0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes) 113 views22 pagesFainstein City Planning
planificacion urbana, 50 tesis de feinstein
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content,
claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
12!
City Planning and
Political Values:
An Updated View"
Susan S. Fainstein
and Norman Fainstein
Contemporary planning theorists have virtually all accepted the
argument that planning decisions are unavoidably political. Nevertheless,
analyses of planning, while increasingly grounded in contemporary social
thought, have largely ignored the classical literature of political theory.
The intent of this chapter is to make explicit the links between current
discussions of planning and long traditions of political thought. An exam-
ination of the political thought that underlies different approaches
to planning can reveal the political value and interests embodied in
planning procedures and allow planning processes to be related to
political culture. The exercise therefore serves two purposes: First, it
shows the implications of each type of planning in terms of political
benefits; that is, it makes clear which social groups each form favors.
Second, it points toward an explanation of why planning has largely been
shunned within the American polity
We define planning here as future-oriented, public decision making
directed toward attaining specific goals; for the purposes of our discus:
sion, we exclude planning carried out by private bodies. Although a plan
‘once enacted constitutes a politically determined public policy, it differs
from other kinds of political decisions in that it is based on formal266 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
| rationality and is explicit about ends and means. This specificity is in |
sharp contrast io many other public decisions, which are left purpovetully |
vague and ambiguous so as to mitigate controversy. While a decision }
need not be labeled a plan in order to fit our definition, political decisions
directed at long-term goals are rarely made except under the auspices of
a planning group,
1t is possible to set up a typology of planning approaches on the basis
of who determines the plan’s goals and who determines its means. While
one can conceive of a number of different bases for typologies of
planning, that of policy determination is politically the most important. t
For once planning is viewed as a political process, and once a typologe is
established that is based upon the location of authoritative decision
making, it becomes possible to equate each planning type with a partic-
ular model of decision making in political theory
The Planning Typology
The categories that follow are derived from the points of view presented
in discussions of planning and are not necessarily either exhaustive or
mutually exclusive. Like the political doctzines to which they will be
elated, they contain internal contradictions and elements in common
with one another. Thus, the planning typology that we are establishing
is empirical rather than strictly logical. But as we shall attempt to show
later, the differences among the types make a great deal of sense within }
the history of political thought.
‘The four kinds of planning we discuss are (1) traditional, (2) demoe-
ratic, (3) equity, and (4) incremental (although we shall attempt to
demonstrate that incrementalism, while often presented as a de facto
planning model, is not truly planning). We trace these four planning
approaches to technocratic, democratic, socialist, and liberal political
theory respectively, although our discussion of socialism shows that
equity planning is a hybrid form incorporating elements of both demo:
cratic and socialist thought.
Traditional planning 6. ; |
In this type of planning, the planner prescribes both the goals of the plan
and the means of attaining them (Gans 1993: chapter 8). The justi-
fication for the elitism involved in such an approach is that there is a |
right and wrong way to developa city. Planners, by virtue of their exper:
tise and experience, know the correct path, can exercise unbiased
judgment, and can be trusted to use their technical knowledge to dis-
cover the public interest
The principal objective of traditional planners is the orderly develop- |
i
i
i |
i
}City Planning and Political Values 267
‘ment of the urban environment, and the proximate goals of the plan are
derived from standards that supposedly measure desirable physical
arrangements. Thus, for example, the amount of land to be devoted to
parks is calculated on the basis of a fixed ratio between green space and
Population density, The use of general standards permits the designation
of planning objectives without consulting groups within the general
Population. Thomas A, Reiner (1967: 232) summarizes the traditional
outlook as follows:
An appealing and plausible idea attracts planners the world over: we are
scientists, or at least capable of becoming such. As scientists, or technicians,
we work with facts o arrive at truth, using methods and lartguage appro
priate to our tasks, and our ways of handling problems are not subject to
outsiders’ criticism,
The conception of scientific planning assumes that planners’ special
qualifications free them from class or special-interest biases when they
are formulating the contents of the plan. Like the entire movement for
municipal reform, of which the planning movement formed part, plan-
ning advocates assumed that elficiency and orderly administtation in
government were general public goals that did not serve particular
social interests. Gans (1993: 128), however, correctly points out that
planners have generally advocated policies that fit the predispositions of
the upper classes but not those of the rest of the population,
The ends underlying the planners’ physical approach reflected their
Protestant upper- and middle-class view of city life. As a result, the master
lan tried to eliminate as “blighting influences” many of the facilities, land
arid institutions of working-class, low-income, and ethnic groups.
The plans called for many parks and playgrounds. but left out the movie
house, the neighborhood tavern, and the local club room; they proposed
museums and churches, but no hot-dog stands and nightclubs; they planned
for industrial parks, but not loft industry; for parking garages, but not auto~
‘mobile repair stations.
The much-criticized replacement of Boston's West End (see Fried
1967; Gans 1967) by a group of neatly arranged, high-rise apartments
for upper-income residents marked the apogee of the movement to
upgrade the urban environment through the imposition of physical
orderliness. The different kinds of order that observers such as Gans
found in the West End were not apparent to the planners, whose criteria
for demarcating slums rated the number of “standard” dwelling units
present in an area
Critics of the claims of sciemific analysis supposedly embodied in268 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
SSS
Planning contend that the vocabulary of planners primarily functioned
to deflect opposition, masking the interests served by the urban system:
Does it make sense even, to tell the inner-city tenant that the rent paid to the
landlord is not really a payment to that man who drives a big car and lives
in the suburbs but a payment to a scarce factor of production? The “scien
tization” of social science seems to have been accomplished by masking real
social relationships — by representing the social relations between people and
groups of people as relations between things. (Harvey 1985: 167; see also
Fischer 1990, 1991)
Even the one element within the planning movement that did con-
cern itself with the plight of the poor incorporated upper-class
assumptions. The advocates of urban playgrounds and public housing
were attempting to improve the welfare of slum dwellers and showed
considerable concer with the lot of the disadvantaged. Their overall
goal of an orderly physical environment for both rich and poor, how-
ever, reflected a class bias against the seeming disorderliness of the lower
lasses, a belief that along with physical neatness went desirable patterns
of social behavior, and an unwarranted hope that social problems
resulting from insufficient income could be remedied through physical
improvements.
Democratic planning
During the 1960s, critics of traditional planning accused planners of
imposing their vision of an idealized bourgeois world on a resistant pop-
ulation. They called for the transformation of planning from a top-down
to a participatory process. For example, Gans, in discussing planning for
the public library, argued that “the planning of its facilities ought to be
determined by whatever goal or goals the community considers impor-
tant . .." (Gans, 1968: 102-3). According to David R. Godschalk (1967:
972), *What is needed is a modus operandi which brings governmental
planners face-to-face with citizens in a continuous cooperative venture,
Such a venture could not only educate and involve the community in
planning, but could also educate and involve the planners in their
community.”
Godschalk’s stress on the importance of constant communication
between planners and the public continues to the present in the works
of such influential planning theorists as John Friedmann and John
Forester. Friedmann (1987: 327) calls for a “struggle .. . for a recovery
of the political community on which our Western ideas of democratic
governance are based.” He discusses the role of radical planners in achiev.
ing this social transformation, stipulating that they must be open to the
knowledge possessed by those “in the front line of action ~ households,City Planning and Political Values 269
Jocal communities, social movements” (Friedmann 1987: 394). Similarly,
Forester (1989: 155) exhorts planners to develop a set of community
relations strategies, for example, cultivating community networks,
alerting less organized interests of significant issues, assuring that
community-based groups are adequately informed and engage in critical
analysis of policies affecting them, exercising skills in conflict manag
ment and group relations, and compensating for political and economic
pressures.
Democratic planners rely on the public as the ultimate authority in the
formulation of plans and take a populist view that differentiates between
special interests and the public interest. Most writers in this tradition
generally side with the underdog, thereby privileging economically or
politically disedvantaged groups in their analysis. To this extent their
arguments merge with those of equity planners (discussed below), and
there is a tendency in theory - although not in practice ~ to favor those
least well off, often at the expense of those in the middle. Inkerently,
however, democratic theory cannot assume that the interests of any
group should be preferred; therefore, there is confusion over which clien-
teles should be involved in the formulation of plans. As Gans (1968: 103)
utsit in his discussion of the public library, “The question is, which users
should be planned for?”
While the problem is not insurmountable in the planning of a library,
where different branches can accommodate different users, it becomes :
much more difficult in cases where there are fewer possibilities of servin,
a plurality of interests simultaneously. For example, should urban rede-
velopment planning involve only present or also potential future
‘occupants of the site? Should it involve business and other groups that
may not occupy the site but may nonetheless have an important stake in
opportunities presented by revitalization? Should zoning regulations and
housing programs be aimed at perpetuating the character of a district as
it is, or should they respond to the desires of outsiders who might wish
to move into the district? Is the issue different when the outsiders are
low-income people seeking to enter a higher-income area than when
they are high-income households gentrifying a low-income one? The
democratic planner must contend with the problem of conflicting inter-
ests and must judge the legitimacy of the representatives of various
dlienteles. By accepting the right of community actors to participate in
the planning process, democratic planners find themselves forced t0
make political judgments that the insulated, traditional planner neve:
had to confront. Vet in making these judgments, they evade admitting
that they are advancing the particular Values or interests of some segment
of society: rather, they claim to be acting in the public interest or, by
pressing for the interests of typically excluded groups, creating the neces-
sary condition for genuine democracy. Although, according to the
democratic planning ideal, the public chooses both ends and means, in270 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
Rractice the planner shapes the alternatives that will be considered by
determining the composition of the planning group.
Equity planning
Fauity and democratic planning are overlapping types, but while demo
plan Panning emphasizes the participatory process, the thrust of equity
Plenning is on the substance of programs, The issue thus shits hom why,
Soverns to who geis what. Planners begin with the ov.
increasing equality; who determines the
depends on the situation
‘ihe concept of equity planning contains an explicit recognition of a
‘multitude of conflicting social interests, some of which may become nec
facilable. From this viewpoint all public programs create winners and
losers, and all 00 often the typical losers are those who already arc eater,
ing from social and economic disadvantages. Rather than attempting o
plan for society as a whole, the equity planner would “promote » waicy
Tange of choices for those . . . residents who have few" (Krumhols and
Forester 1990: 48). Equity planners, rather than engaging in cost-benelit
analyses that determine whether a policy is beneficial in the aggregate,
examine the distribution of costs and benelits
The terms equity and advocacy planning are now used more or less
interchangeably.’ As originally defined by Paul Davidolf, however,
advocacy planning referred to the defense of excluded interests, While
the advocate planner could theoretically work for any social group, the
term has generally been interpreted to mean “advocate for the poor”
Advocacy planning, in this firs formulation, was a more limited concept
than equity planning, since it did not present a model of a planner
Working for a public body. Rather, Davidoff based his model on the legal
system and developed a scenario in which the planner was responsible
to his or her client and unabashedly sought to express only the clients
interests (Davidoff 1967)” Advocacy planning as limited to this
approach, was an extension of what Lindblom calls partisan mutual
adjustment (see below). It depended on a pluralist bargaining system in
which previously excluded groups were given equal standing with other
interests that had always been able to purchase the services of profes
sional planners. Advocate planners were simply consultants who acted
on behalf of groups that could afford their services only if offered pro
bono or financed by outside sources like foundations or government
programs.
The concept of advocacy planning, however, has evolved to inchide
planners inside as well as outside government. The planner’s activities,
paralleling changes in the profession in general, have become more of
Jess fixed and less tied to plan preparation: “This kind of advocacy is more
entrepreneurial than legal - more open in its framework of assumptions
‘erarching goal of
means and intermediate goalsCity Planning and Political Values
Oeics
‘more creative in its solutions, much broader in the kinds of understand-
ingiit tries to synthesize, more interactive and responsive” (Marris 1994)
In this new formulation, there is no distinction between advocacy and
equity planning
Equity planning differs fundamentally from traditional planning, in
that particular planning specifics need not be justified as being in the
general public interest (although equity planners argue that their overall
objective of achieving redistributional goals is in the public interest and,
if they occupy a public office, would certainly try to look nonpartisan)
Unlike traditional planners, equity planners enlist the participation of the
Public or client group in determining substantive goals and explicitly
accept planning as a political rather than a strictly scientific endeavor
Traditional planning was part of the old movement for municipal reform:
equity planning is part of the new movement for urban change that calls
for greater representation of disadvantaged groups in the governmental
process and for the decentralization of governmental policy making.
Equity planners are not always democrats, since they will favor redistri-
butional goals even in the absence of a supportive public. Nevertheless,
as noted above, equity and democratic planning overlap, arising as they
do from the same impulse toward social equality. Democratic planners,
however, are ambivalent on the subject of whether each citizen is to be
counted equally and whether popular majorities should rule, Since the
democratic planner’s ethic is a procedural one of allowing all voices to be
heard, he or she runs into serious difficulty if the popular will conflicts
with the interests of deprived groups. Equity planners, even when
holding office, have a particular responsibility to advance the interests of
the poor and racial or ethnic minorities, even when opposed by popular
majorities. Formulation of those interests ideally includes involvement of
the people on whose behalf planning is being done, but ongoing partici-
pation is not a necessary condition, for the aim is equity, not consultation.
Incremental planning
In incremental planning, policy makers come to a decision by weighing
the marginal advantages of a limited number of alternatives. Rather than
working in terms of long-range objectives, they move ahead through
successive approximations
Decision makers typically consider, among all the alternative policies that
they might be imagined to consider, only those relatively few alternatives that
represent small or incremental changes from existing policies. In this sense
decision making is incremental. In short, policy makers and analysts take
45 their starting point not the whole race of hypothetical possibilities, but
only the here and now in which we live, and then move on to consider how
alterations might be made at the margin. (Lindblom 1965: 144)
ani272 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
EE
Planning is not done by a single agency: “That society requires conscious
control and manipulation is one assertion; that an ‘organizing center’ is
required is quite another” (Lindblom 1965: 5), Like Davidoff, Lindblom
recognizes a multitude of interests. But where the advocate planner sees
irremediable conilict, the incrementalist sees an ultimate harmony (see
Lindblom 1965: 4)
In terms of our definition of planning, incrementalism is not really
planning at all. Policy outcomes are not arrived at through formal ratio-
nality, and there is no specifying of ends and means. But Lindblom claims
that the mechanism of “partisan mutual adjustment” ~ the working out
of different claims through compromise, adherence to procedural rules,
and the market process - results in rational decision making: “The
concern of this study has been . .. with partisan mutual adjustment as a
method: for calculated, reasonable, rational intelligent, wise, policy 4
making* (Lindblom 1965: 294). Even though ends and means are not —
formulated, decision makers work out ways to reach socially desirable
goals:
Behind the incremental and disjointed tactics we have just summarized isa
concept of problem solving asa strategy. In this view public problems are too
complex to be well understood, too complex to be mastered. One develops @
strategy t0 cope with problems, not to solve thems, (Lindblom 1965: 148)
Therefore, while incrementalism embodies the opposite of planningin.
its methods, it produces the fruits of planning in its results. Like an
economic system of numerous buyers and sellers, a political system of
atomized decision makers working at cross-purposes can rely on the
invisible hand to produce orderly progress toward social goals ~ in fact,
to produce the very goals themselves 4
Lindblom (1965: 225) attempts to show that seemingly ad hoc methods
of arriving at public policies result in a hidden rationality. The ultimate 4
decision-making power does not lie with a single group, and it is nol
desirable that any one social interest should prevail. Political interaction
causes the clash of interests to be resolved in a Pareto optimum, so that
‘no group can benefit further without some other group losing out
Lindblom assumes that such an optimum, which implies the preserva.
tion of the existing arrangement of social power, is desirable.*
Four Types of Political Theory
Planners have mainly been satisfied to contain within narrow bounds
their debate over who should make planning decisions. To a large extent,
they have attempted to justify their arguments by evaluating the merits
of the policies each type of planning is likely to produce rather thanCity Planning and Political Values 273
ooking at the fundamental questions of social power and legitimacy that
cach type raises. The principal exceptions to this assertion are provided
by Marxist and poststructuralist planning theorists, who are very
concerned with these fundamental questions but who, for the most part.
have not provided prescriptive theories of planning within capitalist soci.
eties (see Fainstein and Fainstein 1979),* As Peter Hall (1988: 239) says
of the Marxists: “[Their] logic is strangely quietist; it suggests that the
planner retreats from planning altogether into the academic ivory
tower.” Similarly, poststructuralists tend to be critical rather thian proac-
tive, espousing strategies for resistance rather than formulating roles for
planners (see Beauregard, 1991)
Political theorists offer insights into appropriate behavior for planners,
since, like most planning theorists, they endeavor to find models of
decision making that will produce desirable social outcomes. They differ
from other social theorists because they go beyond simply analyzing
social relations to address practical questions of governance. Within the
tangle of political thought in the modern, Western world - that is, in the
Period since Locke ~ we can identify four major types of political theory
that correspond to our typology of planning theories. Even though this
typology of political theories is not exhaustive, it offers a framework by
which we can judge the strengths and weaknesses of the planning
theories and evaluate the fit between the planning theories and
American political traditions.
Technocratic theory and traditional planning
Technocratic thinking is a product of the industrial era. It represents an
effort to come to grips with the central social problems created by the
Industrial Revolution ~ the miserable condition of the lower classes and
the breakdown in the old structure of authority that previously main-
tained order. Like the conservatives, the technocrats désife to restore the
order of the preindustrial world, but untike the conservatives they accept
modernization, welcoming technology as the cure for the ills of mankind.
‘Their motto is “order and progress.” Their most significant thinkers are
Comte, Saint-Simon, and, to a lesser extent, Owen and Fourier.”
~The technocrats stand in opposition to the socal anarchy they see
created by capitalism, In their eyes, capitalism dissolved the bonds of the
ancien régime, replacing community with the marketplace, and the pater-
nalism of the old elite with the laissez-faire of the new. But rather than
intending a return to the days before industrialization — an impossibility
~ they wish to harness the power of technology to create a new society
and thereby to ameliorate the condition of the lower classes, as well as
the threat they pose to social order. The technocrats desire to unleash the
power of reason and science, to transpose the old, theological religion.
into a modern, positivist one. Through rational planning, the power of274 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
————— ae ee
the state will be employed to regulate the economy and advance the
lower classes, as well as to ensure the position of the productive ones, All
of this will be possible only when the scientific and industrial classes
control the state and do away with politics in the name of science and.
reason.
In the words of Comte (n.d. 781)
Since the abolition of personal servitude, the lowest class has never been
really incorporated with the social system; the power of capital. .. has
become exorbitant in daily transactions, however just sits influence through
its generality and superior responsibilty... This philosophy will show that
industrial relations, instead of being left toa dangerous empiriciom and an
oppressive antagonism [between the classes}, must be systematized according
{0 moral laws. The duty [ofthe upper classes} 10 the lower classes, will not
«consist in almsgiving, The obligation will be to procure forall suitable eduea-
tion and employment ~ the only condition that the lower classes can justly
demand.
The Saint-Simonians, who echo Comie’s faith in science arid concen
for the condition of the lower classes, also stress the positive. quality of
power as a tool in remolding society.
‘The most direct method of improving the moral and physical welfare of the
‘majority ofthe population ito give priority in State expenditures to ensuring
work for ail fit men, to secure their physical existence. We must add to this
the measures necessary to ensure that the national wealth is administered
by men most fitted for it, and most concerned in its administration, that isto
Say, the most important industrialists. (Saint-Simon 1964 edn: 77)
The technocrats visualize a hierarchical society in which the lower
orders are secure and happy, but strictly subordinate to the managerial:
scientific elite. In this respect, as in others, technocratic theory, while
more detailed and explicit than discussions of traditional planning
Presents a picture of society that is quite compatible with traditional
planning ideas and useful in baring their hidden foundation. Underlying
traditional planning is the technocratic faith in progress through science
and rationality tied to the constructive use of power in the form of the
plan. The technocrats make explicit the planner’s belief that there is
indeed some unitary public interest that experts of goodwill can identify
and maximise. Like traditional planners, they seek to replace politics with
sciemtific administration,
According to the technocrats, social change must be engineered from
the top, by social strata that command the economy, and in the public
interest, indeed in the interest of the lower classes; for they see a
harmony of interests between themselves and the masses. Here again,City Planning and Political Values 275
ee eee
technocratic theory makes explicit an assumption of traditional planning:
that social change for the benefit ofall society must be initiated patemal-
istically by the upper classes, Because all classes benefit from increasing
productivity and public order, the interests of the upper classes become
identical with the public interest. If the natural rulers fail to play their
roles, sometimes even resist change, itis only because they remain as yet
insufficiently enlightened .
Traditional planners, much more limited in their expectations than the
technocrats, did manage to see some of their programs carried out. Parks
were built, building codes passed and sometimes enforced, transit lines
planned and constructed, slums razed; land-use zoning became a
commonplace. Social change was initiated from the top in the name of
the public good, sometimes in the interest of the lower classes, and
with the ultimate necessity of legislative sanction. —
~ Nevertheless, traditional planning suffered from the basic weaknesses
of technocratic thought within the United States. It was always limited
in its scope by the unwillingness of the upper strata to support reform
(see Foglesong 1986)._In fact, traditional planners have long been
perplexed by the all-too-common refusal of the holders of political and
_sconomic power 10 recognize the importan¢e of rational planning as a
neans for the improvement of lie (see Fainstein and Fainstein 1985)
Equally significant, in a culture permeated by a majoritarian populist
Ideology, technocratic elitism provoked widespread suspicion of its prog.
enitors and its aims. From the time of the defeat of Alexander Hamilton's
national bank to the present, Americans have rejected dominance by
small groups claiming special expertise. Thus, the role of traditional
planning was limited by well-founded distrust of decision makers insu-
‘ated from accountability, generalized hostility to abstract ideas, and the
tefusal of most of the upper class to engage in long-range planning,
Democratic theory and democratic planning
Democratic planning stands squarely within the mainstream of democ-
Ric thought, The following argument relies mainly on the work of
{Alexis de Tocquevillg as exemplifying democratic political thought; other
| democratic theorists diverge considerably in their arguments concerning
appropriate democratic forms, the protection of minority and individual
rights, the role of intermediate groups, and the scope of governmental
action.
Democratic theory begins with the sanctity of the individual and the
icy_of his or-her interests. Not only does all sovereignty emanate
from the people, they are also the only source of public values:
‘Everyone is the best and sole judge of his own private interests” (see
Tocqueville 1957 edn: 67). Everyone is equal and has an equal right to
advance his or her cause. There is no interest in society that cannot be276 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
related to that of its members. Thus, the democrats start with equal indi-
viduals and their desires - rather than the social origin or intrinsic merit
of these desires - and goes on to equate the public interest with the
interests of the public, or at least with those of the majority.
Having accepted individual sovereignty as a basic axiom, the democ:
rats then go on to deal with the problem of government, of how public
power is to be distributed, Some form of differentiation between the
government and the citizenry becomes immediately necessary ~ unless,
of course, the size of the polity is severely limited.* Even though some i
form of representation is necessary, democratic thinkers seek to maintain_
as much political power in the hands of the citizenry as is feasible. The |
rule of the majority becomes the instrument by which citizens control the
government. For “the very essence of democratic government consists in j
the absolute sovereignty of the majority” (Tocqueville 1957 edn: 264)
‘The governors must be forced to remain the delegates of the governed.
Unless they do—and they will only if power remains within the hands of
the citizenry ~ government cannot be expected to advance the interests
of the majority. Government by representatives freed from the control of
the majority, by an independent aristocracy of wealth (or even merit), is
likely to act in its own interests, which are necessarily at odds with those
of the sovereign people
Democratic laws generally tend to promote the welfare ofthe greatest possible
number; for they emanate from the majority ofthe citizens, who are subject
to error, but [who] cannot have an interest opposed to their own advantage.
The laws of an aristocracy tend, on the contrary, to concentrate wealth and
power in the hands of the minority; because an aristocracy, by its very
nature, constiutes a minority (Tocqueville 1957 edn: 247).
Under aristocratic governments public men are swayed by the interest of
their order, which, if it is sometimes confused with the interests of the
‘majority, is very frequently distinct from them (Tocqueville 1957 edn: 249)
Democratic planning requires the planner to act as delegate of the citi-
zenry. But this is not to say that the democratic planner must be a passive
figure blindly following instructions. Rather, the democratic planner, like
the democratic governor, both responds to constituents and attempts to
educate them, to show them alternatives and the relation between partic-
ular policies and their interests, Indeed, the reason that citizens must
participate in government and retain power in their hands is not only to
prevent governmental outcomes contrary to their interests but also so
that they themselves may grow, learn from participation, and become {
even more knowledgeable and betier able to govern themselves.
There are three major criticisms of democratic theory, which apply
equally to democratic planning, First, democratic policy makers are i }City Planning and Political Values 277
immediately confronted with the short-term relative ignorance and self-
‘shness of the citizenry, and the fact that “education through
participation” is a slow process for which public policy cannot wait. In
real life, participating citizens may not readily accept the planner’s under-
standing of how means are related to goals, or of how particular policies
may be derived from their interests. In addition, people are frequently
unwilling to make long-run decisions, that is, to plan, when doing so
necessitates the deferment of immediate gratification. Asa result, democ.
Jacies are less likely to plan than technocracies. Most worrisome is the
problém Rousseau confronted when he established a dichotomy beween
the general will and the will ofall: Instead of acting as citizens seeking to
determine the well-being of the community in which they participate
(hati, acting in accordance with the general will), people will typically
act in their narrow self-interest (that is, in conformity with the will of
all)” The perennial planning problems captured by the term “NIMBYism”
(not in my backyard”) point to the difficulty of getting democratic agree-
ment on necessary but costly policies
Second, it is difficult for democratic theory to explain why citizens
should bother to participate in public policy making or planning at all, for
a rational calculus of the costs and benefits of participation often makes
apathy quite compatible with the private interests of individuals (see
Olsen: 1968, and his followers in the resource mobilization school of
theory"). Given the minimal impact of the individual, the cost of one
person's time and effort outweigh any real benefits that could accrue to
him or her personally. So most citizens are apathetic most of the time,
and the democratic planner has only a small minority with whom to plan
Democratic planning in these circumstances cither becomes impossible
or requires planners to take upon themselves the task of divining the will
‘of the majority, in which case the planning process can hardly be called
democratic."
The final criticism of democratic theory suggests that the rule of the
majority leads to social mediocrity and even to fascist authoritarianism,
Tocqueville regarded democracy as a threat to elevated taste; in a classic
statement of the problem (1957 edn: 262) he stated:
Do you wish to give a certain elevation to the human mind and teach it to.
regard the things ofthis world with genuine feelings, to inspire men with a
corm of mere te tages? Is it your object to refine the habits,
embellish the manners, and cultivate the arts, promote the love of poetry,
beauty and glory? If you believe such to be the principal object of society,
avoid the government of the democracy, for it would not lead you with
certainty 0 the goal,
Although Tocqueville's formulation now sounds dated and :insuffer-
ably elitist, contemporary critics of mass culture mount a similar attack,278 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
eee alee
although their claim, somewhat confusingly, is that the vulgarized forms
of urbanity embodied in Disneyland and “theme-parked” urban spaces
are inherently antidemocratic. Thus, when Michael Sorkin, an architee-
tural critic, argues against synthetic spaces in the name of democracy, he
is echoing Tocqueville's aristocratic claim concerning “genuine” feeling:
The theme park presents its happy regulated vision of pleasure — all those
artfully hoodwinking forms —as a substitute for the democratic public realm,
«and it does so appealingly by stripping troubled urbanity ofits sting, of the
presence of the poor, of crime, of dirt, or work. (Sorkin 1992:.xv)
‘The argument here is essentially that people are fooled into accepting the
rsatz.as real. Rather than blaming democracy for the failures of mass
taste to recognize the genuine, Sorkin castigates those who pander to it.
But the subtext of his argument parallels Tocqueville's: The people are
easily misled into accepting the tawdry over the genuine.
Even more serious, however, is the concern that mass participation is
conducive to the triumph of demagoguery as unscrupulous leaders play
on the fears and aspirations of the public (see Ortega y Gasset 1932). The
danger ‘of mass mobilization behind authoritarian nationalist move-
ments has been glaringly evident in the twentieth century. Even at the
evel of city and community we see, in widespread resistance to school
integration or housing for the homeless, the pitting of incensed
majorities against weak minorities. Within liberal-democratic systems
the protection of minority rights and civil liberties is intended to guard
against immoderate majorities. Clearly, however, the threat of democ-
racy out of control is inherent to this method of governance rather than
aberrational
Socialist theory and equity planning
Since the first formulations of socialist theory in the nineteenth century,
socialists have divided according to whether or not they believed in
peaceful reform as a means of achieving significant social change. The
aspects of the theory of socialism that we will develop here are con-
cerned entirely with obtaining power and benefits for the poor within
an existing democratic capitalist society, as opposed either to socialist
revolution or the operation of a purely socialist government. We are
thus developing a reformist rather than a Marxist mode! of socialism,
since Marxist socialism precludes the possibility of achieving equity
ler capitalism.
Socialism begins with a conflict analysis of society. It highlights the
divergence of interests among different social strata and emphasizes
the extent to which the upper strata maintain control of a dispropor-
tionate share of social resources through their use of power. SocialismCity Planning and Political Values 279
sees the interests of individuals as determined by the objective, material
circumstances of their lives ~ that is, by their class situation, Since the
advantages gained by the capital-owning class are at the expense of the
working class, the conflict of interests is real and unavoidable. This
situation will continue so long as the capitalist class controls the condi-
tions under which the remainder of society labors.
From the argument that interests are class-based, it follows that what
is generally called “the public interest” must not be such at all. Rather,
itismerely a reflection of the values and programs of the politically and
economically dominant groups. Only these groups are in a position to
define what is particularly beneficial to them as being also genetally
beneficial to the whole society. This view was stated most strongly by
Marx and Engels (1947 edn: 39): “The ideas of the ruling class are in
every epoch the ruling ideas: i.c., the class which is the ruling material
force of society, is at the same time its ruling intellectual force.” Even in
varieties with a more flexible diagnosis of thé range of possibility within
capitalist society, socialist thought assumes the prevalence of a dominant
ideology favoring capital
The socialist emphasis on material, rather than simply legal or politi-
cal, equality also characterizes the argument for equity planning. For
equity planners, as for socialists, the general good of society is embodied
in the welfare of its most numerous class: and the fundamental value by
‘which to judge a society is equality. Both groups throw in their lot with
those at the bottom of the social order and realize that doing so places
them in conflict with the particular interests of the upper strata. Equity
planning likewise shares the socialist drive to demystify state policies that
benefit capital while claiming to be in the public interest. Thu:
downtown renewal, which is supposed to promote economic develop-
ment and jobs for the working class, s revealed as providing subsidies to
developers and corporations while displacing low-income people and
failing to improve their employment situation,
Despite their class analysis of society, however, equity planners believe
in the potential of democratic government. Thus, although recognizing
conflict as unavoidable, Krumholz also expresses his faith “that equity in
the social, economic, and political relationships among people is a requi
site condition for a just and lasting society” (Krumholz and Forester 1990:
51). He considers that his logic will lead authoritative decision makers to
support “people less favored by present conditions” (Krumholz and
Forester 1990: 49), even though they lack power and may even be fewer
in number than their opponents. The final outcome will be based on
“ultimate consensus” (Krumholz and Forester 1990: 50),
Equity planning assumes an ultimately benevolent state. Although
the advocacy strand within it posits endemic social conflict, even
Davidoff, in his seminal article on advocacy planning, takes it for granted
that a neutral judge ~ presumably a public official ~ will rule in favor of280 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
CaO___
disadvantaged groups who have adequate spokespersons for their cause.
Hence, while Davidoff begins with a conflict perspective and does not
explicitly deal with the role of the state, he, like Krumholz, accepts an
autonomous role for public policy and a state sector that does not sim-
ply act in the narrow interests of officials dependent on capitalist
largesse,
Equity planning combines the socialist’s belief in equality with the
democrat’s faith in government by the people. Consequently, its philo-
sophical home is within democratic socialism, which extends the concept
of democracy to include social as well as political rights. As the British
political philosopher, T. H. Marshall (1965: 103) stated, “Social rights
imply an absolute right to a certain standard of civilization which iscondi-
tional only on the discharge of the general duties of (democratic)
citizenship.” Within this framework the democratic state, rather than
being overwhelmed by the power of property holders, can force powerful
social interests to give up their privileges to promote the good of others. |
In contrast, for Marx and Engels and their followers, real social
change never takes place from the top. It does not result from the per-
suasive power of reasonable argument directed toward those who
control our government and economy, for the upper classes are willing
to redistribute their power or wealth only when under duress from
those beneath them. Social change, in fact, can be initiated only by a
social force arising from the collective action of an exploited class: it can-
not be produced by public officials acting in accordance with a
philosophical position.
Marxist socialism, however, while internally logical, offers litle
guidance for planners. Within its constraints even reformist planners
have no choice but to uphold the status quo (Harvey 1985: chapter 7).
Planners searching for a role that allows them to assist those with fewest
choices may share much of the Marxist critique of contemporary sodety,
but they almost necessarily must abandon the Marxist remedy of total
social restructuring if they are going to take action short of revolution.
(On the other hand, the democratic socialist stance, while offering a
direction for altruistic policy makers, does not provide a strong defense
against critics on either the left or the right. On the left, adversaries can
demonstrate that the space for state-sponsored reformism is quite
narrow. Because capital is free to flee those places that seriously limit
capitalist autonomy ~ in other words, those that have a “poor business
climate” ~ it holds the upper hand in restricting attempts at redistribu-
tion. On the right, critics contend that well-meaning radicals oppose
policies that benefit hardworking, middle-class taxpayers to favor unpro-
ductive social parasites. In response to both these attacks, democratic
socialists are left arguing a moral position that, unlike Marxism, neither
makes claims to historical inevitability nor, as does belief in the invisible
hand of the marker, purports to produce efficiency or reward individualCity Planning and Political Values
not E ted to'equity planning “because it is right.” Ultimately, the argument
an E {ordemocratic socialism depends on this justification as well.
ea :
list
he 4 ficemental decision making is the form of planning logically implied by
eral political theory. Lindblom’s model is nothing more than the partic-
pt | “llar application of the general premises of liberal thought, as formulated
ee 'Y-Locke in the seventeenth century and developed by Bentham,
Spencer, and a number of other thinkers in the nineteenth century.
alism begins with an atomistic conception of human society, seeing
9 ‘human beings as rational actors who are the best judges of their own
'n private interests, The public interest is accepted as real but is regarded as
a “esting fron ‘of private interests within
bg confines of the political marketplace.
a Es
/The obligation of liberal government is first and foremost to guaran-
' ‘upon procedures; as Locke put it,
> “Aolact as an impartial judge or umpire. Liberalism-in-pure form gives
$ @BBSe government no other function than this role of umpiréJand thus no
} F mandate to address social inequality. There is, hoWever, nother strand
i
“during the carly part of the twentieth century. It does give 10
government the additional function of trying to advance its own con-
= ception of the public interest. In this activist version of the liberal state,
government aids private interests that are ill-treated in the marketplace
Gosilive liberalisin, weds the technocratic conception of constructive
‘governmental action to the mainstream of liberal thought; in its most
radical identity, positive liberalism begins to merge with democratic
(socialism.
Nevertheless, liberalism in all its forms emphasizes the prime impor-
tance of a diffusion of power within society. Freedom is the most
fmportant social value, and efficiency is the outcome of its exercise.
Neither the technocrat’s elite, the democrat’s majority, nor the socialist’s
deprived class should have absolute power. No group or institution
should have so much power that it can corner the political market. The
most proactive liberal conception of government still sees it as being only
= primus inter pares. The largest role played by the governmental decision
‘maker is to add another input to the market of alternative policies — a
‘government may create plans and attempt to implement them, but it can
‘never be assured of their being carried out.
‘Thus, the general direction in which society is to move, or the way in
which political benefits are to be distributed, is not decided explicitly at
all. Rather, itis the result of a large number of decisions, some of which
_ may be made by government. Overall social policy is not made282 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein
ree
deliberately but results from a mechanism that acts like an invisible hand,
producing outcomes that are ultimately rational.
Incrementalism, like classic liberalism, is based on a procedural value
of maximizing individual freedom. Consequently, it benefits primarily
those social groups already most privileged under present conditions.
‘These are the strata that command the greatest share of power resources
(sce Dahl 1961: esp. 94 for use of the term), enabling them to take a dis-
proportionate amount of social rewards. The most acceptable form of
governmental activity for these groups is that which ensures their
present position - hence, the accepiability of zoning ordinances and the
like, Because they have favored government as an arbiter rather than
positive actor, they have rallied behind the values of efficiency and
economy in municipal government rather than bebind those of welfare
and innovation.
Incrementalism thus shares the weaknesses of liberalism. In a society
where not just wealth but also power is unequal, those who are worst off
materially also have the least ability to change the system. Moreover, the
very pluralism of interests makes any transformative change extraordi-
narily difficult, even if the great majority would benelit from it. Thus, for
example, efforts at environmental preservation and conservation of
energy resources founder as a result of a process of incremental decision
making that strictly limits the scope of change.
Significance of the Typology
ur discussion of the relationship between planning types and political
theories shows the concepts of planning to be not just analogous to
certain strains in moder political thought but actually fragments of these
Political formulations. The fuller articulation of the planning types in.
terms of value assumptions and justifications of social power permits us
to understand why America has largely rejected the programs of city.
planners ~apart from certain exceptions, in the area of parks, zoning, and
urban renewal.
For a variety of historical and cultural reasons, the United States has
been dominated by the liberal tradition.” This tradition values
individualism, accepts the primacy of private interests, and prefers
minimal government. Thus, the very notion of planning, which assumes
an overriding and ascertainable public interest that can be realized
through the positive actions of government, is antithetical to general
American political values. As Lindblom correctly argues, most decision
‘making in this country follows his description of partisan mutual adjust-
ment. Policy is determined incrementally; it is arrived at through the
clash and compromise of opposing views within the political market-
place. But this incrementalism itself marks the absence of planning.City Planning and Political Values 283
| Incrementalism and partisan mutual adjustment maximize liberal values:
“They restrict the role of government to that of umpire in the political
“marketplace, thus guaranteeing the enforcement of procedural rules but
‘temaining oblivious to outcomes, to which groups win and which lose in
the process of politics. At a maximum, government becomes another
actor in the political process, offering its own solutions to social problems,
‘with the proviso that its solutions must compete with those offered by
private decision makers.
The American political tradition is, of course, democratic as well as
liberal. Why, then, has there been an absence of democratic planning in
“the United States? For, to the extent that we have had planning, it has
it involved widespread participation. In the United States “positive”
government has been associated with the centralization of power.
© Reasons are both inherent in any effort at democratic planning and also
© specific to the U.S. system of fragmented democracy.
Unlike democratic planning, traditional planning has been inhibited
neither by a lack of institutional mechanisms nor by the absence of
supportive social conditions. Like Europe, the United States has a
‘powerful scientific-industrial class. But this group in America has largely
ejected technocratic thought in favor of liberalism. Thus, planning has
“been much more powerful in Europe, where the capitalist elite has
“consciously visualized itself as an aristocracy of talent, attempting to
supplant the old aristocracy of birth. The technocratic idea has been
“embodied in the Furopean planned city, the mixed public-private cor
poration, the whole dirigiste tendency of the modern western European
economies.
‘American business leaders have tended to see themselves as individual
entrepreneurs rather than as members of an aristocratic class. They have
supported laissez-faire instead of dirigisme. It is extremely significant that
the great successes of traditional planning in the United States have
‘Occurred in those cases where business interests have participated in
“public-private partnerships’ to improve the central city. In these
instances planning was carried on in the name of the general good, but
lis direct beneficiaries were downtown business interests and upper-
middle-class residents (Squires 1989). It was assumed that everyone
‘would benefit from the economic expansion that supposedly would
result from the construction of new office buildings and retail centers,
even though most of the people who received specific advantages in
terms of governmental subsidies were already well off.
‘The relative absence of equity planning, like the limited extent of
traditional planning, can be attributed largely to American political
Values. There are two prerequisites for socialist planning: The first is the
political organization of those seeking redistribution; the second is the
existence of a political spectrum broad enough to permit the presentation
fa radical ideology by advocates for the poor. Except perhaps for a brief284 Susan S. Fainstein and Norman Fainstein i
eee
| period during the 1930s, these conditions did not exist in the United
States at all until the 1960s. Low-income people accepted the individu-
alist bias of the general political culture, The middle-class sympathizers
who constituted the intellectual leadership of European socialist move-
ments were unable to escape from the dominant American liberal
ideology. Thus, they stumbled into technocratic reformism rather than
socialist radicalism. It was only the rise of black militancy, based on the
premise that the interests of lower-class blacks are fundamentally
opposed to those of middle-class white Americans, that led to a new
consciousness on the part of a segment of the lower class. This change in
the consciousness of the lower class, combined with the movement
toward the left among young American intellectuals during the 1960s
and 1970s, laid the foundation for the development of equity planning.
Until the present time, social change in America has largely been
unplanned. While the poor may have benefited from increasing material
prosperity, they have not been the special beneficiaries of change, and
the improvement of their lot - to the extent that it has taken place ~ has
been largely accidental. The planners who intend to ameliorate the
conditions of the deprived must recognize that redistribution of social
goods will not take place without social conflict. As advocates for the
poor, they must admit, at least to themselves, that they are supporting
the particular interests of a particular social group. Realistic planners
must give up the delusions that they can serve the whole public equally
well and that there is an indissoluble social good, which they are partic
ularly well circumstanced to ascertain. They must, in short, reject many
of the technocratic biases underlying the professional rhetoric of
planning and construct a new rationale for themselves.
t
Notes
1 This is a substantially revised version of the article, “City Planning and
Political Values,” originally published in the Urban Affairs Quarterly, 6
(March 1971), pp. 341-62, At the time the original article was published,
planning theory asa distinct realm of analysis barely existed. This situation.
Fs well as the preoccupations of planning theorists, has changed dramati
‘ally in the intervening quarter century. This revision seeks to take into
account this wansformation
2 Sce the articles in the recent forum on advocacy planning in Checkoway
(1994)
3 Krummholz and Forester (1990: 250, 1.6) quote Charles Hoch to this effect
{would argue that you {Krumholz and his staff} were not really advocate
planners, that is identifying with a client and representing their interests in
a partisan manner.
4 Any redistribution of social power would require some other group to suffer
a oss equal to the benelit received by the Up.
5. For Marxist critiques of planning, see Dear and Scott (1981), especially the
{Mea
ae: City Planning and Political Values 285
shanter by 8.7. Roweis: Castells 1977): Harvey (1985: chapter 7). For post.
Stucturaist examinations, see Boyer (1983); Beauregard (1991); Ligget
and Perry (forthcoming)
© fisimportanto recognize that we ae discussing secular systems of thought
that, wrthin the discourse of Weberian sociology, would be defined se
modern. We have seen a resurgence of political conflict in the world that
has been defined by religious principles and inherited identities thot are mot
Part of this “modern” debate. Indeed, our focus may seem a bit of hand
Waving designed to cover up a rather glaring omission, for there is no
‘mension in our typology of tray conservative thought ~ that, for example,
associated with Edmund Burke in England or with Bonald and de Maistre
in France,
We have purposely ignored conservative thought for two reasons. The
frst is that conservative thinking stands antithetical to the whole idea of
tavional policy making, if we took the time to discuss iti would only be to
dismiss it, Second, there is in America a total absence of conservotine
thinking, of the conservative desire to maintain a feudal past. What genuine
conservatism exists is combined with pratse of industealism and thus fg |
under our classification of technocratic thought. What is sometimes called
conservatism in the United States is nothing more than liberalisin at ite
extreme ~ the liberalism of Spencer and the Social Darwinists; as such, we
treat it in our section on liberalism,
7 The reader may note that the last three names are usually associated with
the category “utopian socialism.” The use of this term is, we feel, mislead.
ing and almost entiely a result of the fact that Marx made the label stk
Louls Hartz calls them “feudal socialists,” which is a better choice of words,
since it makes any simplistic association of their names with socialism more
Gilfcalt. By choosing to emphasize Comte and the elements in the though |
of the others most closely related to his theories, we have even further
loosened the connection between technocratic and socialist thought
5 Rousseau imposes precisely such a limitation when he describes his own
democracy
% Rousseau, in the Social Contract, distinguishes between the citizen as a
‘member of the community and unsocialized natural man, who is not evil
bur who does not have the benefits of civilization. Through his theory of
democracy he attempts to make the constraints of civilization legitimate. tn
a democratic society citizens themselves determine the laws that will linie
their freedom rather than having constraints imposed upon them. When
each citizen makes a decision in conformity with the collective good, the
resulting choice embodies the general will When decisions are made only
‘on the basis of narrow self-interest, the consequence is the will of alh
(Rousseau 1950 edn; see Hartz 1990: chapter 5)
10 Olsen develops his argument within the paradigm of neoclassical econom.
ics like all neoclassical economic models, his places the individual prior to
the community and defines rationality as the maximization of individusl
self-interest
11 Altshuler (1965) describes the difficulties encountered by Minneapolis's
Planners when they sought to involve citizens in formulating the goals for
downtown redevelopment. t the stage of general goal setting, few people286 Susan S, Fainstoin and Norman Fainstein
Gould forese the implications of decisions for themselves. But by the ume
the planning process gor down to specicy, the famemonk hed as
sed. tn my own recent work om hinneapols(Elason ea Lan
which bs examined the neihborteod planning proces. veld hg
‘in most neighborhoods, relatively few people parpae anathore eee
ar the low-income, renter population does no tecome nvelees
1D. Forextensveapumenss in support ofthis intepeeation oe hone 55,
Roorstein (1953) and Lipset (i
References
Atle, A.A, 1965, The cy Panning Paces. haca: Cornel Universiy Pes
Beauregard, R.A. 1991. "Widuut ante modern pang oo
owns D315. The enue Ameria alts hago: Universo hago
ong Econ and Retard, 10 (Sumner ony
Castes. 1977. The Urban Quoion, Cambridge MAC hi
Checkoway, Be) 194 "Pal avide
end advocacy planing fa serospe” 4
Comte. Am The Pste Phish of guste Ce rs I. rae
York Pete Ekle,
Dahl. 1961 We Gera New Have: Yale University Pes
David P1965, Advocacy and plus Is planning” Just ofthe rin
Dear Mand A 3. Sot (eds) 1981, Urban Pieming ad Urbanization in Capa
Foinsein. S'S and. 1 fintein, 2985, “is state planning ecessary for
(December) 485-307.
— 19. “New Debates in urban planning: the impac of Mars hear within
"he United States” Ptration aural of Urbano Raionl Renee en
Frinscin. 8S. wih NJ, Glkman, €. Grvoa, and C st 1995 An tater
Elution ofthe Minepots Nghlerhed Reaeaton Proce
Brunswick NU: Center fe Ubon Pley Resear
Fischer, F 1991 “Rsk assessment and enevonmental es toward an eps
ton of scence and partpation.” fal re Quasar hee
1990, Tehnaracy and th Palit of Eger Newby Ear, CA. age
Fopesong RE 198, ling the Capt iy Prneion Pincson Covey
Fried, 1967. “Grleving for alt hom," Pp. 359-879 i J. @. Wine,
‘rbonRenewel Cambridge, MA: MIT res,
Friedmann, J. 1987. Pleo ithe Puss Donn. Fuinceton: Peineenn
wc. erkcly. CA: Univers of Calon