Artificial Intelligence Painting The Bigger Picture For Copyright Ownership
Artificial Intelligence Painting The Bigger Picture For Copyright Ownership
I. INTRODUCTION
intelligence (“AI”),2 the ability of a computer system to ‘perform tasks normally requiring
human intelligence’.3 Global leader in AI, Andrew Ng, has coined AI the ‘new electricity’ as
Creative industries have started experimenting with AI and have employed it to create works
of different kind. The concept of works being created by AI is ‘no longer just the stuff of
science fiction movies.’ 6 AI is currently ‘painting pictures, writing poetry and making music’.7
In 2016 an AI program wrote a short novel that almost won the Nikkei Hoshi Schnichi Literary
Award in Japan.8 Further to this, works by AI are being commercialised. By way of example,
an artwork created by AI, the Portrait of Edmond Belamy, sold at the historic Christie’s Auction
House in New York for almost $620,500.00 (AUD) in October 2018,9 and Warners Music
signed the world’s first-ever record label with an AI algorithm at the beginning of 2019 to
Onformative showcased their audio-visual art installation, Meandering River that comprised
4 Andrew Ng quoted in E Kumar Sharma, ‘AI is the New Electricity, Says Coursera’s Andrew Ng,’ Business
Today (Article, 5 March 2018) <https://www.businesstoday.in/opinion/interviews/ai-is-the-new-electricity-says-
courseras-andrew-ng/story/271963.html>.
5 Peter Stone et al, ‘Artificial Intelligence and Life in 2030: One Hundred Year Study on Artificial Intelligence’,
AI100 Stanford (Report, September 2016) 45 <
https://ai100.stanford.edu/sites/g/files/sbiybj9861/f/ai_100_report_0831fnl.pdf>.
6 Shlomit Yanisky-Ravid, ‘Generating Rembrandt: Artificial Intelligence, Copyright, and Accountability in the
3A Era – The Human-Like Authors are Already Here – A New Model’ [2017] (4) Michigan State Law Review
659, 668 citing Brad Merrill, It’s Happening: Robots May Be the Creative Artists of the Future, MAKE USE
OF (Dec. 17, 2014), http://www.makeuseof.com/tag/happening- robots-may-creative-artists-future/
[https://perma.cc/8AY7-NPDA].
7 Maria Diaz, ‘Artificial Intelligence and Copyright’, Lexology (Article, 17 April 2018)
<https://www.lexology.com/library/detail.aspx?g=ab3340fa-57e5-4145-afe9-110b088c9e36>.
8 Chloe Olewitz, ‘A Japanese A.I. Program Just Wrote a Short Novel, and it Almost Won a Literary Prize’,
Digital Trends (Article, 23 March 2016) <https://www.digitaltrends.com/cool-tech/japanese-ai-writes-novel-
passes-first-round-nationanl-literary-prize/>.
9 Gabe Cohn, ‘AI Art at Christie’s Sells for $432,500’, The New York Times (online, 25 October 2018)
<https://www.nytimes.com/2018/10/25/arts/design/ai-art-sold-christies.html>.
10 ‘Warner Music Signs First Ever Record Deal with an Algorithm’, The Guardian (online, 23 March 2019) <
https://www.theguardian.com/music/2019/mar/22/algorithm-endel-signs-warner-music-first-ever-record-deal>.
11 ‘Work – Meandering River’, Onformative (Web Page, 2018) <https://onformative.com/work/meandering-
river>.
copyright protection requirements and ownership.12 To receive copyright protection for a work
in Australia it is essential that the work originates from one or more human authors.13 This
AI arguably cannot satisfy this requirement. As a result, these works do not receive copyright
protection and immediately enter the public domain. The question emerges whether such
current legal situation is justified or whether any changes in law are needed.
The article will first introduce readers to the concept of AI and its different types. Second, it
will revisit copyright protection requirements and discuss cases that introduced ‘human author’
element as a precondition for a work to get copyright protection. Then, it will argue that it is
worthwhile to provide copyright protection to works created by AI and, finally, assess who
would be the owner of rights into such works. The analysis in this article is based on Australian
AI has been referred to as a ‘suitcase word’ as it can mean many things. 14 Colloquially, it is ‘a
term used for when a machine imitates the cognitive functions commonly associated with
human minds, such as problem solving and learning.’15 AI is capable of imitating the cognition
of creativity and this is shown by the production of works in ‘almost every copyrightable
medium, such as music, poetry, literature, news, and many others.’ 16 This chapter will explore
12 Yanisky-Ravid, n 6, 683.
13 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142, 143.
14 Marvin Minsky cited in Tina Nord, ‘What is Artificial Intelligence’, Lernen Wie Maschinen (Article, 12 April
2018) < https://www.lernen-wie-maschinen.ai/en/ki-pedia/was-ist-kuenstliche-intelligenz/>.
15 Garrett Huson, ‘I, Copyright’ (2018) 35 Santa Clara High Technology Law Journal 54, 55 citing Stuart J.
Russell & Peter Norvig, Artificial Intelligence: A Modern Approach 4-5 (1995).
16 Yanisky-Ravid, n 6, 668 citing Peter Kugel, Artificial Intelligence and Visual Art, 14 LEONARDO 137, 137-
39 (1981).
types of AI. A key distinction will be made between the opaque processes behind computer
Packed into the ‘suitcase’ of AI are various types of AI placed along a spectrum from weak to
strong or narrow to general.17 For the purpose of this paper, the more relevant AI is strong and
general AI that is capable of ‘autonomously creating works, with little to no human input.’ 18
The technology has advanced to a point that we have reached the fourth wave of AI,
autonomy.19 AI is no longer acting as a tool to assist humans to create works; the technology
expanded beyond ‘simple mathematical tasks,’ processing information in ways much like
human brains.21
designed by UK company, DeepMind, to play the intuitive board game called Go. 22 The
significant characteristic of the board game is that the ‘number of possible configurations of
the board are more than the number of atoms in the universe.’ 23 AlphaGo implemented a type
of AI, reinforcement learning, to successfully account for this large number of possible
configurations and teach itself to play the game. AlphaGo became so advanced that it beat 18-
17 Russ Pearlman, ‘Recognizing Artificial Intelligence (AI) As Authors and Inventors Under U.S. Intellectual
Property Law’ (2018) 24(2) Richmond Journal of Law and Technology 1, 11.
18 Ana Ramalho, ‘Will Robots Rule The (Artistic) World? A Proposed Model For The Legal Status Of Creations
By Artificial Intelligence Systems’ (July 2017) 21(1) Journal of Internet Law 12, 13.
19 AI expert, Kai-Fu Lee, identifies four waves of artificial intelligence including internet, business, perception
and autonomous: Kai-Fu Lee, AI Superpowers: China, Silicon Valley, and the New World Order (Houghton
Mifflin Harcourt, 2018) 105.
20 Rex M Shoyama, ‘Intelligent Agents: Authors, Makers, and Owners of Computer-Generated works in
Canadian Copyright Law’ (2005) 4(2) Canadian Journal of Law and Technology 129, 131.
21 Pearlman, n 17, 6 [8].
22 DeepMind Technologies Limited, ‘AlphaGo’, Deepmind (Web Page, 2019) <
https://deepmind.com/research/alphago/>.
23 AlphaGo (Netflix, 2017).
learning is the use of neural networks. The neural networks ‘mimic the function of human
receptors that function like neurons; they find and create connections and similarities within
the data they process.’25 The use of neural networks allows AI to learn from the input data and
teach itself, rather than being supervised by parameters from the already labelled input data.
Therefore, reinforcement learning goes beyond machine learning as it can make decisions.
Reinforcement learning is an aspect of technology that will warrant even further advancements
in AI, and see AI enter ‘the realm of learning about and executing actions in the real world.’ 26
Away from the gaming industry and into the creative industry, there is the example of Google
Magenta that also uses neural networks. Neural networks are used in Google Magenta to
simulate the human brain without the actual aid of human input to compose music. 27 According
to Andrew NG, the basic idea behind how these AI systems produce new and creative works
is akin to building a rocket ship.28 To build a rocket ship, you need a huge engine and a lot of
fuel. The rocket engine is the learning algorithms, and the fuel is the input data. 29 By fueling
the learning algorithms with input data an output is produced and you have take-off.
While the basis of AI in its algorithms and code is mathematical, the subjective world of human
embedded in code’31 and therefore are subjective. This subjectivity supports the contention that
AI can be creative because the input data acts as ‘a verbal or visual vocabulary of its own’.32
The input data is fundamental, as it is equivalent to the subjective world of a human author and
applying a system of rules.’33 It is apparent that computer algorithms and learning machines
The creativity of AI has been described to be determined by a ‘dial of creativity.’ 35 When this
dial is turned up high, AI will be extra creative and produce works that do not always make
sense. An example is Google’s AI program, Poem Portraits, that generates a poem from one
input word. When the word ‘copyright’ was entered, the AI system created the following
perplexing poem: ‘This copyright proceeds and seems, This gloom of the deep dews are still
and grave.’36 On the other hand, when the dial is turned down low, AI will produce an output
that is repetitive and possibly plagiarism of the input data.37 It is when the dial is in the middle
where balance is achieved to create a work that is indistinguishable from a human author.
30 Diaz, n 7.
31 TED, ‘The era of blind faith in big data must end | Cathy O’Neil’ (YouTube, 7 September 2017)
<https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=_2u_eHHzRto>.
32 Annemarie Bridy, ‘Coding Creativity: Copyright and the Artificially Intelligent Author’ (2012) Stanford
Technology Law Review 5, 21.
33 Bridy, n 32, 21 citing Roman Verostko, Epigenetic Art Revisited: Software as Genotype, in CODE: THE
LANGUAGE OF OUR TIME 156, 159-60 (Gerfried Stocker & Christine Schopf eds., 2003).
34 Kalin Hristov, ‘Artificial Intelligence and the Copyright Dilemma’ (2017) 57 The Journal of the Franklin
Pierce Center for Intellectual Property 431, 431.
35 ‘Chocolate Chicken Chicken Cake,’ Sleepwalkers (iHeartRadio, 9 May 2019) 00:10:44.
36 Es Devlin, ‘Poem Portraits’, Arts Experiments (Web Page)
<https://artsexperiments.withgoogle.com/poemportraits?_ga=2.33161846.992826029.1556786810-
799000725.1554196893>.
37 ‘Chocolate Chicken Chicken Cake,’ n 35.
involvement when gathering input data and producing outputs. The Australian courts have
largely considered cases concerning computer generated works, not works created by AI. It is
the examples of computer generated works from the cases discussed in the next chapter that
demonstrate the significant human input required for computer generated works. For instance,
in Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd humans were involved in
audio-visual art installation, Meandering River, that compiles satellite images itself and
transforms them in real-time, ‘changing iteratively and altering the simulated landscape around
it.’39 Unlike computer generated works, AI is not a tool. AI ‘actually makes many of the
decisions involved in the creative process without human intervention.’40 There is a clear
distinction ‘between a computer program that requires a person to control and supply
information to it, and intelligent agents that can autonomously gather information from
AI ‘is imprinted with design choices that can lead to both intended and unintended
consequences’,42 whereas the output of computer generated works can be anticipated. In the
example of AlphaGo, the AI performed moves in the board game by independently identifying
patterns that the programmer did not expect. The term ‘emergence’ describes when programs
produce outputs their programmers and users could not predict. 43 Computer generated works
38 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142.
39 Sedition, ‘Onformative: Meandering River at Google I/O’, Sedition Art (Magazine Article, 9 April 2019)
<https://www.seditionart.com/magazine/onformative-meandering-river-at-
google-i-o>.
40 Andres Guadamuz, ‘Artificial Intelligence and Copyright’ (Issue 5, October 2017) WIPO Magazine.
41 Shoyama, n 20.
42 Australian Human Rights Commission and World Economic Forum, Artificial Intelligence:
Governance and Leadership (White Paper, 2019) 8.
43 Margot E Kaminski, ‘Authorship, Disrupted: AI Authors in Copyright and First Amendment Law’ (2017) 51
University of California, Davis 589, 593 citing Calo, Lessons of Cyberlaw, supra note 10, at 532, 538.
beyond what it is programmed to do demonstrates its autonomy and its distinction from
The first issue that needs to be clarified here is the legal status of works created by AI. In order
to receive copyright protection under Australian copyright law, a work must be expressed in
material form,44 it must fall within the parameters of the categories of works, 45 it must be
original,46 and it must be connected in some way to Australia. 47 Works created by AI are able
to meet essentially all of these requirements, except for the current originality standard.
Historically, the standard of originality under Australian copyright law was ‘quite low.’48 For
a work to be protected under copyright law, a mere ‘skill or labour’ or ‘sweat of the brow’ was
sufficient.49 One of the first cases dealing with the originality standard in Australia was Sands
& McDougall Pty Ltd v Robinson.50 The case held ‘the exercise of judgment and
discrimination’ was sufficient to confer originality. 51 There was no further explicit qualification
that the work had to be by an actual person, as the law currently stipulates. According to Isaacs
J, ‘all literary works are protected if “original.” That is the only condition.’ 52 Therefore, AI,
‘investment of time, money and effort (…).’53 For example, in Desktop Marketing System Pty
Ltd v Telstra Corp Ltd case,54 telephone directories were protected as ‘original’ works since
they required ‘substantial labour and expense’. 55 The substantial labour and expense were
region.56 A team of human workers had ‘laboriously rekeyed’ the data manually. 57 If this lower
originality standard applied today, it is arguable that works created by AI could meet this low
Desktop Marketing System Pty Ltd v Telstra Corp Ltd,58 is analogous to the output of AI.59 AI
‘collects’ from the input data to create output and in some instances gathers the input data itself.
Therefore, the output of AI as the particular collection of input data may have held copyright
Two relatively recent cases have changed the traditional standard of originality in Australia.
First, the IceTV Pty Ltd v Nine Network Australia Pty Ltd case of 200960 that concerned Weekly
Schedules of television broadcast information. IceTV gathered the programme time and title
programme guide called ‘IceGuide.’ 61 Nine alleged that IceTV’s reproduction of the time and
title information constituted a substantial part of their Weekly Schedule and therefore infringed
copyright. However, the High Court found in favour of IceTV and held there was no
infringement because there was no originality in the way the time and title of the television
programmes could be expressed.62 There was ‘little, if any, choice’ in the particular form of
expressing the time and title of the television programmes. 63 Most importantly, in obiter, the
High Court disapproved of prior originality standard of mere ‘skill and labour’ and affirmed
‘that there must be some “creative spark” or exercise of “skill and judgment” before a work is
This higher standard of originality set in IceTV case could still be met by works created by AI.
It is arguable the AI process of discriminating through the input data to create an output satisfies
the exercise of judgment required for a work to be considered sufficiently original. The
problem of originality with relation to AI works arises with the successive cases of Telstra
Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd65 and Acohs Pty Ltd v Ucorp Pty Ltd66
which emphasise that copyright protection can only subsist if a work originates from an actual
person.67
In Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd,68 humans were involved in
gathering and organising the collection of material for the telephone directories, however this
61 IceTV Pty Ltd v Nine Network Australia Pty Ltd (2009) 239 CLR 458.
62 IceTV Pty Ltd v Nine Network Australia Pty Ltd (2009) 239 CLR 458, 477 [42].
63 IceTV Pty Ltd v Nine Network Australia Pty Ltd (2009) 239 CLR 458, 477 [42].
64 IceTV Pty Ltd v Nine Network Australia Pty Ltd (2009) 239 CLR 458, 516 [187] (Gummow, Hayne and
Heydon JJ).
65 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142.
66 Acohs Pty Ltd v Ucorp Pty Ltd (2012) 201 FCR 173.
67 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142, 172 [100] (Perram J).
68 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142.
10
arranging the directories in alphabetical order and subliming the information into electronic
form that constituted the creation of the work.69 As there was no human involvement in this
extraction phase, copyright was held not to subsist in the telephone directories. 70 Namely, in
Telstra Corporation v Phone Directories Company, the Full Federal Court not only followed
the ‘independent intellectual effort’ standard introduced by the High Court in IceTV case, but
also highlighted the requirement ‘that the work originates with an author or joint authors’.71
The absence of a human author behind the collection of directories by Telstra led to the absence
The new originality standard makes it difficult, if not impossible, to award copyright protection
to works created by AI. Similar to Telstra Corporation v Phone Directories case, in cases of
works created by AI, humans do not directly participate in the creation of works. They create
the algorithm and may (or may not) provide some input data, while the output, i.e. the work, is
case is that the equivalent of an extraction phase for AI is more sophisticated than a computer
program generating a telephone directory. Rather than merely organising details in alphabetical
order, AI exercises judgment to discriminate input data that has multiple possibilities beyond
the order of the alphabet. Thus, the output of AI is much more creative than that of computer
program as, for example, the one used by Telstra. Despite this, the output will not be protected
69 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142, 173 [102].
70 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142, 193.
71 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142, [82].
11
Acohs Pty Ltd v Ucorp Pty Ltd,72 the creation of electronic material safety data sheets for
hazardous products involved programmers and transcribers. The programmers wrote the
program, Infosafe System, and the transcribers input data to affect the layout, appearances and
attributes of the data sheet.73 Similarly to Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories
Company Pty Ltd,74 the identifiable human involvement was not considered authorship because
it did not relate directly to the creation of the work. It was the source code by computer program
Infosafe System, not a human, that generated the material safety data sheets. Therefore, the
human involvement in this case was further removed from the direct creation of the work.
Human involvement can be even further removed in cases where AI can write its own code to
generate a work.75
As a result, the requirement that works originate from an actual person presents a significant
hurdle for works created by AI receiving copyright protection. Because origination from an
actual person is an essential requirement to satisfy the originality standard and attract copyright,
it is clear that works created by AI are not currently protected by copyright in Australia as they
The question that will be explored next is whether copyright should subsist in works created
72 Acohs Pty Ltd v Ucorp Pty Ltd (2012) 201 FCR 173.
73 ‘Copyright in Source Code and Digital Products’, Lavan (Web Page, 3 August 2010) <
https://www.lavan.com.au/advice/intellectual_property_technology/copyright_in_source_code_and_digital_pro
ducts>.
74 Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd (2010) 194 FCR 142.
75 See, eg, AI application called Bayou discussed in Jade Boyd-Rice, ‘New A.I. Application Can Write its Own
Code’, Futurity (Article, 25 April 2018) <https://www.futurity.org/artificial-intelligence-bayou-coding-
1740702/>.
12
Utilitarian theory is said to constitute the backbone of intellectual property protection. 76 This
useful works that will benefit society.’ 77 Promoting the creation of artistic or useful works
involves providing an incentive to innovate which is inherent to the utilitarian theory. The
utilitarian theory suggests without this incentive to innovate, authors might not invest the ‘time,
energy, and money necessary to create these works because they might be copied cheaply and
easily by free riders, eliminating authors’ ability to profit from their works.’78
The fundamental issue with an application of utilitarian theory to works created by AI is that
‘AI systems do not need incentives to create artworks.’79 AI systems are not susceptible to
things like short term memory loss, information overload, sleep deprivation or distractions that
humans are susceptible to and require an incentive to overcome. 80 Therefore, the incentive-
copyright protection.
On the other hand, human beings are still indispensable for works to be created, even where an
AI system is involved. First of all, AI systems are created by a human being, a team of them
76 Amir H Khoury, ‘Intellectual Property Rights for “Hubots”: On the Legal Implications of Human-Like
Robots as Innovators and Creators’ (2017) 35(3) Cardozo Arts and Entertainment Law Journal 635, 652.
77 Roberto Garza Barbosa, ‘The Philosophical Approaches to Intellectual Property and Legal Transplants. The
Mexican Supreme Court and NAFTA Article 1705’ (Summer 2009) 31(3) Houston Journal of International
Law 515, 517.
78 Jeanne C Fromer, ‘An Information Theory of Copyright Law’ (2014) 64 Emory Law Journal 71, 74-75 citing
Alina Ng, The Author’ s Rights in Literary and Artistic Works, 9 J. MARSHALL REV. INTELL. PROP. L. 453,
453 (2009); Symposium, The Constitutionality of Copyright Term Extension: How Long Is Too Long?, 18
CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 651, 676 (2000) (statement of Wendy Gordon).
79 Yanisky-Ravid, n 6, 700 citing Shlomit Yanisky-Ravid & Luis Antonio Velez-Hernandez, Copyrightability of
Artworks Produced by Creative Robots, Driven by Artificial Intelligence Systems and the Originality
Requirement: The Formality-Objective Model, 19 MINN. J.L. SCI. & TECH. 1.
80 Yanisky-Ravid, n 6, 700 citing Shlomit Yanisky-Ravid & Luis Antonio Velez-Hernandez, Copyrightability of
Artworks Produced by Creative Robots, Driven by Artificial Intelligence Systems and the Originality
Requirement: The Formality-Objective Model, 19 MINN. J.L. SCI. & TECH. 1.
13
user (a human being) will either provide with some input data or, at least, activate the AI
On a similar vein, in Telstra Corporation Ltd v Phone Directories Company Pty Ltd 81 case, in
the unsuccessful application for special leave to the High Court, 82 the applicant argued that
‘human authorial contributions in the entire continuum of production should be considered, not
just the human involvement at the final point of materialisation.’ 83 This line of reasoning can
be applied to AI works. While a human’s intervention cannot be pinpointed in the final point
the production continuum. For example, humans are behind the code that trains AI to make
decisions and they also use the AI system. While there is no one holding the ‘proverbial pen’
to do the actual writing, 84 there are humans that can be identified as contributing to the works
of AI in earlier stages of the production continuum and could be held ‘responsible for the
One could therefore argue that human beings who in a certain way contribute to the creation
human beings are in no way rewarded for such an activity, if they do not receive any benefits
for creating AI systems or triggering them to create the works, they would not provide their
indispensable contributions and the world community will end up with less (if any) creations
generated by AI.
14
in all cases indispensable in order to stimulate the production of works. Firstly, as far as human
already incentivized by copyright law. The software that underlies AI systems is protected as
a literary work under copyright laws of Australia and other countries;86 protection lasts for 70
years after the death of the (last surviving) author. 87 It is questionable whether an additional
level of protection awarded for software developers would lead to additional incentive and
increased outputs.88 Therefore, under the utilitarian theory, vesting protection for AI-generated
works into software developers might be unjustified as there is no proof that a second layer of
copyright protection would lead to the development of more AI systems and, as a result, more
Another question is whether humans who provide a trigger for AI systems to create works, i.e.
users of AI systems, always need to be incentivized to carry out such activities. The answer
will probably depend on the extent and kind of effort exerted. If the user merely switches on
the AI system or makes effort that is insubstantial or is not of an intellectual nature, it might be
insufficient to attract copyright protection. Although even minor activities, such as activation
disproportionate and excessive to award users with exclusive rights over the works generated.
In contrast, if users vest a sufficiently significant intellectual effort that contributes to the
creation of the work, such contribution might be worthwhile encouragement and, therefore,
15
should be granted only in cases where absence of any exclusive control would lead to lack of
incentive to make an effort and produce works, which would lead to less creative products
reaching society.90 Also, exclusive rights have to be granted only to the extent necessary to
incentivise creativity, but not so excessive as to prevent reasonable access to works by public.91
As a result, utilitarian theory could justify the protection of works created by AI only if human
contribution that triggered the creation of such works is sufficiently significant. Namely, there
is no point of incentivising insignificant contributions by users since they require very little
effort and thus are likely to happen in any case. Under the utilitarian theory it is worth
rewarding only those efforts that humans are not likely to exert without sufficient reward.
Natural rights theory provides another rationale for justifying copyright in works created by
AI.92 Simply stated, the natural rights theory refers to the notion of basic rights that cannot be
denied. Philosopher, John Locke, recognises property as a fundamental natural right, because
‘people are entitled to own both what they produce by means of their own efforts and whatever
they have laboured on.’93 The contextual development of this theory is important to consider,
as it evolved at a time when intellectual property laws were not implemented and therefore
only refers to tangible property if strictly applied. Despite the intangibility of intellectual
property, successive scholars have consistently applied natural rights theory to intellectual
property. Subsequently, intellectual property rights, such as copyright, have been considered
90 Miranda Forsyth, ‘The Digital Agenda Anti-circumvention Provisions: A Threat to Fair Use in Cyberspace’
(2001) 12 Australian Intellectual Property Journal 82, 84.
91 Forsyth, n 90.
92 Owen Morgan, ‘Graffiti – Ownership and Other Rights’ (2007) 12 Media and Arts Law Review 167, 179.
93 Janice Gray et al, Property Law in New South Wales (LexisNexis Butterworths, 4th ed, 2018) 14.
16
JJ pointed out in IceTV Pty Ltd v Nine Network Australia Pty Ltd, copyright is personal
Would natural rights theory justify granting copyright over works created by AI? As in the case
of incentive theory the situation is more complex than it may seem from the first glance. To
start with, it is quite clear that natural rights theory could not justify the granting of copyright
to the AI system since only human beings have natural rights, not machines. Therefore, we
should consider whether human beings who contribute to works created by AI could claim
A metaphor may help to explain the complexity of the situation. When a tree has grown lemons,
the farmer receives property rights in the lemon as a result of his labour, despite not actually
growing the lemon. It is the tree that was directly performing the process of producing a lemon,
yet no one would deny the farmer the ‘fruits of his labour’.97 Similarly, one could argue that,
it is the AI, and not the human, that directly performs the process of creating the work into
material form (the ‘lemon’). However, the human should have a natural right to the work
created by AI because the human created AI system in the first place and/or triggered it to
94 Adam Mossoff, ‘Why Intellectual Property Rights? A Lockean Justification’, Law & Liberty (Web Page, 4
May 2015) <https://www.lawliberty.org/liberty-forum/why-intellectual-property-rights-a-lockean-
justification/>.
95 (2009) 239 CLR 458, 483 [65] citing s 196(1).
96 Joseph Savirimuthu, ‘John Locke, Natural Rights and Intellectual Property: The Legacy of an Idea’ (2013)
8(11) Journal of Intellectual Property Law & Practice 892, 892.
97 Savirimuthu, n 96.
17
from the final output for them to claim ownership of works created by AI? In some cases,
humans designing the AI may envisage what sort of output the AI system will produce. For
instance, in the case of the Meandering River mentioned above, individuals who programmed
an AI system to collect satellite images and put them together into a real time installation could
have had a general vision of a sort of work that AI would generate as an output. In such a case,
when coders had a general vision of an output, it might be reasonable to attribute copyright in
the artwork created by AI to the individuals who designed the AI system in the first place.
On a similar vein, courts in some jurisdictions have recognised that graphical user interface
(GUI) is protected separately from the underlying software.98 The underlying reason is likely
to be the fact that software developers when writing a code can have a sufficiently clear vision
of how the GUI will look like. Therefore, it is reasonable to provide them exclusive rights over
the GUI and prevent others creating identical or very similar GUI by simply writing another
source code. Similarly, in the case of computer games, software developers not only own rights
into an underlying software but also into the result that software provides, ie an audiovisual
expression of the game; it might be protected as an audiovisual work or other type of work
(musical, graphical, etc).99 In these cases software developers acquire rights to both GUIs and
audiovisual expression of video games since they have envisaged them as a final output that
software will produce; they thus count as ‘fruits of their labour’. Similar rationale would apply
to works created by AI as long as AI developers have certain vision of works that AI is going
to produce.
98 See eg EU case law: Bezpecnostni Softwarova Asociace - Svaz Softwarove Ochrany v Ministerstvo Kultury
(C-393/09) [2011] E.C.D.R. 3 (22 December 2010).
99 Andy Ramos et al, The Legal Status of Video Games: Comparative Analysis in National Approaches (WIPO
Report, 2013) [14].
18
that developers of the system are not able to even imagine what sort of outputs this may lead
to. Drawing upon the example of the Portrait of Edmond Belamy, the code was downloaded
online by a French artist who applied a new data set of more than 15,000 portraits between the
14th and 20th century to the ‘borrowed’ code and fashioned the idea of the painting. It is likely
the person who created the code that was downloaded online would not have envisioned the
In such case, when output is very remote from the work of AI developers and they do not have
a vision of a kind of works that AI is going to produce, it becomes unreasonable to give them
exclusive control over such works. In comparison, developers of MS Word software cannot
claim ownership of all texts written when using this software, even if they exercised significant
creativity and intellectual effort when writing the software. Similarly, in the case of the
labour in creating the AI system, it is unlikely that developers had envisaged such kind of
output. Thus, it could be argued that the output is a too remote from the work carried out by
developers and that they should not be able to claim copyright over it.
As far as the AI user is concerned, the question is whether the ‘labour’ that they contribute is
sufficient to give them ownership over the ‘fruits’. In some cases users may have creative
intellectual contribution in what sort of input data will be fed into the system to create a work.
If the contribution is sufficiently significant and not merely mechanical, it might be sufficient
to justify ownership of a final outcome. Following the same example of Portrait of Edmund
100‘Is Artificial Intelligence Set to Become Art’s Next Medium?’, Christie’s (Web Page, 12 December 2018) <
https://www.christies.com/features/A-collaboration-between-two-artists-one-human-one-a-machine-9332-
1.aspx>.
19
set. Such creative idea and effort to implement it is likely to be sufficient to lead to copyright
In contrast, if the user contributes little or insignificant intellectual effort to the generation of
the work, it is questionable whether such contribution would be sufficient to afford user with
ownership over the final result generated by AI. For instance, feeding one single word into a
AI system which then generates a poem is likely to be insufficient to vest copyright protection
in a user who contributed that single word.101 Also, coming back to the lemon example, if a
neighbour waters the lemon plant several times, this effort is not sufficient to claim ownership
over lemon fruits; the owner of the lemon tree will still own lemons that the tree grows. This
is in line with arguments developed under the utilitarian theory suggesting that it is worthwhile
significant.
As a result, under the natural rights theory, the answer whether copyright protection should be
vested into works created by AI depends on the kind and significance of labour exerted by
human beings. Only if the labour is not too remote from the final output and demonstrates
sufficient intellectual effort it might be reasonable under natural rights theory to afford those
human beings with property rights over the final product produced by AI.
Notably, it appears from the above that in cases of some works created by AI, granting
exclusive rights over works might be justified, e.g. when the individual’s contribution is
significant, and when the contribution is not too remote from the final output. In other cases,
20
For instance, if the works created have not been envisaged by the developers and have not
required any significant input by the user (i.e. it was created essentially independently by an
AI system), there seems to be no reason to grant exclusive rights to any of the humans involved
in the process. If their contribution was insignificant, it is not worthy of incentive by providing
protection. Also, if the output of the AI system is too remote from the input made by human
individuals, natural rights theory would not require granting property rights over that output.
Such type of works would then fall into public domain and can be freely used by everyone.102
If we agree that at least certain works created by AI could be granted copyright protection, the
next question is who should own copyright in such works? A number of possibilities have been
explored by commentators.103 In this section four options will be explored: no one, AI itself,
the coder/developer of the AI system and the user. After showing that no single option is
sufficiently adequate, a middle ground solution will be discussed, based on the ownership
A. No one and AI
Let us first discuss and discount the least suitable options, ‘no one’ and ‘AI’, as potential
Firstly, in the section above we reached a conclusion that, at least in certain cases, it could be
justified to grant copyright protection over works created by AI. If protection is granted, there
102Some authors suggest that all AI-generated works could fall into public domain, see, eg, Hristov, n 34, 437.
103See, eg, Pamela Samuelson, ‘Allocating Ownership Rights in Computer-Generated Works’ (Summer 1986)
47 University of Pittsburgh Law Review 1185, 1185; in Copyright Law Review Committee, Computer Software
Protection (Office of Legal Information and Publishing, 1995) 247 [13.19] the following options were
considered ‘(a) the programmer or owner of the copyright in the programs that assisted in creation of the work;
(b) the provider of the data; (c) the user of the computer/computer program; or (d) the investor or owner of the
computer/computer program’.
21
However, in those cases where works created by AI are not granted copyright protection, i.e
when the contributions from humans involved are not sufficient or too remote, then no one will
have rights into the work and it will fall in public domain.104
The second option is to award ownership to AI itself. Although some commentators argue in
favour of this option,105 the suggestion seems to be premature. There are challenges to
allocating ownership in AI itself due to its lack of legal status. Copyright ownership is ‘only a
piece in the constellation of legal standing’ of AI.106 If AI were granted legal status to receive
copyright ownership, it would open the floodgates and bring about ‘serious reflections on the
broader consequences of affording legal personhood to machines.’107 There are certain signs
that legal personality of AI might need to be considered more seriously in the near future. For
instance, Saudi Arabia became the first and, for now, the only country to grant legal status to
AI when they granted citizenship to a robot, called Sophia.108 Further to this, the World
Tipping Points. One of the 21 Technology Tipping Points is that by 2025 there will be an AI
machine on a corporate board of directors. 109 For now, however, it seems to be premature and
22
The two remaining options for attribution of ownership in AI-generated works are the
developer of AI (the coder) and the end user. In the previous section they were identified as
humans who contributed to the generation of works by AI and thus could potentially be
awarded ownership to these works. Which one of them is a more appropriate person to whom
To start with, the developers of AI, or coders, are the ones who put the most significant
intellectual effort into developing the AI system which then in turn generates works. As
discussed above, under the natural rights theory, developers might be entitled to works
generated by AI as to the ‘fruits of their labour’. If AI developers have coded AI with a vision
to produce certain kind of works, similar as in case of GUIs and video games, they should be
At the same time, vesting copyright into software developers would not be justified when
coders’ contribution is too remote from the final output. As an analogy, a person who creates
a camera is not the person who gets copyright for a photo the camera takes. Rather, it is the
person using the camera, who adjusts the settings, frames the photo and presses the button, that
gets copyright in the photo. If the end output was not planned or envisaged by the coder and is
too remote from his contribution, it would not be very reasonable to vest copyright to the work
It is worth noting the practical issues that would arise if allocating copyright to the developer
of AI. It will often be a team of coders (and other contributors) who develop, in a concerted
23
collaboration and development in software. 111 One person could have contributed a substantial
amount to the code but another person could have just made a tweak to the code to make it a
working code that could complete the function of creating works. Therefore, it would be
Also, the legal relationship among coders is not very clear. If their contributions are
inseparable, they might qualify as co-authors and joint owners under Australian copyright law.
A work of joint ownership is defined as ‘a work that has been produced by the collaboration
of two or more authors and in which the contribution of each author is not separate from the
contribution of the other author or the contributions of the other authors.’112 There are multiple
people involved in an AI team, from the software engineer to the data scientist. Some
commentators argue that the kind of agreement and harmony of interest required for joint
authorship is lacking in a typical AI situation. 113 Each team member makes a different and
separate contribution, as demonstrated in the case of Acohs Pty Ltd v Ucorp Pty Ltd,114 where
it was held there was no joint authorship between the programmers and transcribers because
in this situation is difficult since permission of all co-owners is needed to license or assign
rights into a software. 115 These legal issues get solved if the AI system is created in an
111 Simon Stokes, Digital Copyright: Law and Practice (Hart Publishing, 4th ed, 2014) 133.
112 Copyright Act 1968 (Cth) s 10(1) (definition of ‘work of joint ownership).
113 Pamela Samuelson, ‘Allocating Ownership Rights in Computer-Generated Works’ (Summer 1986) 47
University of Pittsburgh Law Review 1185, 1222.
114 Acohs Pty Ltd v Ucorp Pty Ltd (2012) 201 FCR 173.
115 See, eg, Seven Network (Operations) Ltd v TCN Channel Nine Pty Ltd [2005] FCAFC 144, [20].
24
be the employer.116 However, if the coders were working outside employment relationship (e.g.
as contractors) contract would have to be carefully drafted in order to properly allocate the
Looking at another option for ownership allocation – the user of an AI system – we come up
with a similar conclusion. Vesting rights to AI-generated works into user is reasonable in some
instances but lacks reasonableness in other instances. Namely, in situations where the user
significantly contributed to the generation of the work (e.g. in case of Portrait of Edmond
Belamy) both utilitarian and natural rights theories would allow attributing ownership to the
user. However, in cases where the contribution is not significant, it might not be sufficient to
qualify for copyright protection. 117 For instance, in case of Google’s AI Program Poem
Portraits, it is sufficient for a user to type one word in to the AI system to get the poem
generated.118 Although the user was the one who most directly contributed to the output of the
AI system, their contribution arguably does not contain sufficiently significant effort to qualify
The above analysis demonstrates that no single option discussed is adequate since the
ownership of copyright into a work created by AI might vest in different persons depending of
the kind of contribution to the end output. Thus, a broader test is needed to encompass a variety
of scenarios that AI technology may bring. One of such broader tests is offered in the current
UK copyright law.
25
The UK was the first jurisdiction to introduce a provision for copyright protection in computer
generated works.119 The Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (UK) s 9(3) allows copyright
to be awarded to the work generated by a computer. It provides that the author of a computer
generated work is taken to be ‘the person by whom the arrangements necessary for the creation
of the work are undertaken’. While s 9(3) was initially suggested to provide adequate protection
to investors of satellite photography,120 other reasons for its introduction included “an
acknowledgement of the reality that computer technology was being used to create materials
of the kind protected by copyright and that the law should provide flexibility for future
technological developments, the objective of future-proofing copyright law in the face of rapid
changes in technology, and the need to make the law easier to understand apply” (footnotes
omitted).121 A number of countries such as New Zealand, India, Hong Kong and Ireland have
adopted identical or similar ‘necessary arrangement’ test for identifying who the author is of
computer generated works.122 In Australia, the Copyright Law Review Committee Report on
Computer Software Protection 123 recommended the introduction of a similar provision into
Australian Copyright Act 1968 (Cth)124 but the recommendation was not enacted in law. Would
119 Ryan Abbott, ‘Artificial Intelligence, Big Data and Intellectual Property: Protecting Computer-Generated
Works in the United Kingdom’ in Tanya Aplin (ed), Research Handbook on Intellectual Property and Digital
Technologies (Edward Elgar Publishing Ltd, forthcoming).
120 Madeleine de Cock Buning, ‘Artificial Intelligence and the Creative Industry: New Challenges for the EU
Paradigm for Art and Technology by Autonomous Creation’ in Woodrow Barfield and Ugo Pagallo (eds),
Research Handbook on the Law of Artificial Intelligence (Edward Elgar, 2018) 531.
121 Anne Fitzgerald and Tim Seidenspinner, ‘Copyright and Computer-Generated Materials – Is it Time to
Reboot the Discussion About Authorship?’ (2013) 3(1) Victoria University Law and Justice Journal 47, 54.
122 See, eg, in New Zealand “the person by whom the arrangements necessary for the creation of the work are
undertaken”: Copyright Act 1994 (NZ) s 5(2)(a); in India “the person who causes the work to be created”:
Copyright Act 1957 (India) (2)(d)(vi); in Hong Kong “the person by whom the arrangements necessary for the
creation of the works are undertaken”: Copyright Ordinance (Hong Kong) cap 528, s 11(3); in Ireland “the
person by whom the arrangements necessary for the creation of the work are undertaken”: Copyright and
Related Rights Act 2000 (Ireland) s 21(f).
123 Copyright Law Review Committee, Parliament of Australia, Computer Software Protection (Report, 1995).
124 Copyright Law Review Committee, Computer Software Protection (Office of Legal Information and
Publishing, 1995) 15 [2.42(c)].
26
From the first glance this ‘necessary arrangement’ test may seem an example of bad drafting.
It is rather unclear who is supposed to be the person ‘by whom the arrangements necessary for
the creation of the work are undertaken’. It could be anyone involved, from the coder, the
investor in the computer program, to the user of the computer.125 The only case that has been
decided on this section during the last 30 years does not provide much clarification either.
In Nova Productions Ltd v Mazooma Games Ltd,126 Nova claimed copyright in the bitmap
graphics, and the frames generated and displayed to the user when its game was played. Kitchin
J found that the programmer of the software was the owner of a computer generated work in
the case (composite frames) “because he devised the appearance of the various elements of the
game and the rules and logic by which each frame is generated and he wrote the relevant
computer program”.127 Kitchin J was satisfied that the programmer was the person by whom
the arrangements necessary for the creation of the works were undertaken. However,
commentators suggest that such conclusion, although justified in this particular factual
scenario, is unlikely to be true in all cases involving computer generated works. Where
proximity between programmer and the work in question is more remote, other persons might
be the ones who made necessary arrangements, such as the investing company or the user. 128
27
nature of the subject matter at stake (computer generated works and, more recently, works
created by AI), flexible legal provisions might prove to be helpful in accommodating different
industry developments. S 9(3) allows for vesting copyright in different contributors to the
the coder, the user, or the investor (software company). It also does not preclude the possibility
that several persons would be granted ownership to the same work. The provision leaves it to
the courts to assess the situation and decide who deserves copyright on a case-by-case basis.
Such flexibility is especially desirable in the fields of industry that is still emerging.
In an Australian context, the ‘necessary arrangement’ test would not be entirely new either. In
the case of cinematographic films, Copyright Act 1968 (Cth) vests copyright in the ‘maker’ of
a cinematographic film.129 The ‘maker’ of a film is defined as ‘the person by whom the
arrangements necessary for the making of the film were undertaken’. 130 According to the
established case law, the maker can be the producer/investor in the film, the film director or
both of them together, depending on their contributions. For instance, in Seven Network
(Operations) Ltd v TCN Channel Nine Pty Ltd, both the Seven Network and the director of the
film made arrangements necessary for the creation of the film and were both recognised to be
owners in the tapes.131 The existing case law on ‘necessary arrangements’ test in Australia thus
provides at least some legal guidance that the legal community would desire, and at the same
time leaves plenty of space for courts to interpret the concept keeping in mind the most recent
28
AI is an emerging technology and its broader adoption and application by creative industries
is still in the future to come. However, as creative industries are seeing the first works created
by AI entering art markets, it is time to consider copyright implications on these pieces of art.
Under current Australian copyright law, works created by AI do not attract copyright protection
since copyright law requires a human being to be directly involved in the creation of the work.
At the same time, the analysis of utilitarian and natural rights theories that underlie copyright
law demonstrate that, at least in certain cases, when human contribution to the creation of a
work by AI is sufficiently significant and not too remote from the final output, there might be
a good reason to grant copyright protection to such works. This would stimulate human beings
to creatively interact with AI systems, which would result in more creative works reaching the
public.
The other difficulty is establishing who would be the owner of works created by AI that qualify
for copyright protection. After discounting ‘no one’ and ‘AI’ as potential options, we suggest
that the answer will vary depending on the contribution provided by different human beings
involved in the creation of the work. In some cases it might be reasonable to vest copyright
might be a user (artist) whose contribution would be most directly linked to the final output.
For this reason, we suggest considering a broader concept that would encompass different
allocation possibilities and provide for a sufficient flexibility to deal with different new
emerging scenarios. The UK test of ‘necessary arrangements’ is one of the possible options as
it is both a familiar concept in the Australian copyright system, and enjoys sufficient flexibility
29