter breach; weak or strong, damage sanc-
tions are usually irrelevant because the value of continuing relationships
or of good reputation leads to peaceful adjustment; even when relation-
ships are over, the cost of litigation makes resort to law unlikely; and
where significant interests conflict, regulation is almost never left to the
common law, but rather administrative regimes are put in place (e.g.
labor law or insurance). In sum, appellate contracts cases commonly in-
volve "atypical or freak" transactions and "tag ends of problems nobody
cares enough about to regulate in some other way."
begin with, when "significant interests conflict," that is, where we expect
ideologized group conflict and where "administrative regimes are put in
place," judges will constantly make decisions about those regimes that
dispose ideological stakes. Indeed, I asserted in the last chapter that a major
locus of the legitimation effect is the judicial oversight of labor law.
Second, even though "the cost of litigation makes resort to law unlikely,"
the rules often exert a large enough influence on bargaining, "in their
shadow,"6 so that the judges' choices among the possibilities dispose sig-
nificant ideological stakes. Likewise, that people ¡n long-term relationships
feel intense pressure to settle their conflicts without litigation most defi-
nitely does not mean that law is irrelevant to the outcome. The entities
that have the long-term relationships and settle disputes within them get
their particular form under legal influence, and all the participants make
calculations of their alternatives, in deciding what to settle for, about what
they will be able to do if settlement proves impossible.7
Rather than tending to show that appellate adjudication in general is
"insignificant in its impact," this research suggests, and is patently in-
tended to suggest, a quite different but important critical conclusion. From
the perspective of the law school contracts classroom, it might appear that
contract law requires people to be fair to one another. But many judge-
made rules of contract law that purport to give weak parties protections
against strong parties turn out to be illusory in practice.8 The point is not
that appellate law is intrinsically ineffective, but that judges have chosen
to make rules for weak parties that look better on paper than they do in
practice.
Even a savvy student (and a fortiori a cloistered professor) might reach
a quite wrong conclusion about how much strong parties can "get away
with" in the real world, if he or she relied on appellate opinions. Worse,
there are legal reforms that might bring the law in action much closer to
the law in books, effectively restructuring power in favor of weaker parties.
But the illusion that formal law has already taken care of the problem is
a factor contributing to both judicial and legislative inaction.9 Note that
a similar point applies to legislatures, which not uncommonly pass statutes
that seem on their face to give one interest or another a lot more than it
will receive in practice.'°
Like legislatures, appellate courts operate under the constraints imposed
by the plausible limits of enforcement within the existing system. The
New Jersey Supreme Court was no more able to simply impose its "fair-
share" requirement for affordable housing in the suburbs than the U.S.
Supreme Court was able to abolish the third degree by handing down the
Adjudication in Social Theory 27 i
Most of the "early" crits claimed only that legal discourse was "effective"
for the legal intelligentsia itself, and for the broader educated elite that
takes legal discourse seriously.' This limited claim seemed plausible to us
because we had recently been law students struggling against the puz-
zlingly seductive influence of the elite understanding. In this respect, we
adopted more a Gramscian'6 or Althusserian'7 than a Weberian18 approach,
treating appellate courts as an "ideological state apparatus" that produces
one of a plethora of legitimating discourses, such as those of the educational
system and the media, each with a different audience and different subject
matters.
The Pink Theory can therefore embrace skepticism about the size of the
Adjndication in Socia! Theory 273
audience for appellate opinions, and agree that for some audiences, for
example for people of color, as Kimberle Crenshaw argued,2° the law may
be first and foremost the deployment of state force (empirical studies
awaited), while the content of the discourse may be of little or no persuasive
importance. This insight doesn't make the moderation effect, for exam-
plethe hypothetical reduction of the ability of ideologically organized
majorities to bring about significant regime change through the legislative
processless plausible.
The effect depends on the idea that difference splitting, bipolar, and
hostile activist judges have enormous interstitial power to "cool out" the
legislature's regime-changing abstractions, through interpretation. The ef-
fect occurs within the elite group that legislates and judges. lt is a con-
sequence of their understandings and arrangements, not of those of the
people they govern.
The same is true of the empowerment effect. Denied ideology in judicial
law making means that fractions of ideological intelligentsias, and each
intelligentsia as a whole, can get things through the judicial process that
they imagine they couldn't get through electoral politics. Liberals get
Brown y. Board of Education; conservatives get a cutback of affirmative
action. 1f we had both legislative supremacy (no judicial review) and a
consistent practice of legislative oversight of judicial rule making, the
result, according to the hypothesis, would be outcomes less favorable to
the fractions, and perhaps outcomes fulfilling the intelligentsias' symmet-
rically opposed fears of the masses. The empowerment effect appears to be
part of the complex game through which political elites distribute power
and vetoes on power among themselves. It can operate regardless of what,
if anything, the masses know of appellate opinions.
One might even speculate that in so much as moderation and empow-
erment effects favor the interests of moderate liberal and conservative elites
at the expense of masses, they work better when the masses remain in
blissful ignorance of government by judiciary. In this interpretation, the
"backgrounding" of judicial law making, its invisibility for the masses,
stabilizes the system, as long as the formal law that appellate courts make
achieves a modicum of impact on conduct, through criminal enforcement
and private civil actions in lower courts and through obedience and con-
version effects.
But don't legitimation effects, at least, depend directly on the existence
of an audience for appellate opinions outside the legal/political inteili-
gentsia? I defined a legitimation effect as the reinforcement of the status
274 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
We study appellate opinions because appellate judges are major law makers
in our society, on a par with legislators. We also study them in particular
because, following the hypothesis of alienated powers, their law making
is characterized, as that of legislatures is not, by a particular form of de-
nialthe denial that they are legislators.
For Silbey, "the limits of doctrine and form were carefully delineated at
the beginning of the twentieth century." For us, on the contrary, it was
not at all obvious (and still isn't) how legal discourse manages to produce
the "effect of necessity" that allows the denial of ideological content. We
ourselves were not sure just how "formalism" was wrong, or that it was
dead; we were sure that law was political but not about how it was polit-
ical. The critical part of the legal realist project seemed aborted, rather
than something finished we should move on from. It seemed more im-
portant to revive it, and keep at it, than to work at "proving" that the
United States is a society in which elite legal materials are relevant to
political and popular consciousness.
The problem was and is that the judges' claim of impartiality is partially
true, because judges are supposed to, and to a large extent do, behave
differently from legislators in choosing what rules should apply to cases.
Judges are, to a significant extent, practically "bound" by law and often,
often, often declare and apply rules that they would never vote for if they
were legislators. Judges sometimes behave in ways well described as "con-
276 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
External determination
for those law and economics scholars who think efficiency should be the
sole normative criterion in decisions about what legal rules to put in force.
Richard Posner can sharply reject the claim that legal reasoning autono-
mously determines judicial rule making in "hard cases" because he believes
that economic reasoning about the efficiency consequences of rules can and
should take its place.29
The kind of external determination that was popular with the Amherst
Seminar at the time Silbey wrote her critique was descriptive rather than
normative, and from below. The notion was that while formal legal rea-
soning is indeterminate, the ensemble of patterns of official behavior that
influence the actual patterns of social behavior is not. The key to getting
some determinacy at the level of the law in action was to introduce con-
cepts like "culture" and "practice" and, of course, to study what was "really"
going on at the "action end" of law.
Austin Sarat has suggested a conceptual framework for this kind of
effort:
Statutes and court decisions are not abstractly stated goals which could
ever govern legal or social behavior . . . This does not mean that judicial
decisions can't be examined as an influence on, let's say, police arrest
activities. Such a study would, however, ask how does one practice influ-
ence another rather than why does one depart from the other. Moreover,
such an approach allows us to investigate the extent to which the variety
of legal practices comprise a coherent whole. Here, the sociology of law
may embrace the early concerns of critical legal studies at the same time
that it insists on the importance of examining legal practice in the court-
house, the police station and the lawyer's office.3°
These more proletarian, multi-"voiced," from-the-bottom-up-analyses
were supposed to preserve the social theoretical ideal of determination
while purging it of "idealism" and concomitant elite focus. In the European
context, in the form of the theory of "legal pluralism," they also make
possible a challenge to the combination of extreme positivism, formalism,
and focus on national state actors that have characterized the civil law
tradition.3' But neither the American nor the European version has yet
developed into a general theory that could rival the dominant left mode
of arguing descriptive external determination from above,
This mode proposes descriptive external determination from above by
the interests of particular social classes, or by the needs or the necessary
structure of a market economy or a phase of capitalist economic develop-
ment. Here the indeterminacy of legal reasoning is remedied by the de-
Adjudication in Social Theory 279
terminacy of the "big picture," which judges are translating into law all
the time they are pretending to he following their autonomous, internally
determined reasoning procedures. This approach is the subject of the next
section.
The Pink Theory differs from all the variants of external determination
that I am aware of in three respects. First, it does not assert that "law" "is"
globally indeterminate, but only that sometimes judges do legal work on
the legal materials in pursuance of strategies that are well understood as
ideological projects, and that this work often inflects outcomes in ways
that dispose high ideological stakes. Second, the accumulation of such
choices over time produces distributive outcomes radically different from
those that would have been produced by a different series of judicial choices
under conditions of (local) indeterminacy. Third, it seems a plausible hy-
pothesis that the making of this law through adjudication, with concom-
itant denial of ideological influence, generates moderation, empowerment,
and legitimation effects (all mediated by the vagaries of enforcement and
the inattentiveness of the audience).
I propose this model in part for political reasons: as a leftist, I am
interested in questions of distributive justice between groups. I think the
actual distribution is unfair, whereas many think it fair or unfair in ways
that can be remedied only by greater unfairness. This analysis is supposed
to show that the current unfairness is in part produced through judicial
rule making that was neither just "law application" nor a rational response
to the needs or structure of the economy. If we changed the rules by making
choices different from the ones the judges have made, maybe we could
achieve greater distributive justice among groups without the dire con-
sequences that we fear from measures like revolution or gigantic tax-and-
spend programs.
Thus the PT emerged both from a critique of legal reasoning and from
a critique of the notion that there is an external, determinable logic of the
economy, its needs or functions or stages, that could plausibly explain
judicial rule making once we abandon belief that judges are constrained
by the norm of coherence. There are two important points here. In the
rationalism/irrationalism debate, we used minimalist internal critique to
undermine the systematizer's notion of the logic of the economic base. In
doing so, we were trying to use American postrealist legal technique to
contribute (albeit destructively) to the grand sociological tradition. At the
same time, we adapted from neo-Marxism a much chastened (and, we
hoped, much improved) version of the notion that legal reasoning performs
280 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
legitimating functions, the version presented in the last chapter. The rest
of this chapter elaborates this complex relation between the Pink Theory
and Marxism.
The notion went something like this: "We have this system as a matter of
fact (of science). Having this system necessarily (because of science) re-
quires that you have these conditions that according to our (nonscientific
ethical system) are injustices. This knowledge is nonideological."
lt was here that disagreement arose. Systematizers argued, plausibly,
that the content and evolution of the legal system were in some sense
responsive to the content and evolution of "society," so that law could be
understood as a dependent variable. They also argued, plausibly, that the
legal system performed a "function" in the social system, contributing to
its content and evolution as well as reflecting it.
In the late 1970s, there were many extant versions of system among
which to choose, including neo-Marxism, Weber's theory of law in capi-
talism, Parsonian structural/functionalism, and Habermas's theory of com-
municative action. Perhaps the single most common attitude was "post"
in relation to these quite elaborated theories, but influenced by all of them.
It seemed obvious that American society had gone through a series of
stages, from an agrarian, supposedly individualistic, yeoman society,
through industrialization, urbanization, and class stratification, toward a
highly "interdependent" welfare capitalism dominated by large corpora-
tions and state bureaucracies. It seemed plausible that the legal system
had responded to different needs and performed different functions in each
period."
The rationalism/irrationalism debate was about whether this intuition
could be supported through legal scholarship. It focused on a particular
version of system, what I will call the "neo-Marxist theory of law in cap-
italism," not because the participants were Marxists (a few had been), but
because this theory seemed the most coherent and the most leftist. The
critique applied a fortiori to the weaker versions of the needs and functions
thesis, which I will describe in a moment.
rules of the legal system put capitalism into effect according to a deter-
minate logic of the commodity)
According to the theory, what is wrong with the system (injustice and
misery) is a consequence of a basic, pervasive structure of the system,
namely, its commitment to private property. Liberal reformism offers mere
Band-Aids, overestimating what can be done with its moderate methods,
while at the same time understating how bad things are. The positive
social theoretical analysis is therefore leftist in the sense that it argues that
only "radical" change can get us where "we" want to go. The only way to
bring about "real" systemic change would be to have a system based on a
different concept, and that requires the rulership of a different class.
The critique of legal reasoning, whether in its legal realist or its cls version,
at first seems to fit into this project, indeed to contribute mightily to it.
It does so by extending the "false-necessity" critique of the "laws of eco-
nomics" to the rules of the legal system. This extension makes it possible
to incorporate a logic of legal change into the story of capitalism. If law
is indeterminate in its details, as well as at the level of the choice of an
abstract form, we can do a political analysis of judging and of the vast
private law domain left to judges (on the Continent, left to "legal scien-
tists").
Judicial law making practice can be fitted into the general left political
analysis by making judges part of the strategic elite, furthering class in-
terests or working out the logic of the system, rather than merely admin-
istering ("applying") capitalist legal concepts. We can interpret this work
as that of constantly adjusting the whole corpus of specific legal rules to
fit the interests of dominant classes in the successive stages of competitive
and monopoly capitalist development. Competitive market capitalism has
one set of legal needs, but monopoly capitalism has another. Judges make
the needed changes through strategic manipulation of indeterminacy while
maintaining the illusion of legal compulsion.
There is no necessary tension between the more "instrumental" and the
more "structural" theories. Each stage (structure) might produce and be
produced by a capitalist class whose instrumental interests correspond to
that stage's development. The class will then appoint judges who choose,
among the possible meanings of an indeterminate legal corpus, those
284 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
meanings (rules) that will promote the development of the stage and its
dominant class.
there were many legal regimes that might have done the job. These re-
gimes would have produced wildly different distributive outcomes and
indeed wildly different economies)'
The second internal critique was of the distinction between capitalist
and socialist law. Once it is acknowledged that legal rules define the "base,"
we can ask about the "logic" of these rules. (i) Hohfeld's analysis shows
that "property is just a bundle of rights," with no "core"; there are an
infinite variety of particular private law regimes each of which will produce
a different allocation of resources and distribution of income, all fully
consistent with any coherent definition of private property. (2) Socialism,
in the form of collectivist, altruist, egalitarian values, is already present in
the capitalist legal system, and just as much within the supposedly Liberal
individualist core of private law doctrine as in the social democratic reg-
ulatory add-ons.'°
() Modern mixed capitalist legal regimes have no overall system logic:
each is an internally inconsistent hodgepodge of "social" and "individual"
elements with conflicting valences." This was also true oí communist
regimes, which couldn't operate the vague abstraction "state ownership of
the means of production" without elaborating internal rules of decentral-
ization that functioned the way the law of the commodity functions in
capitalism.'2 (4) Rather than a distinction between reform and revolution,
there is a mushy continuum between collectivism and anarchism, hierarchy
and equality. There aren't even any privileges among places to struggle
("bourgeois dinner parties are sites of resistance," and SO on)."
The third critical move was to argue that the proponents oía (rationalist)
left legal theory, whether in the neo-Marxist or the progressive historical
mode, couldn't produce a logic of economic development that was any
more than an ex post description of the consequences of particular ruling-
class legal strategies. Is there a way of using the insight that different
possible legal rules lead to different economic outcomes, to show that a
given legal regime promotes capital accumulation (economic growth, pro-
duction), or some set of class interests?
Since the systematizers didn't have much in the way of an actual theory
of the logic of capital, or the needs of monopoly capital, or whatever (I say
this respectfullyafter all, we irrationalists didn't have one either), a good
part of the debate took place in the critique of efficiency theory, a closely
analogous hut right-wing form. The critical line vas that efficiency, as
defined by economists, just doesn't produce clear answers to the question
288 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
what rules will maximize consumer welfare, let alone a dynamic theory of
welfare over time.'4
It followed that the left-wingers couldn't employ the concept oía "sub-
sidy" through legal rules to organize a theory about how a "dominant class"
can use the legal system to promote its interests, or economic growth, or
capital accumulation. The problem was the absence oía neutral economic
baseline (which would replace a now impossible neutral legal baseline).
There was no point from which to measure the subsidy.
It might be true that the actual legal actors involved all believed that a
particular rule or rule change was necessary (or just desirable) to protect
class interest or the accumulation process. And it was often possible to
show plausibly and concretely how particular interests might gain or lose
from a particular rule choice." But the extant attempts to demonstrate
the connection between legal and economic variables at the much more
abstract level of "capitalism" or economic growth were either no good
internally (see the critique of cost-benefit analysis), ignored counterinst-
ances (where the wrong class adopted the legal program in question, or
the right class adopted the wrong legal program), or were open to the
formulation oían equally plausible but ignored counterstory (in which the
economic effects of legal change were plausibly predicted to be just the
reverse of those asserted).'6 All the systematizers could show was ruling-
class strategies, adopted under conditions of practical and analytic uncer-
tainty, justified by phony appeals to economics, and then critiqued by the
left using equally phony but politically opposite appeals to economics.
As in the critique of legal reasoning, the strictly internal critique was
different from the "incompleteness" critique that showed that you could
construct alternative, equally plausible arguments for opposite results.
"Yeah, but that rule change might have hurt the ruling class; that rule
might have impeded capital formation, indeed probably actually did hurt
and impede, for all you can show, given this alternative version of the
facts."
This kind of argument, as we saw in Chapter 4, is less logically tight
than strictly internal critique. It leaves the field open to determined show-
ings that in fact the effects were indeed x ory, and to endless attempts to
qualify the systematizers' claim just enough to meet the critique without
losing all scientific power (see the debate about "tilt" as a substitute for
the "logic of capital")." There's no way to prove that someone won't soon
come up with a totalizing theory that works.
But until someone does comes up with one, the Pink Theory rejects
Adjudication in Social Theory 289
After the theory of "determination in the final instance," the second most
important element in the neo-Marxist theory of law is the theory of legit-
imation through ideology. This is an important element in the "output"
side of the theory, the part about how law affects society (external deter-
mination being the "input" side). As I mentioned above, the Pink Theory
is a variant, a chastened version of this theory.
Writers in the Marxist tradition, such as Georg Lukacs,'8 Gramsci,'9
and Alrhusser,6° and also Jürgen Habermas,6' have used the term "ideol-
ogy" to describe what I have been calling "Liberalism" (belief in majority
rule, rights, the rule of law, and some version of a regulated market econ-
omy with safety nets).'2 In the classic analyses, it is ideology in this sense
that legitimates. This usage is closely linked to the notion of a logic of
the economic formation and is quite different from the use of the term in
the Pink Theory.
To identify ideology with American liberalism and conservatism is to
adopt a different definition of the word, and a weaker theory, than Marxists
have typically wanted to develop and deploy in their accounts of capital-
ism. A strong version of ideology, which I will call "Ideology" (capitalized),
has four characteristics.
Ideology is an interpretation of reality that is either consciously or
unconsciously shared across the whole social and political spectrum; spe-
cifically, it is something "deeper" than the "surface" disagreements that
mainly preoccupy actors in those areas. Thus a common belief in God
underlies religious sectarian conflict, which looks to the participants to be
a matter of salvation and damnation. Thus a common belief in the natu-
ralness, justice, and efficiency of private property in the means of produc-
tion underlies political conflicts between liberals and conservatives that
seem to them to involve basic questions of social justice.
There is something behind Ideology, something that is not itself
Ideology, that causes or explains it, and thereby indirectly causes or ex-
plains Ideology's effects. The something is the forces and relations of pro-
duction, or the needs of capitalism at a particular stage, "the base." The
play of intense surface conflicts within Ideology reflects divisions in the
base. While there may be feedback from the ideological to the material
domain, a strong version of Ideology privileges the material. "In the final
instance," the base trumps the superstructure, or the theory is not a strong
one.
Adjudication in Social Theory 291
shared across the political spectrum, like Ideology in the Marxist analysis.
Moreover, I have been arguing that attempts to establish the coherence of
the Liberal conception, to show that adjudication is or plausibly could be
nonideological, have failed. The denial of ideology in adjudication is a
response to the incoherence, so that we are dealing with something closely
resembling "false consciousness."
In the Pink Theory, adjudication disposes of the stakes of ideologized
group conflict by defining the rules of the game, and the presence of
ideological motives in adjudication is mystified by its representation as
neutral, impersonal, or objective, so that judges and their audience are in
bad faith (rather than simply deluded). Contrasting this kind of regime
with the counterfactual situation of effective legislative control of all law
making generates the moderation, empowerment, and legitimation effects.
For this reason, the Pink Theory belongs to the same family as the classic
Feuerbach/Marx theory of alienated powers, as well as to the larger family
of Marxist ideology theories.
Moderation and empowerment effects have to do with the evolution of
liberal/conservative conflict within a regime where there is a lot of mys-
tified judicial law making. This part of the analysis uses the non-Marxist
notion of ideology, in the sense of liberal and conservative universalization
projects, and suggests how the Ideology of Liberal legalism affects their
fates as political movements.
In the legitimation effect, the mystified discourse of judge-made law in
general, and numerous specific discourses explaining particular legal re-
gimes, contribute to the naturalization of existing social relations of dom-
ination (hierarchy, inequality, alienation). Both the general and the more
particular discourses contribute to naturalization by making it appear that
background rules that are "really" the product of judicial ideological strat-
egy flow instead from merely technical reasoning.
Naturalization is an Ideological effect because proposals for change that
are outside the liberal/conservative "mainstream," as it defines itself in
relation to the "extremes," seem, to the participants in political culture,
less plausible than they would in a more transparent system. (By "trans-
parent" I mean less mystified by the denial of the ideological in adjudi-
cation.) In other words, these nonmainstream alternatives are "cogni-
tively"6' excluded from consideration as impractical, rather than excluded
on the basis of consideration on the merits. (By "on the merits" I mean
without the mystif,ing effects of bad faith and denial.)
Adjudication in Social Theory 293
The Pink Theory differs from the Marxist analysis in the following
respects.
Lau'c influence on society: What is legitimated is the status quo, rather
than capitalism or the relations of production understood as a structure.
The status quo is an incoherent hodgepodge of heterogeneous elements,
without a system logic. Whatever it may be at any given moment, that's
what gets naturalized by the denial of the ideological element in judicial
law making. In this respect, the analysis is closer to populism than to
Marxism. lt points to the distortion of the results that would occur under
a more transparent law-making process, rather than to necessary functions
of the legal order in a particular kind of regime.
Societ)'s influence on lau': Neither liberalism and conservatism, nor Libera!
legalism (the rule of law with denial of the ideological in adjudication), is
caused or explained by the deep structure of capitalism. To repeat, the PT
denies that any such deep structure has been plausibly demonstrated. Lib-
eral legalism serves the status quo, not a deep structure, but is derived
from it only in this sense: I allege that liberal and conservative judges and
legal theorists share an apologetic motive that influences their descriptions
of adjudication in general and of legal regimes in particular.
That motive is to defend the status quo against the extremes. Denial
and bad faith with respect to the ideological in adjudication are in part a
half-conscious strategy designed to represent judicial institutions and par-
ticular legal regimes as internally coherent and also just, when they are
better understood as the opposite (from my heavily ideological, "extreme"
perspective, of course).
In the article on Blackstone's Conirnentaries that I mentioned in Chapter
3, 1 characterized Blackstone's proto-Liberal project as apologetic in this
sense but also as "utopian." I would say the same about modern Liberal
legalism. The notion of utopian aspiration is implicit in what I have been
calling the "abstract normative element" in liberalism and conservatism,
that is, in their commitment to social transformation in the direction
indicated, however ambiguously, by the body of Liberal principles and
texts (rights, majority rule, the rule of law, a regulated market with safety
nets, Judeo-Christian morality).
The idea of apology is the dark side of the idea that the ideologists are
committed to the interests of the groups they represent. An ideology, seen
as the universalization project oían intelligentsia, "mediates" between the
utopian (abstract normative) element and the apologetic (interest-based)
294 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
The irrationalist attack on the systematizers' left theory doubled the use
of the minimalist internal critique of legal reasoning: law is plastic in the
sense chat it could have been shaped in two or more ways; but che theories
that are supposed to give definition to a plastic legal body fall to the very
same internal critique that had loosened law up in the first place. The
internal critique gets applied, directly when the theory includes legal con-
cepts, and by analogy when it doesn't, to the implicit or explicit theories
of' the logic of capital that were supposed to explain law. Internal critique
becomes a colonizing force ¡n its own right, rather than a condition per-
mitting colonization of legal by economic theory.
This kind of viral progression is something we will see happening over
and over again in the evolution of the theory debate. Right from the start,
it produced a political critique: indeterminacy theory was "going roo far"
if it deprived us of our ability to produce not just "covering laws" but any
meaningful generalizations at all. Internal critique would become a de-
mobilizing force if its argument was that history was just one damn thing
after another. Moreover, it tended to support interest-group pluralism, in
which groups have strategies that they pursue within a "process" frame-
work, with no overall logic of the system. Interest-group pluralism was
associated with legitimation of the status quo by "rules of the game" and
was therefore clearly a bad thing.
The issue didn't go away and still hasn't. The code words are: "What
we need is a general theory. You can't beat something with nothing. lt's
easy to critiquethe hard part is to create a theory. The critical project is
finished; now it's time for reconstruction." The danger of sliding into
liberalism or pluralism, the loss of the sense that theory can orient practice,
and the fear of the demobilizing effect of indeterminacy, contextualism,
complexity, and contradiction, are still major themes of discussion. So is
the idea that the critique "proved too much" and couldn't be right, because
ir would make all knowledge impossible (see Chapter 14).
Critics of cls from che right have exulted in the "lack of" or "failure to
develop" a general cls theory,TM for much the same reason that some cls
people themselves have lamented it. "Outsiders" (not American legal ac-
296 CONSEQUENCES OF ADJUDICATION
Post Rights
12
LTp to now, the critique of adjudication has been designed to make way
for one kind of reconstructive project or another. Illegal reasoning is
frequently indeterminate, and when determinate represents nothing more
than earlier answers to open questions by those who happened to have the
rule-making power, then extralegal normative commitments are inevitably
part of law. So we can argue for "correct" normative commitments.
This is the third part of the Marx/Feuerbach model of ideology-critique.
The revelation of political bias behind a mystifying facade is a prelude to
putting in judges who will "do the right thing." Doing the right thing
means having normative projects that are better than those currently em-
bedded in the law and better chan those oí current judges.
Until World War Il, there were two main left reconstructive projects
in the United States. One was socialism, meaning public ownership of the
means of production, or the more or less complete abolition of the markets
for labor and products. The other was the "reform" program of recon-
structing the market and also influencing it, by a combination of structural
changes (empowering labor unions), fiscal policy (progressive taxation),
welfare programs, and regulation of just about everything.
Both of these groups might have found ultimate justification in ideas
like freedom or human rights, but they were strongly predisposed to un-
derstand outcomes for unfortunate people as the consequence of a failiae
of planning. That is, of a failure to properly understand the social totality
and intervene to shape it from the center to make outcomes correspond to
what the collective wanted, whether the collective was "the working class"
or "the American people." (There were exceptions: the rights of labor versus
the rights of capital rhetoric in labor disputes at the turn of the century,
women's rights). The counterprogram of the American right was usually
299
300 POST RIGHTS
The left intelligentsia has not always been organized this way. Although
the current liberal project has its "origin" in the fifties, during the 196os
the left intelligentsia grew exponentially and then split sharply and re-
peatedly over such questions as direct action versus legal strategies, revo-
lutionary communism versus liberalism, black nationalism versus integra-
tionism, separatist feminism versus "sleeping with the enemy." In each of
these splits, one subelement was different attitudes toward rights and
rights rhetoric, associated with different degrees of "radicalism," as we
defined ir then, meaning different beliefs about how great and possibly
even violent the changes would have to be before anything was "really"
different.
The political radicals' critique of rights had little to do with the kind
of internal critique oí legal reasoning I have been describing. Indeed, they
leaned toward external, economy-based, race-based, or gender-based theory
(consider Shulamith Firestone and Eldridge Cleaver). The political radicals
also failed or were defeated or seif-destructed, however you want to look
at it. In the 1970S and 1980s, the left intelligentsia was much as it had
been in the early 96os, with a small radical fringe and a giant liberal
r
Perhaps the biggest change from the 1950S and early 1960s was that
the white male working class no longer played a significant role in left
thinking. White male left liberals and radicals saw themselves as deserted
or betrayed by that class, had lost their faith in it, or had never identified
with it. For most left political activists, the straight white male working
class was, at worst, the core of the enemy camp and, at best, the necessary
object of conversion.
The hopeful version of the situation of the new New Left is neatly put by
Corne! West, who asserts the existence of an "inchoate, scattered yet gath-
ering progressive movement that is emerging across the American land-
scape. This gathering now lacks both the vital moral vocabulary and the
focused leadership that can constitute and sustain it. Yet it will be rooted
ultimately in current activities by people of color, by labor and ecological
groups, by women, by homosexuals."
The different levels of the left intelligentsia relevant to us herenamely,
fancy legal theorists, law reform litigators and organizersreorganized
around or persisted in rights discourse and successfully reinterpreted what
had happened in the 196os. They remembered it as a triumph, in the civil
rights, women's and antiwar movements, of constitutional rights, repre-
senting the best instincts and true ideals of the American people, over an
earlier regime representing a reactionary or morally torpid version of those
instincts and ideals.
What had happened, according to them, was the triumph of universal-
izing intellectuals (Martin Luther King, Gandhi), allied with civil rights
lawyers and legal services lawyers, allied with community organizers. To-
gether, they asserted, litigated, and then justified rights guaranteed in the
Constitution, against legislative and administrative regimes that denied
those rights.
The rights were usually defined in terms of equality, but equality in a
special sense. They did not involve the demand for equality in the distri-
bution of income or wealth between social classes, regions, or communities,
but rather "equal protection" for individual members of previously sub-
ordinated social groups. The rhetorical emphasis on identity and antidis-
crimination was a complex new synthesis of the "nationalist" and "inte-
grationist" strands in 196os black and women's protest movements.2
By the 1970S and 198os, there were no longer "popular movements"
Rights in American Legal Consciousness 303
aggressively raising rights claims, there were no longer federal courts will-
ing to invalidate legislation and regulations in the interests of oppressed
groups, and there was no longer the sense of the undeniable moral/philo-
sophical correctness and ineluctable coherence of left constitutional theory.
From different places within the left intelligentsia, the causal links be-
tween these three failures looked different.
There were some advantages to the new situation, as well as obvious
disadvantages. The remaining left intelligentsia was rid of the radicals who
had made their lives miserable throughout the 196os and freed of the
worrisome problem of the white male working class. The left liberals were
now the left. They could, sometimes, institutionalize themselves and de-
velop all kinds of more or less oppositional or collaborative attitudes to-
ward the mainstream, without worrying about the horrible dialectic of
"taking up the gun" or "selling out." And the left intelligentsia did sur-
vive, with a good deal more in the way of numbers and resources and ideas
than had been around in the 1950S and early 1960s.
New recruits, post-196os children, continued to trickle in, particularly
women and minority recruits to the law reform and theory intelligentsia
fragments. For many of them, the 1960s seemed a Golden Age. They had
personal memories of that time, often of formative events in their own
lives. But their memories were filtered through childish consciousness, and
there was little in them that might conflict with the rights-oriented re-
interpretation of what had happened. Its nostalgic emphasis on the im-
portance of popular movements, but suppression of intraleft division,
seemed far more plausible than the mainstream story of the 196os as the
Dark Ages.
lt is easy in retrospect to see the weaknesses of this project. But in 1980,
say, the year before Ronald Reagan took office, it was plausible, even if
the times were hard for the left. I think a lot of its strengthas an intel-
ligentsia projectderived from the combination of political correctness
(struggles of oppressed groups), legal correctness (the Constitution was law
and authoritatively demanded massive liberal reform), and philosophical
correctness (the fanciest moral philosophy supported left liberal law reform
on behalf of oppressed groups). Wow.
Against this background, the cls critique of rights (Mark Tushnct,3 Peter
Gabel,' Frances Olsen,' me6) was perverse. But it was not perverse for the
304 POST RIGHTS
reason asserted by the first-stage critics of cis, who saw only one of its
originary strandsnamely, Marx's critique of rights as individualist rather
than communist, and specifically the Marcusian critique of "repressive
tolerance." There is an undeniable genealogical connection between this
critical strand and the communist practice of denying any legal enforce-
ment oí rights against the state, in the name of the revolutionary truth
that "bourgeois civil liberties" were a reactionary or counterrevolutionary
mystification.
The initial critics of cis on this front were veterans of the wars in the
forties and fifties and then again in the late sixties and early seventies
between the communists (and other orthodox Marxists and third world
Marxist-Leninist revolutionary types) and the liberals. For these anti-
Marxists (Louis Schwartz),7 antiNew Leftists (Phil Johnson,8 the New
Republic), and post- or ex-Marxists (Straughton Lynd,9 Edward Sparer,'°
Michael Tigar")any critique of rights automatically smacked of Stalinism.
But the crits were not the radical activists of 1965 tO 1972 reemerging
as Marxist academics to pursue the old war on a new front. Though they
preserved the radicals' animus against mainstream liberalism, their cri-
tique was perverse not because it was Stalinist but because it was modernist.
It developed, with many hesitations and false steps, exactly the kind of
minimalist internal critique, leading to loss of faith, that the crits had
applied to legal reasoning.
Feminists'2 and critical race theorists,'3 who took up the critique of the
critique after the anti- and post-Marxists, saw this clearly. They objected
not on the ground of totalitarian tendency, but on the ground that rights
really did or should exist, or on the ground that it was demobilizing to
criticize them. This response was plausible because rights played more or
less exactly the same role in their post-19605 political thinking that they
played in American political thought in general.
Rights play a central role in the American mode of political discourse. The
role is only intelligible as part of the general structure of that particular
discourse. It is a presupposition of the discourse that there is a crucial
distinction between "value judgments," which are a matter of preference,
subjectivity, the arbitrary, the "philosophical ," and "factual judgments,"
or scientific, objective, or empirical judgments.
Rights in American Legal Consciousness 305
Values are supposedly subjective, facts objective. It follows that the status
of all kinds of normative assertion, including moral or utilitarian assertion,
is uneasy. Claims that something is "right" or "wrong," or that a rule will
"promote the general welfare" are conventionally understood to be on the
subjective side of the divide, so much a matter of value judgment that
they have to be arbitrary and are best settled by majority vote.
While there are many ways to account for or understand the nature of
rights, it seems to me that in American political discourse they all pre-
suppose a basic distinction between rights argument and other kinds of
normative argument. The point of an appeal to a right, the reason for
making it, is that it can't be reduced to a mere "value judgment" that one
outcome is better than another. Yet it ¡s possible to make rights arguments
about matters that fall outside the domain commonly understood as fac-
tual, that is, about political or policy questions of how the government
ought to act. In other words, rights are mediators between the domain of
pure value judgments and the domain of factual judgments.
The word "mediation" here means that reasoning from the right is un-
derstood to have properties from both sides of the divide: "value" as in
value judgment, but "reasoning" as in "logic," with the possibility of cor-
rectness. Rights reasoning, in short, allows you to be right about your
value judgments, rather than just stating "preferences," as in "1 prefer
chocolate to vanilla ice cream." The mediation is possible because rights
are understood to have two crucial properties.
First, they are "universal" in the sense that they derive from needs or
values or preferences that every person shares or ought to share. For this
reason, everyone does or ought to agree that they are desirable. This ¡s the
first aspect of rights as mediators: they follow from values but are neither
arbitrary nor subjective because they are universal.
Second, they are "factoid," in the sense that "once you acknowledge the
existence of the right, then you have to agree that its observance requires
x, y, and z." For example, everyone recognizes that the statement "be good"
is too vague to help resolve concrete conflicts, even though it is universal.
But once we have derived a right from universal needs or values, it is
understood to be possible to have a relatively objective, rational, deter-
minate discussion of how it ought to be instantiated in social or legal rules.
The two parts are equally important. It is no good to be a believer in
306 POST RIGHTS
and formed by legal argumentative practice (legal rules) and entities that
"exist" prior to and outside the constitution. For this reason, an argument
(rom constitutional rights mediates nor just between factual judgments
and value judgments, but also between legal argument (under a duty of
interpretive fidelity) and legislative argument (appealing to the political
values of the community). Once again, the word "mediation" means that
this form of argument participates in the characteristics of both sides of
the dichotomy.
On one side, the argument from constitutional rights is legal, because
it is based on one of the enacted rules of the legal system (the First Amend-
ment, say); on the other, it is normative or political, because it is in the
form of an assertion about how an outside right should be translated into
law. The advocates and judges doing constitutional rights argument ex-
ploit both the notion that adjudication proceeds according to a highly
determinate, specifically legal method of interpretive fidelity, and the no-
tion that the outside right is a universal, factoid entity from whose exis-
tence we can make powerful inferences. Their goal is to make the apparent
objectivity of rights theory dovetail perfectly with the apparent objectivity
of judicial method.'4
Once the interests of the group have been assimilated to the interests
of the whole polity by recasting them as rights, the factoid character of
rights allows the group to make its claims as claims of reason, rather than
mere preference. Since you do or at least ought to agree that everyone has
this universal right, and that reasoning from it leads ineluctably to these
particular rights, it follows that you are a knave or a fool if you don't go
along. To deny these particular rights makes you wrong, rather than just
selfish and powerful.
This general Liberal idea is available to all. In other words, both liberal
and conservative intelligentsias argue that the group interests they rep-
resent should be recognized in law by asserting that the recognition would
be an instantiation of some set of outside rights. The proposed legal rules
are not "partisan" but rather represent political beliefs and commitments
that transcend the left/right divide. Rent control is unconstitutional. Like-
wise, the liberal intelligentsia argues that its program is just the vindi-
cation of outside rights, enacted in the Constitution, against their mis-
translation in wrong legislative, administrative, and judicial decisions.
I argued above that only since the 1970S has the left in general come
to rely on rights as the principal basis for universalizing its positions.
Before the 1970s, there had always been a live controversy between Marx-
ists hostile to the whole rights formulation, social democratic progressive
planners with a universalization project based on savings from eliminating
wasteful and chaotic markets, and civil libertarians.
For the conservative ideological intelligentsia, the alternative to rights
is efficiency. An efficiency claim has many of the same mediating properties
as a rights claim: it is a value judgment that is universal (who can be
opposed to making everyone better off according to their own understand-
ing of better-offness) and factoid (efficiency arguments are nothing if not
technical and they are supposedly empirically based). But while these al-
ternatives exist, rights now bear the main burden of universalization for
both camps.
the right, so that neither side should see it as "in its favor," and that the
privileges of the intelligentsias do not seem to depend in any profound
way on belief in the nonpolitical character of judicial method.
Having thus cleared the ground, argued that American political in-
L
tions of the discourse, one sees the other as mistaken, as having agreed for
a bad reason, however much one rejoices in the success of a good claim.
Bad faith, as in the case of legal reasoning, means simultaneously af-
firming and denying to oneself the presupposed rationality of the discourse,
and of the particular demand cast in its terms. It means being conscious
of the critique of the whole enterprise, sensing the shiftiness of the sand
beneath one's feet, but plowing on "as if" everything were fine. Bad faith
can be a stable condition, as I argued at length above for the case of legal
reasoning. Or it can turn out to be unstable, resolving into loss of faith or
into renewed good faith.
experienced fact doesn't establish, for a person who has lost faith, that
closure was based on something "out there" to which the reasoning cor-
responded. It was just an experience and might have been otherwise (had
one followed another work path, for example).
As for attempts to demonstrate abstractly that legal reasoning does or
could produce closure, the extant examples within law look open either to
internal critique or to the critique of partiality by ignoring equally good
arguments on the other side. The post-faith minimalist critic finds not
that "it can't be done," but only that "it doesn't seem to have been done
yet, and I'm not holding my breath."
Loss of faith is a loss, an absence: "Once I believed that the materials
and the procedure produced the outcome, but now I experience the pro-
cedure as something I a to the materials to produce the outcome I want.
Sometimes it works and sometimes it doesn't, meaning that sometimes ¡
get the outcome I want and sometimes I don't." Loss of faith is one possible
resolution of the tension or cognitive dissonance represented by bad faith.
One abandons the strategy of denial of the ideological, or subjective, or
political, or just random element in legal reasoning. One lets go of the
convention that outcomes are the consequences of "mere" observance of
the duty of interpretive fidelity.
The loss of faith in legal reasoning is the across-the-board generalization
of a process that has gone on continuously with respect to elements within
legal thought at least since Jeremy Bentham's critique of Blackstone. Two
examples are the gradual loss of faith in the forms of action and in the
characteristic eighteenth- and nineteenth-century legal operation of "im-
plication." When faith is gone, people say things like Holmes's remark:
"You can always imply a condition. The question is why do you do it?"6
Or they write, "Much labor and ingenuity have been expended in the
attempt to find some general criterion of legal right and wrong, some
general basis of legal liability. But in vain; there is none."7
Loss of faith in legal reasoning bears a close analogy to one of the many
kinds of experience of loss of faith in God. The atheist who believes that
he or she, or "science," has disproved the existence of God is analogous to
the maximalist who believes that postmodern critical theory has proved
the indeterminacy of legal reasoning. The other kind of maximalist is like
the Catholic who becomes a Protestant, rejecting authority while contin-
uing to hold a theology. Loss of faith, by contrast, is not a theory and is
not the consequence of a theory.
I think of my own initial faith in legal reasoning as like the religion of
Rights in American Legal Consciousness 313
this chapter describes a series of contexts for the loss of faith in rights,
arranged as a kind of route for the progression of the virus. ¡ begin with
the role of rights "inside" legal reasoning, that is, with the way judges
argue about the definition and elaboration of rights that are clearly estab-
lished by positive law. Doubts about this process suggest doubts about the
constitutional rights that "straddle" the inside and the outside. And these
lead in turn to doubts about popular rights discourse and fancy rights
reconstruction projects in political philosophy. I close with an attempt to
dispel some common misunderstandings oí the nature and implications of
rights critique.
The point of closest contact between legal reasoning and rights talk occurs
when lawyers reason about inside rights. This practice is important for
rights talk because through it outside rights are "translated" into the legal
order. As we saw in the last chapter, this translation is a crucial part of the
Liberal program for a good society. Failure in the process of translation-
say, a loss of faith in the possibility of doing it while maintaining the
double mediation between factual and value judgments, and between legal
and political discoursewould be a failure for Liberal theory.
But it would pose (has already posed) another danger as well: doubt
about the coherence of legal rights reasoning at the business end, so to
speak, of the rights continuum threatens to spread "back" to constitutional
rights, which "straddle," and thence to fully outside rights. It is just such
a progression that I will suggest here.
315
316 POST RIGHTS
terest, which should be legally protected as a new right. The classic ex-
ample is the generation of the right to privacy, first by Louis Brandeis in
the private law context, then by W. O. Douglas in constitutional law.1
Another part of the mundane legal practice of rights argument is the
critique of your opponent's rights claims. The most basic technique is che
internal undoing of a rights argument by showing that it relied on a false
deduction, typically on a conceptualist overstatement of what was entailed
in the definition of the right. The right to contractual performance does
not entail the right to expectation damages.'
The upshot, when both sides are well represented, is that the advocates
confront the judge with two plausible but contradictory chains of rights
reasoning, one proceeding from the plaintiff's right and the other from the
defendant's. Yes, the employer has property rights, but the picketers have
free-speech rights. Yes, the harasser has free-speech rights, but the harassed
has a right to be free of sex discrimination in the workplace. Yes, the
landowner has the right to do whatever he wants on his land, but his
neighbor has a right to be free from unreasonable interference. And each
chain is open to an internal critique.
Sometimes the judge more or less arbitrarily endorses one side over the
other; sometimes she throws in the towel and balances. The lesson of
practice for the doubter is that the question involved cannot be resolved
without resort to policy, which in turn makes the resolution open to ideo-
logical influence. The critique of legal rights reasoning becomes just a
special case of the general critique of policy argument: once it is shown
that the case requires a balancing of conflicting rights claims, it is im-
plausible that it is the rights themselves, rather than the "subjective" or
"political" commitments of the judges, that are deciding the outcome.
Once again, the prevalent experience, first, of the manipulability of legal
rights reasoning and then of its reduction to balancing tests, doesn't pre-
clude instances in which rights reasoning produces the opposite experience
of closure. Nor does it show that outside rights don't exist. lt is just another
context for loss of faith.
The application of the critique to legal reasoning about inside rights re-
veals yet a third mediating function of rights in political culture. Within
legal discourse, rights arguments are situated midway between merely "tech-
nical" or deductive arguments about rule application, appealing to ideas
320 POST RIGHTS
like the plain meaning of words, legislative intent, stare decisis or the
"will of the parties," and "pure" policy argument. Remember that policy
arguments are understood to be inevitably present within legal argument,
but they are disfavored and marginal in status, compared to arguments
that appear more consonant with the supposedly objective character of
adjudication.
Rights arguments involve something more than the logic of the valid,
because they explain and justif rules, rather than merely apply them, but
they are less "subjective" than pure policy arguments, because of their
"factoid," half-fact/half-value character. Loss of faith, or the failure of me-
diation, occurs when we begin to see the techniques of "manipulative"
rights argument as potent enough to reduce "every," or at least any par-
ticular, rights argument to a question of balancing.
The second context for loss of faith in rights is the specific history of
balancing, or of conflict between rights, in constitutional law. I think the
attitude of political lawyers in the United States toward rights has been
profoundly influenced by this nationally specific history. As I see it, it has
four parts.
drawing the line in one place rather than another, then it would seem that
judges are less "institutionally competent" to the task than legislators.'
The realist position was that interpretive fidelity just "runs out" in many
(not all) cases, because they involve conflicts for which there is no other
resolution than balancing. In other words, the emergence of balancing was
an extension of point two of the basic minimalist critical routine: given
the internal critique of extant attempts at determinative legal reasoning,
many questions of law can be resolved only by looking at them as questions
of policy that will evoke differing responses according to one's ideology.
This extension of the critique did not necessarily produce loss of faith
in constitutional rights. The emergence of balancing occurred in an odd
and complex context. Balancing was initially liberal because, in private
law (right against right), it undermined the claim of judicial objectivity
and, in public law (right against power), it undermined the legitimacy of
the Supreme Court's protection of property rights against progressive leg-
islation. As such, it was not antirights but only antiproperty rights. At
the same time that the liberal Court was drawing most clearly the conclu-
sion that questions of economic regulation were so "legislative" that ir was
inappropriate to interfere, the liberals were gearing up for the defense of
human rights, through the Carolene Products footnote'4 Powell y. Ala-
bama,' "picketing as free speech,"6 and the flag salute cases.'7
When the Democrats gained control of the Supreme Court in the New
Deal, their legal realist appointees developed a new body of constitutional
law doctrine that glorified legislative power. The Supreme Court exploited
the gaps, conflicts, and ambiguities of legal rights doctrine, plus the power
to overrule its own decisions, to make legal reasoning a principal support
of legislative supremacy.'8 The realist critique of adjudicationthat it
often involves policy choices, which amount to value judgments that are
ideologically contestedwas an important element in the argument for
this turn.
But once the liberals were in control, and fascism and Stalinism emerged
as the threat, the realists abandoned the project of internal critique, in
favor of the more pressing task of managing the new liberal, regulatory,
interventionist state. As post-1945 legislatures turned conservative, while
liberals retained control of the judiciary, the left intelligentsia went for
324 POST RIGHTS
the adjudicatory empowerment effect. That is, it adopted the position that
the federal Constitution enacted a wide range of liberal policy preferences
and flatly prohibited a wide range of conservative policy preferences.
It is important to see that this project had two parts. One was to develop
the kind of reasoning from individual constitutional rights that liberals
had allowed a marginal survival during the period of their attack on con-
stitutionalized property rights. Faced with McCarthyism, police brutality,
and conservative gerrymandering, and positively committed to racial jus-
tice, the left liberals attacked the jurisprudence of legislative supremacy
they themselves had constructed, and became civil libertarians with a ven-
geance.
The second part was to reconstruct the theory of the judicial role, re-
pairing the damage that their parents and grandparents, or they them-
selves, had done to the mana of the Judge in the process of storming the
robing room. Though some, like W. O. Douglas, weren't able to do it
with a straight face, the liberal intelligentsia in general followed Herbert
Wechsler (neutral principles)'9 or Hugo Black (absolutes),2° according to
taste, in reaffirming the possibility of judicial neutrality and the distinc-
tion between law and politics. Here again, balancing was the key.
The initial battle was over the criminalization of the Communist Party.
Moderates and conservatives argued that because it was necessary to bal-
ance communist free-speech rights against the legislative power to protect
national security, and because the balancing process was nothing more than
the redoing of the (ideologically charged) policy decision that the legis-
lature had made in passing the statute, the judges should "defer" to the
legislature.2' In short, they used the liberal legal realist critique of judicial
activism against the left.
The left liberals answered that the First Amendment was an "absolute,"
thereby both firmly tying their position to the vindication of individual
rights against the state and establishing a basis for nonideological judicial
enforcement through adjudication.22 The conflict played out in a long
series of cases. Though the liberals won many of these cases, "absolutism"
did not survive the realist critique.23 Balancing became a paradigm for
constitutional decision in one area after another.
In the second round, the moderates and conservatives critiqued judicial
activism in the civil rights areas, producing counterrights that had to be
balanced against left liberal claims. Wechsler, in his famous article, pointed
out that white segregationists were asserting their right of free association
with just as much subjective sense of entitlement as the blacks demanding
The Critique of Rights 325
The violent Southern racist reaction to the civil rights movement, com-
bined with the triumph of the liberals on the Court of the 196os, had an
impact on the critique of rights quite similar to the impact of fascism,
Stalinism, and the Roosevelt Court on the realist critique of adjudication.
In short, there are no atheists in foxholes.
326 POST RIGHTS
and ambiguities in the system of rules, the open texture of the doctrine of
stare decisis, and the semiotic, formulaic, pro/con character of policy ar-
gument to cut back and dismantle the liberal victories much as the liberals
had done with the conservative victories forty years earlier. Of course, it
was possible to interpret this trend, yet again, as no more than the triumph
of vice over virtue. But the demonstration, yet again, of the manipulability
of rights arguments back and forth across the political spectrum provided
a third context for loss of faith.
In the late 1970S and the 198os, at the same time that the left legal
intelligentsia was constructing its version of the sixties as a constitutional
rights revolution, organizers, activist lawyers, and theorists all began to
come up against a kind of rights-overkill problem. Rights for gays, old
people, the mentally retarded, Native Americans, children, mental pa-
tients, animals, prison inmates, endangered species, the handicapped, pros-
titutes, crime victims, people with AIDS, all made sense, if what one meant
by each of them was a specific program of law reform in favor of the group
in question. But remember that the whole point of adopting rights rhetoric
was to get beyond or outside the posture of the mere ideological or interest
group demanding something on policy grounds.
Left thinking evolved in reaction to internal debates about the content
of these "proliferating" rights claims, whether phrased in terms oi equality
within the legal order or in terms of substantive rights to freedom of
action. The most striking of the equality debates addressed "equal treat-
ment versus special treatment" within the feminist legal community. A
series of efforts to use the notion of a right to equal treatment as the basis
for a program of law reform ran up against the classic problem of deciding
between formal and substantive equality as the content of the right. In so
much as the debate had an outcome, it seemed to be that rights definition
should proceed ad hoc, through something very like balancing.2
The equivalent within the black community was the dispute about
whether equal protection meant affirmative action in the form of integra-
tion or in the form of development of black institutions. In such contexts
as schools and housing projects it seemed that the price of integration
would be subjection to unending white racial hostility, acceptance of white
social norms, and loss of black power and opportunity within the inte-
grated settings.29 At the same time, a black conservative movement began
328 POST RIGHTS
While I have no theory of loss of faith, I would hazard the hypothesis that
in the legal context "erosion," "undermining," "unraveling," and "conta-
gion" are likely to be precipitated by the spectacle of reversal: the anti-
rights arguments of the old left used by the new right, the left occupying
the exact position of an earlier right. This kind of flip by the two opposing
camps undermines belief in the technique in question in a way that criti-
cizing something that is simply analytically incoherent and politically
incorrect doesn't. I wonder how abolitionist litigators dealt with their own
dramatic shift, from nationalists to states' rights advocates, after the Fu-
gitive Slave Law put the federal government on the side of the South
against resisti ng Northern state governments.
A second hypothesis is that it is undermining to experience the unex-
pected disintegration oían apparently robust rights discourse within one's
own camp. In both the 1950S and the 1980s, a discourse understood un-
problematically as a righteous weapon against the wrong thought of ene-
mies suddenly foundered on the inability to convince one's supposed allies
that a particular right was good rather than bad.
entities to conclusions about what law should be. This was the mode of
reasoning of those abolitionists who saw the Constitution as a pro-slavery,
hence immoral, document. They were antilegalists but in no sense critical
of rights.
Moreover, it is still possible to believe that one chooses one's intralegal
rhetorical posture by reference to the extra- or prelegal element in consti-
tutional rights discourse. Advocates making constitutional rights argu-
ments can go on believing that the part that is outside, existing prior to
the legalization of the right in the Constitution, has a kind of reality quite
different from the reality of the right understood as incorporated into
positive law, and subject to all the mechanisms of legal interpretation.
If you can be correct about the outside right, it isn't so bad to have to
give up the objectivity of legal rights reasoning. You can be extremely
"legal realist," or even "nihilistic," about law but still believe that correct
reasoning from rights solves ethical problems. The point, then, is just to
get judges who will manipulate the plastic substance of legal reason to
achieve the results that are correct in terms of outside rights.
Or you can believe in the correctness of the outside rights judgments
but believe that these judgments are "in the abstract." They may have to
be modified "in practice" by the kinds of nonrights considerations typically
raised in legal reasoningutilitarian or institutional competence con-
straints, for example.34
But if the inside/outside divide is breached, and the critical spirit gets
applied to the outside rights, there may be trouble. Given the content of
the critique of constitutional rights, there is little reason to hope that either
fancy theory or lay rights discourse will be able to sustain their extralegal
normative claims.
In lay discourse, the word "right" is used in all the ways it is used in
constitutional discourse. There is, to begin, a strictly legal positive usage:
"women have no rights in Iran," "there was no right of free speech in
Stalin's Russia." Rights just mean rules in force to protect particular in-
terests. But the word is also used in lay legal argument about what the
U.S. courts should do about particular statutes or executive actions. The
speaker assumes the existence of a "straddling" constitutional right, and
reasons from it to a conclusion, deploying some version of the standard
legal interpretive techniques, including precedent (consistency) and moral,
utilitarian, institutional competence and administrability arguments.
The Critique of Rights 33'
Civil libertarians shriek about the right to privacy of those infected with
AIDS. To me, Kimberly Bergalis had more a right to live than her dentist
had to privacy. In the balancing act, there is no contest. But it is im-
portant to protect those who test positive with strong antidiscrimination
laws.
Those opposed to mandatory testing argue that the risk of patients
contracting AIDS from workers is very low, that workers are more likely
to contract AIDS from patients. So why not test all patients who are to
undergo "invasive" procedures, while at the same time testing health care
workers who perform such procedures? Protect everyone, rather than no
one."
In this passage, the writer treats rights argument very much as would
a lawyer disabused of the sense that "rights are trumps." Rights conflict;
they are quantitatively rather than qualitatively powerful; they have to be
balanced; how we do the balance depends on the practical context and on
nonrights arguments about things like the degree of harm that will flow
from different resolutions of the conflict.
The same presuppositions may underlie statements like "there is a con-
flict between privacy rights and free-speech rights," "the statute gives in-
adequate recognition to the right of free speech," "the statute should have
recognized a free-speech right," "we should recognize a right of privacy,"
"our society has a consensus in favor of a right of privacy," "this is an
attempt to cut back the right of privacy," "we have to find a way to rec-
oncile landlord's rights with tenant's rights."
The justifying role of rights here is ambiguous. The speaker might go
on to explain that the reason the statute gave inadequate recognition to
free speech was that free speech is an interest more important than the
interest in, say, national security, that there were other ways to achieve the
national security objective, that the resolution gives courts too much
power, and so on. Rights then function as no more than interests (perhaps
with an exclamation point). Because the discourse treats rights arguments
as no more than policy arguments, they perform no mediating function,
produce no transcendence of the fact/value or law/politics divides, as those
are commonly presupposed in the discourse.
The same is true of explanations like "we should establish a right of
privacy in order to safeguard people from unreasonable searches. ." or "to
332 POST RIGHTS
assure a woman control over her reproductive life." Here, the idea is to
change a legal rule by inserting a right-concept, but the reason given is
to change a state of affairs defined otherwise than in terms of violation of
the right. If you have lost your faith in the mediating power of legal rights
discourse, having come to experience it as no more than a form of ideo-
logically permeable policy talk, then you are not likely to see these forms
of lay discourse as any different.
Sometimes lay people appeal to fully outside rights without employing
either positivist legal reasoning or legislative policy argument. The rights
claim is intended to be something more than just a claim about what is
politically and morally best. The speaker seems to presuppose that it is
more "objective" or "absolute" or "conclusive," that it is possible to "be
right" about it, to make a "correct" argument, in a way that differentiates
it from other kinds of claims: "Banning abortion is wrong because it denies
a woman's right to control over her own body," "rent control is wrong
because it denies the landlord's right to private property."36
When challenged, the speaker may quickly turn to defense of the right
in the normal legislative way, offering all kinds of arguments as to why a
legal decision maker should agree. (Institutional competenceit should
be up to the woman rather than the court to decide; social welfareback-
alley abortions will increase and are an unacceptable cost.) When this
happens, it reemerges that the right is a "value judgment," supported by
a rhetoric, perhaps a rhetoric one finds utterly convincing, but without
the mediating power promised in the initial formulation.
When the speaker sticks to unadulterated rights talk, the problem is
that the assertion is conclusory. The speaker seems unaware that there is a
counterright that can be asserted in the same tone of voice and that cancels
out the first right. I may be missing the existence of a lay rights discourse
that avoids this pitfall without slipping into mere balancing. But my own
experience has been that the critique of constitutional rights reasoning has
spread corrosively from legal to lay discourse.
It is not, not at all, that someone has proved that rights "do not exist,"
or that they are "nonsense on stilts." It is not a question of proof. It is a
question of mediationof whether one gets any more from rights talk
than from social welfare or morality or administrability talk.
People sometimes say, "A critique of rights? But if you got rid of rights,
then the state could do anything it wanted to you! What about the right
of privacy? We wouldn't have any way to object to state intrusion!" They
are just missing the point!
In the Western democracies, rights "exist" in the sense that there are
legal rules limiting what people can do to one another and limiting the
executive and the legislature. The critique of rights recognizes the reality
of rule-making, rule-following, and rule-enforcing behavior. It is about
faith in the rational procedures through which legislators, adjudicators, or
334 POST RIGHTS
The Marxist origin of the critique of rights lies in the project of showing
that the inclusion of the proletariat in the regime of the Liberal Rights of
Man did not end illegitimate domination of that class. Its first point was
that if you had, under capitalism, all the revolutionary freedoms, and
strictly equal civil and political rights, you would also have, through the
very economic mechanism defined and protected by those rightsthe "free
market"exploitation even to the point of death.39
Its second point was that rights were by their very structure, their
definition as "trumps" against the claims of others, immoral, because they
were based on the idea that the invoker of the right can disregard the
wishes, over some subject-matter domain, of the people under the duty
corresponding to the right. This was Marx's utopian communist critique
of Lasallean "equal rights" socialism, quite distinct from the positive anal-
ysis of how the property and contract system necessarily worked under
capitalist conditions. It was an argument about how to conceptualize a
good society. Specifically, it was an antiformalist assertion of the priority
of consensus, sharing, and sacrifice over any assertion (group or individual)
of the legitimacy of ignoring a person affected by one's accions.°
Though they are important origins, neither the first nor the second point
is implicit in the minimalist internal critique of rights. Marx's necessitar-
ian model of the evolution of capitalism was a "rationalist" construction.
It has been, I argued above, a victim of minimalist critique rather than an
extension of it. As to the second point, the minimalist internal critique
and the posture of loss of faith do not suggest an alternative faith that,
336 POST RIGHTS
Why do it?
In part for these reasons, leftists engaged in the rights debate, myself
included, often feel that it is dangerous. I don't mean now to critique an
argument but to describe an emotion. The discussants may be willing to
confront the critique and take in good faith the risk of loss of faith. But
isn't it an experience we should all wish to avoid if that were only possible?
One part of this question I have already discussed in the analogous contexts
of legal reasoning and rationalism versus irrationalism. It is the sense that
if "we" lose our belief in rights, we will be disarmed in dealing with our
opponents. The notion is that rights rhetoric is or at least once was effec-
tive, and we would be giving that up by losing faith in rights.
Of course, it is not an argument in favor of rights that rights rhetoric
"works." The critique is not about effectiveness, though possibly useful in
understanding that subject." One can lose one's faith in an utterly effective
rhetoric and keep it in a rhetoric that practically no one seems to find
plausible. And it is not a response to the critique of rights rhetoric chat
everyone uses it, or that our heroes or our parents used it, any more than
it is a critique of rights that conservatives used or use them to great effect.
But to explain the sense of danger, one might respond that if "we" lose
our faith ¡n rights rhetoric but "they" don't, then they will gain an ad-
vantage over us. This is plausible ro the extent that the "we" in question
derives some measure of power, in confrontation with "them," from the
sense of righteousness, of mediation, that rights have historically provided.
"Giving up" rights would be like a professional athlete giving up steroids
when all her competitors were still wedded to them.
If you have already lost your faith in rights, the argument has the sound
of that in favor of religious faith for the masses, no matter how delusive,
on the ground of its beneficial consequences. It is the same kind oí idea
of beneficent error that Scott Altman propounds for judges. Yet if we are
really talking about effectiveness, it seems merely conjectural.
My own experience has been that some people who lose faith in rights
338 POST RIGHTS
become more politically committed, some become less, and some stay the
same. Some switch sides, and some gain rhetorical astuteness in dealing
with the good-faith, bad-faith, or cynical rights arguments of opponents,
becoming more powerful rather than less. Many committed leftists, in-
cluding most of those in the anarcho-Marxist, or Western Marxist, or neo-
Marxist anti-Stalinist tradition, today and yesterday, never had faith in
rights to begin with. If we are speaking of actual, empirical effects, I think
it's hard to make the case one way or another.
Rights are not the "core" or "centerpiece" or "heart" of Liberal legalism,
either as an ideology or as a social formation generating a complex mix of
happiness and unhappiness, legitimacy and oppression. The prevailing
consciousness doesn't have, to my mind, a heart or a core. It is an enor-
mously plastic, loose congeries of ideas, each of which appears from mo-
ment to moment to have the force of many army divisions and then no
force at allfrom Gramscian hegemony to Roseanne Rosannadanna's
"Never mind." The critique of rights, even when totally convincing, is a
good deal less "effective" than it seems from the position of threatened
faith.
But there is an aspect of the sense of danger that I want to acknowledge
as rationally grounded. Undermining faith in rights threatens to under-
mine the unity of the left and its sense of inclusion in "American citizen-
ship." If some on the left have lost faith in rights, and others have not,
then those who have will face a constant dilemma, forced to choose between
arguing with those who haven't, keeping silent, or engaging in cynical or
bad-faith manipulation of the discourse within the movement.
Given that the critique is not a solution to any problem of the left, not
a panacea or a program, given that the consequences for militancy and
commitment are at best uncertain and at worst disastrous, then why
do it?
'4
Conclusion: Landscapes along the Highway
of Infinite Regress
339
340 Conclusion
Why do it?
describing here. One motive is leftist and the other is mpm. Suppose for
the moment chat one didn't have to worry about the leftist implications,
what would be mpm motives for critique? The answer is that legal cor-
rectness and rights are important parts of the overall project of bourgeois
rightness, or reason, or the production of texts that will compel imper-
sonally. An important strand, a defining strand in the mpm project, is a
particular attitude toward rightness.
This is the attitude that the demand for agreement and commitment
on the basis of representations with the pretension to objectivity is an
enemy. The specific enemies have been the central ethical/theoretical con-
cepts of bourgeois culture, including the autonomous individual choosing
self, conventional morality, the family, manhood and womanhood, the na-
tion state, humanity. But the central ethical/theoretical concepts of the
left have also been targets, including the proletariat, class solidarity, party
discipline and socialist realism, and, more recently, sexual and racial iden-
tity.
The mpm impulse is to counter or oppose the producers of these artifacts
with others. The transgressive artifacts are supposed to put in question the
claims of rightness and, at the same time, induce a set of emotionsirony,
despair, ecstasy, and so onthat are crushed or blocked when we experi-
ence the text or representation as "right."
1f we define the left project as the struggle for a more egalitarian and
communitarian society, it is not intrinsically connected to rightness in any
particular form. But within the left project it has always been true that
rightness has played a central role. Leftism has been a bourgeois cultural
project within which many leaders and many followers have believed that
they were not just left but also right, in the strong sense of possessing
coherent and complete ("totalizing") descriptive and prescriptive analyses
of the social order.
Of course, critique has been crucial to the dominant "rightness" faction
of leftismthat is, critique as ground clearing for the erection of new
edifices of rightness. In the Marxist tradition, the slogan of the "scientif-
icity" of Marxism was the repository of the impulse to be right. For the
non-Marxist left, the slogans of "planning," "rational social policy," and
"the public interest" played the same role. But in the United States, by
the end of the 1970s, with the rise of identity politics, left discourse
merged with liberal discourse, and the two ideas of the rights of the op-
pressed and the constitutional validity of their legal claims superseded all
earlier versions of rightness.
Moreover, in the diffuse general culture of the bourgeoisie, the rule of
342 Conclusion
law and rights seem to function as crucial paradigms of rightness for ev-
eryone. There has been a kind of concentration of experiences of rightness
into the two contrasts of law versus politics and rights versus mere pref-
erences. Finally, in the specialized legal academic culture of the United
States, legal discourse in general, and rights discourse in particular, un-
derwent an aborted, or perhaps just a compromised, modernist revolution
in the legal realist period. Some 1950S postrealist scholars adopted a de-
tached, superior, ironic, nostalgic posture toward law and lawyers and their
fellow law professors, a kind of dandified modernism (particularly associ-
ated with international law, naturally, since American modernists have
always been fascinated by Europe and North Africa). But legal culture as
a whole seemed to slide backward into a combination of resurgent for-
malism with a reified version of policy analysis.
Remember that we are assuming, just for the moment, that it is possible
to pursue the mpm project without hurting the left project of change in
an egalitarian and communitarian direction. A person with mpm aspira-
tions would "naturally" choose adjudication and rights as targets, and try
to counter or oppose the demand of leftists for agreement and commitment
based on correct legal reasoning or on the existence of rights. And such a
project would have a larger mpm appeal to the extent that the rule of law
and rights have become prime vehicles of rightness for the whole society,
and for legal discourse in particular.
The mpm counter to rights and the rule of law looks, at first, like the
more traditional mode of left theory, based, say, on the model of alienated
powers. It deploys internal critique to loosen the sense of closure or ne-
cessity that legal and rights analyses try to generate. But rather than put-
ting a new theory in place, it looks to induce, through the artifactual
construction of the critique, the modernist emotions associated with the
death of reasonecstasy, irony, depression, and so forth.
There are two familiar ways to misunderstand this kind of mpm proj-
ectas proposing "authenticity" as an alternative to classical form, and as
proposing a theoretical demonstration of the impossibility of objectivity.
In the first, intoxicated phase, you don't expect the rights argument to
work any more. You even stop wishing or hoping that it will work. Most
of the time it seems all right, indeed even preferable to be "grappling with
the real issues," at least when one compares one's situation to that of people
who still spend a lot of time generating and believing in rights arguments
that seem transparently circular, ambiguous, or incomplete. Grappling
with the "real issues" can produce frustration or despair but also wild
moments of breakthrough insight and intense moments of emotional in-
volvement with others who are also grappling, perhaps with youin short,
it can produce intersubjective zap.
You purge the conclusory or otherwise "incorrect" use of rights discourse
from your own vocabulary, though you find yourself occasionally sponta-
neously producing it. Then you have to wonder, as you work at the internal
critique of your own utterance, whether to interpret it as "just a hangover,
a bad habit," in which "the language is speaking me rather than me speak-
ing the language," or as "a trace of a true discourse that I have subordinated
by a mere act of power." After working at this conundrum for a bit, you
give it up, just the way you gave up trying to prove, first, that legal
reasoning, second, that "scientific" social theoretical discourse, and, third,
that rights rhetoric "can never work." lt might be a trace oí a true dis-
coursethere's no way to be sure it's not.
On the other side of this experience is the anxiety that is often expressed
and often responded to in both the legal and the literary theory versions
of the debate, that if you can do this to rights discourse, you can do it to
any other discourse as well. In the legal version, both Jeremy Paul2 and
Jack Balkin3 have interpreted my own work as presupposing that critique
made room for "authentic" discourse and as failing to see that there is no
possibility of authenticity, given the critique of the subject as situated
within discourse and, Balkin adds,4 the "social construction" of everyone's
subjectivity.
"Authenticity" is the last thing people like me meant to appeal to as
the "behind" that we might liberate through the critiques of adjudication
and of rights. It would be more accurate to say we were trying to liberate
"contradiction," "alienation," "desire," "irony," "doubleness," "despair,"
"ecstasy," and "yearning." Of course, maybe we wanted to liberate them
because we thought that they were authentic and that the conventional
forms of legal discourse were not. But it seems, at least in hindsight, more
accurate to say that we wanted to liberate them because we felt them, and
felt their exclusion as a wound.
346 Conclusion
In art, postmodern style follows the cultural modernist style I've been
talking about, whereas postmodern "theory" follows not that, but another
modernismthe rationalist modernism of "the Enlightenment." These
usages give rise to a lot of confusion. The mpm I'm referring to has cultural
modernism, the avant-garde of the period from the 189os through the
195os, as its referent for "m." It has both postmodern style in architecture
and painting and postmodern theory, in the sense of Foucault, Derrida,
Jane Gallop, and Judith Butler, as its referent for "pm."
Conclusion 347
This makes mpm an odd duck. I have been emphasizing the "unity" of
mpm by defining it in terms of formal innovation, disrupted rational grids,
prima! underforces, and dangerous supplements. Just now, I tried to draw
them together in the critique of rightness, whether in the sense of repre-
sentational objectivity in art or descriptive and normative objectivity in
theory. But one might critique this formulation by emphasizing the dif-
ferences between artistic and theoretical practices, or the ways in which
both aesthetic and theoretical postmodernism have a critique of aesthetic
modernism, as well as a critique of the Enlightenment.
Aesthetic modernism as I've been reading it is revolt against the En-
lightenment fetishes of rationality and objectivity, and the bourgeois fetish
of conventional morality, but it is open to the posrmodern critique that it
glorifies the auteur. In modernism, the moment of critique and the mo-
ments of alienation, doubleness, irony, ecstasy, and despair, especially as
condensed in the artist's moment of transgressive artifact creation, all can
still be totalized or theorized as an aesthetics and an ethic, even a heroic
ethic.
Moreover, the auteurs insisted on theorizing their practicethe creation
of transgressive artifactsin just this way. Wassily Kandinsky wrote about
painting, Ezra Pound about poetry, Henry James about the novel, Le Cor-
busier about architecture, François Truffaut about cinema, Arnold Schoen-
berg and Omette Coleman about music. Ernest Hemingway propagated
his own mystique.
Postmodernism generalizes the critical element, turning it against mod-
ernism as aesthetics, as ideology, as ethic, as system, as mystique, accusing
the avant-gardists of mythologizing the subject as the locus or site of the
dissolution of everything that was not the subject. Postmodern art end-
lessly critiques the auteurflaunting eclecticism, copying, the mundane,
and the mechanical, in the face of our hope for Prometheus. Postmodern
theorists argue their hypercool ethic against Prometheanism through the
critique of the subject/auteur as the product rather than the creator of
culture. But here again there is a case for the continuity of the project.
The postmodern critique applies far better to the writings of modernists
about modernism than to the artifacts they created. The artifacts seem no
less "critical of the subject" than those ofpostmodernism. The Promethean
auteurs were premodern as critics; they slid back into mere rationalism or
romanticism the minute they began to theorize their transgressive artifacts.
By contrast, the postrnodemn critics are modernist performers. Derrida and
Jane Gallop and Judith Butler are stylistically Promethean, and their writ-
348 Conclusion
The easiest of all the ways to misread mpm is as a global internal critique,
an impossibility theorem that invalidates or refutes the possibility of ob-
jectivity, rationality, subjectivity, or representation, or all of them at one
blow. In law, for example, the moment oí loss of faith has been, since the
beginning of the realist critique, often formulated in Holmes's general
proposition that "general propositions do not decide concrete cases." In
the first attempts to appropriate postmodernism for the use of cls (after
the rationalism/irrationalism debate but before the rights debate), it was
common to read Jacques Derrida in particular as proposing a general im-
possibility theorem about representation that could be applied to all claims
of determinacy in law. A recent pragmatist version of critical maximalism
is the following from Frank Michelman and Margaret Radin:
I have been describing a series of contexts for loss of faith. In each context,
the precipitating factor is critique, and then critique "spreads" to a new
context. But critique, when it has an mpm motive, doesn't spread of its
own accord, and it is "no accident" when it produces loss of faith. Here
are two explanatory frameworks in which one might understand what is
happening as something that people do to themselves and to others. The
Conclusion 35'
acter of the premodern moment can never be restored. But it is only from
a peculiar positioneither far above the fray, or very frightened of en-
gagementthat the relationship between action and reaction, between
aggression and victimization, between exhibitionist and audience, is so
utterly effaced.
Closer to the ground, it is obvious that the aggression and exhibitionism
are directed not mainly at reactionaries but rather toward the unselfcon-
scious. The project has always been situated within capitalism, with its
complex relationship between intelligentsias, middle classes, and masses.
It arose and thrives on cultural heterogeneity, but not just any heteroge-
neity. It is directed at the vital, or at least still breathing, traditions of the
bourgeoisie and at the bourgeois project of assimilating peasants, and then
workers, into a particular version of "Western" culture.
It has also always drawn on, without merging with, "subjugated knowl-
edges," from African art and African American jazz and rock and roll to
"the feminine," "the sexually perverse," and the addicted.9 In other words,
we have to put it in the same frame with leftism, an alternative opposi-
tional/utopian project, but aiming at bourgeois cultural hegemony rather
than at bourgeois ownership of the means of production. This is not to say
that the image from physics of action and reaction saves us from confusion.
The modernist action that "produces" reaction is itself produced just a
little earlier (though not necessarily in the family romance). Further, the
exhibitionist strand in the modernist project makes it dependent on the
proffered attention of an audience, an atTention that structures the pro-
vocateurs.
from oppressed, marginalized, and victimized groups, and mpm types have
identified, however hypocritically in the eyes of their critics, with "out-
laws." This makes it elite in a second sense, in the sense of being a society
of self-conscious "illuminati," who reject conventional ideas and indicia of
status in favor of the superior ethics, taste, and style of mpm, seen as a
project of opposition to the bourgeoisie. lt is important to understand that
mpm types from nonelite backgrounds often come to it through experi-
ences of rejection or marginalization in their own oppressed communities.
Their presence confirms the sense of secret society, both for them and for
those from privileged backgrounds.
In this second sense, mpm networks tend to be elitist as well as elite.
By this I mean that, just as they are driven by aggression, exhibitionism,
and the desire to successfully enact a particular script, they are driven by
the pleasures and fears that are associated with belonging to a group that
sees itself as "better than," more sophisticated than, ahead of, those it
habitually opposes.
There is an analogy to the way liberals in the United States have tended
to regard conservativesthat is, as in some sense primitives, people who
"just don't get it," as behind the curve cognitively as well as politically.
But mpm elitism is neither that of the left in regard to the right, nor that
of the "cultural elite" in regard to the "masses." My sense is that it is best
grasped by the notion of the "revenge of the nerds," meaning specifically
the revenge of the alienated fringe of the intelligentsia against the middle-
brow establishments of bourgeois culture, on the one hand, and against
the bourgeois leadership of committed leftist groups, on the other.
Finally, mpm is elite, and open to the charge of elitism, because it is
organized around performance (the production of transgressive artifacts
rather than political "actions") that is supposed to produce reaction. Mpm
takes the premodern cultural Other as object (audience), whether that
Other is conceived as premodern through and through or as an only par-
tially realized mpm person like the artist herself. lt aims to épater les bour-
geois (rather than to nationalize their property), in the modes of aggression
and exhibitionism described above. It presupposes the superiority of
mpm, the "right" of mpm performers to hurt the audience, as well as to
induce ecstasy and depression, in the name of higher values accessible to
the artist/performer and "good for" the audience (while commonly de-
nyingdefensively and hypocriticallythat it cares at all about audience
reaction).
Conclusion 355
against the compromises those elites are willing to make on the cultural
level to sustain what they imagine are more serious political projects.
It is common for anti-mpm leftists to respond simply that what they mean
by leftism is a set of goals, and a set of methods for achieving them, that
are incompatible with mpm, so that mpm leftism is an oxymoron. It is
also common for them to respond that if we regard mpm not as an (er-
roneous) theory, but as a set of attitudes or a cultural style, then it is an
unattractive, obnoxious style that is inferior to the style of the rest of the
left. And it is common to argue that if mpm is to be regarded as one of
the theories available for use by leftists, then leftists should be wary of its
"tendency," which is to demobilize, to sap the will to fight.
The basic left/mpm response here is not to claim that there is a superior
definition of leftism that would allow us to be included as leftists, let alone
to show that we are the only "true" leftists. A project, as I defined it in
Chapter i, is an amalgam of a social organization with a textual tradition,
and (outside the world of party-building groups) there is no mechanism
to settle disputes about inclusion and exclusion other than long-term so-
cial/intellectual conflict within the milieus and the discourse of the project.
In short, we left/mpm people engage in ideological struggle with others
who define themselves as leftists, hoping to convert them if possible, to
win particular battles, and to acquiesce with good humor when we lose,
and the dialogic moment gives way to the moment when people have to
take action of various kinds without full agreement.
This section responds to two versions of mainstream left critique of left/
mpm: first, that it trashes objectivity, rationality, representation, subjec-
tivity, legal correctness, rights, and identity, just at the moment when
previously oppressed and marginalized groups have, at last, a chance to
deploy them against the dominant discourse; and, second, that mpm cri-
tique (a) destroys our ability to decide what to do, and (b) leads to total-
itarianism.
First, however, let me list some genealogies of left/mpm, for no other
reason than to suggest that we have been present within the left for a long
time. Victor Serge and Rodchenko and Stepanova; the early Wilhelm
Reich, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Herbert Marcuse; Ralph Ellickson, James
Baldwin, Harold Cruse, and Michelle Wallace; surrealism, situationism,
and Michel Foucault; Virginia Woolf, W. H. Auden, and Jean Rhys; the
Dos Passos of U.S.A., Alan Ginsberg, and the yippies.
Conclusion 357
One way to respond to a new player is to fold the game. Isn't it "odd" that
just when women and minorities are getting some rights, the left/mpm
types (or is it "white males" in general?) decide that rights are meaningless?
Just when third-world peoples overcome colonialism, these same "allies"
produce a supposedly devastating critique of sovereignty. And so it goes.
The people doing the trashing have seen themselves as, in some sense,
"free" to do it, because they have not been contending for state power or
for mass acceptance of their ideas. Initially, it didn't seem sensible to ask
questions like, "what will happen to the women's movement if people lose
faith in rights?" But, over the last fifteen years, identity politics has revived
the academic left. The newly arrived white women and minority academic
activists see themselves as having both an audience in the educated non-
academic left and some voice in the national policy debates organized by
the media. They have revived the question of the political consequences
of different rhetorical choices.
In the last chapter, ¡ argued that it is an empirical issue whether loss of
faith increases or decreases activism, and that the argument "but they use
steroids" embraces bad faith without, to my mind, making a case that
there really is a nasty trade-off between honesty and effectiveness. More-
over, liberals have trashed Marxist grand theory, Marxists have trashed
rights theory, and left/mpm types have trashed both, for generations, since
long before the civil rights movement or the second wave of feminism. All
this trashing may have been wrong from the start, but mpm types have
engaged in it for a long time as a strategic activity, and not only as a
response to the (limited) empowerment of oppressed groups.
The left/mpm position is critical of the middle-class intellectual leaders
of the new social movements, to the extent that they assimilate themselves
to the dominant discourses of legality, rights, and identity, whether they
do so out of faith or as an effective maneuver. It is not a "demand" that
they stop doing so, nor a claim that there is a more effective alternative
way, but merely a comradely expression of disagreement, in the form of a
transgressive artifact or two.
A variant is that it is easy enough for upper-middle-class white males
to trash legal correctness, rights, and identity because they don't need
them, being immune through white skin privilege and maleness to the
oppressions visited on Others. The discourses of legal correctness and
rights are, I argued at length in Parts Four and Five, powerful stabilizing
elements in the American political system. If one can imagine a left aca-
358 Conclusion
demic critique that "destroyed" them, then I suppose one can imagine a
political free-for-all, in which conservatism would have a good chance of
doing in liberalism and moving the system as a whole ro the right in a
way far more profound than the Gingrich Revolution. The principal vic-
tims of such a shift to the right would be the poor, white women, and
minorities.
So, as I said in the last chapter, I am all in favor of deploying these
discourses for strategic reasons, whether before courts or in general political
debate, as long as the deployer has in mind the element of bad faith in his
or her performance. And I agree that there is an element of "luxury" in
the identity position of the academic who renounces the struggle for state
power, so as to be "true" to the truth-telling impulse, even while denying
the possibility of truth. The left in left/mpm supports spending some time
looking for ways to intervene in policy debates that seem likely to be good
for the oppressed, without betraying mpm. And, as I will argue at the end
of this chapter, it also supports, without requiring one to choose, the
alternative of left workplace politics, localism without national resonance.
One presupposition of left/mpm is that the system is stable over the
long term, in spite of the endless Marxist and post-Marxist production of
crisis theories and in spite of real crises all the time in particular places.
A second is that developments in academic theory have virtually no con-
sequences for national politics (other than to provide, in the titles of PMLA
panels, material for right-wing parody).'°
This may be wrong, and it may be that academic leftists should spend
all of their time developing rhetorically effective interventions in national
political debate and no time helping the virus on its course. I think this
makes some sense for left liberals and for white women and minorities in
general. But I don't think it makes sense for the very small group of
academics, male and female, white and of color, whose post-Marxist or left/
mpm sentiments make it difficult to imagine masquerading effectively as
mainstreamers. And I don't believe the reason I think this is that I per-
sonally have less to lose from, say, the erosion of civil liberties than my
colleagues whose backgrounds are less privileged than my own.
It was once plausible to make the much stronger response that mpm
was intrinsic to leftism, because loss of faith represented the recovery of
alienated powers. In other words, internal critique showed us the ways in
which we allowed our understanding to be controlled by reified entities,
forms of necessity invented and projected out onto nature or society (God,
the market, the law, Marxism). And the projections could be seen as em-
Conclusion 359
Against reconstruction
It was once the case that the answer to left/mpm was a theory, whether
Marxism or Liberalism. That is no longer the case, at least in che academic
left. The answer to left/mpm is rather a charge, the charge of "nihilism,"
a critique of the bad consequences of nihilism, and a projectreconstruc-
tion.
Sometimes the author has a specific reconstruction in mind and presents
it full blown as the next step after critique» as something to replace what
has been critiqued. When this is the case, the only fair response is to
critique it in its turn, subscribe to it, or just ignore it. More often, the
author proposes the project of reconstruction, rather than any particular
reconstruction. One favors the project not because one has a proposal but
because one believes that we ought to do it, or at least try it, that bad
consequences will follow if we fail, and that there are at least some inter-
360 Conclusion
esting possibilities, some hopeful avenues, some useful bits and pieces
available for the task.
A striking aspect of calls for reconstruction is that the author not un-
commonly treats critiques as decisive refutations of previous theories. An
important trope is the suggestion that critique is easy, while reconstruction
is hard, that it is self-indulgently pleasant to go on trashing one thing
after another, since we all know how to do it, but morally bracing to roll
up our sleeves and get down to the less fashionable but in the long run
more constructive task oí reconstructing.
A second striking aspect is that the same reconstructionist who asserts
the validity of prior critiques, and claims that they are easy to do, is likely
to explicitly or implicitly call for reconstructions that will perform just
the same function that was performed by the critiqued entities. This is the
function of representing social order in a way that would allow us to have
some assurance that we are right to be left, and right to pursue particular
strategies in favor of equality and community. Here is an example, from
the very end of an article about international legal scholarship:
Ultimately, by following modernism to its logical conclusion, the New
Scream puriststhose arguing from within the limits of critical epis-
temologyproduced what can be understood as the last modernist text
of international law . . The next wave of international legal literature
.
Nihilism
making it impossible to figure out enough about how the social order
works to choose a strategy of left action within it. Those of us who are not
moral realists (believers in the objective truth of moral propositions) are
used to committing ourselves to projects, and deciding on strategies, on
the basis of a balancing of conflicting ethical and practical considerations.
In the end, we make the leap into commitment or action. That we don't
believe we can demonstrate the correctness of our choices doesn't make us
nihilists, at least not in our own eyes.
We misunderstand internal critique if we imagine that it might lead to
a situation in which we had lost faith in "everything," so that we just
wouldn't know what to believe in or do. Critique changes our attitude
toward a particular theory (whichever we successfully critique) that gen-
erated a particular sentiment of rightness. It leaves us whatever we had
before critique, in the way of tools for working out our commitments and
our concrete plans for the future. It seems odd to me to suppose that we
could ever, conceivably, be without resources of this kind, even if each of
us was a veritable Hercules of critical destruction.
Of course, a person might be committed to egalitarianism only because
of belief in rights, and in particular rights. The loss of faith in rights in
general might lead such a person to abandon egalitarianism, in favor of
another attitude, say, belief in natural inequality, that seemed more plau-
sible when not countered by a particular belief in rights now undermined
by critique. But the causal chain might move in the other direction as
well: loss of faith in property rights might permit previously thwarted
egali tarjan sentiments to flower.
It might be possible to make convincing generalizations about the causal
tendency of the left/mpm project of critique, loss of faith, and attendant
emotions. After the proposal that the tendency is demoralization, the most
popular may be that left/mpm leads to Hitler and Stalin. As I understand
this argument, it goes something like this. Stalinism and Nazism represent
the powerful, irreducible force of evil in human nature. But they inflicted
previously unimaginable suffering, degradation, and destruction, far be-
yond the normal. They were able to do this because they were nihilist,
meaning that they denied the validity of fundamental human rights.
Nietzsche's cult of the Superman and the moral relativism of Weimar are
responsible.
The mirror image: Stalinism and Nazism represent the powerful, irre-
ducible force of evil in human nature. But they inflicted previously un-
imaginable suffering, degradation, and destruction, far beyond the normal.
Conclnsion 363
They were able to do this because they were totalitarian, meaning that
they proclaimed the absolute truth of their theories. Therefore, skepticism
is the true antidote to the repetition of the Holocaust and the gulag.
Hegel's cult of Absolute Reason and blind obedience to authority are re-
sponsi ble.
It may be possible to combine the theory that the evil of the twentieth
century is caused by the denial of reason (nihilism) with the theory that
it is caused by excessive commitment to reason (totalitarianism). Perhaps
on a higher level true believers are nihilists and vice versa. Or perhaps one
should be a true believer in fundamental human rights and a nihilist about
racist and Marxist theories.
But from the point of view of loss of faith in reason (which is not an
impossibility theory about reason), it seems unlikely that either believing
or disbelieving in reason in general, or in any particular rational construc-
tion, has this kind of causal power. It seems more likely that belief and
denial of reason can each have many different meanings and combine in
an infinite number of ways with idiosyncratic or socially constructed at-
titudes, sentiments, and dispositions. Belief and denial more likely were
constitutive but not controlling elements in many forms of collaboration
with and opposition to Nazism and Stalinism, rather than elements with
a single intrinsic or inherent tendency.
Left/mpm artifacts are at the intersection of two projects, one leftist and
the other mpm. These are designed to play two dramas on this single
stage. One idea is to modernize or postmodernize the leftist project, and
the other is to move the world leftward by doing in right-wing forms of
rightness. What this means is that there is strategic behavior within the
intersection. The mpm part of left/mpm aims to move the left project
along rather than to destroy itallegiance to mpm is no more "absolute"
than allegiance to leftism. In ideological struggle/dialogue with the right,
we choose our themes/targets with an eye to converting waverers, and avoid
themes/targets that can be predicted to demoralize other leftists (would
that we were so powerful) when the left/mpm payoff is small or nonexis-
tent.
In other words, the left, as I am using the term, is a "site" for particular,
outward- and inward-looking ideological encounters and coalitions, rather
than a set of principles or a program.'4 It is, for me, a "position" as well,
364 Conclusion
by which I mean that I much prefer to hang with liberals, identity poli-
ticians, and post-Marxists, rather than with the varieties of right-wing or
centrist/mpm types. But it is no more conceivable, to me, to be left
through and through than to be mpm through and through.
I think the protective impulse toward one's own sense of rightness is so-
cially constructed, by which I mean that we learn rightness as a way to
deal with despair, depression, and internal contradiction, and also learn it
as a script that promises social power to those who master it. I don't mean
to propose a theory of human nature, an anthropology that would explain
or be right about the origins of rightness. The following Foucaldian ac-
count of legal education is meant to suggest that there are investments in
rightness that one might give up without threatening one's selfhood, rather
than to show what rightness "is."
I want also to urge a social theoretical claim about modern Western
society: that legal discourse and legal education are sites for the production,
through discipline, of the modern subject's commitment to rightness.
Rightness may be a defense mechanismarmory through reified texts
against fears and longingsor it may be the superego, but it is also a
structural element in a disciplinary society. Law and legal education are
among the producers of the attitude of the professional who operates dis-
ciplinary mechanisms from the location of a disciplinarian self constituted
by discipline.
client is on) and then argue according to the predilections of the decision
maker (here the teacher, later the judge). The self that emerges from this
experience will be committed to the kind of bad faith I described in Chap-
ter 8. Strategic behavior is everywhere. But the student and the lawyer
learn that they must always suppress it, submerge it in a necessitarian
discourse that everyone knows is only part of the story.
Rightness is a complex technique one has masteredsomething other
people can't do, something that has effects in the world (first grades, then
appellate decisions)and simultaneously "just a rhetoric." On the surface,
the law speaker says that he is right because the materials and good legal
reasoning in the particular situation compel the outcome (whether a jury
verdict or a rule choice) impersonally. Below the surface, we scramble to
psyche out the client and judge as anything but impersonally motivated,
with predictions of effectiveness the only basis of choice about what to do.
It is, I think, easy to see how one develops a deep investment in rightness
thus understood. For the lawyer and the judge, though in different ways,
rightness is simultaneously power and safety: power because it works,
safety because it protects against the charge of moral nihilism for the
lawyer and against the charge of arbitrary violence for the judge who wields
state power. But it also delivers these with a safety valve: legal rightness
is not totalitarian, because "everyone" understands that, at the same time
that it empowers and protects in fact, one doesn't have to take it altogether
seriously.
This may explain its iconic status in popular culture. The lawyer and
the judge are hardly omnipresent in everyday life. But the attitude they
represent, the bad faith, inside-outside, strategized production of the dis-
course of rightness, is omnipresent. In both the corporate world and in
that of public administration, actors constantly assert that they are just
following the rules, doing their jobs by the book, without responsibility
for the "political" consequences. They plead compulsion by correct inter-
pretation to do things they would never do, they claim, if they were them-
selves the legislator (board of directors).
The objects of administration, both in the private corporate sphere and
in the public one, are more and more likely to be themselves administrators
in another context. We know, from our lives as administrators, that when
those who are administering us speak the language of rightness in the
interpretation of their bureaucratic mandates, they are as likely as we are
in our jobs to be strategizing for or against, rather than merely "applying
the regs." And we know there is real drama in their decisions, because we
368 Conclusion
know that sometimes we ourselves are "really" bound, that we allocate our
time according to ideological projects that may be no more than prejudices,
but may be also what we believe in most deeply, and that in the allocation
we make endless economic choices about credibility and plausibility with
our interpretive communities.
roles. What the corporation does will, for example, sometimes have a mas-
sive effect on the economic life of the community where it is located. But
profit maximizing is far too vague to specify how to direct that effect.
Internally, everyone knows that different workplaces have radically differ-
ent "corporate cultures," ranging, for example, from the relatively hierar-
chical and formal through the relatively egalitarian and informal. Man-
agement consultants develop typologies on the assumption that corporate
culture is not uniquely determined by mission.
Like judges making legal rules with distributive effects, managers cast
decisions about what these organizations should do, externally and inter-
nally, in the manipulable rhetorics of institutional mission, profit making,
health, education, and public interest, all referring back to the explicit
mandates of corporate organizational documents or statutes. The strategy
chosen, within the general role specification, is like a judge-made rule, in
that it may have massive distributive effects without being compelled by
the discourse that legitimates it. This seems equally true for corporations,
hospitals, schools, universities, and government agencies.
The people who run institutions operate in bad faith in the same way
judges do. On the one hand, they often experience their missions as suf-
ficiently defined, given the practical circumstances, so that they are com-
pelled to adopt particular strategies and reject others. To do anything else
would be "unprofessional," a "breach of trust," "suicidal from the point of
view of the bottom line," or whatever. On the other hand, they also ma-
nipulate the discourse of necessity to present all kinds of strategic choices
that are not thus compelled as necessary and right. They constantly deploy
their resources, they constantly work, just as judges do, to shape and re-
shape the necessity that they are supposedly merely submitting to. Com-
petent "players" know this to be crue, although there will often be dis-
agreement about when and where there is "really" discretion. But the
public discourse, as opposed to the back-room discourse of the organiza-
tion, resolutely denies it.
Like lega) discourse, the discourses of management seem remarkably
stable, by which I mean that, for most participants, most of the time, there
seems to be no alternative to casting decision making in their terms and
little danger that the widely perceived element of indeterminacy will lead
to erratic or even unpredictable organizational behavior. To some extent,
this stability reflects the prevalence of the experience of being bound or
constrained by widely accepted mission definitions. Organizations do what
they do because chat's what they were organized to do. But given the
370 Conclusion
sense that his own side has a correct theory that shows that the other side
is evil. The ideologue is a character, unable to compromise, a polarizer or
splitter, the enemy of collective good feeling.
This diffuse combination of connotations, including faction, corruption,
and the fanaticism of the "true believer," puts the ideologue outside the
tenuous, intermediate position of bad faith. In bad faith, one honors both
the idea that the discourse of decision is a neutral one, within which the
parties are searching for a right answer, and the idea that we all know that
there is an element of manipulability to that same discourse. Staying in
bad faith is tricky work. You push your agenda through the discourse,
never indicating the slightest doubt about its necessitarian presupposi-
tions, while honoring the implicit rules about what would be going too
far.
Politicizing is disloyal almost by definition. First, it endangers the or-
ganization's ability to perform its mission. Second, it endangers everyone's
investment in institutional life, including the investment in a particular
set of "private" patterns of interaction and the investment in the prestige
of the institution in the world it serves.
Loyalty is partly a contractual idea and partly a notion of solidarity based
on the concrete history of group life. When you join the institution, you
implicitly sign on to the set of arrangements, styles of nteraction, collec-
tive conceptions of role, and so on, that define it. When you work with
people every day, depending on them in many ways that aren't codified,
and don't have anything to do with large political issues, you need an ethic
of mutual forbearance, of compromise and boundary observance, or every-
one will be miserable. Avoiding this misery is more than a matter of self-
interestthere is an ethic of collegiality that is independent of interest,
just as it is independent of politics.
Loyalty is a "spirit" that you can have more or less of and that you can
also just plain lack. Then you are disloyal, which is positively to be bad,
rather than ranked low on a common scale. Groups reward people accord-
ing to loyalty, but they sanction them for disloyalty. Moreover, loyalty
issues invoke the raison d'état aspect of administration. Usually, you aren't
fired for it, or formally sanctioned in any way. But once your bosses, per-
haps tuned in to coworker gossip, clearly identify you in their own minds
as in this category, then everyone expects them to exercise all their different
kinds of low-level discretion to make sure, for the good of the organization,
that you don't get promoted or otherwise rise to power.
Everyone understands that gossiping groups, administrators, and clique
372 Conclusion
Loyalty to the institution, in this complex sense of the will to preserve its
bad-faith discourse, so as to preserve its external and internal equilibrium,
can be the faith of bad faith. By this I mean that loyalty can be deeply
Conclusion 373
felt, even though it can also be feigned; it can be wholehearted even though
it can also be coerced. Loss of faith in loyalty as something to strive for
can be like loss of faith in God or legal correctness. Sometimes one feels
loyalty as a fact, as one feels legal constraint as a fact. But one loses any
sense that it is better to be loyal than disloyal, that the constraint when
one feels it is the reflection or emanation of something behind, that is
"intrinsically" right, and so forth.
Disloyalty of this kind is a characteristic left/mpm attitude. It starts
from the idea that you are wherever you are, so that "if you don't like it
here, go back to Russia, where you belong" isn't an alternative. The con-
tractual idea lacks force, because we middle-class, highly educated types
grow up in a world in which the question is which large organization to
work for. They all have missions that are partial and ethics of loyalty that
you will be expected to sign on to. But they are also compromised or
complicit in the larger order.
From a left point of view, there are a few public interest organizations
that have explicit progressive goals such that loyalty to the organization
does not require even a pro forma renunciation of the idea that political
and private life can be integrated. If, for one reason or another (including,
perhaps, lack of moral fiber, mpm intolerance, or student loans), you are
not going to work for one of these, you have to decide what attitude to
take toward che particular mission definition and demand for loyalty im-
posed by an ostensibly apolitical organization.
A typical attitude is to recognize the left critique of the organization,
and to hope, first, that it won't be as bad as its bad rap and, second, that
the leeways of the bad-faith discourse will permit moving it in a progres-
sive direction, once one has done one's time and acquired some power.
Liberal recruiters subtly or blatantly encourage this understanding. But
often, often, it turns out that the leeways are narrow, and the implicit
metadiscourse of avoiding politicization and demonstrating loyalty effec-
tively closes down any possibility of left workplace politics.
Then you will find yourself not believing in what they say you have to
believe in if you are to be a "true" member of the community. If you
declare this, you will be ostracized. So you play the game, but without
giving up your reservations. You find yourself endlessly speaking a lan-
guage of rightness, while internally denying its presuppositions. You re-
sign yourself, but feel complicit in the retrograde aspects of the organi-
zation's performance and guilty about not using your institutionally
granted powers for the good of the oppressed.
374 Conclusion
For people who have lost (or never had) faith in bad faith, who have lost
the capacity to believe and not believe at the same time, so that they
experience the discourse sometimes as brute (desacralized) constraint and
sometimes as merely instrumental, the demand for loyalty to avoid polit-
icization is completely understandable, however unmeetable. Indeed, one
reason for keeping up bad faith is the belief that if one loses faith in it,
one has to choose between politicization and hypocrisy or time serving.
What about the left/mpm project? If there's nothing else to do, I'm all in
favor of abandoning it.
But it can't be that there is never anything else to do. If there are any
possibilities at all, I'm proposing not a solution but an attitude, taking
hope from Holmes's aphorism that every idea is an incitement. Sometimes
it makes sense to strategize, not the best result within the discourse that
will leave the discourse and its implicit metanorm of moderation intact,
but the politicization of the setting. Sometimes it doesn't make sense, in
which case passivity by ail means. Alternating between politicizing and
passivity might be a better attitude than alternating between bad faith
and passivity. Better a contradiction than a defense mechanism.
Politicizing the environment doesn't mean setting out to destroy it, and
in the mpm version of leftism, it obviously doesn't mean believing fanat-
ically in one's truth. It does mean trying to set up a political identity to
the left of liberal bad faith, without being or seeming to be a wrecker.
Conclujion 375
If, as some would argue, most human societies to date fail this test, if
most of them are such that their members (ought to) feel shame in their
societies and guilt by association for their character and actions, then
there is little we can learn about the law in general from the notion of
an approximately decent society.'8
If, as a leftist, one feels shame in one's society and guilt by association
for its character and actions, then the dilemma posed by the alternatives
of politicizing, of bad-faith strategic behavior in interpretation, and of
376 Conclusion
passivity is a real one, even though this is neither Nazi Germany nor
Stalin's Russia.
The left/mpm actor who politicizes insists that it is not enough, in
defending a particular course of institutional conduct, external or internal,
to appeal to the general understanding that the organization has a spe-
cialized, nonpolitical role in the social division of labor. If in the particular
context there is enough shame and guilt by association, then there needs
to be some further discussion of whether it isn't possible to exploit gaps,
conflicts, and ambiguities or frankly to reject the norm of role specializa-
tion given the circumstances. Of course, the left/mpm actor won't propose
a general theory of how far we can go in bending the mission statement
before we break it, or of when we ought to break it.
Politicization has its attendant costs, including the risk of defeat, the
deterioration of the quality of group life that comes from finding the
political everywhere when it had been elsewhere, and the risks to one's
own career and to the careers of friends and allies that are present the
minute one goes against this particular grain. Sometimes these costs are
worth paying. I am talking about a balance, not politicization at all costs,
above all not "principled" politicization, which to my mind is just another
way to be right.
Rather, opportunist politicization that recognizes four maxims: find a
friend/collaborator, live to fight another day, extremism in the defense of
liberty is indeed a vice, the personal is political. When these maxims
suggest that, in the particular circumstances, oppositionism is the wrong
thing to do, then quit or go back to passivityanother form of disloy-
altyrather than denial. In other words, doubleness, in the mode of
W. E. B. Du Bois's doubled consciousness of people of color, vis-à-vis the
very institutions that nurture us and make it possible for us to fight against
their complicity, our complicity, in group oppression.
NOTES
INDEX
NOTES
I. INTRODUCTION
x. Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology,
trans. Hazel Barnes (New York: Citadel Press, 1965); Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of
Dialectical Reason, trans. Alan Sheridan (London: Verso, ¡990).
Herbert Marcuse, Reason and Revolution: Hegel and the Rise of Social Theory (Bos-
ton: Beacon Press, 1968); Herbert Marcuse, One Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology
of Advanced Industrial Society, 2d ed. (London: Routledge, 1991).
Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheri-
dan (New York: Vintage, ¡979); Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews
and Other Writings, 1972-197 7, ed. and trans. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon
Books, 1980); Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, 3 vols., trans. Robert Hurley
(New York: Vintage, 1988-1990).
See Duncan Kennedy, "Psycho-Social CLS: A Comment on the Cardozo Sym-
posium," 6 Cardozo L. Rev. 1013 (1985); Gerard Clark, "A Conversation with Duncan
Kennedy," The Advocate; The Suffolk University Law School Journal, 24 (no. 2, Spring
¡994), 56; Duncan Kennedy, "Noce sur l'histoire de cls aux états-unis," in Dictionnaire
encyclopédique de théorie et de sociologie du droit, 2d ed., ed. André-Jean Arnaud (Paris:
L.G.D.J., '993).
Guy Debord, The Society o/the Spectacle. trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith (New
York: Zone Books, ¡994).
Paul D. Carrington, "Of Law and the River," 34f. Leg. Ed. 222 (1984).
Ludwig Feuerbach, The Essence of Christianity, trans. G. Eliot (New York: Pro-
metheus Books, ¡989).
Karl Marx, "On the Jewish Question," in Writings o/the Young Marx on Philos-
ophy and Society, ed. and crans. Loyd Easton and Kurt Guddat (Garden City, N.Y.:
Anchor, ¡967), p. 216; Karl Marx, "The Fetishism of Commodities and Its Secret,"
in Capital: A Critique ofPolitical Economy, vol. 1, trans. Ben Fowkes (New York: Vintage,
1977), p. 163. See Chapters ii and 13 and, on the fetishism of commodities, Duncan
Kennedy, "The Role of Law in Economic Thought: Essays on the Fetishism of Com-
modities," 34 Am. Univ. L Rev. 939, 968 (1985).
See Jules L. Coleman and Brian Leiter, "Determinacy, Objectivity, and Au-
thority," 142 U. Pa. L. Rev. 549 ('993); Heidi L. Feldman, "Objectivity in Legal
Judgment," 92 Mich. L. Rev. 551 (1994).
Stanley Fish, "Working on the Chain Gang: Interpretation in Law and Liter-
ature," 6o Texas L. Rev. 551 (1982).
David L. Shapiro, "Courts, Legislatures, and Paternalism," 74 Va. L. Rev. 519,
556-557 (1988)(emphasis mine).
Jeffrey Rosen, "Breyer Restraint," New Republic, June ii, 1994, p. 20.
1 don't mean to be taking sides in any extant debate here. Even Ronald Dworkin
agrees that judges make law in the minimal sense indicated in the text. Ronald Dwor-
kin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986), p. 6.
Linda Greenhouse, "Fierce Combat on Fewer Battlefields," New York Times,July
3, 1994, S. 4, p. i.
Anthony Flint, "Breyer Set for Senate Hearings," Boston Globe, July 10, 1994,
s. i, pp. i, x6.
John Noonan, "Master of Restraint," New York Times Book Review, May i, 1994,
p.7.
IO. Vincent Blasi, "Judge Him Unpredictable," New York Times Book Review, June
19, 1994, p. 3.
ii, Adam Levine, letter to the editor, "Unpredictable Justice Powell," New York
Times Book Review, July IO, 1994, p. 3'.
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law, 2d ed. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994).
Hart's attitude toward this question is perhaps well represented by this state-
ment: "At this point [where the law runs out] judges may again make a choice that
is neither arbitrary nor mechanical; and here often display characteristic judicial vir-
tues, the special appropriateness of which to legal decision explains why some feel
reluctant to call such judicial activity 'legislative.' These virtues are: impartiality and
neutrality in surveying the alternatives; consideration for the interest of all who will
be affected; and a concern to display some acceptable general principle as a reasoned
basis for decision." Ibid., p. 200.
Hans Kelsen, Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, trans. B. Litschewski
Paulson and S. L. Paulson (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), s. 36. For an interesting
collection of essays on Kelsen's theory of interpretation, see Cognition and Interpretation
of Law, ed. Letizia Gianformaggio and Stanley Paulson (Turin: G. Giapichelli, '995).
i. Roberto M. Unger, Knowledge and Politics (New York: Free Press, 1975), p. 88.
i 6. Mark V. Tushnet, Red, White, and Blue: A Critical Analysis of Constitutional Law
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1988), pp. 52-57.
17. Gary Peller, "The Metaphysics of American Law," 73 Cal. L. Rev. i,,,, zi8i
(1985).
i8. James Boyle, "The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social
Thought," 133 U. Pa. L. Rev. 68, 710-711 (1985).
,9. Owen Fiss, "Objectivity and Interpretation," 34 Stan. L. Rev. 739 (1982).
Notes to Pages 32-37 38!
pp. 153T 54. I think Hunt misunderstood the method I was then and still am trying
to deploy, because he imagines that the imputation of motive or intent (or preference-
I use them all interchangeably), in the phrases he quotes, could be "substantiated" in
the sense of "proven," or, for that matter, disproven. Substantiation in his sense is,
first, impossible and, second, unnecessary for the analysis to work as it is supposed to.
My imputation of an "apologetic" or "legitimating" motive to Blackstone was of the
hermeneutic kind, although what I imputed to him and, by mere "inference," to legal
thinkers in general, was neither liberalism nor conservatism. I tried to substantiate
the imputation by critiquing Blackstone's explanations of the rules as unconvincing,
indeed close to unintelligible, unless read in light of a motive of the type I proposed.
L had and have no direct evidence as to whether his motive, if it was as I interpreted
17. See, generally, Brian Tamanaha, "An Analytical Map of Social Scientific Ap-
proaches co the Concept of Law," z, Oxford). Leg. Studies 501 (s9).
i8. Karl N. Llewellyn, The Bramble Bush, or, Our Law and Its Study (New York:
Oceana Publishing, 1960), p. 12 (emphasis in original).
See Tamanaha, 'An Analytical Map," pp. 515_5 ii.
Sally Merry, Getting Justice and Getting Even: Legal Consciousness among Working-
Clais Americans (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990); Barbara Yngvesson,
Virtuous Citizens, Disruptive Subjects: Order and Complaint in a New England Court (New
York: Routledge, 1993).
Robert H. Mnookin and Lewis Kornhauser, "Bargaining in the Shadow of the
Law: The Case of Divorce," 88 Yale L]. 950 (içî,'9).
See, for example, Duncan Kennedy, "Sexual Abuse, Sexy Dressing, and the
Eroticization of Domination," in Sexy Dressing, Etc., Pp. 131-162; Molly McUsic,
"Reassessing Rent Control: Its Economic Impact in a Gentrifying Housing Market,"
ici Han'. L. Rev. 1835 (1988); Lawrence Kolodney, "Eviction Free Zones: The Eco-
nomics of Legal Bricolage in the Fight against Displacement," i8 Ford. Urban L.J.
507 (xu).
Marc Galanter, "Why the 'Haves' Come Out Ahead: Speculations on the Limits
of Legal Change," 9 Law &Soc'y Reu 95
Alice Dembner, "Female Athletes Gain in Legal Game," Boston Globe, October
1, 1994, S. 1, pp. i, 20.
Ibid.
1974).
6. Mitchel Lasser, "Judicial (Self-) Portraits: Judicial Discourse in the French Legal
System," 104 Yale L.]. 1325 ('995).
. H. L. A. Hart, "American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare
ro. Ugo Mattei, "Why the Wind Changed: Intellectual Leadership in Western
Law," 42 Am.]. Comp. L.att' 195, 205 (1994).
r z. Rodolfo Sacco, "Legal Formants: A Dynamic Approach to Comparative Law,"
the public/private distinction, see Duncan Kennedy, "The Stages of the Decline of the
Public/Private Distinction," 130 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1349 (1982).
For a perceptive description and critique of this state of mind, see Pierre Schlag,
"Normative and Nowhere to Go," 43 Stan. L. Rev. 167 (1990).
DeShaney y. Winnebago County Dept. of Social Services, 489 U.S. 189, 203-
112 (1989XBrennan, J., dissenting).
Lucas y. So. Carolina Coastal Council, 505 U.S. 1003, 1036-1061
(1992XBlackmun, J., dissenting).
Benjamin Cardozo, The Nature oftheJudicial Process (New Haven: Yale Univer-
sity Press, 1957), p. 98. Llewellyn's "situation sense" and "rule of the Singing Reason"
are contextualized versions of the same idea. See Karl Llewellyn, The Common Law
Tradition: Deciding Appeals (Boston: Little, Brown, 1960), p. 6o. See Charles Clark and
David Trubek, "The Creative Role of the Judge: Restraint and Freedom in the Com-
mon Law Tradition," 71 Yale L.]. 255 (1961).
Lon Fuller, "The Forms and Limits of Adjudication," 92 Harv. L. Rev. 353
(1978). See James Boyle, "Legal Realism and the Social Contract: Fuller's Public Ju-
risprudence of Form, Private Jurisprudence of Substance," 78 Cornell L. Rev. 37!
('993).
Henry M. Hart and Albert Sacks, The Legal Process: Basic Problems in the Making
and Application of Law, ed. William Eskridge and Phillip Frickey (Westbury, N.Y.:
Foundation Press, 1994). See Gary Peller, "Neutral Principles in the i 9505," 21 Univ.
Mich.]. Law Reform 561 (1988).
Hart and Sacks, The Legal Process, p. ii 3.
Ibid., ch. i.
Herbert Wechsler, "Toward Neutral Principles of Constitutional Law," 73 Harp.
L. Rev. i ('959).
See Peller, "Neutral Principles in the 1950'S," p. 6i,John Ely, Democracy and
Distrust: A Theory ofJudicial Review (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1980), p. 87.
William Eskridge and Phillip Frickey, "Historical and Critical Introduction,"
in Hart and Sacks, The Legal Process, pp. licxxxvi.
A dramatic example is Henry Hart and Edward Prichard, "The Fansteel Case:
Employee Misconduct and the Remedial Powers of the National Labor Relations
Board," 52 Harv. L Rev. 1275 (iç».
See Henry Hart, "The Supreme Court, 1958 Term, Foreword: The Time Chart
of the Justices," 73 Harv. L. Rev. 84 ('959) (endorsing Herbert Wechsler's critique of
Brown y. Board of Education in "Toward Neutral Principles"), and see generally Mor-
ton Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 1870x 960: The Crisis of Legal Or-
thodoxy (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), pp. 252-268.
Specifically, Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, Mass.: Har-
vard University Press, 1978); Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985); Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986).
See, generally, Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence, ed. Marshall Ber-
Notes to Pages 120-125 39'
man (Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Allanheld, 1984). My favorite liberal critiques are
Andrew Altman, "Legal Realism, Critical Legal Studies, and Dworkin," i Phil. &
Pub. Aff 205 (1986), and Joseph Raz, "The Relevance of Coherence," 72 B. U.L. Rev.
273 (1992). See also Peter Gabel, Book Review, 91 Haro. L. Rev. 302 (x977Xreviewing
Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously).
Dworkin, Law's Empire, pp. 167-168.
Ibid., at pp. 225, 255.
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, pp. 22, 90; Dworkin, Law's Empire, p. 223. 1
discuss Dworkin's elaboration of this distinction at note 74 below. Deduction plays
almost no role at all in Dworkin's theory. His view of precedent is even more radical
than Liewellyn's-see Taking Rights Seriously, pp. lIC-113, 122.
,,. H. L. A. Hart, "American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare
and the Noble Dream," ii Ga. L. Rev. 969 (1977).
Raz, "The Relevance of Coherence," p. 273.
MacCormick, Legal Re.asoning, ch. 9.
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, pp. 95, 97, 102, io6.
Dworkin, "Liberalism," in A Matter of Principle, pp. ¡8 1-204.
6. Dworkin, "Law as Interpretation," in A Matter of Principle, pp. 164-165. Al-
though this article appears before "Liberalism" in A Matter of Principle, it was first
published four years after that article.
Dworkin, L.au"s Empire, p. 399.
Ibid., at pp. 4 5-46.
Ibid., at pp. 359-369.
6o. Ibid., at pp. 369-379.
6,. Dworkin, "Law as Interpretation," p. x6o.
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, p. 6o; Dworkin, A Matter o/PrincipIe, pp. 137-
145.
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, p. ii8.
Dworkin, Lau"s Empire, p. 354.
Ibid., pp. 269-27 1.
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, pp. 83-85; Dworkin, Lau"j Empire, pp. 243-
244.
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, p. 184 ("[t]he debate does not include the
issue of whether citizens have some moral rights against their Government. It seems
accepted on all sides that they do").
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, p. 88.
Dworkin, Lau's Empire, p. 378; see also pp. 397-398.
Dworkin, A Matter of Principle, p. 70.
Dworkin, "Law as Interpretation."
Kent Greenawalt, "Policy, Rights, and Judicial Decision," ji Ga. L. Rev. 991,
992 (1977).
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, p. 294.
392 Notes to Pages 125-133
15. See Frances Olsen, "From False Paternalism to False Equality: Judicial Assaults
on Feminist Community, Illinois, 186ç-I895, 84 Mich. L. Rev. 1518 (1986).
i6. See, for example, Martin Shapiro, Freedom ofSpeeth: The Supreme Court andJudicial
Review (Englewood, NJ.: Prentice Hall, 1966), p. 103.
17. Javins y. First Nat'! Realty Corp., 428 F.2d 107! (D.C. Cir. '970).
r8. Escola y. Coca-Cola Bottling Co. of Fresno, 24 Cal. 2d 453, 150 P.2d 436
(,944) (Traynor, J., concurring).
Duncan Kennedy, "Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication," 89 Harv.
L. Rev. ¡689 (1976).
Ibid., pp. 1702-1710.
Ibid., pp. 1766-1776. See also, Duncan Kennedy, "The Structure of Black-
stone's Commentaries," 28 Buff L. Rev. 205 (1979), and Duncan Kennedy and Peter
Gabe!, "Roll Over Beethoven," 36 Stan. L. Rev. i (1984).
all fields are "really" loopified. See Kennedy, "Freedom and Constraint," pp. 68-69,
and Duncan Kennedy, "The Stages of the Decline of the Public/Private Distinction,"
130 U. Pa. L. Rev. '349 (1982).
See Paul Brest, "Interpretation and Interest," 34 Sian. L. Rev. 765 (1982).
Neil MacCormick, "Reconstruction after Deconstruction: A Response to CLS,"
10 OxfordJ. Leg. Stud. 539, 553-554 (z99o).
If he accepts interpretive fidelity, he will give up if he can't achieve what he
sees as the just result, and he will be open to conversion to the other side through the
experience of delving into the materials.
Reagan y. Farmers Loan & Trust, 154 U.S. 362 (1894).
io. DePeyscer y. Michael, 7 Selden 467 (N.Y. 1852).
i,. Brown y. Bd. of Educ. of Topeka, 347 U.S. 483 (19S4Xschool desegregation).
Notes to Pages 174-185 395
2, 1hope the reader will remember that I did not attempt to prove that legal
reasoning could never produce closure or that the experience of boundness is mere
illusion. My goal was only to show that there are gaps, conflicts, and ambiguities, that
these are a function of legal work as well as of the materials the judge works with,
that the experience of "freedom" to shape the legal field is common, and that one
cannot say with certainty that when closure occurs it is a product of a property of the
field rather than of the work strategy adopted under particular constraints.
Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind (New York: Coward, McCann, 1935).
No rationalist version of explanation can be "saved" by interpolating a "text/
event" distinction at the last minute. But that is not the goal. The point in the text
is that we will sometimes reach explanatory closure, in the sense that we feel con-
strained, by our theory of why the case came out the way it did, to respond in a
particular way. If we feel constrained to the conclusion that the judge chose as she did
because she felt constrained by her understanding of her own liberalism, then it will
make sense to offer her an alternative version of liberalism, to invest energy in internal
critique. If we think she was bribed, or hates the particular class of plaintiffs, this
strategy will appear a waste of time, and we will act accordingly. This pragmatist version
of explanation is enough for me.
Sigmund Freud, "Certain Neurotic Mechanisms in Jealousy, Paranoia, and Ho-
mosexuality" (1922), in Sigmund Freud, Sexuality and the Psychology of Love(New York:
Collier Books, 1963), p' 151.
Anna Freud, The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense, trans. C. Baines (London:
International Universities Press, 1937, 1966), p. 6o.
See Scott Altman, "Beyond Candor," 89 Mich. L. Rev. 296, nn. 6, (5990). My
approach differs both from the earlier realist versions and from his, not in my definition
of denial, but in the specification of what is being denied and why. Altman's specific
psychology of judging seems to me largely vitiated by his failure to distinguish clearly
between "following a rule" and "following the law" in the work of interpretation (rule
choice), and by his related failure ro distinguish clearly between what he calls "activ-
ism" and what he calls "manipulation." His development of the parallel between de-
fense mechanisms and cognitive dissonance is helpful, but there doesn't seem to be
enough difference between the vocabularies to merit incorporating cognitive disso-
nance theory into the discussion beyond the mention in the text. Altman's reconstruc-
tion of "the CLS position" on indeterminacy, id. at 333-347, is even more outlandish
than his self-described "caricature" of my position, id. at n. 48. Some earlier critical
discussions of denial in legal thought are Duncan Kennedy, "The Structure of Black-
stone's Commentaries," 28 Buff L. Rev. 205, 209-22 I (5979); Mark Kelman, A Guide
to Critical Legal Studies (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 3,
286-290; Pierre Schlag, "Contradiction and Denial," 87 Mich. L. Rev. 12x6 (1989).
Anna Freud, The Ego, p. 48.
Ibid., p. o.
Notes to Pages 200-222 397
"Judicial Deradicalization of the Wagner Act and the Origins of Modern Legal Con-
sciousness, 1937-1941," 62 Mints. L. Rev. 265 (1978); Alan Freeman, "Legitimizing
Racial Discrimination through Antidiscrimination Law: A Critical Review of Supreme
Court Doctrine," 62 Mina. L. Rev. 1049 (1978); Duncan Kennedy, "The Structure of
Blackstones Commentaries," 28 Buff L. Rev. 205 (1979); Robert Gordon, "New Ap-
proaches to Legal Theory," in The Politics of Lau': A Progressive Critique, ed. David Kairys
(New York: Pantheon, 1982), p. 281; Peter Gabel and Paul Harris, 'Building Power
and Breaking Images: Critical Legal Theory and the Practice of Law," ii N. Y. U. Rev.
L. & Sx. Change 369 (1982-83); Gerald Frug, "The Ideology of Bureaucracy in Amer-
ican Law," 97 Hart'. L. Rev. 1276 (1984); Mark Kelman, A Guide to Critical Legal
Studies (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1987), pp. 262-295. For a re-
view, see Carol Steiker and Jordan Steiker, "Sober Second Thoughts: Reflections on
Two Decades of Constitutional Regulation of Capital Punishment," 109 Hart'. L. Rev.
355, 429-432 (1995). 1 discuss cnt versions in specific doctrinal areas later in this
chapter and the relationship between the neo-Marxist and cnt versions in the next
chapter.
See Morton Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 1788-1860 (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1977), pp. 117-121.
James Bradley Thayer, "The American Doctrine of Constitutional Law," 7 Hart'.
L. Ret: 17 (1893).
Franz Wieacker, A History o/Private Law (u'ith Particular Reference to Germany),
trans. Tony Weir (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 431-441.
Sally Merry. Getting Justice and Getting Even: Legal Consciousness among Working-
Class Americans (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), pp. 96-97.
Michel Rosenfeld, "Deconstruction and Legal Interpretation: Conflict, Indeter-
minacy, and the Temptations of the New Legal Formalism," it Cardozo L. Rev. ¡211,
1245 ('990).
Duncan Kennedy and Frank Michelman, "Are Property and Contract Elli-
cienc?" 8 Hostra L. Rev. 711 (1980).
There is an ambiguity as to why the structure of rules is in the background in
the first place. It might be because we think that they are obviously right, or that
they are the natural rules to govern this type of interaction, or that they flow logically
from some uncontroversial premise. But to be in the background is to be outside
continuous consciousness and attention. Naturalization in this sense is not a conscious
operation that people perform on the rules; it is more like an assumption. The rhetoric
of naturalness and necessity comes into play only when for some reason people advert
co the background, and then it is most likely a way to dismiss it and get back to the
foreground. This gives rise to the question whether the rules don't get naturalized
because they are in the background, rather than backgrounded because naturalized.
We dont need to solve this conundrum. Even if backgrounding some elements, and
naturalizing what is background, are cognitive necessities, we can still work at par-
ticular figure/ground reversals.
See, generally, Duncan Kennedy, "The Stakes of Law, or Hale and Foucault!"
400 Notes to Pages 249-254
in Sexy Dressing, Etc. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, xc). This way
of looking at the constitutive role of law in the economy also applies to conflict between
firms. See Rudolph Peritz, Competition Policy in America, 1888-1992: History, Rhetoric,
Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996); Kipp Rogers, "The Right of Pub-
licity: Resurgence of Legal Formalism and Judicial Disregard of Policy Issues," i6
Beverly Hills BarAnoc.J. 65 (7982).
io. Hagai Hurvitz, "American Labor Law and the Doctrine of Entrepreneurial
Property Rights: Boycotts, Courts, and the Juridical Reorientation of 1886-1895," 8
md. Rel. L.]. 307 (1986); Ellen Kelman, "American Labor Law and Legal Formalism:
How 'Legal Logic' Shaped and Vitiated the Rights of American Workers," 8St.John's
L. Rev, i (1983); John Nockleby, "Tortious Interference with Contractual Relations in
the Nineteenth Century: The Transformation of Property, Contract, and Tort,' 93
Harv. L. Rev. 1510 (1980).
xi. William Forbath, Law and the Shaping of the American Labor Movement (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991).
Felix Frankfurter and Nathan Greene, The Labor Injunction (New York: Mac-
millan, 1930).
Klare, "Judicial Deradicalization," p. 62. The second foundational piece is
Katherine Stone, "The Post-War Paradigm in American Labor Law," 90 Yale U. 1509
(1981).
Stone, "Post-War Paradigm," pp. 1514-15 15.
i. Klare, "Judicial Deradicalization," pp. 309-310.
Karl Klare, "Critical Theory and Labor Relations Law," in The Politics of Law:
A Progressive Critique, ed. David Kairys (New York: Pantheon Books, 1982), p. 82.
The labor critique was preoccupied from the start with race and gender issues,
and it quickly incorporated the later cls approach co law as constitutive of sexual and
racial identity. See Karl Klare, "The Quest for Industrial Democracy and the Struggle
against Racism: Lessons from Labor Law and Civil Rights Law," 6x Oregon L. Rev, 157
(1982); Karl Klare, "Power/Dressing: Regulation of Employee Appearance," 26 New
Eng. L. Rev. (1992).
i8. Neatly summarized in Robert G. McCloskey, The American Supreme Court (Chi-
cago: University of Chicago Press, 1960), pp. '44-15°. See Edward S. Corwin, Com-
merce Power vs. States Rights (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1936); Robert Stern,
"That Commerce Which Concerns More States Than One," 4 Harv. L. Rev. 1375
(1934).
Summarized in William O. Douglas, "Stare Decisis," 49 Colum. L. Rev. 735
('949).
Henry Hart and Herbert Wechsler, The Federal Courts and the Federal System
(Brooklyn: Foundation Press, 1953).
2 I. Nathaniel Berman, "'But the Alternative Is Despair': Nationalism and the
Modernist Renewal of International Law," io6 Harv. L. Rev. 1792 (1993).
22. See David Kennedy, "The Move to Institutions," 8 Cardozo L. Rev. 841 (1987);
Notes to Pages 254-25 7 401
Berman, "'But the Alternative' "; Nathaniel Berman, "Modernism, Nationalism, and
the Rhetoric of Reconstruction," 4 Yale J. Law & Human. 351 (1992); Nigel Purvis,
"Critical Legal Studies in Public International Law," 32 Harv, ¡nl. L.]. 8i ('99');
Olivier DeSchutter, "Critical Legal Studies dans le Droit International," 31 Droit et
Société i (1992).
David Kennedy, "Primitive Legal Scholarship," 27 Han'. ¡'it. L.]. i (1986);
David Kennedy, "Spring Break," 63 Texas L. Rev. 1377 (1985); David Kennedy, "The
International Style in Postwar Law and Policy," 1994 Utah L. Rev. 7; David Kennedy,
"The Sources of International Law," 2 Amer. Univ. J
¡ni. Law & Polity i (1987);
Nathaniel Berman, "Nationalism Legal and Linguistic: The Teachings of European
Jurisprudence," 24 N. Y.UJ. mt. Lau' & Politics 1515 (1992); Karen Engle, "Interna-
tional Human Rights and Feminism: When Discourses Meet," i Mich.]. Int'l Law
517 (,92).
Gerald Frug, "The City as a Legal Concept," 93 Hart'. L. Rev. 1057 (1980);
Gerald Frug, "Decentering Decentralization," 6o Unit Chic. L. Rev. 253 (1993); Ger-
ald Frug, Local Government Lau' (St. Paul, Minn.: West Pub. Co., 1988); Richard Ford,
"The Boundaries of Race: Political Geography in Legal Analysis," 107 Hari L. Rev.
¡843 (1994).
Gerald Frug, "The Geography of Community," 48 Stan. L. Rev. (May 1996);
Ford, "Boundaries of Race."
Derrick Bell, "Brown y. Board of Education and the Interest Convergence Di-
lemma," 93 Han'. L. Rev. i8 (1980).
Derrick Bell, And We Are Not Saved (New York: Basic Books, 1987).
Alan Freeman, "Legitimizing Racial Discrimination," p. 1049; Alan Freeman,
"Antidiscrimination Law: A Critical Review," in The Politici 0/Law: A Progressive Cri-
tique, ed. David Kairys (New York: Pantheon Books, 1982).
Kimberle Crenshaw, "Race, Reform, and Retrenchment: Transformation and
Legitimation in Antidiscrimination Law," 101 Harv L. Rev. '33' (1988).
Gary Peller, "Race Consciousness," 1990 Duke L.]. 758; Neil Gotanda, "A
Critique of 'Our Constitution Is Colorblind': Racial Categories and White Supremacy,"
44 Stan. L. Rev. 1 ('99').
See Critical Race Theory: The Key Writings That Formed the Movement, ed. Kimberle
Crenshaw, Neil Gotanda, Gary Peller, and Kendall Thomas (New York: New Press,
¡995), "Introduction," pp. xiiixxxii.
Catharine MacKinnon, Only Words (Cambridge, Mass.: I-Iarvard University
Press, '993).
Words That Wound: Critical Race 7'heory. Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment,
ed. Mari Matsuda et al. (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1993).
Mark Tushnet, "Corporations and Free Speech," The Politics ofLau': A Progressive
Critique, ed. David Kairys (New York: Pantheon Books, 1982); Jack Balkin, "Some
Realism about Pluralism: Legal Realist Approaches to the First Amendment," 1990
Duke U. 375; James Boyle, "A Theory of Law and Information: Copyright, Spleens,
402 Notes to Pages 259-261
Blackmail, and Insider Trading," 8o Calif L. Reu 1413 (1992); John Nockleby, "Hate
Speech in Context: The Case of Verbal Threats," 42 Buff L. Reti. 653 (1994).
Robert Stein feld, The invention of Free Labor: The Employment Relation in English
andAmerican Law and Culture, 1350-1870 (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina
Press, 199!).
Catharine MacKinnon, "Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State," 8 Signs
650 (1983).
Frances Olsen, "The Family and the Market: A Study of Ideology and Legal
Reform," 96 Harv. L, Rev. 1497(1983); Frances Olsen, "The Myth of State Intervention
in the Family," i8 Micb.J. Law Reform 835 (1985); Frances Olsen, "The Politics of
Family Law," 2 Lau' & inequality 1 (1984).
Andrea Dworkin, Right-Wing Women (New York: Putnam's Sons, 1983); Andrea
Dworkin, Intercourse (New York, Free Press, 1987).
Olsen, "The Family and the Market,"
See Catharine MacKinnon, Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1987), p, ; Dworkin, Right-Wing
Women, pp. 2 1-23. See also Kennedy, Sexy Dressing, pp. 147-162.
4 1. Mary Joe Frug, "A Post-Modern Feminist Legal Manifesto (an unfinished
draft)," 105 Harv. L. Rev. 1045 (1992); Janet Halley, "Sexual Orientation and the
Politics of Biology: A Critique of the Argument from Immutability," 46 Stan. L. Rev.
503 (i). Cf. Robin West, "The Difference in Women's Hedonic Lives: A Phenom-
enological Critique of Feminist Legal Theory," 3 Wisc. Women's L.J. 8i (1987).
42. Clare Dalton, "An Essay in the Deconstruction of Contract Doctrine," 94 Yale
L.J. 999 (1985); Mary Joe Frug, "Re-Reading Contracts: A Feminist Analysis of a
Contracts Casebook," 34 Am. Univ. L. Rev. 66 (1985); Elizabeth Schneider, "Describ-
ing and Changing: Women's Self-Defense Work and the Problem of Expert Testimony
on Battering," 9 Women's Ris, L. Rep. 195 (1986); Vicki Schultz, "Telling Stories about
Women and Work: Judicial Interpretations of Sex Segregation in the Workplace in
Title VII Cases Raising the Lack of Interest Argument," 103 Hart'. L. Rev. 1749(1990);
Lama Abu-Odeh, "Crimes of Honour and the Construction of Gender in Arab Socie-
ties," in Feminism and islam, ed. Mai Yamani (Reading, Eng.: Garnet, 1996), p. 141.
Frances Olsen, "Statutory Rape: A Feminist Critique of Rights Analysis," 63
Tex, L. Rev. 387 (1984); Engle, "International Human Rights,"
Susan Keller, "Viewing and Doing: Complicating Pornography's Meaning," 8i
Georgetown L.]. 2195 (1993); Lama Abu-Odeh, "Post-Colonial Feminism and the Veil:
Considering the Difference," 26 New Eng. L. Rev. 1527 (1992); Dan Danielsen, "Rep-
resenting Identities: Legal Treatment of Pregnancy and Homosexuality," 26 New Eng.
L, Rev. (1992); After Identity: A Reader in Law and Culture, ed. Dan Danielsen and
Karen Engle (New York: Routledge, '995).
,. For example, Susan Keller, "The Rhetoric of Marriage, Achievement, and
Power: An Analysis of Judicial Opinions Considering the Treatment of Profes-
Notes to Pages 262-2 64 403
sional Degrees as Marital Property, 21 Vi. L. Rev. (1996. See also Chapter ii,
n. 21.
Kimberle Crenshaw, "Mapping the Margins: Identity Politics, Intersectionality,
and Violence against Women," 43 Stan. L. Rev 1241 (1991).
Kendall Thomas, "Beyond the Privacy Principle," 92 Co/um. L. Rei' 501 (1992);
Danielsen, "Representing Identities"; Halley, "Sexual Orientation."
For example, Duncan Kennedy and Leopold Specht, "Limited Equity Cooper-
atives as a Mode of Privatizacion," in A Fourth Way? Privatization. Property, and ¡he
Emergence of New Market Economies, ed. Gregory Alexander and Grazyna Skapca (New
York: Rourledge, içsØ, p. 267.
Elizabeth Schneider, "Equal Rights to Trial for Women: Sex Bias in the Law
of Self-Defense," 15 Harz'. C.R.-C.L. L. Revi 623 (1980).
Merle Weiner, "From Dollars co Sense: A Critique of Government Funding for
the Battered Womens Shelter Movement," 9 Lau' & Inequality 1985 (1991).
Gregory Alexander, "Pensioners in America: The Economic Triumph and Po-
litical Limitations of Passive Ownership," Karl Klare, "Legal Theory and Democratic
Reconstruction: Reflections on 1989," and William Simon, "Republicanism, Market
Socialism, and the Third Way," all in A Fourth Way? Pris'atization, Property, and the
Emergence of New Market Economies, ed. Gregory Alexander and Grazyna Skapca (New
York: Routledge, 1994); Katherine Stone, "Labor and the Corporate Structure: Chang-
ing Conceptions and Emerging Possibilities," U. Chi. L. Rev. 73(1988); Karl Klare,
"Workplace Democracy and Market Reconstruction: An Agenda for Reform," 38 Cath.
U. L. Rev 1 (1988); Alan 1-lyde, "In Defense of Employee Ownership," 67 Chi.-Kent
L. Rev 159 (1992). For a similar approach ro agricultural law, see Marjorie Benson,
Agricultural Lau' in Canada, 18671 995: Vitli Particular Reference io Saskatchewan (Cal-
gary: Canadian Institute of Resources Law, 1996).
Words that Wound (see n. 33).
Regina Austin, "Employer Abuse, Worker Resistance, and the Tort of Inten-
tional Infliction of Emotional Distress," 41 Stan L. Rev i (1988).
Gerald Frug, "Decentering Decentralization."
Lawrence Kolodney, "Eviction Free Zones: The Economics of Legal Bricolage
in che Fight against Displacement," 18 Fordham Urban L.). 507 (1991).
in the spring of 1970. His and Roberto Unger's work has continued to influence mine,
as is evident throughout the text that follows, in spite of their different emphases and
different conclusions. Roberto Unger, Knowledge and Politics (New York: Free Press,
'975); Roberto Unger, Law in Modern Society: Toward a Criticism of Social Theory (New
York: Free Press, 1976); Roberto Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986); Roberto Unger, Politics: A Work in
Constructive Social Theory, 3 vols. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
Susan Silbey, "Ideals and Practices in the Study of Law," 9 Leg. Stud. Forum 7,
io (1985).
Points a and b remain part of the conventional wisdom of the school of Amherst:
"By offering deconstructions of specific texts, critical legal studies tends to associate
law with the textual pronouncements of judges and legal theorists. The very idea of
law as rhetoric focuses almost exclusively on the discursive aspects of the lawthe
professional grammar invoked by those responsible for linguistically justifying the use
of a legal regulation or the imposition ola legal sanction. Such linguistic justification,
however, can be seen as but a small part of the law. Fitzpatrick, by contrast, reaches
toward a more capacious understanding of law, one which, though never explicitly
theorized, would include practices of administrators and legal 'subjects' rather than
merely pronouncements of judges." We learn that Peter Fitzpatrick "begins where
much of critical jurisprudence endsby observing the deeply contradictory nature of
law." Lawrence Douglas and Austin Sarat, "(De)Mythologizing Jurisprudence: Speak-
ing the 'Truth' about 'Myth," 19 Law & Soc. Inquiry 523, 529-530 (i994) (footnotes
omitted).
See the "implementation" research cited in Alan Hyde, "The Concept of Le-
gitimation in the Sociology of Law," 1983 Wisc. L. Rev. 379, 410, n. 89.
,. Jean Braucher, "The Afterlife of Contract," 90 Northwestern L. Rev. 49, 8o (1995)
(summarizing Robert Gordon, "Book Review," 1974 Wijc. L. Rev. 1216, 1223-1225).
Robert H. Mnookin and Lewis Kornhauser, "Bargaining in the Shadow of the
Law: The Case of Divorce," 88 Yale U. 950 (Içr,9).
See Duncan Kennedy, "Sexual Abuse, Sexy Dressing, and the Eroticization of
Domination," in Sexy Dressing, Etc. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1993).
Braucher, "Afterlife," p. 88.
In other words, the sociologists are suggestingwithout, lamentably, any at-
tempt at empirical verification-.--a legitimation effect.
io. See, for example, Rand Rosenblatt, "Health Care Reform and Administrative
Law: A Structural Approach," 88 Yale L.]. 243 (1978).
ii. Lon Fuller, The Morality of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1964).
12. Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, vol. i, trans. Robert Hurley (New
York: Vintage, 1978), pp. 92-96. See, generally, Duncan Kennedy, "The Stakes of
Law, or Hale and Foucault!" in Sexy Dressing, Etc, (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1993).
Notes to Pages 272-275 405
Hyde, "Legitimation," pp. 408-409 (footnotes omitted; the quote is from Hans
Adamy, "Legitimacy, Realigning Elections and the Supreme Court," 1973 Wicc. L.
Rev. 790, 808; emphasis in the original).
Frank Munger and Carol Seron, "Critical Legal Studies versus Critical Legal
Theory: A Comment on Method," 6 Law & Polky 257, 269 (1984).
Hyde, "Legitimation," p. 383, tI. 5.
Antonio Gramsci, Prison Notebooks, ed. Joseph A. Buttigieg, trans. Joseph But-
tigieg and Antonio Callan (New York: Columbia University Press, 1992).
Louis Althusser, "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes toward an
Investigation)," in L.enin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster (New
York: Monthly Review Press, 1971), p. 127.
See Hyde, "Legitimation."
See Robert Gordon, "New Developments in Legal Theory," in The Politics of
Law: A Progressive Critique, ed. David Kairys (New York: Pantheon Books, 1982).
Kimberle Crenshaw, "Race, Reform, and Retrenchment: Transformation and
Legitimation in Antidiscriminacion Law," 101 Harv. L. Rev. 1331 (1988).
The "cultural studies" variant of cls shows that the rhetoric of opinions, say,
the images of women they deploy, is a part of the general cultural discourse of identity
and as such worth study. The discourse both reflects and contributes to the reproduc-
tion of widespread, culturally dominant ideas about what women and men, for ex-
ample, are naturally like. Moreover, cultural imagery may weigh more heavily than
either deduction or policy in influencing judicial rule choice. This is an extension of
the idea that appellate adjudication is a forum of ideology, where liberals and conser-
vatives fight it out and where the marginal, more extreme positions are "silenced."
The discourse of the forum may legitimate, say, gender roles. But this is not the kind
of effect I address in the text. Legitimation, as I am using the term, is an effect of the
specific institutional practice of adjudication rather than of authoritative discourse i n
general. See Peter Gabel, "The Mass Psychology of the New Federalism: How the
Burger Court's Political Imagery Legitimizes the Privatization of Everyday Life," 52
Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 263 (1984); Rosemary Coombe, "Contesting the Self: Negotiating
Subjectivities in Nineteenth-Century Ontario Defamation Trials," 11 Studies in Law,
Politics, and Society 3 (1991); Nathaniel Berman, "A Perilous Ambivalence: Nationalist
Desire, Legal Autonomy, and the Limits of the Interwar Framework," 33 Harv. mt.
L.]. 353 (1992); Lisa Binder, "'With More Than Admiration He Admired': Images
of Beauty and Defilement in Judicial Narratives of Rape," i8 Harv. Women's Law].
265 (1995); Susan Keller, "The Rhetoric of Marriage, Achievement, and Power: An
Analysis olJudicial Opinions Considering Professional Degrees as Marital Property,
21 Vt. L. Rev (1996).
See Sally Merry, Getting Justice and Getting Even: Legal Consciousness among Work-
ing-Class Americans (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), p. i t.; Barbara
Yngvesson, Virtuous Citizens, Disruptive Subjects: Order and Complaint in a New England
Court (New York: Routledge, 1993), pp. II-12.
406 Notes to Pages 276-284
SeeChapter2.
Thomas Heller, "Structuralism and Critique," 36 Stan. L. Rev. 127 (1984).
See Joseph Singer, "The Legal Rights Debate in Analytical Jurisprudence from
Bentham to Hohfeld," 1982 Wisc. L. Rev. 975,
Roberto M. Unger, Knowledge and Politics (New York: Free Press, i7), p. 88.
Duncan Kennedy, "Legal Formality," 2f. Legal Studies 351, 364, im. 21, 22
(1973); Duncan Kennedy, "Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication," 89
Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976).
This form of normative external determination is the subject of the next two
chapters.
Richard A. Posner, Problems ofJurisprudence (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1990), pp. 459-460.
Austin Sarat, "Legal Effectiveness and Social Studies of Law: On the Unfortu-
nate Persistence of a Research Tradition," 9 Leg. Stud. Forum 23, 30-31 (1985).
Boaventura de Sousa Santos, Toward a New Common Sense: Law, Science, and
Politics in the Paradigmatic Transition (New York: Routledge, 1995).
What follows is an account of an actual debate, carried out over four or five
years at conferences and summer camps. The account is no doubt seriously defective
as history because of the vagaries of memory and the distorting influence of narcissistic
investment. The debate was only partly reflected in the writings of the participants I
refer to in the course of the narrative.
Morton Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 1788-1860 (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, ,çy,ri); Karl Klare, "Judicial Deradicalization of the
Wagner Act and the Origins of Modern Legal Consciousness," 62 Minn. L. Rev. 265
(1978); Peter Gabel, "Intention and Structure in Contractual Conditions: Outline of
a Method for Critical Legal Theory," 6x Minn. L. Rev, 6oz ('977); Mark Tushnet, "A
Marxist Analysis of American Law," i Marxist Perspectives 96 (1978); Trubek, "Com-
plexity and Contradiction"; Jay Feinman and Peter Gabel, "Contract Law as Ideology,"
in The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique, ed. David Kairys (New York: Pantheon
Books, 1982).
Evgeny Pashukanis, Lawand Marxism: A General Theory, trans. Barbara Einhorn
(London: Ink Links, 1978); Isaac Balbus, "Commodity Form and Legal Form: An Essay
on the 'Relative Autonomy' of the Law," u Law &Soc'y Rev. 57' (1977).
Willard Hurst, Law and the Conditions ofFreedom in the Nineteenth Century Unirei
Stares (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1956).
Lawrence Friedman, A History of American Law (New York: Simon and Schuster,
1973). For the neo-Marxist critique, see Mark Tushnet, "Perspectives on the Devel-
opment of American Law: A Critical Review of Friedman's 'A History of American
Law," 1977 Wisc. L. Rev. 8i.
Duncan Kennedy, "Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication," 89 Hart'.
L, Rev. 1685 (1976); Unger, The Critical Legal Studies Movement.
Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law.
Notes to Pages 284-287 407
z. For example, Gerald Frug, "The City as a Legal Concept," 93 Harv. L. Reiz
1057 (1980); Mark Kelman, "Interpretive Construction in the Substantive Criminal
Law," 33 Stan. L. Rev 591 (1981); William Simon, "Visions of Practice in Legal
Thought," 36 Sian. L. Rev. 496 (1984); William Simon, "The Invention and Reinven-
tion of Welfare Rights," 44 AId. L. Rev. i (1985).
Robert Gordon, "Unfreezing Legal Reality: Critical Approaches co Law," 15
F/a. St. L. Ret' 195 (1987).
Hyde, "Legitimation"; Crenshaw, "Retrenchment."
Some examples of the underlying attitude I'm talking about are Alan Freeman,
"Truth and Mystification in Legal Scholarship," 90 Ya/e U. 1229 (1981); Mark Kel-
man, "Trashing," 36 Stan. L. Rev. 293 (1984); Duncan Kennedy and Peter Gabel,
"Roll Over Beethoven," 36 Stan. L. Rev 1 (1984).
5. I)uncan Kennedy, "The Structure of Blackstone's Commentaries," 28 Buff L.
Rev 205 (1979); John Nockleby, "Tortious Interference with Contractual Relations in
the Nineteenth Century: The Transformation of Property, Contract, and Tort," 93
Hart'. L. Rev 1510(1980); Kenneth Vandevelde, "The New Property of the Nineteenth
Century: The Development of the Modern Concept of Property," 29 Buff L. Rev 325
(1980); James Kamen, "Nineteenth Century Interpretations of the Federal Contract
Clause: The Transformation from Vested to Substantive Rights Against the State," 3 i
Buff L. Rev. 381 (1982); Joseph Singer, "The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and
Legal Theory," 94 Ya/e U. i (1984).
Kennedy, "Blackstone's Commentaries," pp. 362-363, n. 56; Duncan Kennedy,
"The Role of Law in Economic Thought: Essays on the Fetishism of Commodities,"
34 Amer. Univ L Rev 939 (1985).
Karl Klare, "Law Making as Praxis," Telos, Summer ¡979, 123.
Robert Gordon, "Critical Legal Histories," 36 Stan. L. Rev. 57, 110-113(1984).
W. N. Hohfeld, "Some Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial
Reasoning," 23 Ya/e U. 16(1913). See Joseph Singer, "The Legal Rights Debate in
Analytical Jurisprudence from Bencham to Hohfeld," 1982 Wisc. L. Rev 975.
50, Kennedy, "Form and Substance"; Duncan Kennedy, "Pacernalist and Distrib-
utive Motives in Contract and Tort Law, with Special Reference to Compulsory Terms
and Unequal Bargaining Power," 41 Mary/and L. Rev. 563 (1982).
51. Duncan Kennedy and Frank Michelman, "Are Property and Contract Effi-
cient)" 8 Hofsrra L. Rev. 7'' (1980); Kennedy, "Role of Law." See generally the dis-
cussion of "contradictionism" in Chapter 4, particularly n. i6.
408 Notes to Pages 287-291
[New York: Monthly Review Press, '9701) that emphasizes the impossibility of op-
erating without some inevitably partial cognitive framework.
Mark Kelman, A Guide to Critical Legal Studies (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1987), p. 269.
Hunt, Explorations. p. 154. This formulation is meant to be responsive to Ha-
bermas's brilliant critique of structural Marxist theories in Knowledge and Human In-
teresu, trans. Jeremy Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1971).
For a great collection, see Michael Fischi, "The Question That Killed Critical
Legal Studies,' 17 Law & Soc. Inquiry 779, 78 1-782 (1ç)2).
stitutional law about the proper role of unenacted outside rights. See Calder y. Bull,
3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 386 (1798), and Loan Association y. Topeka, 87 U.S. (20 Wall.) 655
(1875). Opponents of judicial reasoning from unenacted outside rights have insisted
that there is a clear difference between being outside and being inside, and that judges
should concern themselves only with the inside. Outside rights don't "really" exist;
even if they exist they are too much open to ideological controversy; even if they exist
and are clear they are nor "law."
The opponents of a "strictly positivist" position argue the flip side: that appeal to
outside rights can and should resolve gaps, conflicts, and ambiguities that arise when
the judge tries to ignore the normative sources of law, and so forth. In other words,
the positivists celebrate judicial method and denigrate rights theory, while the inter-
pretivists do the opposite. This discussion remains marginal. Most of the time, the
ideological intelligentsias that deploy constitutional argument confront each other in
the intermediate zone. In the intermediate zone, both sides claim enacted constitu-
tional rights and the objectivity of judicial method.
i. Minow, "Interpreting Rights"; Schneider, "The Dialectic of Rights and Poli-
tics"; Gabel, "Phenomenology."
i 6. Oliver Wendell Holmes, 'The Path of the Law," in Colleaed Legal Papers (Buf-
falo, N.Y.: William S. Hein, 1985), p. i8i.
17. Henry Terry, "Legal Duties and Rights," ¡2 Yale L.]. i8,
¡88 (1903).
still be plenty threatening to the idea that identifying them in the abstract will get
away from the kind of "value judgment" that you invented them to avoid. This doesn't
seem to have occurred to political philosophers outside law, but it is close to an
obsession, in the form of the "countermajoritarian difficulty," of American jurispru-
dence.
5. BelL English, 'Keeping Rights in Perspective," Boston Globe, July 22, 1991,
5. 2, p. 13.
36. "1 can engage in homosexual intercourse because I have a right to sexual free-
dom." "1 can organize a PAC with corporate contributions because I have a right of
free speech." "Slavery is wrong because it denies the inalienable rights of life, liberty,
and property." "Nondisclaimable strict products liability is wrong because it denies
the right of freedom of contract." "Compulsory membership in a labor union is wrong
because it denies the right of free association; the banning of strikes is wrong because
it denies the right to strike." "The banning of sale of contraceptives is wrong because
it violates the right to privacy."
3. An exemplary critique of this kind is Jeremy Paul, "Book Review," 88 Mich.
L. Rev. 1622 (z99oXreview of Jeremy Waldron, The Right to Private Property).
Martha Minow, "Interpreting Rights: An Essay for Robert Cover," 96 Yale L.].
x86o (1987); Elizabeth Schneider, "The Dialectic of Rights and Politics: Perspectives
from the Women's Movement," 6i N.YU.L. Rev. 589 (1986).
Karl Marx, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, vol. i, trans. Ben Fowkes
(New York: Vintage Books, 1977).
Karl Marx, Critique of the Gotha Program (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1971).
Karl Marx, "On the Jewish Question," in Writings of the Young Marx on Philos-
ophy and Society, ed. and trans. Loyd Easton and Kurt Guddat (Garden City, N.Y.:
Anchor, 1967), p. 216. This essay is full of neo-Hegelian anti-Semitic ideas. I think
this is one of those cases where the dross doesn't corrupt the gold. It is also typically
"early Marx."
See, for example, Peter Gabel, "The Phenomenology of Rights Consciousness
and the Pact of the Withdrawn Selves," 62 Texas L. Rev. 1563 (1984); Alan Freeman
and Elizabeth Mensch, "The Public-Private Distinction in American Law and Life,"
36 Buff L. Rev. 237 (1987); Duncan Kennedy, "The Structure of Blackstone's Com-
mentaries," 28 Buff L. Rev. 205 (1979); Duncan Kennedy and Peter Gabel, "Roll
Over Beethoven," 36 Stan. L. Rev. i (1984).
There are a number of critical analyses of the role of rights rhetoric at different
stages of social movements and at different moments in American political history.
See Gabel, "Phenomenology," and Alan Hunt, "Rights and Social Movements:
Counter-Hegemonic Strategies," ¡7]. Law & Soc'y 309 (1990). They aren't examples
of the rights critique, although they sometimes presuppose it.
14. CONCLUSION
i. To my mind, the best statement of this way of looking at mpm is Nathaniel
Berman's discussion of modernism in "Modernism, Nationalism, and the Rhetoric of
Notes to Pages 345-358 413
Reconstruction," 4 Ya/eJ. Law & Human. 351 (1992). For an interesting interpretation
of cls as left modernism, see David Luban, "Legal Modernism," 84 Mich. L. Rev. i66
(1986).
Jeremy Paul, "The Politics of Semiotics," 69 Texas L. Rev. 1779, 1812-1813
(199!).
Jack Balkin, "The Politics of Legal Semiotics," 69 Texas L. Rev. 1831, 1846-
1848 (1991).
Ibid.
,. Clare Dalton, "Book Review," 6 Harv. Women's L. Rev. 229 (1982) (reviewing
The Politics of Lau; ed. David Kairys); Gerald Frug, "The Ideology of Bureaucracy in
American Law," 97 Harv. L. Ret: 1276 (1984); David Kennedy, "The Turn to Inter-
pretation," 8 So. Cal. L. Rev I (1985); Gary Peller, "The Metaphysics of American
Law," 73 Cal. L. Rev 1152 (1985); David Kennedy, "Critical Theory, Structuralism,
and Contemporary Legal Scholarship," 21 New Eng. L. Rev. 209 (1986). I tried to
counter this approach in Duncan Kennedy, "Freedom and Constraint in Adjudication:
A Critical Phenomenology," 36f. Legal Educ. 518 (1986), and Duncan Kennedy, "A
Semiotics of Legal Argument," 42 Syracuse L. Rev. 75 (1991) (and same article with
"European Introduction: Four Objections," in Collected Courses o/the Academy ofEuropean
Lau'. vol. 3, book 2 ['994], p. 309). The view I favor is close to that of Gerald Frug
in "Argument as Character," 40 Stan. L. Rev. 869 (1988), and Matthew Kramer, Legal
Theory, Political Theory, and Deconstruriion: Against Rhadamanthus (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1991), p. 248: "Determinacy, for deconstructive critics, presents itself
as a function or a moment in an unstoppable interweaving of fixed structures and free
play. Dererminacy and indeterminacy generate and exclude each other in a process that
is itself both indeterminate and determinate . . . Derrida has made much the same
point . . : '[T]he production of differences, différance, is not astructural: it produces
.
systematic and regulated transformations which are able, at a certain point, to leave
room for a structural science. The concept of di//france even develops the most legiti-
mate principled exigencies of "structuralism" (citing Jacques Derrida, Positions [Chi-
cago: University of Chicago Press, 1981], p. 28)." But Kramer seems to me to fall
into the error of believing that it is always possible to deconstruct, even though it
may not happen in a given case, whereas to my mind deconstruction has nothing to
say about its own possibility or impossibility outside a particular instance. See Part
Three.
Frank Michelman and Margaret Radin, "Pragmatist and Poststructuralist Crit-
ical Legal Practice," 139 U. Pa. L. Rev ¡019, 1035-1036 (199!).
Jacques Derrida, Spectres o/Marx, trans. Peggy Knauf (New York: Routledge,
1994), pp. 77-88.
Sanford Levinson and Jack Balkin, "Law, Music, and Other Performing Arts,"
139 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1597 (1991).
. Michelle Green, The Dream at the End o/the World: Paul Bow/es and the Literary
i i. In law, some different efforts of this kind that I am aware of are François Geny,
Science et technique en droit privé posiuj nouvelle contribution à la critique de la méthode
juridique (Paris: L. Tenin, 1914-1924); Roscoe Pound ,Jurispruànce (St. Paul, Minn.:
West Pub. Co., 1959); Harold Laswell and Myres McDougal, "Legal Education and
Public Policy: Professional Training in the Public Interest," 52 Yale L.]. 203 (ii);
Richard Posner, Problems ofJurisprudence (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1990); Frank Michelman, "Law's Republic," 97 Yale U. '493 (1988); Margaret Radin,
Reinterpreting Property (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, '993); and Roberto Un-
ger, Politics: A Work in Constructive Social Theoy (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 1987). The last of these is full of things I agree with, for all my reconstructive
unmusicality.
Nigel Purvis, "Critical Legal Studies in Public International Law," 32 Harz
mt. U. 8i, 127 (199lXemphasis in original).
Michael Fischi, "The Question That Killed Critical Legal Studies," 17 L.au'&
Soc. Inquiry 779, 800 (1992).
Kimberle Crenshaw, "Mapping the Margins: Identity Politics, Intersectionality,
and Violence against Women," 43 Stan. L. Rev. 124! (199!). On the relation between
mpm metaphysics and politics, see Kramer, Legal Theory, pp. 246-247.
'5. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth o/the Prison, trans. Alan Sheri-
dan (New York: Vintage, 1979).
i6. Scientific education also involves extensive normalization but is understood to
measure a much narrower band of capacitiesmemory and pure cognitive ability. Law
school resembles the prep school I went to, where you were called on in most classes
most days, took endless quizzes and tests as well as several different national aptitude
and achievement tests each year, and in one class got a grade on your oral recitation
in Greek every single day.
I 7. Duncan Kennedy, Legal Education and the Reproduction of Hierarchy (Cambridge,
Mass.: AFAR, 1983); Duncan Kennedy, "Liberal Values in Legal Education," 19 Nova
L.]. 603 (1986); Duncan Kennedy, "Politicizing the Classroom," 4 U.S.C. Rev. Law &
Women's Studies 8i (1995). See also Toni Pickard, "Experience as Teacher: Discovering
the Politics of Law Teaching," 33 Univ. Thronto L]. 278 (1983).
i8. Joseph Raz, "The Relevance of Coherence," 72 B.U.L. Rev. 273, 304, n. 52
(1992).
INDEX
415
416 Index
Broadening, 140-142, 145, 147 z6o-,6i, 171, 205, 207; external vs. in-
Brodin, Mark, 211 ternal, i6,, 167; and deduction, 164; in
Brown y. Board of Education, 67, 80-8 1, 119, policy work, i6; frequency of, iva; in
127-128, 174, 206, 273 moderation effect, 220-22 i. See also Con-
Butler, Judith, 346-347 strained activist judge; Role constraint
Contested concept, 49-50
Calderv. Bull, 410n14 Continent, 32, 36-37, 92-95, 109, ¡79,
Capitalism, 18-19,92, 237, 249-251, 278, 263, 283. See also Europe
352; stages of, 278, 281, 283; role of law Contradiction: in judicial role constraint, 35,
in, 280-296; rights in, 335-337; manage- 120, ,8o, 202-2 12; ¡0 liberalism and
rial discourse in, 368 conservatism, 50-54, 187-19 i; 'contra-
Cardozo, Benjamin, 33, 35, 75, 96, 101, dictionism,' 83-92, 95, 239-240, 287; in
114, ii8, 120, 195 modernist legal consciousness, x; as mo-
Carrington, Paul D., 379n6 tive for denial, 193, 202-2 12; in psycho-
Carrino, Agostino, 384n1 analytic theory, 207-208; mode of in cnt-
Cheney y. Doris Silk Co., 4 10n9
¡cal legal studies, 284-285; in
Civil law, 36-37, 75-78, 102, 278; code neo-Marxist Ideology theory, 291; demo-
system in, 32, 36, 76-78, 83, 239, 241. bilizing, 295, 361-363; in managerial
See alio Continent; Europe discourse, 367-376
Clark, Gerard, 379fl4 Conversion effect, 114, 117, 124, 128, 227,
Clusters, 138, 145-146, 154 273; defined, 63-65, 70
Cohen, Felix, 82, 86-87, 105, 386n24 Cook, Walter Wheeler, 82, 385n13, 386n24
Coherence: in legal argument, 33-37; in Coombe, Rosemary, 405 fl2 I
civil law, 36-37, 6; of ideologies, o-s4; Corbin, Arthur, 82, 385n13
realist critique of in private law, 82-92; Cornell, Drusilla, 300
in continental critique, 92-95; and policy, Corwin, Edward S., 400n18
112-130; through evolutionary theory, Crenshaw, Kimberle, 262, 273, 4o1nn29,31,
z i8; through process models, ¡ ¡e-z i; in 407(143, 4o9n13, 41 ¡flfl3o,32, 414fl14
Dworkin, 119-120; and ideological work, Critical legal studies (cis): defined, 8-12; on
157, i6, 179; of constitutional law, 233- indeterminacy of legal rules, 31-32, 37;
235; of common law, 2 39-240; of regimes on rule of law, -7; and legal realism,
in social theory, 264 82-92, 113; and Dworkin, 121, 129-130;
Coleman, Jules L., 379(12 and British positivism, 172-179; and ju-
Common law: judicial regime change dicial role, 203; and delegitimation, 247-
through, 223-224; and legitimation, 263; critique of liberalism, 248, 274; as
238-247; legal realism and, 238-240; vs. radicalism, 248; contrast with legal real-
legislation, 240-247 ism, 249-263; policy proposals, 262-263,
Communism, 7, 8, 53, 73-74 271; and social theory, 265; mandarin ma-
Community, 6, 48, 359, 360 terials controversy, 265-280; skeptics cri-
Compulsory terms, 138, 145-155, 165, 176, tique, 265-280; rationalism/irnationalism
190 debate, 280-296; lack of a theory, 295;
Conservatism: defined, 46-48; ontology of, rights debate, 296, 337. See also Pink
50-54; determinacy of, z8o; in Theory
Dworkin, 121 Critical race theory, 256-257, 263, 286,
Constrained activist judge, i8o, 202, 219- 304, 327-329
223, 226, 245, 273; defined, 182-184; Critique: global internal, 32, 86, 92-95,
and denial, 194-196 179, 198, 276-277, 280; internal, 38,
Constraint: iconology of, -; by the text, 81-96, 117, 129, 164, 277, 288, 311-
index 417
312, 344, 358, 360, 362; minimalist in- DeSbaney y. Winnebago County Dept. o/Social
ternal, 86, 91, 95, 179, 279, 280, 286, Services, 116
295, 304, 311-312, 349; maximalist, 89, de Sousa Santos, Boavencura, 4o6n3 i
311-312; local, 92; global external, 92, Determinacy: of legal reasoning, i 8-20, 60,
198; of determinacy of ideology, 187-191; 92, 98, 159, i6i, 265, 267, 275-280; of
of rights, 261, 301, 303-304, 315-338 economic theory, 18-20, 279-280, 286-
Cultural critique. 254, 261, 405fl21 289; of liberalism and conservatism, ,o-
54, i8o, 187-191; ontology 01,169-171,
174; as function of work, 170; of Consti-
Dalton, Clare, 402fl42, 413fl5
tution vs. constitutional law, 230-235; of
Danielsen, Dan, 402n44, 403n47
rights reasoning, 305-306, 311-314,
Dawson, John, 76
3 16-333; and deconstruction, 348-350;
Debord, Guy, 379fl5
of managerial discourse, 367-376
Deconstruction, 15, 267, 348-350
Deutsch, Jan, 41 1n26
Deduction, 25, 30-38, 97-108; mode vs. Difference splitting, 156; judge, i8o, 184-
policy mode, -ioo; defined, 98; kinds i8, 196-198, 202, 2 19-223, 226, 245.
of, toI-1o5; ontology of, 101,107,168; 273
legal realist critique of, 103-113; guided Distributive approach, 51, 65-69, 87, 242-
by policy, 1o4-1o5; revival of, io8; in 263, 265, 279, 302, 368-370
left project, ill; in evolutionary and pro- i
cess theories, z i8-i i; in Dworkin, 120;
Donahue, John, 398n1
Dorsen, Norman, 398n9
in structure of legal discourse, 135; com- Douglas, Lawrence, 404fl3
pared to balancing, 148; as constraint, Douglas, William 0., 319, 324, 400nl9,
as work, 164-165, i68; in rights ar- 41 ini8
gument, 318-3 19, 321; and deconstruc- s'. Sand/ord, 8o, ¡74
Dred Scoff
tion, 348-350; in legal education, 366 Dworkin, Andrea, 260, 402fl40
Delgado, Richard, 409fl13 Dworkin, Ronald, 24, 33-37, 50, 75, 91,
Denial: in theory of alienated powers, 2o; in 95-96, 117, 119-1 30, 148, 162, 172,
jurisprudence, 23; of ideological in adjudi- 176, 196, 204-205, 300, 380fl6, 394f!
cation, 55-56, 67, i8, 396n7; as judicial
strategy, i8o, defined, 191-194; in differ- Economic sympathies. See Ideological prefer-
ent types of judges, 194-198; half-con- ences
scious, 199-200; as collective phenome- Economics, law and, 111, ii6, 278; critique
non, 200-202; as response to role conflict, of, 287-288
202-205; motives for public, 205-207; Edmunson, William, 395nn18,23
and contradiction, 207-209; coercive con- Effect of necessity, 161-162, i68, 187, 275
sensus and, 209; projection and, 209-212; Eisenberg, Melvin, 388n12, 389n29
and jealousy, 211-212; in the moderation Ely, John, 390fl42
effect, 2 iB; in the empowerment effect, Empowerment effect, 246, 247, 249-262,
224; in the legitimation effect, 236; in 266, 273, 279. 292, 309, 324; and denial,
Liberal legalism, 292-294; in rights dis- 202, 224-235; defined, 216
course, 336-337; in art, 344; in manage- Engle, Karen, 401fl23
rial discourse, 370.-376 Equality, 237-238, 243-246, 359, 362; and
Dennis : U.S., 411 nn 12,21 left project, 6, 302, 327-328, 360; and
DePeysier y. Michael, 394fl IO liberalism, 47, 51
Derrida, Jacques, 31, 92, 300, 346-348, 350 Esco/a y. Coca-Cola Bottling Co. of Fresno, 149,
deSaussure, Ferdinand, 133 174
DeSchutter, Olivier, 401fl22 Eskridge, William, 113, 390n43
4x8 Index
Kelsen, Hans, 31, 92, 102 Legitimation effect, 202, 216, 285; defined,
Kennedy, David, 400fln22, 4o1n23, 413fl5 2 36-238; of the status quo rather than of
pean version,92-95, iii;socialism as, ism, 282, 291-296; and neo-Marxist Ide-
299; progressivism as, 299; rights as, ology theory, 290-296; and rights, 307,
300-301; identity politics as, 302-303; 334-337
critique of rights in, 311, 316, 337-338, Liberal legalism, 13o; dilemma of, 113-117,
340-342; and workplace politics, 339- 124; Dworkin as liberal legalist, 127-130
340, 358, 368-376; mpm critique of, LIe'wellyn, Karl, 33, 35, 6-66, 75, 82, 89-.
344, 355-356; critique of mpm, 356-364 90, 96, 120, 140, 173, 385n16, 390036,
Legal education, 364-368 391n50
Legal realism: Hart's explanation of, 77, 178; Loan Association y. Topeka, 410fl14
summary genealogy of, 82-92; view of Local government law, 254-256
policy in relation to ideology, 88; relation Lochnerv. New York, 128, 174, 225, 388011
to European social current, 92-95; cri- Loss of faith: defined, 8; in reason, 286; in
tique of deduction, 103, 164, i8o; project neo-Marxism, 288-289, 314, 358, 361;
abandoned, 112, 275; Dworkin in relation and will to fight, 295-296, 337-338,
to, i1; and balancing, 147; Mac- 340; in rights, 304, 311-314, 361; if le-
Cormicks view of, 178; theory of denial, gal reasoning, 311-314, 318, 361, 373;
192; and judicial role, 203; and common not a theory, 312; in God, 312-314, 358,
law, 2 38-244; and doctrinal fields, 249- 361, 373; psychologizing, 350-353; dis-
263; contrasted with critical legal studies, loyalty as, 372-374
249-263; and social theory, 264-266; Luban, David, 4I3fl1
books/action skepticism, 265-27!; cri- Lucas y. South Carolina Coastal Council, 116,
tique of rights, 311, 320-325 389024
Legislative supremacy, counterfactual, 14, Lukacs, Georg, 290
187, 215-217, 230-231, 238-240 Lynd, Staughton, 304
Index 421
256, 332; in Dworkin, 119-130, 392n74; Scalia, Antonin, 8o, ioó, 253
oncology of, 123, 307, 319, 332, 333; as Schauer, Frederick, 388n7
argument-bites, 138, 175-177; as rules Scheuerman, William, 408n62
and as reasons, 139; constitutional, 139, Schlag, Pierre, 390n33, 393fl6, 396n7,
230-235, 315, 320-329; role in left pro- 413f 10
ject, 300-301; cls critique of, 303-304; in Schmitt, Carl, 4o8fl62
American political discourse. 304; Marxist Schneider, Elizabeth, 4o2n42, 403fl49,
critique of, 304, 335-337; "faccoid," 3°,; 409fl12, 410fl15, 412fl38
as mediators, 305-306, 331, 334, 336; Schultz, Victoria, 402fl42
decerminacy of reasoning from, 305-306, Schwartz, Louis, 304
316-333; inside and outside, 306-308, Semiotics, 15, 90, 133, 147, 176, 190, 254,
315, 316-320, 329-333, 410n14; objec- 327
tivity of reasoning from, 308; and iden- Seron, Carol, 272
tity, 308, 320, 327-329, 334-335; rea- Shapiro, David L., 25
soning from parallel co legal reasoning, Shapiro, Martin, 394n16
309-31 i; bad faith in argument from, Sherry, Suzanna, 387fl37
310-311, 338; realist critique of, 311, Sic ucere tuo, 85, 91, 329, 343
320-325,411n34; loss of faith in, 311- Silbey, Susan, 266, 275, 277-278
314, 311-338, 361-362; deduction in Simon, William, 4o3n5r, 407fl41
reasoning from, 318-319, 321; mediate Singer, Joseph, 385n16, 386n2o, 4o6n25,
between law and policy, 3 19-320, 336; 407nn45,49
reduction of to morality and social welfare Socialism, 287, 299
argument, 329, 332; lay discourse of, Social vs. formal conceptions of law, 92-95,
330-332; argument ideologically perme- 111
able, 332; and bourgeois revolutions, 334- Social welfare arguments: in liberalism and
337; mpm critique of, 340-346 conservatism, 47, 148; in policy argu-
Rodot, Stefano, 387n4o, 389n28 ment, 99, 138, 148; universal nature of,
Rogers, Kipp, 400fl9 iio;inDworkin, 120, 123, 125-127;as
Role constraint, 35, 120, 202-2 12 argument-bites, 138, 175-177; in relation
Rosen, Jeffrey, 38on5, 395f! to rights arguments, 317
Rosenblatt, Rand, 404f ¡0 Sociology of law, 14-18, 57-70; American,
Rosenfeld, Michel, 399n6 266-280; neo-Marxist, 280-296; and le-
Rule of law: defined, 13-14; in theory ofal- gitimation effect, 404n9
ienated powers, r8; in Liberalism, 27; in Solum, Lawrence, 395fl23
liberalism and conservatism, 47; contrast Southern Burlington County NAACP , Tou'n-
with ideology, in Europe vs. America, ship of M:. Liurel, 225
73-75; consistency with policy argument, Southern Pacific y. Jensen. 38! n 2
113; consistency with ideologically ori- Sowell, Thomas, 4111130
ented legal work, 163, 204; and denial, Sparer, Edward, 304
194-198; as guide vs. constraint, 202- Specht, Leopold, 4o3n48, 4o8n52
212; and moderation effect, 222; and em- Stalin, Joseph, 330, 362, 375-376
powerment effect, 227-228 Stalinism, 304, 323, 361-363
Rules of the game. See Background rules Standards, 99, 137, 138; as rules and as rea-
sons, 139, 144, 15 1-152, 393fl5
Sacco, Rodolfo, 78, 387n41 Status quo. See Ideology; Legitimation effect
Sarat, Austin, 278, 404fl3 Statutory interpretation, 89, 98; and modera-
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 6, 82, 199-201, tion effect, 2 17-223; and empowerment
205, 208, 356 effect, 224
424 Index