0% found this document useful (0 votes)
109 views53 pages

Budget Constraint Preferences and Utility

- The budget constraint defines the combinations of goods a consumer can afford based on prices and income. Increasing income shifts the budget constraint outward in a parallel fashion, while changing prices affects the slope. - Consumer preferences are represented by indifference curves, with higher curves indicating higher levels of satisfaction. Preferences should be complete, reflexive, and transitive. - The marginal rate of substitution measures the amount of one good that would compensate for a small decrease in the other good, keeping utility unchanged.

Uploaded by

Toshia Mc Donald
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
109 views53 pages

Budget Constraint Preferences and Utility

- The budget constraint defines the combinations of goods a consumer can afford based on prices and income. Increasing income shifts the budget constraint outward in a parallel fashion, while changing prices affects the slope. - Consumer preferences are represented by indifference curves, with higher curves indicating higher levels of satisfaction. Preferences should be complete, reflexive, and transitive. - The marginal rate of substitution measures the amount of one good that would compensate for a small decrease in the other good, keeping utility unchanged.

Uploaded by

Toshia Mc Donald
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 53

Budget Constraint,

Preferences and Utility


Varian: Intermediate Microeconomics, 8e, Chapters 2, 3 and 4

() 1 / 53
Consumer Theory
Consumers choose the best bundles of goods they can afford.
• This is virtually the entire theory in a nutshell.
• But this theory has many surprising consequences.

Two parts to consumer theory


• “can afford” – budget constraint
• “best” – according to consumers’ preferences

() 2 / 53
Consumer Theory (cont´d)
What do we want to do with the theory?
• Test it. See if it is adequate to describe consumer behavior.
• Predict how behavior changes as economic environment changes.
• Use observed behavior to estimate underlying values.

These values can be used for


• cost-benefit analysis,
• predicting impact of some policy.

() 3 / 53
Budget Constraint

The first part of the lecture explains


• what is the budget constraint and
the budget line,
• how changes in income and prices
affect the budget line,
• how taxes, subsidies and rationing
affect the budget line.

() 4 / 53
Consumption Bundle
For goods 1 and 2, the consumption bundle (x1 , x2 ) shows how much
of each good is consumed.

Suppose that we can observe


• the prices of the two goods (p1 , p2 )
• and the amount of money the consumer has to spend m
(income).

The budget constraint can be written as p1 x1 + p2 x2 ≤ m.

The affordable consumption bundles are bundles that don’t cost more
than income.

The set of affordable consumption bundles is budget set of the


consumer.
() 5 / 53
Two Goods

Theory works with more than two goods, but


can’t draw pictures.

We often think of good 2 (say) as a


composite good, representing money to
spend on other goods.

Budget constraint becomes p1 x1 + x2 ≤ m.

Money spent on good 1 (p1 x1 ) plus the money


spent on good 2 (x2 ) has to be less than or
equal to the available income (m).

() 6 / 53
Budget Line
Budget line is p1 x1 + p2 x2 = m. It can be also written as
m p1
x2 = − x1 .
p2 p2

Slope of budget line = opportunity cost of good 1.

() 7 / 53
Change in Income
Increasing m makes parallel shift out.
The vertical intercept increases and the slope remains the same.

() 8 / 53
Change in One Price
Increasing p1 makes the budget line steeper.

The vertical intercept remains the same and the slope changes.

() 9 / 53
Changes in More Variables
Multiplying all prices by t is just like dividing income by t:
m
tp1 x1 + tp2 x2 = m ⇐⇒ p1 x1 + p2 x2 = .
t

Multiplying all prices and income by t doesn’t change budget line:


tp1 x1 + tp2 x2 = tm ⇐⇒ p1 x1 + p2 x2 = m.

A perfectly balanced inflation doesn’t change consumption


possibilities.

() 10 / 53
Numeraire
We can arbitrarily assign one price or income a value of 1 and adjust
the other variables so as to describe the same budget set.

Budget line: p1 x1 + p2 x2 = m
The same budget line for p2 = 1:
p1 m
x1 + x2 = .
p2 p2
The same budget line for m = 1:
p1 p2
x1 + x2 = 1.
m m
The price adjusted to 1 is called the numeraire price.

Useful when measuring relative prices; e.g. English pounds per dollar,
1987 dollars versus 1974 dollars, etc.
() 11 / 53
Taxes
Three types of taxes:
• quantity tax – consumer pays amount t for each unit she
purchases.
→ Price of good 1 increases to p1 + t.
• value tax (or ad valorem tax) – consumer pays a proportion of
the price τ .
→ Price of good 1 increases to p1 + τ p1 = (1 + τ )p1 .
• lump-sum tax – amount of tax is independent of the consumer’s
choices.
→ The income of consumer decreases by the amount of the tax.

() 12 / 53
Subsidies

Subsidies – opposite effect than the taxes


• quantity subsidy of s on good 1
→ Price price of good 1 decreases to p1 − s.
• ad valorem subsidy at a rate of σ on good 1
→ Price price of good 1 decreases to p1 − σp1 = (1 − σ)p1 .
• lump-sum subsidy
→ The income increases by the amount of the subsidy.

() 13 / 53
Rationing
Rationing – can’t consume more than a certain amount of some good.
Good 1 is rationed, no more than x̄ units of good 1 can be consumed
by any consumer.

() 14 / 53
Taxing Consumption Greater than x¯1
Taxed only consumption of good 1 in excess of x¯1 , the budget line
becomes steeper right of x¯1

() 15 / 53
The Food Stamp Program
Before 1979 was an ad valorem subsidy on food
• paid a certain amount of money to get food stamps which were
worth more than they cost
• some rationing component — could only buy a maximum
amount of food stamps
After 1979 got a straight lump-sum grant of food coupons. Not the
same as a pure lump-sum grant since could only spend the coupons
on food.

() 16 / 53
() 17 / 53
Summary

• The budget set consists of bundles of goods


that the consumer can afford at given prices
and income. Typically assume only 2 goods –
one of the goods might be composite good.
• The budget line can be written as
p1 x1 + p2 x2 = m.
• Increasing income shifts the budget line
outward. Increasing price of one good changes
the slope of the budget line.
• Taxes, subsidies, and rationing change the
position and slope of the budget line.

() 18 / 53
Preferences

The second part of the lecture explains


• what are consumer’s preferences,
• what properties have well-behaved
preferences,
• what is marginal rate of
substitution.

() 19 / 53
Preferences - Introduction

Economic model of consumer behavior – people


choose the best things they can afford
• up to now, we clarified “can afford”
• next, we deal with “best things”

Several observations about optimal choice from


movements of budget lines
• perfectly balanced inflation doesn’t change
anybody’s optimal choice
• after a rise of income, the same choices are
available – consumer must be at least as well of
as before

() 20 / 53
Preferences
Preferences are relationships between bundles.
• If a consumer chooses bundle (x1 , x2 ) when (y1 , y2 ) is available,
then it is natural to say that bundle (x1 , x2 ) is preferred to
(y1 , y2 ) by this consumer.
• Preferences have to do with the entire bundle of goods, not with
individual goods.

Notation
• (x1 , x2 )  (y1 , y2 ) means the x-bundle is strictly preferred to the
y-bundle.
• (x1 , x2 ) ∼ (y1 , y2 ) means that the x-bundle is regarded as
indifferent to the y-bundle.
• (x1 , x2 )  (y1 , y2 ) means the x-bundle is at least as good as
(or weakly preferred) the y-bundle.
() 21 / 53
Assumptions about Preferences
Assumptions about “consistency” of consumers’ preferences:
• Completeness — any two bundles can be compared:
(x1 , x2 )  (y1 , y2 ), or (x1 , x2 )  (y1 , y2 ), or both
• Reflexivity — any bundle is at least as good as itself:
(x1 , x2 )  (x1 , x2 )
• Transitivity — if the bundle X is at least as good as Y and Y
at least as good as Z , then X is at least as good as Z :
If (x1 , x2 )  (y1 , y2 ), and (y1 , y2 )  (z1 , z2 ), then
(x1 , x2 )  (z1 , z2 )
Transitivity necessary for theory of optimal choice. Otherwise, there
could be a set of bundles for which there is no best choice.

() 22 / 53
Indifference Curves
Weakly preferred set are all consumption bundles that are weakly
preffered to a bundle (x1 , x2 ).
Indifference curve is formed by all consumption bundles for which
the consumer is indifferent to (x1 , x2 ) – like contour lines on a map.

() 23 / 53
Indifference Curves (cont’d)
Note that indifference curves describing two distinct levels of
preference cannot cross.

Proof — we know that X ∼ Z and Z ∼ Y . Transitivity implies that


X ∼ Y . This contradicts the assumption that X  Y .

() 24 / 53
Examples: Perfect Substitutes
Perfect substitutes have constant rate of trade-off between the two
goods; constant slope of the indifference curve (not necessarily −1).

E.g. red pencils and blue pencils; pints and quarts.

() 25 / 53
Examples: Perfect Complements
Perfect complements are consumed in fixed proportion (not
necessarily 1:1).

E.g. right shoes and left shoes; coffee and cream.

() 26 / 53
Examples: Bad Good

A bad is a commodity that the consumer doesn’t like.

Suppose consumer is doesn’t like anchovies and likes pepperoni.

() 27 / 53
Examples: Neutral Good

Consumer doesn’t care about the neutral good.

Suppose consumer is neutral about anchovies and likes pepperoni.

() 28 / 53
Examples: Satiation Point
Satiation or bliss point is the most preferred bundle (x¯1 , x¯2 )
• When consumer has too much of good, it becomes a bad –
reducing consumption of the good makes consumer better off.
• E.g. amount of chocolate cake and ice cream per week

() 29 / 53
Examples: Discrete Good
Discrete good is only available in integer amounts.
• Indiference “curves” – sets of discrete points; weakly preferred
set – line segments.
• Important if consumer chooses only few units of the good per
time period (e.g. cars).

() 30 / 53
Well-Behaved Preferences
Monotonicity – more is better (we have only goods, not bads) =⇒
indifference curves have negative slope (see Figure 3.9):
If (y1 , y2 ) has at least as much of both goods as (x1 , x2 ) and more of
one, then (y1 , y2 )  (x1 , x2 ).
Convexity – averages are preferred to extremes =⇒ slope gets
flatter as you move further to right (see Figure 3.10):
If (x1 , x2 ) ∼ (y1 , y2 ), then (tx1 + (1 − t)y1 , tx2 + (1 − t)y2 )  (x1 , x2 )
for all 0 ≤ t ≤ 1
• non convex preferences – olives and ice cream
• strict convexity – If the bundles (x1 , x2 ) ∼ (y1 , y2 ), then
(tx1 + (1 − t)y1 , tx2 + (1 − t)y2 )  (x1 , x2 ) for all 0 ≤ t ≤ 1

() 31 / 53
() 32 / 53
() 33 / 53
Marginal Rate of Substitution
Marginal rate of substitution (MRS) is the slope of the
indifference curve: MRS = ∆x2 /∆x1 = dx2 /dx1 .
Sign problem — natural sign is negative, since indifference curves will
generally have negative slope.

() 34 / 53
Marginal Rate of Substitution (cont’d)

MRS measures how the consumer is willing to trade off consumption


of good 1 for consumption of good 2 (see Figure 3.12).

For strictly convex preferences, the indifference curves exhibit


diminishing marginal rate of sustitution

Other interpretation: marginal willingness to pay – how much of


good 2 is one willing to pay for a extra consumption of good 1.

If good 2 is a composite good, the willingness-to-pay interpretation is


very natural.

Not the same as how much you have to pay.

() 35 / 53
() 36 / 53
Example: Slope of the Indifference Curve

1) Calculate the slope of the indifference curve x2 = 4/x1 at the point


(x1 , x2 ) = (2, 2).
dx2 −4
Slope of the indifference curve = MRS = = 2 = −1.
dx1 x1

2) Calculate the slope of the indifference curve x2 = 10 − 6 x1 at the
point (x1 , x2 ) = (4, 5).

dx2 −3 −3
Slope of the indifference curve = MRS = =√ = .
dx1 x1 2

() 37 / 53
Summary

• Economists assume that a consumer can rank


consumption bundles. The ranking describes
the consumer’s preferences.
• The preferences are assumed to be complete,
reflexive and transitive.
• Well-behaved preferences are monotonic and
convex.
• MRS measures the slope of the indifference
curve. MRS can be interpreted as how much of
good 2 is one willing to pay for an extra
consumption of good 1.

() 38 / 53
Utility

The third part of the lecture


explains
• what is utility,
• what is a utility function,
• what is a monotonic
tranformation of a utility
function,
• how can we use utility
function to calculate MRS.

() 39 / 53
Utility

Two ways of viewing utility:

Old way - measures how “satisfied” you are


(cardinal utility)
• not operational
• many other problems

New way - summarizes preferences, only the


ordering of bundles counts (ordinal utility)
• operational
• gives a complete theory of demand

() 40 / 53
Ordinal Utility

A utility function assigns a number to each bundle of goods so that


more preferred bundles get higher numbers.

If (x1 , x2 )  (y1 , y2 ), then u(x1 , x2 ) > u(y1 , y2 ).

Three ways to assign utility that represent the same preferences:

() 41 / 53
Utility Function is Not Unique

A positive monotonic transformation f (u) is any increasing


function.

Examples: f (u) = 3u, f (u) = u + 3, f (u) = u 3 .

If u(x1 , x2 ) is a utility function that represents some preferences,


then f (u(x1 , x2 )) represents the same preferences.

Why? Because u(x1 , x2 ) > u(y1 , y2 ) only if f (u(x1 , x2 )) > f (u(y1 , y2 )).

() 42 / 53
Constructing Utility Functions
Mechanically using the indifference curves.

() 43 / 53
Examples: Utility to Indifference Curves
Easy — just plot all points where the utility is constant
Utility function u(x1 , x2 ) = x1 x2 ;
k
Indifference curves: k = x1 x2 ⇐⇒ x2 = x1

() 44 / 53
Examples: Indifference Curves to Utility
More difficult - given the preferences, what combination of goods
describes the consumer’s choices.

Perfect substitutes
• All that matters is total number of pencils, so u(x1 , x2 ) = x1 + x2
does the trick.
• Can use any monotonic transformation of this as well, such as
ln(x1 + x2 ).

Perfect complements
• What matters is the minimum of the left and right shoes you
have, so u(x1 , x2 ) = min{x1 , x2 } works.
• In general, if it not 1:1, the utility function is
u(x1 , x2 ) = min{ax1 , bx2 }, where a and b are positive numbers.
() 45 / 53
Examples: Indifference Curves to Utility (cont’d)

Quasilinear preferences
• Indifference curves are vertically parallel (see Figure 4.4). Not
particularly realistic, but easy to work with.
• Utility function has form u(x1 , x2 ) = v (x1 ) + x2

• Specific examples: u(x1 , x2 ) = x1 + x2 or u(x1 , x2 ) = ln x1 + x2

Cobb-Douglas preferences
• Simplest algebraic expression that generates well-behaved
preferences.
• Utility function has form u(x1 , x2 ) = x1b x2c (See Figure 4.5).
1
• Convenient to take transformation f (u) = u b+c and write
b c
x1b+c x2b+c or x1a x21−a , where a = b/(b + c).

() 46 / 53
() 47 / 53
() 48 / 53
Marginal Utility
Marginal utility (MU) is extra utility from some extra consumption
of one of the goods, holding the other good fixed.

A partial derivative – this just means that you look at the derivative
of u(x1 , x2 ) keeping x2 fixed — treating it like a constant.
Examples:
• if u(x1 , x2 ) = x1 + x2 , then MU1 = ∂u/∂x1 = 1
• if u(x1 , x2 ) = x1a x21−a , then MU1 = ∂u/∂x1 = ax1a−1 x21−a

Note that marginal utility depends on which utility function you


choose to represent preferences.
• If you multiply utility 2x, you multiply marginal utility 2x =⇒
it is not an operational concept.
• However, MU is closely related to MRS, which is an operational
concept.
() 49 / 53
Relationship between MU and MRS
An indifference curve u(x1 , x2 ) = k, where k is a constant.

We want to measure slope of indifference curve, the MRS.

So consider a change (∆x1 , ∆x2 ) that keeps utility constant. Then,


MU1 ∆x1 + MU2 ∆x2 = 0

∂u ∂u
∆x1 + ∆x2 = 0.
∂x1 ∂x2

Hence,
∆x2 MU1
=− .
∆x1 MU2

So we can compute MRS from knowing the utility function.


() 50 / 53
Example: Utility for Commuting

Question: Take a bus or take a car to work?

Each way of transport represents bundle of


different characteristics: Let x1 be the time of
taking a car, y1 be the time of taking a bus.
Let x2 be cost of car, etc.

Suppose utility function takes linear form


U(x1 , ..., xn ) = β1 x1 + ... + βn xn .

We can observe a number of choices and use


statistical tech- niques to estimate the
parameters βi that best describe choices.

() 51 / 53
Example: Utility for Commuting (con’t)
Domenich a McFadden (1975) report a utility function
U(TE , TT , C ) = −0.147TW − 0.0411TT − 2.24C ,
where
TW = total walking time to and from bus or car in minutes
TT = total time of trip in minutes
C = total cost of trip in dollars.

Once we have the utility function we can do many things with it:
• Calculate the marginal rate of substitution between two
characteristics. How much money would the average consumer
give up in order to get a shorter travel time?
• Forecast consumer response to proposed changes.
• Estimate whether proposed change is worthwhile in a benefit-cost
sense.
() 52 / 53
Summary

• A utility function is a way to represent a


preference ordering. The numbers
assigned to different utility levels have no
intrinsic meaning.
• Any monotonic transformation of a utility
function will represent the same
preferences.
• The marginal rate of substitution is equal
to MRS = ∆x2 /∆x1 = −MU1 /MU2 .

() 53 / 53

You might also like