Donnellan Speaking of Nothing
Donnellan Speaking of Nothing
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
http://www.jstor.org
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
3
KEI TH S. D ONNELLAN
4
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
5
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
8 See Middleton and Adair, "The Mystery of the Horn Papers," William
and Mary Quarterly, 3rd series, IV (I947); reprinted in Winks (ed.), The
Historian as Detective (New York, i968).
9 The denial of Snow White's existence, it should be noted, is in discourse
about actuality, while the statement that she enraptured a prince is in discourse
about fiction. (If the question of existence arose in discourse about fiction alone,
Snow White existed, whereas Hamlet's father's ghost, again presuming we are
talking about fiction, probably did not.) This does not disturb the point:
no such contrast can be made out for Jacob Horn; if Jacob Horn did not
exist then there are no true predicative statements to be made about him.
6
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
7
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
8
BOOK REVIEWS
270
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
always have descriptive content. The question is, does this mean
that perhaps ordinary singular expressions may fulfill the function
that Russell thought only "genuine" names, with all their pecu-
liarities, could? And, if so, how can the historical explanation
view deal with the puzzles about reference?
What was the motivation for introducing "genuine" names?
Russell often talks in ways that can seem nonsensical-that, for
example, when a definite description such as "the author of
Waverly" is involved, the denotation of the definite description,
Scott in this case, is not a "constituent" of the proposition ex-
pressed. The implied contrast is that if "Scott" is a genuine name
and were there in place of the definite description "the author of
Waverly" then Scott would be a constituent. But it certainly
sounds queer at first glance to find a flesh-and-blood person in a
proposition!
Russell's analysis of statements containing definite descriptions
and, by extension, ordinary proper names, shows, he believed, that
such statements are not really about, do not really mention, the
denotation of the description or the referent of the name. Russell
emphasizes this again and again. "Genuine" names, on the other
hand, can somehow perform the feat of really mentioning a
particular individual. To try to put much weight on such terms as
"about" would lead us, I think, into a morass. What it is for a
statement to be about an individual, if that requires any attempt
to define aboutness,is a question better avoided if we are ever to get
on with the problem. (After all, Russell himself recognized a
well-defined relationship that a statement containing a definite
description can have to some particular individual-its denotation.
It would be a delicate task to show either that in no sense of
"about" is such a statement about the denotation of the definite
description or that there is some clear sense of "about" in which
it is not.)
But I believe we can say something useful about the reasons
Russell had for talking in this way. On his theory of definite
descriptions the singular expression, the definite description, is
really a device that introduces quantifiers and converts what
might seem at first sight a simple proposition about an individual
into a general proposition. "The 0 is f" expresses the same propo-
IO
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
sition as "There is a S and there is at most one b and all O's are
if's"; and the latter clearly would express a general proposition
about the world. Ordinary proper names, of course, function on
his view in the same way, since they are in reality concealed
definite descriptions. Now if we contrast these singular expressions
with ones, if there are any, that do not introduce quantifiers, that
when put as the subject of a simple subject-predicate sentence do
not make the sentence express a general proposition, then I think
there is a strong temptation to say that only the second kind of
singular term can be used to really mention an individual.
Russell clearly believed that there must be the possibility, at
least, of singular terms that do not introduce quantifiers; that
seems in large part to be his reason for believing in "genuine"
names. Whether or not there is some argument that shows the
necessity of such singular terms, I believe that prior to theory the
natural view is that they occur often in ordinary speech. So if one
says, for example, "Socrates is snub-nosed," the natural view
seems to me to be that the singular expression "Socrates" is simply
a device used by the speaker to pick out what he wants to talk
about while the rest of the sentence expresses what property he
wishes to attribute to that individual. This can be made somewhat
more precise by saying, first, that the natural view is that in using
such simple sentences containing singular terms we are not saying
something general about the world-that is, not saying something
that would be correctly analyzed with the aid of quantifiers; and,
second, that in such cases the speaker could, in all probability,
have said the same thing, expressed the same proposition, with the
aid of other and different singular expressions, so long as they are
being used to refer to the same individual. To illustrate the latter
point with a different example: if, at the same moment in time,
one person were to say, "Smith is happy," a second "You are
happy," a third "My son is happy," and a fourth "I am happy,"
and if in each case the singular expression refers to the same
person, then all four have expressed the same proposition, have
agreed with each other.
What I see as the natural pre-theoretical view might be cap-
tured as a certain way of representing what proposition is ex-
pressed. For example, the sentence "Socrates is snub-nosed" might
II
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
12
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
I now want to begin to lay out the bare bones of the theory of
reference I want to discuss. As I have said, I will not here argue
for its correctness nor will I try to fill in all the gaps.
Russell and the majority of philosophers in contemporary times
who have discussed (ordinary) proper names have held that by
one mechanism or another they are surrogates for descriptions. For
Russell, as I have mentioned, they are simply abbreviations for
definite descriptions; for others-for example, Searle"1-they are
correlated with a set of descriptions and what one is saying in, say,
a simple subject-predicate sentence employing a proper name is
that whatever best fits these descriptions has whatever property is
designated by the predicate. The descriptions, both on Russell's
13
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
view and on the looser view of Searle and others, which the proper
name masks, are thought of as obtained from the people who use
them-roughly speaking, by what they would answer to the
question, "To whom (what) are you referring?" This view of
ordinary proper names embodies what I have called the "principle
of identifying descriptions."12 The theory of reference I am con-
cerned with holds that the principle of identifying descriptions is
false.
What this means, to give an example, is that, supposing you
could obtain from me a set of descriptions of who it is that I
believe myself to refer to when I say, "Socrates was snub-nosed"-
perhaps such things as "the mentor of Plato," "the inventor of the
'Socratic method,' " "the philosopher who drank the hemlock,"
and so forth-it is theoretically possible that I am referring to
something about which no substantial number of these descrip-
tions is true or that although there is something that fits these
descriptions to whatever extent is required by the particular
variation of the principle, that is not in fact the referent of the
name I used.
On this theory, then, ordinary proper names are like Russell's
"genuine" names at least in so far as they do not conceal descrip-
tions in the way he thought. This is, I think, a virtue of the theory.
As David Kaplan has remarked, there was always something
implausible about the idea that a referent of a proper name is
determined by the currently associated descriptions.
14
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
'5
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
i6
SPEAKING OF NO THING
'7
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
I8
SPEAKING OF NO THING
13
That is to say, the first use of a name to refer to some particular individual
might be in an assertion about him, rather than any ceremony of giving the
individual that name. (In fact, my own name is an example: I discovered that
colleagues were pronouncing my last name differently than my parents do-so,
orally, they referred to me by a different name-and I let it stand. But I was
never dubbed by that new name. I am sure that the first use of it was either
an assertion, question, or whatever about me and not a kind of baptism.
And I think it is probable that whatever audience there was knew to whom
the speaker referred.)
I9
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
14
See my "Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions," op. cit.
20
SPEAKING OF NO THING
15
Given that this is a statement about reality and that proper names have
no descriptivecontent, then how are we to represent the proposition
expressed?
2I
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
22
SPEAKING OF NO THING
23
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
24
SPEAKING OF NO THING
Claus. The fact that the story of Santa Claus, told to children as
fact, is historically an invention constitutes a block even if the
story happens to contain only descriptions that accurately fit
some person.
25
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
26
SPEAKING OF NO THING
27
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
28
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
29
KEITH S. DONNELLAN
If this discussion has been on the right track, then at least the
outline of a solution to some problems concerning nonexistence
statements is available to the historical explanation theory. One
point emerged in the course of the last sections. We can perhaps
point to criteria for saying when two existence statements invol-
ving names express the same proposition, but these criteria take a
different form from those for predicative statements involving
names. In particular, it cannot be a matter of sameness of referent.
For predicative statements we were able to suggest a way of
representing propositions, as ordered n-tuplets, but no obvious
way of representing propositions expressed by existence statements
suggests itself. This does not seem to me to count against the
theory, since the notion of a proposition is not, I think, a clear one
that has established use outside of a theory. The fact that the
representation suggested for predicative statements involving
proper names has no counterpart for existence statements,
however, may account in part for the fact that Russell took the
alternatives for proper names to be either a Meinongian view or
30
SPEAKING OF NOTHING
3I