Man in The Age of Technology
Man in The Age of Technology
Abstract: This paper argues that technology is no longer merely a tool for man’s use
but has become the environment in which man undergoes modifications. The author
traces the role of technology from the Greeks to the present day. For the Greeks, Nature
was governed by necessity and therefore unchangeable whereas in the Judeo-Christian
tradition, nature was entrusted to man for him to dominate. Modern science studies
the world in order to manipulate and dominate nature through the use of technology
which has now become an end in itself, governing the solution of political problems and
confronting us with problems beyond our competence to resolve. The ethical impact of
technology has been to create a change from ‘acting’ which assumes responsibility for
one’s actions to ‘doing’ which is concerned only with the effective execution of a ‘job’
without concern for the wider consequences. It can no longer be argued that technology
is good or bad according to the use we make of it since technology now makes use of us
and thus transforms our ethics, social relationships and psychological being.
0021-8774/2009/5401/3
C 2009, The Society of Analytical Psychology
Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
4 Umberto Galimberti
object. Even the ‘sexual drive’ itself is so little instinctive that it is possible to
respond to a sexual stimulus in any manner of perverse ways—something that
appears to be impossible for animals. In the same way the sexual drive can be
‘sublimated’, diverted to non-sexual aims such as a work of art, a poem or a
musical composition, etc.
If man is deprived of instincts therefore, his very survival depends on his
capacity to develop his ‘technological’ skills and in this sense we could collocate
the birth of humanity in the moment in which the first anthropoid made use
of a stick to obtain a piece of fruit. If the technological dimension has allowed
man to overcome his lack of instincts, it is only through technology that man
has discovered the possibility of freedom.
Freedom is not a gift from heaven. Man is free because he is not rigidly
codified by instincts. We are only free because we are biologically undetermined
as opposed to animals whose behaviour is pre-determined from the moment of
birth to that of death.
The theory that man is deprived of instincts was first enunciated by Plato
in ‘Protagoras’ where he narrates how Zeus assigns Epimetheus (epi-metis, he
who thinks afterwards, and therefore he who is improvident, the unwary one)
with the task of attributing qualities (instincts) to all living creatures. By the
time he arrives at man Epimetheus has no qualities left as he has been too
liberal to start with. Zeus, moved by the fate of man, asks Epimetheus’ brother,
Prometheus (pro-metis, he who thinks before) to endow man with his own
quality of foresight or prevision.
Hobbes too maintains that while animals eat only when they are hungry, man
is famelicus famis futurae, he is hungry with his future hunger. Man does not
need to be hungry to search for food as he is able to anticipate that even when
he is full, the time will come when he will need food again. This is the essential
virtue of man: the capacity to anticipate.
Man therefore is born a ‘technological’ being from the very start. In a more
articulated way, we could say that the being we call man was born the day that
the anthropoids made their first technological gesture.
2. Even before the birth of philosophy, the Greeks had begun to reflect on the
problem of technology, as we can see from Aeschylus’s tragedy, Prometheus
Bound. It is an error to think of the Greek tragedies as theatrical representations
designed merely to make the audience laugh or cry. The Greeks were probably
the most serious people ever to walk the earth. When problems arose in the city,
they were represented in the theatre, that is to say they were collocated within
a sacred dimension. All Greek words that begin with the root theos (God, from
which the word Zeus is derived) such as theorema (theorem) or theatro (theatre)
contain within themselves a specific reference to the sacred.
In Aeschylus’s tragedy, Prometheus, the friend of men, consigns the gift
of fire to men to enable them to transform metal and create tools. He
gives men the capacity to calculate and to make previsions and thus in a
Man in the age of technology 5
certain sense, the rudiments of technological skill. At this point however, Zeus
intervenes as he has become frightened that men, through their technology,
will become more powerful than the gods themselves. Already in this passage,
the theme of the conflict between religion and science is evident. Through
science and technology man can obtain for himself that which once he
needed to pray to the gods for. Zeus punishes Prometheus by chaining him
to a rock where an eagle continually gnaws at his liver which miraculously
regenerates every evening in order to guarantee the never-ending nature of his
punishment.
We should always take myths seriously as they are never only stories, fables
or the inventions of fantasy. Myths always contain a kernel of science and
of knowledge. In the hypothesis that the liver is capable of regenerating, for
example, we can see the level of competence achieved by the doctors of the
school of Kos, who had already discovered a fundamental characteristic of the
liver for as we now know every three or four weeks the liver cells are completely
renewed. This myth therefore contains exact scientific notions.
To go back to Aeschylus’s story however, at a certain point the Chorus
asks Prometheus which is stronger, nature or technology. To understand the
significance of this question we need a profound knowledge of the nature of
Greek thought and we need to free ourselves of that Christian conception
of nature which permeates our own thinking whether we are believers or
not.
For Judaeo-Christian culture, nature is the product of the will of God which
created it and like all products of a will, nature has determined characteristics
but it could just as easily have others. Furthermore, this nature produced by
the will of God was given over to men so that they can exert power over it and
obtain sustenance from it. In Genesis, God gives to Adam dominion over all the
animals of the earth, the fish of the sea and the birds of the sky. Nature is thus
conceived of as the product of the will of God and consigned to the dominion
of man.
For the Greeks all this was literally unthinkable, since, for the Greeks, nature
was an unchangeable whole, governed by that most powerful of categories:
necessity (ananke). The laws of nature could never be modified. ‘This cosmos
which no God and no man created’, says Heraclitus, ‘always was, always is and
always will be unchangeable’ (fr.30). Not a product of will therefore that may
be like this but which could equally be like that and still less something over
which man can dominate. As Plato says: ‘Miserable man, do not think that this
cosmos was created for you. Rather you will be just only if you conform to the
universal harmony’ (The Laws, 903 c.).
All those therefore that believe that the Greeks—and Plato in particular—
anticipated Christian culture, either do not understand the Greeks or they do
not understand Christianity. There is an abyss between these two worlds. In the
Greek world men contemplated nature in order to understand its immutable
and constant laws and these laws lay at the heart of the principles through which
6 Umberto Galimberti
they ordered their cities and their souls. Nature was therefore the fundamental
point of reference both for politics and for that good government of the soul,
which today is the task of psychology.
In the Judaeo-Christian world, there was no contradiction between technol-
ogy and nature, for nature had been entrusted to man so that he could dominate
it. In the Greek world on the other hand, this contradiction was present in all its
force for if nature was immutable what would be the consequences if technology
were to succeed in bringing about change? The answer of Prometheus to the
Chorus is lapidary: ‘techne d’anankes asthenestera makro’; technology will
always be less powerful than necessity which binds nature to immutability and
to the regularity of its laws.
Sophocles too, in Antigone narrates that when the plough furrows the earth,
the earth closes back again after its passage, when the ship fends the waves, they
quickly return to a dreamy calm. Nature cannot violate the law of necessity
and technology can never overcome the laws of nature. This response of
Prometheus is correct however only because technology in the Greek age was
still rudimentary.
3. If we now jump 2,000 years and move from the age of Aeschylus to 1600, we
find men still cultivating their fields in exactly the same way as the Greeks had
done and we conclude therefore that very few innovations had taken place in the
field of technology. Despite the advent of Roman architecture and hydraulics,
men still continued to take advantage of natural inclinations and the sources of
energy that nature offered. In medicine too, drugs were not considered to cure
themselves but held merely to assist nature in the process of healing. In a word,
the ancient primacy of nature still held.
In 1600 however something absolutely new emerged: modern science. Men
such as Bacon, Descartes and Galileo no longer believed that it was necessary
to behave like the Greeks and merely contemplate nature in the attempt to
capture its laws. Instead they insisted that it was necessary to proceed in exactly
the opposite way: first by formulating hypotheses on nature, then by testing
these hypotheses through experiments and only then, if the experiments were
successful, were these hypotheses given the status of laws of nature. This way
of proceeding is the basis of so-called modern science.
Two centuries later Kant described this event as a ‘Copernican revolution’.
Previously men believed that the earth was the centre of the universe, but
Copernicus inverted the relationship between the earth and the sun and it was
now the sun which was the centre around which the earth revolved. Kant also
cited two Italians: Galileo and Torricelli. These scientists, said the philosopher
of Königsberg, behaved towards nature not as scholars content to follow the
footsteps of their teacher but as judges forcing the accused to answer their
questions. Nature had now become an accused who responded to the questions
posed by men. Only if the hypotheses formulated by men were confirmed, were
they adopted as ‘laws of nature’.
Man in the age of technology 7
were unable to do and the collapse of the Soviet Union seemed impossible. By the
1980s however, the level of American technology had become vastly superior
to that of the Soviet Union and it had become clear that they were losing the
arms race. At that point, the collapse of the Soviet Union was inevitable. As
Emanuele Severino notes in The Decline of Capitalism, if the end, communism,
could only be achieved through the means of technology, once its technology
failed, there was nothing left to shore up communism.
In the same way, if technology becomes the universal condition through
which all aims are satisfied, technology is no longer a means but an end
in itself that is desired by all for in its absence it becomes impossible to
achieve what are considered the true aims of society, whether they are universal
communism or global capitalism. All this has enormous consequences on the
anthropological level, but for brevity I will consider only the political and ethical
implications.
5. Politics was substantially invented by Plato and is therefore a somewhat
recent innovation. Before politics, there was only tyranny. Today however, as
Giacomo Marramao puts it in Dopo il Leviatano (After Leviathan), politics
resembles a deposed sovereign, useful for representation, for gathering in and
organizing affects, identities and social ties but irrelevant as far as any decision
making is concerned. This is because politics looks to economics to guide it
in its decisions, while economics in its turn is guided in its investments by the
availability of technological resources.
When it is said that we can only defend ourselves against the Chinese by
improving our technology through research it is as though we are recognizing
the primacy of technology over economics and the primacy of economics over
politics. Politics has become a representation of decision making, not the place
where decisions are made. This is extremely dangerous because, as Plato reminds
us, technology knows how to make things but not whether they should be made
in the first place and why they are made. From this, Plato derives the necessity
of that government of technology (basilike techne), that capacity to assign to
technology the purpose of its procedures, which is the true task of politics. The
problem is that today the position has been reversed and it is technology that
governs politics.
In fact the situation is even more dramatic as technology has subverted the
very structure of power which in the pre-technological age was represented by
a triangle with the decisional moment—the king’s will, the laws, power—at
the top, and at the base obedience or transgression, legitimacy or illegitimacy,
citizens or subjects.
Today technology no longer allows this type of representation of power as
it assigns power only to those who operate from within an apparatus. It only
needs ten air-traffic controllers to bring air traffic to a standstill whereas in
more traditional forms of strikes, around 80–90% of the work force had to lay
down their tools for a strike to be successful.
10 Umberto Galimberti
7. Heidegger was one of the first to comprehend the true nature of the age of
technology, possibly because of his affiliation with the Nazi ideology. After
having seen the consequences of that ‘provincial theatre’ of which Anders
speaks, he writes:
What is really disturbing is not that technology has taken over the world and
transformed it. It is infinitely more disturbing that man is in no way ready for this
radical change in the world. It is infinitely more disturbing that we are still not capable
of arriving, through the mediation of thought, at an adequate confrontation with what
is really emerging in our world.
(Gelassenheit, 1959)
Today we have at our disposition only that kind of thought that Heidegger
calls ‘calculating’ thought (Denken als Rechnen), thought that is able only
to add up sums, to think in terms of what is useful and advantageous, to
operate in that brief space which separates means from ends in order to optimize
the relationship between effort and cost. Beauty too becomes involved in this
mechanism as even a work of art is considered such only when it enters into
the market, when it is given a monetary value. The work of art would seem to
have no value in itself if it is not ‘marketable’ and therefore ‘calculable’. In this
way we no longer identify the ‘beautiful’, the ‘good’, the ‘just’, the ‘virtuous’,
the ‘holy’, the ‘true’.
Man in the age of technology 15
There are still a few free thoughts around but they have become merely a
pastime, something to engage in the weekend and they have no effect on the
real world where everything circles around utility and the optimization of the
relationship between means and ends.
Technology radically changes the way we think as, even if machines have been
invented by man, they now contain an objectification of human intelligence
that is superior to the competence of single individuals. The memory of a
computer is vastly superior to our memories, even if it is a ‘stupid’ memory.
Using computers modifies our thinking, transforming it from ‘problem-solving’
thinking to ‘binary’ thinking which follows the scheme 1/0 and renders us able
only to say yes, no or at best, ‘I do not know’.
It is not by chance that human thinking began to evolve when we were able
to overcome this kind of imposition. Primitive thought was based on binomial
oppositions: light and dark; day and night; earth and sky. At the beginning of
our history there were only two parameters but then we began to think in more
problem-solving and complex ways. Today however this kind of thinking has
once again imploded into the binary logic which we can find in quiz shows and
in multiple-choice examinations.
The objection that technology is good or bad according to the use we make
of it is no longer valid, because what modifies us is not whether it is used well
or badly but the very fact that we use it at all. Using technology transforms us.
Talking to our friends in a chat room signifies changing the modalities of our
relationships because there are enormous differences between talking in a chat
room and talking to someone face to face. If our children watch television for
four hours or more every day, it is inevitable that their way of thinking and
feeling will be modified independently of whether the programmes are good or
bad. It is the length of exposure that counts.
Even our feelings are being significantly altered. Our psyche responds to the
surrounding environment (Um-welt) into which we were born and in which
we cultivate our relationships, but what happens when the media brings us
into contact with the whole world (Welt) and how can we cope with this? If my
brother dies I cry, if my neighbour dies I go to the funeral, if I am told that every
second 8 children in the world die, I am sorry but this becomes merely a statistic
for me: I no longer react when I am presented with events that go beyond my
capacity for emotional perception. The ‘too large’ leaves me indifferent and
in order not to become aware of my impotence to change things, I prefer to
repress the information. Not even emotionally are we up to the level of the
‘technological’ event.
Once again we are forced to realize that technology is not a means at the
disposition of man but the environment in which man undergoes modifications.
Technology represents an absolutely new and perhaps irreversible historical
moment in which the question is no longer ‘what can we do with technology?’
but ‘what will technology do to us?’
16 Umberto Galimberti
TRANSLATIONS OF ABSTRACT
Cet article avance l’idée que la technologie n’est plus un simple outil au service de
l’homme mais qu’elle est devenue un environnement au sein duquel l’homme subit des
modifications. L’auteur retrace le rôle de la technologie de l’Antiquité grecque à nos
jours. En Grèce antique, la nature était gouvernée par la nécessité et donc immuable,
tandis que dans la tradition judéo-chrétienne, la nature était confiée à l’homme pour qu’il
la maı̂trise. La science moderne étudie le monde dans le but de manipuler et de maı̂triser
la nature au moyen de la technologie, devenue une fin en soi, régissant la politique et
ses conflits et nous confrontant à des problèmes bien au-delà de nos compétences à les
résoudre. L’impact éthique de la technologie a été de provoquer une transformation de
l’« agir », qui impliquait la responsabilité de nos actes, en un « faire » qui ne se soucie
que de l’efficacité de l’exécution d’un « job », sans considération des conséquences à
une plus vaste échelle. Il n’est plus possible de soutenir l’idée que la technologie est
bonne ou mauvaise selon l’usage qu’on en fait car la technologie à présent fait usage
de nous, transformant par là-même notre éthique, nos relations sociales et notre être
psychologique.
Dieser Artikel hypostasiert, daß Technologie nicht länger lediglich ein Werkzeug zum
Gebrauch durch den Menschen ist, sondern zum Bedingungsumfeld geworden ist, in
dem der Mensch Veränderungen unterworfen wird. Der Autor verfolgt die Rolle der
Technologie von den Griechen bis zum heutigen Tag. Für die Griechen galt die Natur
als von Notwendigkeit bestimmt und deshalb unveränderbar während in der jüdisch-
christlichen Tradition die Natur als dem Menschen anvertraut angesehen wird, damit
dieser sie beherrsche. Moderne Wissenschaften untersuchen die Welt in der Absicht, die
Natur durch technische Eingriffe zu manipulieren und zu beherrschen, was nun sein
immanentes Ende findet beim Versuch, etwa politische Probleme zu beeinflussen. Wir
sind erkennbar mit Problemen konfrontiert, die außerhalb unserer Lösungsmöglichkeiten
liegen. Die ethischen Auswirkungen der Technologie haben einen Wandel geschaffen von
‘handeln’, was Verantwortlichkeit für die Handlungen beinhaltet, zu ‘tun’, was lediglich
der erfolgreichen Ausführung eines ‘Jobs’ verpflichtet ist ohne Rücksichten auf weitere
Konsequenzen. Es kann nicht länger darüber argumentiert werden, ob Technologie gut
oder schlecht ist im Hinblick auf das, wofür wir sie benutzen, da Technologie inzwischen
uns benutzt und dadurch unsere Ethik, unsere sozialen Beziehungen und unser seelisches
Sein verändert.
In questo lavoro si sostiene che la tecnologia non è più un semplice strumento nelle mani
dell’uomo, ma è divenuto l’ambiente nel quale l’uomo subisce modificazioni. L’autore
traccia il ruolo della tecnologia dai Greci ai giorni attuali. Per i Greci la Natura era
governata dalla necessità e quindi non modificabile, mentre nella tradizione Giudeo-
Cristiana la natura era affidata all’uomo, perché lui la dominasse. Le scienze attuali
studiano il mondo per poter manipolare e dominare la natura attraverso l’uso della
tecnologia che ora è divenuta un fine in se stessa, governando la soluzione dei problemi
politici e ponendoci davanti a problemi troppo al di sopra delle nostre competenze perché
Man in the age of technology 17
En este trabajo se argumenta que la tecnologı́a ya nos es solo la herramienta para uso
del hombre sin que se ha convertido en el Medio Ambiente en el cual los humanos
se desenvuelven. El Autor sigue la ruta del papel de la tecnologı́a desde los Griegos
hasta el presente. Para los Griegos, la Naturaleza estaba gobernada por la necesidad
y pr tanto inmodificable, mientras que la tradición Judeo-Cristiana, la Naturaleza fue
confiada al Hombre par que la dominara. La ciencia moderna estudia al mundo para
poder manipular y ordenar a la Naturaleza a través del uso de la tecnologı́a la cual ahora
se ha convertido en un fin en sı́ misma, gobernando la solución de problemas polı́ticos
y confrontándonos con problemas que superan nuestra competencia para resolverlos.
El impacto ético de la tecnologı́a ha sido el de crear un cambio entre ‘actuar’ que
connota responsabilidad pos nuestras acciones a ‘haciendo’ que solo tiene que ver con la
ejecución efectiva de un ‘trabajo’ sin preocuparnos por sus mas amplias consecuencias.
No podemos seguir discutiendo si la tecnologı́a es buena o es mala de acuerdo con el
uso que le demos ya que ella ahora hace uso de nosotros y por tanto transforma nuestra
ética, relaciones sociales y ser psicológico.