0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes) 347 views20 pagesThe Interpersonal World of The Infant - Daniel N. Stern 106-145
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
differen situations: “I'm gonna get you” games, “walking finger
‘riche the tummy.” and a host of other suspense games that ate
stands fare at chis age. The infantis alo likely to have experienced
4 doten ot more varstions ofthe peek-a-boo game 10 begin with:
diaper over baby's face, diaper over mother’s face, mother's face ges
covered by baby’s feet as they are broughe togeter, Ber fae res
abore and scts below the horizon of the bed, and so on. No matter
how mother does it, che infant experiences her antes ax belonging
to her at a core other: this is only one of the many ways of
capericncing her organization, coltesion, and agency.
“Moreover, the same general feeling states» engendered in the
infant, regardes of which way the mother plays the game” And it
is likely that ehis family of games has been paved withthe infant
by others—fcher, bbysicer, and 30 00. The purticula afer, then,
remains, despite variations in the interaction and changes in the
fneractant. I sony the feeling state chat belongs to the self, cae
is what permis the infan to triangulated identify what
invariant belong to whom. And normal purent/infant interactions
are, of coune, necesarilyextensely variable. To highlight che excl
tole of variety of experience in dsinguishing eelFinvariansy fom
other-invarants, imagine che flowing
Seppose that an infant experienced jyfal cytes of anticipation
and resolution only with mother, and chat mother always regulated
these eycles in the exact same way (vicilly imposible. That infant
would be im a ricky spot. In this particular, unchanging activi
mother would be semed a core ether brcate her behavior would
bey most of the laws (agency, coherence, continuity) that specify
ches as agsinat selves. However, the infant could not be site 10
‘what extent his or her feeling sate was an invariant property of self
or of mather's behavior since both would ineurably seempsny tht
feeling. (Ths is close to the pictare of sel/other wndifferentiaion
assumed by many, except that we have derived ie from the mother's
‘Weittions racer than from the infa's)
Under the normal conditions of inevitable variety, then, che infant
should have no trouble én sensing who is who and what belongs to
‘whom in thes kinds of encounters Theve are, however, may games
and routines in which s great degree of similarity of behavior
Therween parent and init is the role, May not thee prstat a more
106
THE SEN
E OF A GORE SELF: I
dificult task for the infant in distinguishing self from other and
from “ex”? These inclode eat
‘makes her hands and the infant's hands do the same ch
‘imitation routines, afect leading and following. as in the mutual
cacalation of smiles, and many more. One could imagine that at such
fines the cues that specify selEimrarsns and othernvarints coold
parially break down, because in imitative interactions, the behavior
ofthe other may he comorphic (similarly contoured 38 far 36 intenity
and vitality affects are conceraed) and often simula
synchronous with the behavior of the infant. One enight expect that
these experiences are the ones that come closest eo the nations of
merging or of dissolution of sclt/ot
peteepaual grounds (Sern 1980),
Even under these conditions, however, itis quite
cnough of the differentiating eves ean be obliterated.
[pier Tey cn des pi-cond de
Simultaneity. For istance, if mother's face is shown
of three months on television screen but her voce i delayed by
several hundred milliseconds the snfant picks up the discrepancy it
synchrony and ix disturbed by it, as by a badly dubbe
forms of pae-avcake, where mother
8, various
boundaties, at least on
likely that
a infat
(Trevarthan 1977; Dodd 1979) Similarly, it isthe ability to estimate
time in the split-second range that permits the infane to distinguish
the sounds /ba/ and /pa/, which differ only én timing of voice onset
(Eimas etal. 1971, 1978), Even if the parent could ac like a perfect
ricror, che memorial continuity of a core sense of self could not be
abliterated”
‘What happens to the sense of self in thote mutual interactions11/ THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
involving the regulation of the infant's seeuity or state transforma
tions? While these interactions are 10 more devoted to affective
alterations than the interactions already discussed, they are historically
considered mote conducive to experiences of merger. During, these
texpericnces, the parent's behaviors are complementary to the infant
(holding the infant, who is being held). In this sense, each partner
fs generally doing something quite diferent from the other. The
intacness of self and other is therefore readily maintained, since the
perceptual cues reveal the other to be following a different temporal,
spatial, intensity, and/or movement organization from the slf. In
other words, all the eves that specify selGinvariants o* other
invariants (discussed in chapter 4) are undisturbed, 0 chat no
confusion in che sete of self versos sense of other need occu atthe
Jeyel of core-elatednes. I is thus resonable that the sense of a core
self and 4 core other need not be breached by the presence of self
regulating others, even when the experience concems the infant's
affect ate.
‘A second question now arises. What isthe relationship berween
the altered sel-experience and the regulating role of the other who
helped alter the infun’s se-experience? Or, more tothe point. how
is that relationship experienced by the infant? We can answer for an
adule or older chil. Sometimes it screams out and seems to fill the
entire attentional fied as in the powerful felings af being with
someone when you ate imecure or seared, being enfolded in chat
person's arms and engulfed in something like security, of almost
falling into the other's personhood (what 4 normal “meager” expe-
rience is purportedly like)
[Atother times, the relationship between the altered slf-experience
and the regulatory role of the other is silent and goes unnoticed.
This situation is analogous co the silent or invisible presence of the
“self-ccher* as well expresied inthe terminology of Self Psychology
by Wolf (1980) and Stechler and Kaplan (1980).
Setting mii, Sorte moment, my: pricalar wge-eppropriate form of
the selfbject aced, one may compas the need for the continaoys
‘mesence of 4 perchologiclly mourshing selfohject milieu with the
continuing physiological ned for an environment containing oxygen. Rt
{eaelatively silent need of which one becomes aware sharply only when
its nox being met, when a hash wll compels one co daw the breath
Jinn. And foi goes ako with the efobyect needs. As ony a3 person
08
THE SENSE OF 4 CORE
LP:
‘i securely embeded in a cal matrix that proves him with a fell in
Teh ad at dan os Lee tll wing ceo etd
eearyra Pec ey of ate wn be
‘wll cofeehy fine phn ttl a paral ral
teen seltaticien, a ironomovs. a, by some avery of
tea ete celta escarole aes
eal eed a eed a eka or ere ee
friendly it mighe be disposed tomard him, Even strong selves tend 0
fngment under such circumstances. One can fel lonelet i» crow
sialppennersbelencnleabeniau cheaeesbe mie (af 1905
Piz
“Whether the relationship between altered selfexperienee and the
regulating role of the other is abvious or unobtrusive, the alteration
in selfexperience always belongs entirely to the self. Even in the
obvious situation ofa security need being met, the other may appeat
to provide—may actully even seem to porsest—the “security
before enfolding you, But the feeling of becoming secure belongs
only to the self In those situations when the regulatory role of the
‘other goes unnoticed, ehe experience of selfalteration belongs only
t the self by defval-
“The previous dseusion addressed the question of who subjectively
‘owns, 10 0 speak, the alteration in selfexperience—the self, che
other, ot some “we or fused amalgam. The answer seems to be
that it falls completely within the domain of the sense of self. This
issue of subjective ownership, however, leaves unanswered the ques:
tion of how the relationship is sensed.
Somme relationship nots comme to exist between the change i scf
experience and the regulating role, obvious or unobtrusive, of the
other, simply because they tend t0 occur together. They become
related as do any attributes of a repeated lived experience. They are
not elements that are fused or confused; they are simply relate.
‘They are two of the more salient elements (that i, attributes) of any
pparicular lived experience with a self-regulating other. Merger
‘experiences at this age are simply a way of being with someone, but
someone who acts as self-regulating other. Any such lived experience
includes: (1) significant alterations in the infant's feeling state that
seem to belong vo the self even though they were mutwally created
by self with an other, 2) che other person, as seen, heard, and felt
at the moment ofthe alteration, (3) a intact sense of score self snd,11/ THE FOUR SENSES OF SELE
cove ther ils which allthis cacy, and (6) vay of
pote fl ean pe Wr eh
form « mlipcive wae cat peers fon nore wes a
ad Seley saan Goad ae ceed ee
Yoling covert ln Che frm oft toma euode fe lved. The
Fraley fl memory tthe tl nt Bock he leat
scuets of te capercae one ratiomhips one with the od
he elas oe ea a ool a th irl apa
Viewers ae) ales hacerlo
faba ha cer bo eeepc a ad ap
Jisy ct ceased i ee Gecko ADE
the plans tured toe bea ony wi eke be a
ose ke ee fe Seria
Ind the perception of the other donot have wo cllape ino one
pret ve ery cian berpesrer wry ennee ara
poeta ateune poate yoy en ari lee yarnere
pos
Lived episodes immediatly become the speci eps for mem
cay ud wih epeson they Keer eased spans ot dered
in chapter 4 They are gerald pode of ineractive experience
cieeirciaraclly sepreeseci Rat CRM
‘fetive experience as « dyadic evest, and this comceptoalizstion fs
Iecessary to a generic view of antersubjectivity, It also possible
that the deminssce of separition/individastion theory t explain the
ie period under discussion acted as an sbstacle toa fle apreciation
‘of the role of snersubectvity.
“To be more specific on this pot, ego prychoanalyticcheory has
‘viewed the perad after seven to nine months athe time of emerging
snore ally (hitching i the metaphor) Fim che undiferentiated
and fased state that preceded it. This phase was predominantly
devoted to establishing «separate and individuated self to dinolving
merger experiences, and t© forming a more autonomous self that
could inteuct with « tote separated other. Given tht view of the
tnajor life task of chie period, ts bs not nmprining thet the theory
filed to notice thut the appearance of intersubjective relitedness
permitted, for the fis time, the crestion of mutually held ental
states and allowed for the realry-ased joining (even merging) of
«experince. Paradoxcily, ts only with the advent of inter-
subjectivity that anything like the joining of subjective psychic
experince can actualy occur. And cis i indeed what the leap 9
an imcrubjective sense of self and other makes possible, jst a che
developmental moment when traditional theory had the ede begin~
ning te flow the other way. In the present slew, both separation
individuation and new font of experiencing unin (or being-with)
merge eqully ov of the same experience af imerabjectvty."
1," ut rhage sen Br len
deciogeets te Te1/ THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
In. spite of a general disregard of intersubjective experience as a
dyadic phenomenon, theorist: have regularly appeared, often just
‘outside of the mainstream, who have held positions receptive to the
concept of intessubjectivity or subjective relatedness. Vygotsky's
notion of the “intermental” (1962), Fairbaim’s of the infan's innate
interpersonal relatedness (1949), and MacMurray’ af the field of ehe
‘Perional (1961) ay-well os Sullivan's of the interpervonal fell (1953),
fare influential examples. It was against this background that the
recent findings of the developmentaltes acted to bring the develop
imental leap of eruibjectivity into its present sharp focus. Its not
surprising that these developmentalies were Largely interested cithee
in the role of intentionality in the mother-infant interaction or in
how infants acquire language. Both routes would ultimately lead to
the issue of ineersubjectvity and its underlying assumptions, which
the philosophers had long been dealing with
‘The Evidence for Intersubjectve Relatabnes
‘What, then, is the evidence for the appearance of interiubjective
relatedness at seven to nine months? Trevarthan and Hubley (1978)
have provided a definition of intersubjetivity chat can be operation
alized: “a deliberately sought sharing of experiences about events
nd things.” What subjective experiences docs the infant give
evidence of sharing or, atleast, expecting the mother to share?
Recall that infants at this poioe in development are sill paevesbal
The subjective experiences that they can share must be of a kind
that do mor require tanslation into language. Three mental sates
that are of great relevance to the interpersonal world and yet do aot
require Language come to mind. These are sharing joint attention,
sharing intentions, and sharing affective states. What behaviors do
infants show 0o suggest that they can conduct or appreciate these
deg?
128
THE SENSE OF A SUBJECTIVE SELF: 1
SHARING THEE FOCUS OF ATTINTION
“The geiure of pointing and the act of following another's line of
vision are among the first overt act that permit inferences about the
sharing of atention, oF the establishing of joint atention. Mothess
pint and infants point. Let us start with the mother's pointing, For
her pointing to work, the infant must know to stop looking at the
pointing hand itself and look in the direction i indicates, to the
target. For a Tong time it was believed that infunts could nat do this
tunel well into their second year because they could not escape their
egocentric position. But Murphy and Messer (1977) showed that
rine-month-oldsdo- indeed detach their gaze from the pointing hand
and follow the imaginary line to the target. “What has been mastered
2 this stage isa procedure For homing in on the attentional Focus of
another. Ir isa disclosure and discovery routine... highly generative
within the limited world inhabited by the infant im the sence that it
is nos limited to speciic kinds of object. Ie has, morsover, equipped
the child with a technique for transcending egocentriem, For inset
as he can appreciate another's line of regard and decipher their
marking intentions, he has plainly achieved a hasis for what Piaget
has called decentration, using 2 coordinate system for the world
other than the one of which he is the center” (Bruner 1977, 276).
Parlier than nine months, infants show a preliminary form of this,
discovery procedure: they follow the mother’s line of vision when
she turns her head (Scaife and Bruner 1975), jast as the mocher
follows the infant's line of vision (Collis and Schaffer 1975)
So far, we have sten only a routine of procedure for discovering
another's attentional focus. Infants of nine months, however, do
moge than that. They not only visually follow the diection of the
point but, after resching the target, look back at the mother and
appear to wie the feedback from her face to confim that they have
arrived at the intended target. This is now more than a dicovery
procedure. It is 4 deliberate attempe to validate whether the joiet
attention has been achieved, chat is, whether the focus of atteaion
is heing shared, although the infant is not self-aware of these
‘operations
‘Similarly, infants begin to point at aboot nine months of age,
though they do so less frequently than mothers do, When they do,
their gaze alternates between the target and the mother's face, asM1/ THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
when she is pointing to see if she has joined in to shate the
stventional focus be seems reasonable to assume that, ezen prior £0
pointing, the infants beginning capacity to move about, to craw! of
‘ruiz, is crucial in discovering altemative perspectives a i necessary
for joint attention. In moving about, the infant continually alees the
perspective held on some known stationary sight. Perhaps this initial
acceptance of serially diferent perspectives iv a necesary precursor
to the mote generic “realization” that others can be using 2 different
coordinace system from the infant's own,
‘These observations lead one to infer that by nine months infants
have some sense that they can have 4 particalar attentional focus,
that mother can alko have a particular acentional focus, that these
two mental states can be similar or not, and tha if they are not
they can be brought into alignment and shared. Interatentionality
becomes area.
SHARING ineTENTIONS
Researchers interested in infants’ language acquisition have natuelly
been drawn to look at the most immediate origins of language use
These origins include the gestures, postures, actions, ane nonverbal
vocalizations that infants display jost prior to and presumably as a
precunor to language. Such provolinguisic forms have been examined
closely by a number of researchers, all of whom agree in one way
for another that beginning at about nine months the infant intend
to communicate (Bloom 1973, 1983; Brown. 1973; Bruner 197
1977, 1981; Dore 1975, 1979; Halliday 1975; Bates 1976, 1979;
Ninio and Bruner 1977; Shield: 1978; Bates etal. 1979; Bretherton
and Bates 1979; Harding and Golinkoff 1979; Trevarthan 1980;
Harding 1982), The intention to communicate is diferent from the
intention simply eo influence another person. Bates (1979) provides
4 working debnition of intentional communication that we cam we:
Inventions! commaniciion it signaling behavior in which the seer
is aware, a prion, of the effec thatthe signal will have om hs lence,
ani he persis in hat behavior anti the effect is obtained oF failure
dlealy indicated. The behavioral evidence that permits us 0 infer the
2 Ping soup signe in rahing, which dally gre conned a 4
Fl my ethyl bmg ger agrmareeel
‘ern tec es wx cc wh w maser ue mots aching at
130
THE SENSE OF A SUBJECTIVE SELF: 1
presace of communicative ineetions inclades (4) alterations in eye
faze contact hetween the goal and the intended Iisteners, () augment
tions, ations, apd subseitution of signals until che goal has been
‘bisiaed, and) changes fa the foem of the slp towards sbbveriaed
ani/or exaggerated pater that are appropriate only for achieving a
‘communicative gal (p. 34)
‘The mow seightforward and common examples of intentions
“communication ae protlinguistic forms af requesting. For example,
the mather i holding something the infant wants—iay, a cookie
“The infant reaches outa hand, palm wp towards mother, and while
making grasping movements and looking back and forth between
hand and mother’s face intone, “Eht EI” with an imperative
prosody (Dore 1995) Those acts, which are ected ata refeeat
person, imply that che infnt aterbutes an intermal etal sate f0
that person—namaly, compecherson of the infants intention and
the capacity to intend to sitefy thet ineation. Intcotions have
‘become shareable experiences Ineiniewionslity becomes rea.
Once again t need not be self-aware.
"Dunn has obierved the interactions
‘older and younger siblings and has richly describes ma
subtle events between them that imply that they have shared
moments of intersubjecivity, For instance, a three-year-old and a
‘one-year-old suddenly burst into laughter over 2 private joke fi
which no one ele can find the eliciting cause. Similar eruptions of
‘easing episodes occur that alto rermin opague to adult comprehension
(Dunn 1982; Dunn and Kendrick 1979, 1982). Such events requite
the attribution of shareable mental states that involve intentions and
‘expectations. You can't tease other people unless you can correct
jruess what is “in their minds" and make them suffer or laugh because
‘of your knowing
‘Can infants alse atcibuce shareble affective ates to their 100
panes? A group of scscarchers (Emile et al. 1978; Klinert 1978/ THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
‘Campos and Stenberg, 1980; Emde and Sorce 1983; Klinest et al
1983) have described a pheniomenon they call socal referencing,
‘The yearald infants ate placed in a situation bound to ereate
uncertainty, usually ambivalence between appeoach and withdesmrl
‘The infant may be lured with an attractive toy to crave across a
vial cli (an apparent drop-off, which is mildly frightening at
fone year of age or $0) or may be approached by an unusual but
highly stimulating objece such at 4 Meeping, Mashing: robot like
RaDz2 fram Siar Wars. When the infanss encounter these siuations
and give evidence of uncertainty, they look towards mother to read
ther face For its affective content, essentially to see what they should
feel, to get 4 second apprsil t9 help resolve their uncertainty. Tf
the mother hat been instructed eo show facial pleasure by smiling,
the infane crosses the visual cif. If che mother has been instructed
to show ficial fear, the infant turns back from the “cli” reeeats,
and pethaps becomes upset. Similarly, if che mother smiles at the
robot, the infant will too. If che shows fear, the infane will become
‘more wary. The point for our purposes is that infants would not
check with the mother in this fashion unless they ateshuced to her
the capacity wo have and to signal an affect tha has relevance to their
own actual or potential feeling states
‘Recent preliminary findings in our laboratory (MacKain et al
1985) suggest that infants a about nine months notice the congruence
berween their own affective wate and the affect exprenion seen on
someone's face. IF infants are made sad and upset by several minutes’
separation from mother (this is the age of acute separation reactions).
as soon as they are reunited with her they stop being upset but
remain solemn and are judged by mother and experimenters sill co
be sadder than usual, If then, right after the reunion when they are
still sad, the infants are shown. a happy face and a sad face, chey
prefer to look at the sad face. This does not hippen if the infants
ae either made to Laugh first o hid not been separited in the first
place. One conclusion i that the infant somehow makes a match
hecween the feeling state as experienced within and as seen “on or
"in" anocher, a match that we car call iuraltvey.
Interactivity may be the first, most pervasive, and most imme-
iseely important form of sharing subjective experiences. Demos
(1980, 1982s), Thoman and Acebo (1983), Tronick (1979), and
132
THE SENSE OF A SUBJECTIVE SELF: 1
others, as well as peychoanalysts, propose that early in life affects are
both the primary medium and the primary subject of communication.
‘This is in accord with our observations. And at nine to rwelve
months, when the infane has begun to share actions
about objects and to exchange propositions in prelinguistic form,
affective exchange is sill the predominant mode and substance of
‘communications with mother, Iti for this reason that the sharing
‘of affective states merits primary emphasis in ou views of infants of
i intentions
these ages. Mont protolinguistic exchanges involving intentions and
‘objects are atthe same time affective exchanges. (When the baby for
the first time says “bi-s” and points to the ball, the people around
sexpond with delight and excitement) The rwo go on simultaneously,
and findings chat define a given event as primarily linguistic or
‘primarily affective depend on perspective. However, the infant who
is just learning the discursive mode appears to be far more expert in
the domain of affect exchange. In a similar vein, Trevarthan and
Hubley (1978) have commented thatthe sharing of affective moods
and states appears before the sharing of mental states that reference
‘objets, that is, things outside of the dyad. It seems clear that the
sharing of affective states is of paramour imporeance during the fre
part of intersubjective relatednes, 20 much so that che next chapter
ill be devoted to a different view of che intersubjective sharing of
ecling, states
The Nature of the Leap to Intersubjectve Relaedness
Why does the infant suddenly adope an organizing subjective pere
spective about self and others that opens the door to antersabjectii
1 this quantum leap simply the result of a newly emergent, specific
capacity of skill? Or docs it result from the experience of social
interactions? Or is it the maturational wafolding of a major human
rnced and motive sate? Piaget (1954), Bruner (1975, 1977), Bates
(1976, 1979), and others whose primary approach. is cognitive or
linguistic view this achievernent mainly in terms of an acquited
social skill the infant discovers generative rales and procedures for
988Lf THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
dewcracions that ultimately lead to the discovery of ineerabjctviy
Trevachan (1978) has called this a eonstructionise approach
Shields (1978), Newson (1977). Vygotsky (1942) and others have
understood this achievement more as the result of mother’s entrance
into “meaning” exchanges, beginning a& the saints bith. She
interprets all the inf’s behaviors in terms of mranings that i she
ateributes meanings to them. She provides the semantic element all
by herself a fst, and continues o bring the infane’s behavior into
her framework of created meanings. Gradually, as the infant is able
the framework of meaning becomes mutually creat, This approach,
‘ed on social experience, might be called the approach of incerpe-
somal meanings.
‘Many thinkers in France and Switzerland have independently
approached the problem along similar lines and pushed the notion
cof maternal interpretation into richer clinical seriory. They anert
that mothers “meanings” reflect noe only what she observes but also
her fantasies about who the infant is and is t become. Intersubje-
tivity, for them, ultimately involves interfunasy. They have asked
hhow the fantasies of the parent come 10 influence the infane's
behavior and ultimately to shape the infan's own fancaies. This,
reciprocal fantay intercon ‘+ a form of created interpenonal
meaning atthe covert level (Kreis, Fair, and Soulé 1974; Keiser
sind Cearer 1981; Cramer 1982, 198%: Lebovici 1983: Pinal
Douricz 1983). The creation of such meanings has been called
“interactions fntasmatique." Fraierg etl. (1975) and Stem (1971),
dn the Unite States have sno paid close attenion tothe relationship
between maternal fantasy and overt behavior.
“Trevarthan (1974, 1978) has stood relatively alone in maintaining
hae intenubjeciviey is an inna, emergent human capacity. He
joins out thatthe other explanations forthe appearance of ieerub-
Jecsivity, especialy the constructionist explanation, do not allow for
‘ny special awareness of humans or forthe shared sorareness that i
se highly developed in humans, Ele sees this developmental leap as,
the “eliferentition of + coherent feld of intentionality” (Crevarehan
and Hubley 1978, p. 213) and views iaerubjecivicy as human
‘capacity preset in a primary form fram the eatly months of life*
4 tna hn cing meri Tvl wane"
(Tewetan and Hbley 199 che lee dren fs wane Banas ence
eel der emt be st emergent ama Spit. Howe ht
‘THE SENSE OF A SUBJECTIVE SELF: |
All thrce viewpoints seem necessary foram adequate explanation
of the emergence of intesubjectivty. Trevarthan is right hat some
special form of awareness must conse into play at this point and that
the capacity for it must wnfold maturationally, And that special
awareness what we ate calling an organizing subjective perspective
However, the xpacity mast have some tools to work with and the
constructivist approach has provided the tools in the form of rule
structures, action formats, and dicovery procedures. Finally, che
Capacity plus the tools would be operating in a vacuum without the
addition of inerperonal meanings that are mutually created. All
‘three taken together ar required fora fuller account of intersubjective
relatedness.
‘Once intersubjectivity has been tasted, 30 f0 speak, dors it just
remain 3 a espacty to be used of not, ot a penpetive on elf and
‘ther to be adopted or not? Or does it become a new psychological
‘need, the need to share subjective experience?
‘We cannot caaliily add to the lst of basic psychological needs
cvery time we came upon a new potentially autonomous capacity ae
need. The usual psychoanalytic solution to this problem, since the
pioneering work of Hartmann, Kris, and Lowenscin (194), is t0
call all such aueonomously functioning capacities and need-like states
“autonomous eo fonctions," rather than instincts or morivational
systems, This label gives them their self-evident primary autonomous
satus but also puts them potency 3¢ the service of the “basi”
rpvehoanalytic needs, whose higher starus is protected. (Iti mainly
fn the area of infancy research thatthe presence and pervasiveness
of newly recognized capacities and needs has become apparent and
poses the problem)
‘Up to a point, this solution of autonomous exo functions has
proven extremely helpful and generative forthe Fld. The question
| when does an autonomous exo function become of such magnitude
that it is beter conceived asa “has need or motivational system?
Curiosity and stimalus seeking are good cases in point. These appeat
‘mesmo yes of yma chr ee ea acto ea Tet
‘hee (1909 Thc er 0 got tht the eae peti eh
ed mempeio. Oly
"Thee tech mse to hve Ga oer sal say fr example, eb
capes aeajr eng wel ne1 / THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
te parake more of the quality of motivtional systems that of mere
autonomous ego functions.
‘What, then, ahout intersubjective relatedness? Are we #o consider
Or are we dealing with a
primary psychobiological need? ‘The answers to these questions are
this another autonomous ego fanet
actually momentous for clinical theory. The more one conceives of
interuubjective relatedness a8 a bisic psychological need, the closer
cone refashions clinical theory taward the configurstions suggested
by Self psychologists and some existential psychologist.
rom the perspective of infancy research, the question remains
open. One consideration in this inue ix wo figure ost what it 10
reinforcing about intersubjectivity. There is no question but that its
seinforcing power cin be relied. to achieving security needs or
attachment goals. For instance, intersubjective successes can result in
feelings of enhanced security. Similaely, minor flares in intcrsab
Jectivity cam be interpreted, experienced, and acted upon as toca!
‘ruptures in a relationship. This fs often seen in therapy.
‘A parallel view is that an overriding human need develops for
Ihamnat-group paychie-metabership
group a5 a member with potentially sharcable subjective experiences,
in contrast w a nonmember whose subjective experiences are wholly
tanigue,idioryncratic, and nonshareable. The issue is Basic. Opposite
poles of this one dimension of psychic experience define different
prychotic states. At one end is the sense of cosmic prychic isolation,
alienation, and aloncness (the last person Left on earth), and at che
‘other end isthe feeling of total prychie transparency, in which no
single comer of potentially shareable experience can be kept privat.
‘The infant presumably begins to encounter this dimension of psychic
‘experience somewhere in the middle, between the extreme poles, as
hati, ineloion in the huraan,
‘most of us continue to do.®
Speaking teleologically, 1 assume chat nature in the course of
‘evolution ‘created several ways to assure survival through group
THE SENSE OF A SUBJECTIVE SELF: 1
‘membership in social species. Ethology and attachment theory have
spelled out for us the behivioe patterns that serve to asiure thoie
vals that enhance
physical and psychological itcemeshings of ind
survival. I suggest that nature has also provided the ways and means
for any subjective intermeshings of individaals that would add
survival value. And the survival value of intersuyjeetvity is potentially
There is no question that different societies could minimize or
‘maximize this need for inersubjectivity. For instance, if a society
were socially structured so that it was assurned that all members had
essentially identical, inner subjective experiences, and if homogeneity
of this apect of felt life were stressed, there would be litte need,
and no societal pressure, 0 enhance the development of intersubjec=
tivity. Ifo the other hand a society highly valued the existence and
the sharing of individual differences at this level of experience (as
cours docs), then their development would be facilitated by that
‘Let us return to life as lived from moment to moment and examine
noce fully how affective experiences cin enter the intersubjective
domain, 2 phenomenon that I call afc atumement.Chapter 7
The Sense of a
Subjective Self:
IL, Affect Attunement
‘The Problem of iSheringiAlfitine States,
‘The sharing of active states is the most pervasive and clinically
scriaine feature of intersubjective celatedness. This is expeca
when the infant first enters this domain. Interffectivity is mainly
what i meant when clinicians speak of parental “mizroring™ and
“empathic responsiveness.” Despite the imporance of these events,
it is not a all clear how they work. What ae the ats and process
that let other people know that you are feling something very like
what they ate feeling? How can you get inside of” other people's
subjective experience and then let them know that you have arrived
there, without suing words? After all, the infants we are talking
about are-only | months od
Trnitation in co mind 28 a possible way one might
show this. The mother mighe imieate the infant's ficial expressions
and gestures, and the haby would see her doing this. The problem
with this solution is that che infant could only tell from the mother’s
THE SENSE OF A SUBJECTH
SELF/UL.
inmitation that mother got what the infant did; she would have
reproduced the same overt behaviors, but she need no have hud any
similar inner experience. There is no reason why the infant should
make the further assumption that mother also experienced the same
feeling state that gave rise to the overt behavior.
For there to be an intersubjective exchange about affect, che,
strit imitation alone won't do. In fact, seve
place JBimphe parent mast be able to read the infant's fecling state
from the infiat’s overt behavioe. the parent mus perfoen|
tome behavior thae is noe a srit ination but nonctheles corexpon
in some way ta che infants avert behavior, JIM, the infant must
be able to read this corresponding parental respome as having to do
with the infant's own original feeling experience and noe jus
inmieting the infan's behavior. It is only in the presence of tse
three conditions that feeling states within one person can be knowable
to another and that chey can both sense, without sing language,
thar the transaction has occurred.
‘To accomplish this tarsscio papeyma cote
detail (1981). What is striking in these descriptions is that the
one wi
procenea must take
fn fact, musical—dlomain sm great
slight changes in her contribution at each dialogic twM1/ THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
fe oa her vocalization may be slightly different each time
“Whieat che infant is around rine months old. however. one berinsyy
ke
(fe is not clear how
mothers know this change has occurred in the infant; it seems to be
are of thelr innaitive parssval sense.) She begins to expand ber
Eu yond tra tation ine «new ccpory of bebvor we
‘The phenomenon of affect attunement is best shown. by examples
(Stem 1985). Affect attunement is often so embedded in other
‘behaviors that relatively pure examples are hard! to find, but che Best
five examples that follow are relatively unencumbered by other
soings-on
A sinesmonth-old gil becomes very excited about a ay and aches
Page ape tar eyepin| ipa eee lenn/ peyer
a2 her meet Her mother Moka back, sachs op her shonbion
and performs a tric shimmy with her upper boy, like a go-eo
dance The shimmy lass only aboot Tong. as her daughters
Samah” hit equally excited, onl an intense
J cloementhcld boy tgs Lit bod ona sft pat Bt i me
anger bot graualy wih psu, exubernes and humor, He se
‘ps steady thythm. Mother falls into his hyn and ay, “Kanne
im, Kstasshom," the "hon fling othe sek andthe lass”
fing with the pepurtory eponing and he mupersfal holding of
bisa alo hefore fale aa 2
‘hn cightand-ane-hlfamoath-old boy races fora toy ja beyond
teach, Slenly he stretches towaed leaning and extending sms
{agers out filly Sell shore of the toys be tne hs body 0
iqocere ou the en inch he ned 10 reach i At chat moment is
mother says "uaouah . avobah!” witha crescendo of vocal efor.
the expintion of sr pusing sist her tensed toms. The mothers
seccering roabesprntory Bort matches the ina’ scelering
Bhp fore
| teemonth-old ge accomplishes an amasing routine with mother
dnd then lok athe. The gel opens op her ie (er mouth opens
her eyes widen, he eyebrows ic) and the loses tack nee
of changes whove contour can he represented by 4 smooth sich
(7), Moser responds by ntoning "Yeaby” with pic line
that rise and alt asthe volume crescendor and decreed
‘THE SENSE OF A SUBJECTIVE SELF: 1
“YR” The mother's prosodic contour has matched the chil’
‘eu inetic cortour
‘Arnine-month-old boy is siting facing is mother, He his
‘mis hand and i shaking e up and doven wich daplay of
And ik amosement. As mother watches she begins to nod ber
hnead up and down, keeping 2 tight heat with her won art motions
‘More often the attunement is 50 embedded in other actions and
‘purposes that i is putially masked, asin che next example:
[A tem-month-old itl finally gees a piece in jg saw pura, She
tects toward ner tether, hres fet heed op tn the ssfand wich
forcefal arm flap raises hersef partly off the ground in a furry of
fnubersnce. The mother says "YES, thats gin” The "YES" i
fetoned wth mach stem. Te has an explonine re that choos the
fi Hing of penuee and power.
(One could easly argue that the “YES, thats girl functions as 4
rourine response in che focm of a postive reinforcer, and it certainly
does do so. But why does the mother noc just xy “Yes, carta giel"?
Why docs she need to add the intense intonation to “WES” that
vocally matches the child's gestures? The “YES.” 1 suggest, isan
attunement embedded within 4 routine response
‘The embecling of attunements is $o common and most often s0
subtle that unles one is looking for it, or asking why any behavior
i being. performed exactly the way itis, the attunements will pass
unnoticed (except, of course, that one will gather from them what
ve imagine to be “really” going on clinically),
‘Attunements have the following characteristics, which makes them
ideal for sccomplishing the interactive sharing of affect:
1, They give the impresion that a kind of imitation has oscurres
‘There tt no faithful rendering of the infnt's over behusio, but
ee nt
‘2 "The matching is Iargely romrmodal. Thai the channel or modalicy
‘of exprenion wied by the mother 19 match the infants Behavior
‘by the infant Inthe
feat example, che iaenaey level and duration of the gis voice is
fected bp eared ty meepren fa fs focal cater
festors of the boy's erm rnovcoents are wetcbed by fae ofthe
matber's voice.1L/ THE FOUR SENSES OF SELF
3. WR ic heing matched is nat the other person’ behewor pre hae
‘ate The ultimate reference forthe match appears
‘stam (infered or sirectly apprehended), not the external behavioral
trent. Thos the match appear to occur betwcen the expersions of
inner ste. These expresons cam difer in mode ot Form. but they
ie ta aces alee chee i mtlciataen
rantage of soggesting complete temporal synchrony. “Echoin
taken litelly, at last avoids the tempor constraint. In spite of
these semansc limitations, however, thete concept reptetent attempt
to grapple with the ssue of one person releting another's inner
state nth important respect, unlike imitation a contagion. they
are appropriately concerned with the subjective state rather than the
manifest behavior
“This meaning of reflecting inner state has been used mostly in
clinical cheories (Maier etal. 1975; Kohut 197%; Lacan 1977),
which hhave noted that reflecting back an infu’ feling state i
importne to the infan’s developing knowledge of his or her own
aMfetvity and sense of self When used in this seme, however,
“mirroring” implies chat the mother is helping to create something,
within the lafaat that was only dimly or purty theee uel hee
reflection acted somehow so vlily iy existence, This concept goer
far beyond just participating in another's subjective experience. It
involves changing the other by providing something the ocher did
tc have before of if t was present by consolidating it
‘A second problem with miroring at term i the inconsvtency
anu overinclusivenes of its usage. In elnial writings. ic sometimes
refers to the behavior itelf—ehat is, to true imitation, a Bveral
reflecting back, in the domain of core-e
to the sharing or aignenent of internal sete
sdness—and sometimes
in. ous terms, affect
attunement in the domain of intersubjective relatedness. sill cher
/BJECTIVE SELF; I
times, it refer: to verbal reinforcements or consensual validation at
the Ievel of verbal relatedness, “Mirroring” is thus commonly wsed
to embrace three different processes. Moreover, itis not clear which
subjective states are to be included in mitroring affects—intentions?
motives? belief? ego functions? In shor, while mirroring has focused
‘upon the estence ofthe pralem, the indeterminate usage has blurred
what appear to be real diferences in mechanism, form, and Function
Finally, there is “empathy.” Is attunement suficiently close %0
‘what is generally meant by empithy? No, The evidence indicates
that artune almost automat
ically. Empathy. on the wther hand, involves the mediation of
. What is generally called empathy consists of at
least four distinct and probably sequential processes {1} the resonance
(of feeling state; (2) she abstraction of empathic knowledge from the
experience of emotional resonance; (3) the integration of abstracted
‘empathic knowledge into an empathic response; and (6) a ernsient
role identification, Cognitive processes such as theve involved in the
second and third events are crucial ro empathy (Schaffer 1968;
Hoffman 1978; Ornstein 1979; Buch 1963; Demos 1984). (Cognitive
imaginings of owhae it mut be like to he another perion, however,
are nothing more than elaborated acts of roe taking and aot empathy,
unless they have been ignited by at least a spurk of emotional
resonance) Affect attunement, then, shares with empathy the inital
process of emotional resonance (Holfiman 1978); neither can occur
without it. The work of many paychoanalytic thinkers concurs on
this formulation (Basch 1983). But while affect attunement, like
empathy, stares with an emotional resonance, it dos something
dliflerent with it, Attunement takes the experience of emotional
resonance and automatially recasts that experience into anothes forts
of expression, Attunement thus need not proceed towards empathic
knowledge ot response. Amanement is a distince form of affective
transaction in its own right.