Gramsci - The Prison Years
Gramsci - The Prison Years
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Studies in
Critical Social Sciences
Series Editor
David Fasenfest (soas University of London)
Editorial Board
Eduardo Bonilla-Silva (Duke University)
Chris Chase-Dunn (University of California-Riverside)
William Carroll (University of Victoria)
Raewyn Connell (University of Sydney)
Kimberle W. Crenshaw (University of California, LA, and
Columbia University)
Raju Das (York University)
Heidi Gottfried (Wayne State University)
Karin Gottschall (University of Bremen)
Alfredo Saad-Filho (King’s College London)
Chizuko Ueno (University of Tokyo)
Sylvia Walby (Lancaster University)
volume 164
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
A Companion to
Antonio Gramsci
Essays on History and Theories of History,
Politics and Historiography
Edited by
Davide Cadeddu
leiden | boston
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Cover illustration: Sketch of Antonio Gramsci
Typeface for the Latin, Greek, and Cyrillic scripts: “Brill”. See and download: brill.com/brill-typeface.
ISSN 1573-4234
ISBN 978-90-04-42650-4 (hardback)
ISBN 978-90-04-42651-1 (e-book)
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Contents
Preface VII
Acknowledgements X
Notes on Contributors XI
Part 1
History
Part 2
Theories of History
Part 3
Communism
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
vi Contents
Part 4
Hegemony
Part 5
Historiography
Bibliographic Abbreviations 155
Index 156
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Preface
Over the course of the twentieth century, Antonio Gramsci became an author
so often cited and so extensively studied at the international level that it now
sometimes seems his cultural origins have been overlooked. Thanks to transla-
tions of his writings into English (and many other languages), Gramsci’s
thought has acquired a truly global audience and inspired scholars in different
disciplinary areas by reaching beyond the original utterance in Italian. Almost
daily, new research is being carried out: articles and books are published com-
pletely neglecting the scientific literature produced in the language that he
himself spoke. This can be considered legitimate when Gramsci’s thought is –
more than anything else – an occasion and a stimulus with the aim of saying
something other than what he himself affirmed, but the difficulty of accessing
the primary sources of his political thought can sometimes produce an unin-
tentional misunderstanding and conceptual inaccuracy. Reflecting on the rela-
tionship between scholarly studies in Italian and in other languages may per-
haps lead us to speculate that while the first might be able to guarantee a
greater philological precision and hermeneutic penetration, the second may
demonstrate themselves to be more prone to developing the reformulation of
Gramscian categories in the areas of sociology and anthropology besides those
of historiography and politics.
On the occasion of the 80th anniversary of Gramsci’s premature death,
therefore, it was thought to organize a sort of intellectual account of the situa-
tion, including some of the most important Italian scholars of Gramsci’s
thought, and to arrange their musings around the relation between culture and
politics, history and historiography. The results of this work forms a type of
“companion” that is useful for a deep understanding of this author within an
international dialogue which must express itself, nowadays, in English.
The volume is organized into five parts. In the first two essays – entitled
Gramsci: From Socialism to Communism and Antonio Gramsci: the Prison
Years –, under the general heading of “History”, a concise and updated recon-
struction of his biographical events is offered. The second part, dedicated to
the “Theories of History”, provides three different perspectives – summarized
by the titles The Crisis of European Civilization in the Thought of Antonio Grams-
ci, Notes on Gramsci’s Theory of History and The Layers of History and Politics
in Gramsci – permitting an analysis of the ideas and theories of history which
emerge from Gramsci’s writings. In the third part, addressing the concept of
“Communism” – with the essays Gramsci and Marx: Notes and Reflections,
Gramsci, the October Revolution and its “Translation” in the West and On the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
viii Preface
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Preface ix
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Acknowledgements
I wish to thank Professor Daniela Saresella, who had the idea of organizing
(and helped me to arrange) the conference devoted to Antonio Gramsci that
elicited many of these reflections, and Professor Antonino De Francesco, direc-
tor of the Department of Historical Studies at the University of Milan, which
financially supported the English translation. I would like also to thank
Professors Marco Cuzzi and Irene Piazzoni, who supported me during the
above-mentioned conference that took place in Milan (Italy) on October 2017,
and Doctor Elia Zaru, who copy-edited the texts.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Notes on Contributors
Alberto Burgio
is Full Professor of History of Philosophy at the University of Bologna. He is a
member of the Scientific Committee for the Italian National Edition of Anto-
nio Labriola’s works and the Scientific Committee for the Italian Edition of
Marx and Engels’ Complete Works. He is also member of the CeRC – Centre for
Governmentality and Disability Studies Robert Castel and of the Permanent
Seminar of Political Philosophy “Penser la transformation” at the Université
Paul-Valery – Montpellier 3. Since July 2011, he is a member of Accademia delle
Scienze dell’Istituto di Bologna (Italy). He has dealt with history of political
philosophy and philosophy of history, with studies on Rousseau, Kant, Hegel
and Marx, racism, nationalism and Italian Marxism. On Gramsci, he published
the monographs Gramsci storico. Una lettura dei “Quaderni del carcere” (Later-
za, 2003), Per Gramsci. Crisi e potenza del moderno (DeriveApprodi, 2007) and
Gramsci. Il sistema in movimento (DeriveApprodi, 2014).
Davide Cadeddu
is Associate Professor of History of Political Thought at the University of Milan
and Coordinator of the Scientific Committee of “Globus et Locus” association.
Executive Editor of Glocalism: Journal of Culture, Politics and Innovation, he is
member of the editorial board of “Il pensiero politico”, editor of the series Bib-
lioteca di cultura politica europea (Rubbettino) and Filologia e politica (Giappi-
chelli), and director of the “Permanent Seminar on the Classics of the Political
Thought” at Giangiacomo Feltrinelli Foundation. He collaborates with the
HuffPost (Italian edition). He has mainly studied the history of twentieth cen-
tury political thought, with emphasis on the problems of the relationship be-
tween politics and culture. He edited writings of Leo Strauss, Julien Benda and
Norberto Bobbio, and published the monographs Luigi Einaudi tra libertà e
autonomia (FrancoAngeli, 2018), Reimagining Democracy (Springer, 2012),
Adriano Olivetti Politico (Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, 2010).
Giuseppe Cospito
is Assistant Professor of History of Philosophy at the University of Pavia and
member of the Scientific Committee for the Italian National Edition of Anto-
nio Gramsci’s Writings. He is also member of the International Gramsci Soci-
ety and of the Scientific Committee of the Gramsciana: Rivista internazionale
di studi su Antonio Gramsci, the series Per Gramsci (Edizioni Unicopli), the
Ghilarza Summer School and the Fondazione Casa Museo Antonio Gramsci.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
xii Notes on Contributors
Angelo d’Orsi
was Full Professor of History of Political Thought at the University of Turin and
is member of the Scientific Committee for the Italian National Edition of both
Antonio Gramsci’s Writings and Antonio Labriola’s Writings. He founded and
is editor of Gramsciana: Rivista internazionale di studi su Antonio Gramsci, His-
toria Magistra: Rivista di storia critica and also BGR. Bibliografia Gramsciana
Ragionata, composed of three volumes (published the first: 1922–1965, Viella,
2008). He founded “FestivalStoria” (Italy) and was president of the Scientific
Committee of Fondazione Luigi Salvatorelli. He has dealt with the history of
historiography, political ideas and intellectual groups. On Gramsci he pub-
lished Il nostro Gramsci. Antonio Gramsci a colloquio con i protagonisti della
storia d’Italia (Viella, 2013), Inchiesta su Gramsci. Quaderni scomparsi, abiure,
conversioni, tradimenti: leggende o verità (Accademia University Press, 2014),
Gramsciana. Saggi su Antonio Gramsci (Mucchi, 2015) and Gramsci. Una nuova
biografia (Feltrinelli, 2018).
Michele Filippini
is Assistant Professor of History of Political Thought at the University of Bolo-
gna and coordinator of the digital library Gramsciproject.org. He has mainly
studied the history of Marxism, the birth of sociology in the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries as well as the forms of political legitimation and political
power. He is member of the editorial board of Scienza & Politica and Politics:
Rivista di studi politici. On Gramsci, he co-edited Gramsci e la sociologia, special
issue of Quaderni di Teoria Sociale (Morlacchi, 2013) and published the mono-
graphs Using Gramsci: A New Approach (PlutoPress, 2016), Una politica di mas-
sa. Antonio Gramsci e la rivoluzione della società (Carocci, 2015) and Gramsci
globale. Guida pratica alle interpretazioni di Gramsci nel mondo (Odoya, 2011).
He is also the author of Leaping Forward: Mario Tronti and the History of Politi-
cal Workerism (Jve-Crs, 2012) and co-editor of Mario Tronti, Il demone della po-
litica (il Mulino, 2017).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Notes on Contributors xiii
Guido Liguori
is Associate Professor of History of Political Thought at the University of Cal-
abria, President of the International Gramsci Society Italia and Senior Editor
of Critica Marxista. On Gramsci, he organized, with F. Frosini, the IGS Seminar
on the “Prison Notebooks” and edited (with G. Baratta) Gramsci da un secolo
all’altro (Editori Riuniti, 1999); (with F. Frosini) Le parole di Gramsci (Carocci,
2004); (with C. Meta) Gramsci. Guida alla lettura (Unicopli, 2005); (with P.
Voza) Dizionario gramsciano 1926–1937 (Carocci, 2009); (with L. Durante)
Domande dal presente. Studi su Gramsci (Carocci, 2012); Gramsci e il populismo
(Unicopli, 2019); A. Gramsci, Masse e partito. Antologia 1920–1926 (Editori Ri-
uniti, 2017); A. Gramsci, Come alla volontà piace. Scritti sulla Rivoluzione russa
(Castelvecchi, 2017); and he published Sentieri gramsciani (Carocci, 2006; En.
tr. Gramsci’s Pathways (Brill, 2015); and Br. tr.) and Gramsci conteso. Interpre-
tazioni, dibattiti e polemiche 1922–2012 (Editori Riuniti, 2012).
Marcello Montanari
was Full Professor of History of Political Thought at the University of Bari and
is member of the advisory board of Il pensiero politico. He has dealt with the
history of Marxism and Italian political thought, publishing articles on Al-
thusser, Lenin, Vico, Croce and Gramsci. He edited A. Gramsci, Pensare la
democrazia. Antologia dai “Quaderni dal carcere” (Einaudi, 1997), and pub-
lished La liberta e il tempo. Osservazioni sulla democrazia tra Marx e Gramsci
(Editori Riuniti, 1991); Studi su Gramsci. Americanismo, Democrazia e Teoria
della Storia nei “Quaderni del Carcere” (Pensa, 2002); Politica e Storia. Saggi su
Vico, Croce e Gramsci (Publierre, 2007) and Il revisionismo di Gramsci. La filoso-
fia della prassi tra Marx e Croce (Biblion, 2016). His latest books are Cultura e
vita politica nell’Italia del Novecento (Liberaria, 2012); Studi su Vico (Pensa, 2013);
Pinocchio e le altre favole (Aracne, 2014); La storia non finisce (Aracne, 2015).
Vittorio Morfino
is Associate Professor of History of Philosophy at the University of Milano-Bi-
cocca, where he coordinates the Specialization Course in Critical Thoery of So-
ciety. He is Directeur de recherche at the Collège international de philosohie.
He is member of the editorial board of Quaderni materialisti and Décalages:
An Althusserian Journal. He was visiting professor at the Universidade de São
Paulo, Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne, Université Bordeaux-Montaigne
and l’Universidad Nacional de Cordoba. He edited (with P.D. Thomas) The Gov-
ernment of Time: Theories of Plural Temporality in The Marxist Tradition (Hay-
market Books, 2018). His other works include Il tempo e l’occasione. L’incontro
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
xiv Notes on Contributors
Spinoza Machiavelli (Led, 2002; Fr. tr. 2012); Incursioni spinoziste (Mimesis,
2002); Il tempo della moltitudine (Manifestolibri, 2005; Fr. tr. 2010; Sp. tr. 2013),
Plural Temporality. Transindividuality and the Aleatory between Spinoza and Al-
thusser (Brill, 2014); and Genealogia di un pregiudizio. L’immagine di Spinoza in
Germania da Leibniz a Marx (Olms, 2016).
Stefano Petrucciani
is Full Professor of Political Philosophy at the Sapienza University of Rome and
President of the Italian Society of Political Philosophy. He is member of the
editorial board of the journals La Cultura, Parole Chiave, Critica Marxista, and
of the scientific committee of Iride and Fenomenologia e Società. He is Editor-
in-Chief of Politica e Società, foreign correspondent of Actuel Marx and mem-
ber of the scientific committee of Fondazione Gramsci. The main subject of his
research was the critical theory of society of the Frankfurt School. Recent
works edited include Storia del marxismo (Carocci, 2015) and Il pensiero di Karl
Marx (Carocci, 2018). He is author of Introduzione a Habermas (Laterza, 2000),
Modelli di filosofia politica (Einaudi, 2003), Introduzione a Adorno (Laterza,
2007), Marx (Carocci, 2009), Democrazia (Einaudi, 2014), A lezione da Marx
(Manifestolibri, 2014), A lezione da Adorno (Manifestolibri, 2017), Marx critique
du libéralisme (Mimesis, 2018).
Michele Prospero
is Full Professor of Political Philosophy at the Sapienza University of Rome,
Executive Editor of Democrazia e diritto and member of the direction commit-
tee of the Centro per la riforma dello Stato (Centre for the Reform of the State).
His main interests are the Italian institutional system and the left-wing politi-
cal thought. On Gramsci, he edited A. Gramsci, Il Sindacato (Bordeaux, 2017)
and authored La scienza politica di Gramsci (Bordeaux, 2017). His works in-
clude Storia delle istituzioni in Italia (Editori Riuniti, 1999), La politica moderna
(Carocci, 2002), Politica e società globale (Laterza, 2004), Alle origini del laico
(FrancoAngeli, 2006), La costituzione tra populismo e leaderismo (FrancoAnge-
li, 2007), Filosofia del diritto di proprietà (FrancoAngeli, 2009), Hans Kelsen
(FrancoAngeli 2012), Il partito politico (Carocci, 2012), Il libro nero della società
civile (Editori Riuniti, 2013), Il nuovismo realizzato (Bordeaux, 2015), La ribellione
conservatrice (Edup, 2019).
Leonardo Rapone
is Full Professor of Contemporary History at the University of Tuscia and mem-
ber of the scientific committee of the Italian National Edition of Antonio
Gramsci’s Writings. He is executive editor of Studi Storici, member of the Scien-
tific Committee of Fondazione Gramsci and of the journal Annali della
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Notes on Contributors xv
Fondazione Gramsci. He has dealt with the European left political tradition in
the twentieth century (socialist and social-democratic parties, Socialist Inter-
national, communist parties), the Italian antifascism and European integra-
tion. On Gramsci, he edited A. Gramsci, Scritti (1910–1926), vol. 2, 1917 (Istituto
della Enciclopedia italiana, 2015) and authored Cinque anni che paiono secoli.
Antonio Gramsci dal socialismo al comunismo (Carocci, 2011). He published also
Trotskij e il fascismo (Laterza, 1978), Da Turati a Nenni (FrancoAngeli, 1992); An-
tifascismo e società italiana 1926–1940 (Unicopli, 1999); La socialdemocrazia eu-
ropea tra le due guerre (Carocci, 1999); Storia dell’integrazione europea (Carocci,
2015).
Giuseppe Vacca
is President of Fondazione Gramsci and President of the Scientific Committee
of the Italian National Edition of Antonio Gramsci’s Writings. He was Full Pro-
fessor of History of Political Thought at the University of Bari. He dealt with
the first editions of Gramsci’s Letters from Prison and Prison Notebooks and
published Togliatti editore di Gramsci (Carocci, 2005). On Gramsci, he pub-
lished Gramsci e Togliatti (Editori Riuniti, 1991), Appuntamenti con Gramsci
(Carocci, 1999), (with C. Daniele) Gramsci a Roma, Togliatti a Mosca. Il carteg-
gio del 1926 (Einaudi, 1999), Vita e pensieri di Antonio Gramsci (1926–1937) (Ein-
audi, 2012) and Modernità alternative. Il Novecento di Antonio Gramsci (Einaudi,
2017). His works include Fra Italia ed Europa (FrancoAngeli, 1991), Pensare il
mondo nuovo (Edizioni San Paolo, 1994), Per una nuova costituente (Bompiani,
1996), Vent’anni dopo. La Sinistra fra mutamenti e revisioni (Einaudi, 1997), Da
un secolo all’altro (Bompiani, 1998) and Riformismo vecchio e nuovo (Einaudi,
2001).
Marzio Zanantoni
is Editorial Coordinator of Unicopli Editions in Milan. He has dealt with some
topics of philosophy and historiography in Italian culture during the nine-
teenth and twentieth century. He edited (with A. Vigorelli) La filosofia italiana
di fronte al fascismo (Unicopli, 2000); A. Labriola, Origine e natura delle passioni
secondo l’“Etica” di Spinoza (Ghibli, 2004), A. Labriola, Del socialismo e altri
scritti politici (Unicopli, 2004); (with A. Vigorelli) Gramsci oltre l’ideologia. Let-
ture e interpretazioni (1960–2010) (Unicopli, 2011), (with A. Vigorelli) F. F ergnani,
Antonio Gramsci. La filosofia della prassi nei “Quaderni del carcere” (Unicopli,
2011) and (with S. Mancini and A. Vigorelli) E. Agazzi, La filosofia di Piero Mar-
tinetti (Unicopli, 2016); and authored Anarchismo (Bibliografica, 1996), Grams-
ci e la storia della nazione italiana nei “Quaderni del carcere”, in Gramsci oltre
l’ideologia (Unicopli, 2011), Albe Steiner. Cambiare il libro per cambiare il mondo
(Unicopli, 2013), Positivismo (Bibliografica, 2016).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Part 1
History
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 1
1 Cf. Rapone 2011 for this part of the political and intellectual biography of Gramsci.
2 Cf. d’Orsi 1999.
3 Cf. Carlucci 2013.
4 Cf. ppw: 3–7 (Gramsci 1914).
by the party. He resumed political activity only near the end of 1915, when he
began to work as a journalist, having been hired (once again in Turin) by the
editorial board of “Avanti!”.5 Here is the fundamental point – Gramsci became
a militant politician in the guise of a journalist. In the early years, his political
activism was exclusively expressed in his journalistic activity. Furthermore, the
articles he wrote were articles that were mainly inspired by the reality of the
daily life of Turin’s citizens – the events and happenings of life in Turin. More
weighty articles from the early years are rare, articles that address questions of
a more general relevance. Still, even in articles inspired by daily life in Turin
one can extract important elements that help to examine the inner workings
of his mind. In fact, commenting on the citizens’ doings – taking a cue from the
small episodes of daily life – Gramsci develops a series of considerations that
illuminate us as to the ideal premise of his socialism: his vision of the world
and his concept of moral life in particular. In this first phase, what is the politi-
cal profile that can be inferred from his interventions? These are the war years
and his political position is, above all, against the war. Gramsci leads a tireless
campaign through his articles against nationalist rhetoric, against the cultural
miseries of war propaganda and against the demagogic artifices to which Ital-
ian interventionists resort in order to excite public opinion.
Nationalism and patriotism act against some of the fundamental premises
of Gramsci’s socialist vision. From the outset, Gramsci thought of socialism as
the stimulus for humankind to exit from the constrained dimension of its
more immediate experiences, in order to consider itself part of a more vast
community. Thus, Gramsci’s socialism is from the beginning positioned in op-
position to any form of corporatism, be it in the form of a category, a village, a
neighborhood or a region. Nationalism is also a form of corporatism, to which
Gramsci opposes with a strong sense of belonging to humanity – each com-
munity belonging to all of all humanity. In the beginning, Gramsci’s interna-
tionalism is strongly inspired by the sentiments of the universality of mankind
and the rebuilding of humanity. Even when the internationalist projection of
Gramsci later on assumed a stronger classist coloring, the theme that could be
defined as the unity of the world – the unification of humanity – would remain
on its horizon, witnessing a plurality of ideal reasons not reducible only to
class solidarity. This, for Gramsci, motivated the need to supersede the nation-
state as a structurally inadequate space both for the development of cultural
life and civil progress and the development of the economic fundamentals of
associated life.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: From Socialism to Communism 5
6 Gramsci 1918a.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
6 Rapone
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: From Socialism to Communism 7
Turin in the struggle against customs protectionism.9 This tells us two things:
that in this moment, Gramsci was absolutely not yet thinking about the possi-
bility in Italy of an extension of the revolutionary process that had just started
in Russia – we are in the intermediate phase between the February Revolution
and the October Revolution; and that principle of international liberty in trade
had a place of utmost importance in the socialist vision of Gramsci. In his eyes,
protectionism is an agent of war, for the commercial revelry that it triggers.
Therefore, if peace is to be guaranteed once the carnage of world war is fin-
ished, striving against the raising of new trade barriers is needed. But above all,
protectionism for Gramsci appears to be anti-historical behavior, contrary to
the interest of capitalist development. For Gramsci, productive forces gener-
ated by the capitalist system do not adapt themselves to the frame of the
nation-state and tend rather to interpenetrate, developing transnational bonds
of solidarity. At this moment, what is already hinted at is that contradiction
between the transnational dimension of the economic processes and the na-
tional organization of politics and institutions, which will be presented in the
Quaderni as the principal factor of twentieth-century social and political con-
vulsions. The war appears to Gramsci to be a distortion of the pure capitalistic
mechanism, contrary to the needs of development of this system and its com-
plex. This also means that Gramsci is very far from the idea of imperialism as a
superior phase of capitalist development. At the same time, free trade for him
has a strong anti-reformist valence because its opposite, protectionism, en-
globing sectors of the proletariat in the system of protected interest – is an
encouragement to the collaboration between the classes.
Only at the beginning of 1919, almost two years later, the theme of the actu-
ality of the revolution entered Gramsci’s view. In this moment what began to
dawn on him was the catastrophic vision of the post-war capitalist crisis of the
Bolsheviks and of the newly born Third International, which envisaged the de-
struction of capitalism as the only alternative to Europe’s regression towards
barbarism. Gramsci is strongly influenced by these first theorizations on the
general crisis of capitalism and was strengthened in the conviction of the revo-
lution’s maturity in the light of the spectacle showed in the countries just com-
ing out of the defeat of war, in which the default of state structures coincided
with the diffusion of revolutionary movements. Only those that he called “pro-
letarian revolutions of 1919”,10 referring to Germany, Bavaria, Hungary, and to
analogous movements in Austria, convinced him that it was a passage through
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
8 Rapone
a historical phase and that revolution could actually become a political pro-
gram for Western Europe.
Setting out the conclusion, I want to quickly consider the starting point –
socialism – and the arrival point – communism – of Gramsci’s intellectual and
political journey, which I outlined. The theoretical basis on which Gramsci
founded his loyalty to socialism is a conception of history in which the propul-
sive function of mankind encamps itself – a concept of humankind as a con-
scious and strong-willed entity, a creator of history and at the same time pro-
duced by history itself. The starting point is the tenacious will of humankind.
Gramsci operated within the context of a cultural climate marked by the anti-
positivistic reaction, by the rehabilitation of the subjective and spiritual side of
human experience and was strongly involved in it. The social-economic envi-
ronment, the material conditions of existence cannot determine the human
path without humankind’s intervention: a decisive possession of the space
that offers itself to human initiative. In this phase, there were two targets for
Gramsci’s criticism: on the one hand, transcendentalism and providentialism
in the catholic vision of the relationship between God and the world; on the
other hand, the positivization of socialism – the reduction of historical mate-
rialism to a deterministic conception of development and the claim that the
scientific nature of socialism consists of the representation of social processes
as natural processes, without regard for human initiative. We arrive at the
question of the influence that idealism had in the formation of Gramsci’s
thought, how Gramsci explicitly recognized later in his Quaderni del carcere
(“Prison Notebooks”) and in the letters that he would write from prison,11 ad-
mitting to being in 1917 substantially “rather a supporter of Croce”, without,
however, making reference to, as per self-censorship, the influence of Gentile.
In Gramsci’s vision, idealism had the merit of having redeemed humankind
from the mortgages – from the religious transcendentalism and positivistic de-
terminism; and the language of idealism was the one through which Gramsci
initially expressed his anti-providential and anti-naturalistic conception of the
history. Here arises the question: and Marx? What place does Marx have in the
conceptual universe of early Gramsci? Marx is hardly ever quoted; Gramsci
clearly reveals a certain initial difficulty in fully putting the vision of human-
kind as builder of history in relation to Marx’s doctrine. It’s almost as if Grams-
ci could not fully satisfy, remaining on the perimeter of Marxism, the need to
see the will and conscience placed at the center of the process of transformation.
11 Cf. fspn: 355 (Q 10i, § 11: 1233), letter to Tania Schucht, August 17, 1931.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: From Socialism to Communism 9
Here then, he uses the conceptual apparatus, and also the lexicon of idealism,
in order to express the volitional and activistic content of his vision of social-
ism. It is on this background that one needs to view one of Gramsci’s most
notable articles, which he wrote after the Bolsheviks take power. The article
bears the title La rivoluzione contro “Il Capitale” (“The Revolution Against ‘Capi-
tal’”) in “Avanti!”, December 22, 1917: the Bolsheviks did justice to the theories
of Marx, those that foresaw that socialism could only appear on the scene at
the end of a succession of historical phases that included a compulsory pas-
sage through capitalism. Now, though, my impression is that, beyond the title
(self-consciously paradoxical) this article signals the real beginning of Grams-
ci’s Marxism: the Bolsheviks did not overturn Marx, they overturned the deter-
ministic interpretation of Marx, the pretense of deducing a theory of necessary
succession of historical phases from historical materialism. This is the real be-
ginning of the relationship of Gramsci with Marx also for an immediately evi-
dent reason: the Bolsheviks declare themselves Marxists, and thus, in the mo-
ment in which Gramsci puts himself in solidarity with the Bolsheviks and fully
recognizes their political determination, he cannot avoid asking himself about
the problem of his relationship with Marx. Consequently, Gramsci progres-
sively persuades himself of the possibility of a non-naturalistic definition of
Marxism: a reading of Marxism that gives space to the function of human will.
Gramsci will understand Marxism as a philosophy that already contains the
principle of the determining function of the subject in the construction of re-
ality. The core truth of idealism – this becomes the fixed point of Gramsci’s
vision – that is the function of human will, is fully present in Marx’s theoretical
system so there is no more need for spurious grafts in order to found the poli-
tics of socialism on the principle of creative power of man.
As for the initial profile of Gramsci’s communism, one observes that, be-
yond the immediate solidarity with the revolutionary process in Russia, re-
flecting on the chains of events Gramsci persuaded himself that the “essential”
fact of the Bolshevik Revolution is the construction of a new type of State;12
therefore not only the overturning of the old ruling classes, but the construc-
tion of an “organized system of power”,13 radically different than the typical
one found in the liberal society of West: the Stato dei Consigli. Gramsci’s adher-
ence to communism is characterized by a strong underlining of the function
that the Stato dei Consigli assumes not only in Russia, but also later in the
“Revolutions of 1919” that reiterate that aspect from the Russian example and
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
10 Rapone
are also being articulated in council movements. At that time – in the first
months of 1919 – Gramsci arrived at the conviction that the construction of the
Stato dei Consigli could be an equalizing factor for the revolutionary processes
in all of Europe: hence the commitment that, entering the orbit of commu-
nism, he put into the realization in Italy of that organizational model, through
the development and conversion of “commissioni interne” (internal union
commissions) into factory councils.14 It is necessary to add, though, that the
factory councils were conceived as a the cellular base of an institutional sys-
tem that should be characterized, at the same time, by a strong capacity for
control and command, by “a strong socialist State, that halts as much before
dissolution and indiscipline, giving back a concrete form to the social body,
defending the revolution from external aggressions and internal rebellions”
(Lo Stato e il socialismo, “L’Ordine nuovo”, June 28-July 5 1919). Gramsci’s new
state is at the same time Stato dei Consigli and State of Authority and Com-
mand: a State in which base units express direct participation by the masses to
organization of social activities and a State that exercises a disciplining func-
tion inside of the social body – democracy of the workers and dictatorship of
the proletariat. To the latter, Gramsci assigns a double function. On one hand
it has a repressive function – keeping counterrevolutionary forces in check,
consenting to the new dominant class to complete the revolutionary transfor-
mation; on the other hand it has a liberating function, because underneath the
protection of the dictatorship a new organization of power was consolidating
“into which the dictatorship, having accomplished its mission, will be
dissolved”.15 Authoritarianism and the exercising of force are conceived there-
fore as temporary characteristics of the new state under construction that then
must dissolve into a new system of liberty and democracy. With the assump-
tion of the theme of dictatorship, on Gramsci’s horizon enters the question of
the historical task of the minorities – of that “aristocracy of statesmen”: how he
defines the Bolshevik leadership,16 that through the exercising of state power,
interprets the will of the multitude and guides it to its maturity towards an
adequate awareness of their position and of their interests. It is from this mo-
ment that he began to consider the problem of building social consensus to-
wards the revolutionary project and the problem of the relationship between
different social groups mobilized or mobilizable in support of this project. This
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: From Socialism to Communism 11
Bibliography
Other Works
Carlucci, A. (2013), Gramsci and languages: unification, diversity, hegemony (Boston,
Leiden: Brill).
d’Orsi, A. (1999), Lo studente che non divenne “dottore”. Gramsci all’università di Torino,
in “Studi Storici”, 1, pp. 39–75.
Martinelli, R. (1972), Una polemica del 1921 e l’esordio di Gramsci sull’“Avanti!” torinese, in
“Critica marxista”, 5, pp. 148–157.
Monticone, A. (1972), Gli italiani in uniforme 1915–1918. Intellettuali, borghesi e disertori
(Bari: Laterza, 1972).
Rapone, L. (2011), Cinque anni che paiono secoli. Antonio Gramsci dal socialismo al co-
munismo (1914–1919) (Roma: Carocci).
Righi, M.L. (2014), Gli esordi di Gramsci al “Grido del popolo” e all’ “Avanti!” (1915–1916), in
“Studi Storici”, 3, pp. 727–758.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
12 Rapone
Salvadori, M.L. [1973] (2007), Gramsci e il problema storico della democrazia (Roma:
Viella).
Spriano, P. (1971), L’Ordine nuovo e i consigli di fabbrica (Torino: Einaudi).
Spriano, P. (1972), Storia di Torino operaia e socialista. Da De Amicis a Gramsci (Torino:
Einaudi).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 2
Gramsci spent time in several prisons (Regina Coeli in Rome, San Vittore in
Milan, Civitavecchia, Turi…) and in two clinics (Cusumano in Formia and Qui-
sisana in Rome). The task of reconstructing this long phase of Gramsci’s life
entails following two lines of study: (a) retelling the events in such a way that
the reconstruction serves to illuminate the psychology, choices and ideas de-
veloped by Gramsci; (b) concentrating on the ideas and putting into focus their
course while seeking to grasp elements of continuity and/or discontinuity.
During the period between his arrest and his death, there were six years
(between the spring of 1929 and the spring of 1935) of powerful theoretical
creativity starting from the moment in which he was allowed to write for a few
hours each day in his cell, keeping a limited quantity of necessary materials
(notebooks and volumes) for this allotted number of hours.
From the moment of his arrest (November, 1926) until the beginning of the
Quaderni del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”) (February 1929), Gramsci did not
remain inert: first of all, there are his letters and then there is evidence of study
that bears witness to the pedagogical-political work he developed during his
confinement in Ustica. With regard to the letters, it is immediately necessary to
specify (for me it is a reconfirmation) that they should not be understood as
private, emotional or affective, that is, the representation of Gramsci the man –
the medium through which he confided his hopes and pains, his illusions and
delusions – but as a body of work that can be considered along with the Quad-
erni del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”), providing important clues for their un-
derstanding. The Lettere dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”) help us not only to
correctly place the texts enclosed within the 33 Notebooks on the temporal
plane, but also to understand them. One must underline the fact that Grams-
ci’s letters are stuffed (almost to the point of redundancy) with bibliographic
notes, linguistic, philosophical, literary, theatrical, artistic and historical ideas
as well as historiographical indications. This implies the need for a parallel
reading of the two bodies of work, or even a blended reading that integrates
the letters with the notebooks and vice versa.
1 Gramsci 1994a: 45, Gramsci to Tatiana, December 19th, 1926 (LC: 17; LT: 13; LC2: 14).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Antonio Gramsci: The Prison Years 15
impossibility, no matter how many efforts are made, of dating every single note
of the 33 Notebooks – and should oblige us also to notice that in Gramsci’s
process emerges a desire to overcome or at least to limit the fragmentary na-
ture of the works (even though the thoughts are written in a dialogue format).
Thus, in a certain sense, the work is “fragmentary”. Otherwise, why at a certain
point did he feel the need to rewrite, to return to texts already written and even
to sketch essays (in the “special notebooks”)? In short, what is evident is his
will to go beyond the fragment and to give, with the passing of months and
years, a more systematic and organized character to his own reflection.
There is a nexus between the logistical situation (the physical and psycho-
logical condition) of the prisoner and his intellectual work. A serious parallel-
ism can be established between the degradation of the physical (the sickening
body) and theoretical elaboration, reflection and self-reflection, on his person-
al, private, emotional affairs; even the writer’s style is affected and this should
be subject to a more reasoned assessment. In general, however, the elaboration
of Gramsci’s thought is very strongly conditioned by the concrete situation in
which he finds himself living: the constriction, both physical and mental, that
he is subjected to by force; the acknowledgment of the blocked political situa-
tion and the observation of the historical course that does not adhere to the
vision held before his loss of freedom. Above all, the perception of defeat – the
central idea, the common thread of Gramsci’s thinking and feeling after No-
vember 8th, 1926 – is the fundamental evidence that the course of time led to
a rethinking of his own theories: a dialectic between continuity and disconti-
nuity which must be followed with maximum attention. Another dialectic, this
time human, must also be taken into account. Between serenity and prostra-
tion, between the desire to fight and the desire to abandon oneself, “like a peb-
ble in the current”. On November 20th, a few days after his arrest, he wrote to
his mother:
That bit of humor, over the years, before the elimination of every possibility of
returning to freedom, would lessen into a gradually more tired dialectic, be-
tween the “principle of hope” and the “principle of desperation”.
2 Gramsci 1994a: 37, Gramsci to his mother, November 20th, 1926, (LC: 7; LC2: 6).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
16 d’Orsi
In general, the trip has been for me a very long cinematic event: I’ve come
to know and I’ve seen an infinity of types, from the most vulgar and re-
pugnant to the oddest replete with interesting traits. I’ve understood how
difficult is to know the true nature of men from outward signs.4
3 There are no specific studies on Gramsci’s stay in Ustica. Cf. the two interviews of islanders
(Stochino 2016) and a recent film documentary titled Gramsci 44, by Emiliano Barbucci
(2016).
4 Gramsci 1994a: 70, Gramsci to Tatiana and Giulia, February 12, 1927 (LT: 44)
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Antonio Gramsci: The Prison Years 17
He remained at San Vittore for almost a year and a half, a period during
which the judge, Enrico Macis was able, with subtle cunning, to make the ac-
cused into a sort of victim-accomplice: to render him, to a certain extent, to be
a collaborator in his own ruin.5 Macis’ lies did not only serve to worsen Grams-
ci’s legal position, but also caused doubts and suspicions to grow in his mind,
especially towards the Party, even though he was still leader. With the passing
of the years and the worsening of his physical and mental health, these doubts
and suspicions, would not have only not disappeared but would have flour-
ished, because of a syndrome provoked by the sensation of affective solitude,
isolation from the world and his tormented relationship with Giulia. Gramsci
died without having found out about the truth about his arrest, the failed ne-
gotiations for his release, and the heavy sentence that weighed him down until
the end of his life.
The case revolved around a letter that another important leader, Ruggero
Grieco, had addressed to Gramsci, but also, some nearly exact copies sent to
two other detained companions: Terracini and Scoccimarro.6 Rivers of ink
have been spilled on the subject of these letters, by the pressure of political and
journalistic controversy more than the desire for an accurate interpretation –
sine ira et studio.7 Even if the hypothesis that it was a fake case constructed
ad hoc by the police is true – excluding the idea that Grieco was a spy of the
regime (excluding the fact that he wanted to harm his imprisoned partner) –
what remains is only to interpret it as a gesture of thoughtlessness with the
possible consequences not having being well calculated. Grieco probably had
aimed to probe the capacity of repressive apparatuses while still showing af-
fection and closeness to Gramsci and to the other two captive leaders. It was
the judge who imprinted an unwanted meaning on that letter and it actually
did not have that meaning in trial (according to the fact that the document was
not used in the court arguments). Falling into Macis’ trap, that letter became a
torment for Gramsci that accompanied him to his death, in the fear of having
been abandoned, if not betrayed by his Party outright, or at least by some-
one who made sure that he remained in prison. This someone, in Gramsci’s
mind, could have only been Togliatti, after the bitter exchange in the letter of
October 1926 (regarding the struggle within the Russian Communist Party) and
the consequent rupture of relations between the two. In reality, thanks to the
special role of Piero Sraffa, the link between Gramsci and the Party, including
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
18 d’Orsi
Togliatti, did not ever completely break, even if it sometimes unravelled to the
point of rupture.
At the San Vittore prison, Gramsci carried the burden of several accusations
that slowly worsened into a situation where he started to suffer abandonment –
by the Party, even after failed attempts for his liberation, and from Giulia –
revealing his own weakness, and at the same time, his own strength. The dia-
lectic between these strengths and weaknesses would be the common thread
of Gramsci’s detention.
Not yet being a condemned inmate, but an inmate waiting for judgement,
Gramsci had the possibility to write even to people outside of his family circle.
The letter to Giuseppe Berti, his communist comrade, in which after having
declared that he could not work and that his condition was not “worse than it
was in the past years” and feigning tranquility: “I read a lot, but in a disorderly
way”, he added: “I possess a fairly happy capacity to find some interesting side
even in the most modest intellectual production, such as serial novels, for ex-
ample”. We are at the beginning of the theory, later put into focus, of the
“national-popular”. In the same letter, he undertook a fast and efficient review
of Nello Rosselli’s book, Mazzini e Bakunin, proffering opinions of great inter-
est. As a political leader, he gave method lessons to young historians: “I do not
know Rosselli personally, but I would like to tell him that I do not understand
the acrid bitterness he puts in his book of history”. And then Gramsci descends
into the details of his analysis, arriving at the conclusion that with an apology
of “historical criticism”, and an invitation to liberate oneself from certain dia-
tribes of the past, perhaps even led by a mistaken point of view such as the one
Rosselli ends up adhering to: namely a use of Mazzini against Garibaldi…, but
generously acknowledging that the book “really fills a gap”.8 In this first period
he still did not renounce his role as a studious professor even when he fully felt
like a militant politician.
At San Vittore prison, Gramsci started to toughen himself, adopting rules for
survival: “If one wishes to remain strong and keep intact one’s power of resis-
tance one must subject oneself to a regime and follow it with an iron will”.9 He
found the force to tidy his cell, transforming it a small way into his “home”. He
gardened, planting seedlings, he raised animals such as sparrows, and he be-
came an attentive observer of their habits.10 At the same time, he made use
of the prison’s library and bought newspapers and weekly magazines at the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Antonio Gramsci: The Prison Years 19
I am obsessed […] by this idea: that I should do something für ewig […].
In short, in keeping with a preestablished program, I would like to con-
centrate intensely and systematically on some subject that would ab-
sorb and provide a center to my inner life. Up until now I’ve thought of
four subject […] and they are: (1) a study of the formation of the public
spirit in Italy during the past century […]. (2) A study of comparative
linguistics! Nothing less; but what could be more “disinterested” and für
ewig than this? […] (3) A study of Pirandello’s theatre and of the trans-
formation of Italian theatrical taste that Pirandello represented and
helped to form. […] (4) An essay on the serial novel and popular taste in
literature.11
This first program contained, in a nutshell, a part of the drama of the Quaderni
del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”). The “für ewig”, besides its translation (“forev-
er” or “disinterestedly”, such as was specified in another letter),12 should not be
11 Gramsci 1994a: 83–84, Gramsci to Tatiana, March 19, 1927 (LC: 60–66; LC2: 54–58; LT:
60–63).
12 Gramsci 1994b: 155–157, Gramsci to Giulia, March 28, 1932 (LC: 597–599; LC2: 552–554).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
20 d’Orsi
Dubbed the “big trial”, with a conviction of more than twenty years, arriving at
Turi Gramsci is now an inmate with a definitive sentence, needing to strength-
en his determination in order to keep working and to survive: something that
was granted to him only in February of 1929. The already severe prison rules
became even more rigid with time, in a paradoxical parallelism with the wors-
ening state of the Gramsci’s health.
In such an uncomfortable situation, Tatiana’s proximity was providential
even if the pressures of his sister-in-law were often excessive and even wrong,
provoking contrariness in Antonio. The conclusion was always the same: who
is outside cannot understand what it means to be in prison. Giulia, his wife,
seemed to understand this least of all. Tatiana, on her part, does not only ap-
pear as an Antigone fighting against the tyrannical power that is killing Anto-
nio (she is not only the one who tries to give him the strength to go on, but she
is also a woman in love) and in a certain sense, reciprocated by the man who
continues to reject the attitudes of those who are trying to give him comfort:
“I am not an afflicted person who must be consoled; I shall never become
one”.14 The man who continues to say that he has become insensitive: “in two
years”, he wrote in October 1928, “I have lost almost all of my sensitivity” and
“the conviction of not being understood, to the limits within I am obliged to
write, pushes me lower and lower into a state of passive and blissful indiffer-
ence, from which I can not get away”. A bitter paradox for one who a decade
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Antonio Gramsci: The Prison Years 21
before shouted his hatred of indifferent people. The conclusion was dramatic:
“I feel that I am sinking deeper and deeper”.15
In spite of this, he started work in February – first with translation exercises
(having important implications for content) introducing us to the grandiose
construction of the Quaderni del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”). Laid out roughly
following the plan enunciated in 1927, then re-worked two years later,16 but en-
larged according to different guidelines, between theatrical and literary criti-
cism, history and historiography, philosophy and political science, economics
and human and social sciences. A type of construction site that initially ap-
pears, for what one can reconstruct chronologically, really in progress, passing
from more impromptu and provisional notes to an attempt at organic organiza-
tion, within possible limits given the situation (lack of sources, censorship, con-
stant aggravation of his health, progressive psychological prostration…). The
letters are a snapshot of all this, but they are also a valuable tool for entering
Gramsci’s workshop and better understanding the innumerable implications.
In addition to the translation exercises, the drafting of the first notes of the
Prison Notebooks, between 1929 and 1931 coincide with the “turning point” in
the Comintern: the expulsion of Gramsci’s friend Tasca by the Italian Com-
munist Party and the expulsion of Trotsky from the Soviet Party – a moment
of serious crisis within the international communist movement. It was an op-
portunity for Gramsci to rethink history and the problems of the community
he feels a part of, with the distance of no longer being a political actor. He
continues to think politically, even when the method is historical, and the
disciplines that he practices are more varied. The Prison Notebooks propose
a progressive emergence of concepts that Gramsci extracts, like Machiavelli
(not by chance one his favorite authors) both from direct experience and from
study. A work strongly steeped in history, in truth it transcends history and
proposes an extraordinary repertoire of ideas in the working out of its themes.
Hence the importance of dating, but without yielding philological exaspera-
tion (a very strong risk today in Gramscian studies), the different notes from
the Prison Notebooks, taking into account that they have a sort of “reticular
structure” in which the author proceeds with “spiral writing”. Gramsci seems
to want to put order, changing topic and at the same time changing note-
book. This confirms the difference between the “miscellaneous” notebooks
and the “special” notebooks, that is, monographic, in which there is a strategy
of content characterization at the start of a new notebook. It is necessary to
15 Gramsci 1994a: 228–230, Gramsci to Tatiana, October 20, 1928 (LC2: 217–219; LT:
269–271).
16 Cf. Gramsci 1994a: 252, Gramsci to Giulia, March 11, 1929 (LC: 262; LC2: 244).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
22 d’Orsi
recognize Gramsci’s rules. With that in mind one can try to enter the labora-
tory of the 33 Quaderni del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”), giving priority not
to the mere chronology, but to the choice to reconstruct the lattice of themes
brought into focus by Gramsci, who proceeds by reviewing the texts of the
first draft (the “miscellaneous notebooks”), then adding and specifying and
sometimes introducing changes into his work.17
Fragmentation of the draft (partly unavoidable, partly determined by
choice, and thus the reference to “fragmentism”, which corresponds to the dia-
logic will of the author) and, often, allusive writing (for fear of censorship and
subject to self-censorship), do not prevent a result that, in the serious limits of
the given situation, can be permissibly considered “a work”. And despite the für
ewig, the fundamental intent of the Prison Notebooks is political: a painful
meditation on the defeat of the Party, the international movement to which it
belongs, and on personal defeat – both as a manager and as a militant. To this
is added the growing feeling of being vanquished as a man, husband and fa-
ther: “understanding the reasons for the defeat was for him […] the only way to
continue the work of the revolution”; not just because he could not have done
anything else while being in jail, but also because “from Marx he had learned
that this is the only attitude of the revolutionary who does not resign himself
to the subordinate part of the martyr”. The militiaman had to become a man of
science, without losing his militant spirit or renouncing the ultimate goal: the
liberation of the oppressed classes.18 We come across the term “defeat” 44
times in the Prison Notebooks, referring to historical situations, political events
and the events of individuals. As he said several times, he was prepared for the
eventuality: “since defeat in the struggle must always be envisaged, the prepa-
ration of one’s own successors is as important is as what one does for victory”.19
Some pages are obviously more political, even in encrypted form; others are
a mediated discussion that favors a historical approach while also being atten-
tive to the languages of the humanities and social sciences. The notes dedi-
cated to the history of Italy are substantiated by politics, in which there is a
constant cross-reference between past and present. Gramsci searches for the
causes of defeat, but that means reflecting on the victors, i.e. the forces (Fas-
cism) that beat the international proletarian movement, but also American-
ism: in essence, the two faces of capitalism. Gramsci has an incredible ability
to penetrate that world with analysis that, for many, seems to anticipate the
analysis of the exponents of the “Frankfurt School”. In relation to the crisis of
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Antonio Gramsci: The Prison Years 23
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
24 d’Orsi
In theory, he could receive whom he wanted, had the possibility of going out,
moving away from the hospital perimeter, but the invasive police control
combined with his constantly worsening physical condition soon discour-
aged him. Probably, towards the end of the stay in Formia, at the height of
1935, Gramsci started to give up. The temptation to “disappear like a stone in
the ocean”,20 seems to prevail, from time to time coming to the fore, and this
explains the end of the drafting of the Quaderni (“Notebooks”), and the thin-
ning out of the letters; and lastly it explains the increasingly bitter the tone
and the progressive emergence of a sentiment that he rejected in the past,
self-pity: “this hell in which I am slowly dying”.21 He wrote in this way in 1933,
months after the serious crisis that had struck him in March. From this point,
though still managing to hold the pen in his hand, the following years were
an ordeal. His last notes are from May 1935. During this period, he only wrote
occasional letters to his family (with an increase of those to his children),
while the relationship with his wife worsened, even though he continued in
vain to urge her return to Italy. The transition to another clinic, the Quisisana
of Rome, did not have the desired effects. His body was too worn out; the
spirit had suffered too much. The period in Rome was inactive, in essence,
while his fears, anxieties and sense of failure increased, and Giulia’s expecta-
tion became self-deception.
Death arrived on April 27, 1937 and freed Gramsci from everything. As soon
as he heard the news, Piero Sraffa was right to say, that it was “a disgrace with-
out equal”22 – not only for his friends and companions and for the story of
world communism, but for the history of international culture.
Bibliography
20 Gramsci 1994b: 5, Gramsci to Giulia, January 13, 1931 (LC: 398; LC2: 387).
21 Gramsci 1994b: 308, Gramsci to Tania, July 6, 1933 (LC: 798; LT: 1320; LC2: 727).
22 Sraffa 1991: 180, Sraffa to Tatiana, April 27, 1937.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Antonio Gramsci: The Prison Years 25
LT: Natoli, A., Daniele, C. (eds.) (1997), A. Gramsci, T. Schucht, Lettere. 1926–1935 (Tori-
no: Einaudi).
Q: Gerratana, V. (ed.) (1975), Quaderni del carcere (Torino: Einaudi), 4 vols.
spn: Hoare, Q., Nowell-Smith, G. (eds.) (1971), Selection from the Prison Notebooks (New
York: International Publishers).
Other Works
d’Orsi, A. (ed.) (2014), Inchiesta su Gramsci. Quaderni scomparsi, abiure, conversioni,
tradimenti: leggende o verità? (Torino: Accademia University Press).
d’Orsi, A. (2018), Gramsci. Una nuova biografia. Nuova edizione rivista e accresciuta (Mi-
lano: Feltrinelli).
Fabre, G. (2015), Lo scambio. Come Gramsci non fu liberato (Palermo: Sellerio).
Francioni, G. (1984), L’officina gramsciana. Ipotesi sulla struttura dei Quaderni del car-
cere (Napoli: Bibliopolis).
Francioni, G. (2009), Come lavorava Gramsci, in Francioni, G. (ed.), Quaderni del car-
cere. Edizione anastatica dei manoscritti (Roma-Cagliari: Biblioteca Treccani-
L’Unione Sarda).
Gerratana, V. (1997), Gramsci. Problemi di metodo (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Giacomini, R. (2017), Gramsci e il giudice (Roma: Castelvecchi).
Sraffa, P. (1991), Lettere a Tania per Gramsci, Introduzione e cura di V. Gerratana (Roma:
Editori Riuniti).
Stochino, G. (2016), Gramsci al confino di Ustica: Due interviste raccolte da Giulia Sto-
chino, in “Gramsciana”, 3, pp. 151–167.
Suppa, S. (2016), Ordine e conflitto. Una trama per rileggere Gramsci (Torino:
Giappichelli).
Vacca, G. (2012), Vita e pensieri di Gramsci. 1926–1937 (Torino: Einaudi).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Part 2
Theories of History
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 3
Giuseppe Vacca
The First World War influenced the whole development of Gramsci’s thought.
For him, the war was the culminating manifestation of a crisis in European
civilization that had been building since 1870. What distinguishes Gramsci
from other important thinkers of his time is not just his capacity to identify the
causes of Old Europe’s decline, but his ability to intuit the features of the na-
scent “New World”.
In describing the “world of yesterday” submerged by the war, Gramsci em-
phasizes the breakdown of the world market – something which to him seems
“irremediable”:
The war – he writes in “L’Ordine Nuovo” (The New Order) on November 8th,
1919 – has irretrievably broken the worldwide equilibrium of capitalistic pro-
duction. Before the war, a dense network of trade relations had been estab-
lished in the world. Economically speaking, the world had become like a living
organism with blood coursing through its veins. The capitalists had accom-
plished a huge amount: for decades, millions of individuals driven by the de-
sire for personal profit had worked in the world seeking relationships, foster-
ing them in order to sustain a healthy variety of venous and arterial blood
vessels (so to speak), through which the life of the world circulated with the
pulses of a multiplicity of “hearts”: the various large markets of production and
consumption.1
This grandiose process, triggered by the vocation of capitalist production to
unify the world, had happened “spontaneously” thanks to the economic ener-
gy of capitalism. The aim indicated by Gramsci in the Quaderni del carcere
(“Prison Notebooks”) was that of contributing to consciously creating the “con-
ditions of an economy according to a worldwide plan”. Along the way, his diag-
nosis of the crisis unfolds – leading from the analysis in real time of the war to
his personal reflections found in the Quaderni del carcere. The war had not
only destroyed the old checks and balances and the old civilization, it had also
established a new world order: a hierarchy of power that immediately after the
peace of Versailles he considers “catastrophic”:
The myth of war – the unity of the world in the League of Nations – was
realized in ways and in the form that could be achieved under private and
national property: in the monopoly of the globe exercised and exploited
by the Anglo-Saxons. The economic and political life of the states is
strictly controlled by Anglo-American capitalism […]. It is the death of
the state, which is, as it is sovereign and independent. National capital-
ism is reduced to the condition of a vassal […]. The national state is dead:
becoming a sphere of influence, a monopoly in the hands of foreigners.
The world is “unified” in the sense that a world hierarchy has been creat-
ed that the whole world regulates and controls authoritatively.2
These blazing insights springing from the war will, ten years later, coalesce into
a true and proper theory of crises enunciated in a long note from February
1933,3 specifically dedicated to the global economic crises of 1929–1932. Grams-
ci asks himself: “When did the crisis begin?” And he responds: “since this is a
development and not an event, the issue is important. One can say that there
is not beginning date for the crisis as such, but only of some more clamorous
“manifestations” that are erroneously and tendentiously identified with the
crisis”. It is very significant that between the “tendentious” interpretations, he
points out those which isolate the crash of the New York Stock Exchange, since
they come from those that “want to find the origin and the cause of the crisis”
in “Americanism”. But we will return to this later. Here, it is worthwhile to dwell
on the connection between the (economic) crisis and the war:
All of the postwar period was a crisis, with attempts to prevent it, some-
times turning into good fortune in this or that country, but nothing else.
For some (and perhaps not wrongly) the war itself was a manifestation of
this crisis, indeed the first manifestation. The war was precisely the politi-
cal and organizational response of those responsible for it.
This way of analyzing the crisis does not separate economic processes from the
social antagonisms and political changes. The correlation between the crisis
and war and the consideration of both as more “complicated” “manifestations”
of historical processes linking the internal life of states to their position in
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Crisis of European Civilization 31
i nternational relations. Analyzing the first point, Gramsci reaches a more pre-
cise periodization of the crisis, giving emphasis to “issues” that had been ac-
cumulating inside of states starting from 1870. In June 1933, he wrote: “Every-
body recognizes that the war of 1914–1918 represents an historical break, in the
sense that a whole series of questions which piled up individually before 1914
have precisely formed a ‘mound’, modifying the general structure of the previ-
ous process”. Gramsci enumerated these “questions” one by one, systematically
categorizing them as a “trade-union phenomenon”, and between them he un-
derlines the birth of the socialist movement, after which the progressive en-
trance of the subaltern classes into the life of the state had become a decisive
question.4 Returning then to the chain of events between the origin of the cri-
sis and that of the war, Gramsci’s annotation of February 1933 reaches a com-
plete formulation of the theory of these crises: the war, as much as the crisis,
had arisen from the “contradiction” between the cosmopolitanism of the econ-
omy and the “nationalism” of politics, intensifying during the “age of empires”
and culminating in the war:
Clearly, Gramsci does not predict a necessarily “catastrophic” outcome for the
crisis6 and this constitutes its distinctive trait in the communism of the 1930s
(and not only). Above all, he indicates a way out with the condition that the
ruling class knows how to remove this asymmetry, creating new balances be-
tween the “space” of the economy and that of politics. Nevertheless, the ruling
classes are prevalently molded by national politics, and thus the leaders
are principally responsible for the war and economic crisis and are rendered
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
32 Vacca
i ncreasingly more inept by the way in which the war and crisis impact the big-
gest creation of European modernity: the nation state. We must therefore look
at the way in which Gramsci comes back to the theme of the crisis of the state
in the Prison Notebooks.
The lexicon changes: he no longer speaks of “death” as he did in the 1920s,
but of the “crisis” of the State and he does not only inflect it in relation to the
exercise of sovereignty. Certainly, he is very attentive to new limitations of the
sovereignty of State that he considers particularly negative, such as in the case
of the Concordat,7 but he does not recognize the strength of the State in the
exercise of a (presumptuous) absolute territorial sovereignty, but rather in the
capacity to open up to supranationality.
Before analyzing the solutions, it is worthwhile pondering the vision of the
crisis of the State. Differently than the period immediately postwar when, as
we have seen, the “death of the State” was attributed to prevalently exogenous
factors, in the 1930s the emphasis falls on the “crisis of authority” of the tradi-
tional ruling classes, made even more serious by the incapacity of the subal-
tern classes to indicate a way out. In a note dating from December 1930, Grams-
ci calls attention to the changed behavior of important European intellectuals
before the nascent society of the masses. He affirms: “Today, a phenomenon
similar to that of the separation between the ‘spiritual’ and ‘temporal’ in the
Middle Ages has occurred in the modern world: a much more complex
phenomenon – he adds – than that of the past, more complex than modern
life”. This has, as a consequence, the loss of a fundamental contribution to the
development of hegemony, as much as for the ruling classes as for the subal-
tern classes:
regressive and conservative social groupings are shrinking back more and
more to their initial economic-corporative phase, while progressive and
innovative groupings are still in their initial phase – which is, precisely,
the economic-corporative phase. The traditional intellectuals are detach-
ing themselves from the social grouping to which they have hitherto giv-
en the highest, most comprehensive form and hence the most extensive
and complete consciousness of the modern state. Their detachment is in
fact an act of incalculable historical significance; they are signaling and
sanctioning the crisis of the state in its decisive form.8
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Crisis of European Civilization 33
The shot is aimed at Benedetto Croce, who in his speech given at the World
Congress of Philosophy at Oxford, had denounced “a certain weakening and
mental fading” caused by the war, heaping everything in to the same bundle:
futurism and neoclassicism, imperialism and nationalism, “Marxist socialism,
statism which heralds itself as ‘ethical’, the revival of the Catholic and clerical”
(the reference is to the Concordat).9 Gramsci urges: “Today, the ‘spiritual’ that
is detaching itself from the ‘temporal’ and setting itself apart is something dis-
organic, decentered, an unstable scattering of great cultural personalities,
‘without a Pope’ and without territory”.10
Croce, appeared to Gramsci to be moved by the intention of drawing up the
“political manifesto for an international union of the great intellectuals of all
countries, especially the Europeans”, and he intuited “that this might become
an important party and play a significant role”;11 thus, in the Quaderno 10
(“Notebook 10”) he defines Croce as the most effective “ideologist” of a “passive
revolution” aimed at stopping the rise of the popular classes in Europe.12 The
crisis of European civilization is summarized then by the “disintegration of the
modern State”, that placed on the historical-political field, could give rise to
different solutions, provided that old and new “social groupings” know how to
lay the base of a new civilization. These can emerge from the dialectic between
Europe and America that Gramsci considers very differently from ten years
before, from the creation of a “European union” and lastly from a new direction
of the international communist movement.
The rejection of anti-Americanism is widespread in the Prison Notebooks,
where Gramsci judges Taylorism and Fordism as the vehicles of a more ad-
vanced industrial capitalism than that of Europe – more democratic and above
all destined to accelerate the creation of “planned economy”.13 Arguing with
Luigi Pirandello, who had judged the spreading of “Americanism” as dissonant
against European custom “like the make-up on the face of an old prostitute”,
Gramsci asks himself
9 Gramsci was looking at the published text in the dossier of “La Critica” from November 20,
1930 with the title Antistoricismo (401–409).
10 PN3: 9 (Q 6, § 10: 691).
11 PN3: 8 (Q 6, § 10: 690).
12 Cf. spn: 118–120 (Q 10, § 9: 1227–1229). On the concept of passive revolution cf. Vacca 2017:
chapter ii.
13 spn: 279–280 (Q 22, § 1: 2139–2140).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
34 Vacca
This would have happened anyway, though only slowly. In the immediate
perspective it is presented as a repercussion of American super-power. In
other words, whether we are undergoing a transformation of the material
bases of European civilization, which in the long run (though not all that
long, since in the contemporary period everything happens much faster
than in the pas ages) will bring about the overthrow of the existing forms
of civilization and the forced birth of a new.14
it is not from the social groups “condemned” by the new order that recon-
struction is to be expected, but from those on whom is imposed the bur-
den of creating with their own suffering the material bases of the new
order. It is they who “must” find for themselves an “original”, and not
Americanised, system of living to turn into “freedom” what today is
“necessity”.15
These statements take us back to the way in which Gramsci rethinks the future
prospects of Communism, once the myth of “worldwide revolution” fades.16 In
concrete terms, he advocates the reorientation of international communism
based on a realistic forecast of the possibilities that, driven by the unification
of the world, can prevail over the “crisis”. In this way he hopes for a “national-
ization” of the communist parties with the aim of contributing to the recon-
struction of a new world unity.17 Gramsci’s prediction is that the unification of
14 spn: 317 (Q 22, § 15: 2178–2179). Gramsci commented on the Pirandello text in an inter-
view with Corrado Alvaro published in “L’Italia letteraria”, April 14th, 1929.
15 Ibid.
16 A theme that I cannot deal with here. Cf. Vacca 2017: chapter i.
17 spn: 241 (Q 14, § 68: 1729): “A class that is international in character has – in as much as it
guides social strata which are narrowly national (intellectuals), and indeed frequently
even less than national: particularistic and municipalistic (the peasants) – to ‘nationalise’
itself in a certain sense. Moreover, this sense is not a very narrow one either, since before
the conditions can be created for an economy that follows a world plan, it is necessary to
pass through multiple phases in which the regional combinations (of groups of nations)
may be of various kind” (July 1933).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Crisis of European Civilization 35
the human race might move forward step by step through the “regionalization”
of the world economy; and his aim is that the Communist movement redefines
its mission, becoming the creator of a “type of modern cosmopolitanism”. Ac-
cording to Gramsci, the “regionalization” of the world economy is a solid out-
look and can make decisive strides in Europe:
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
36 Vacca
In the first draft of the quoted passage dated November 1932, Gramsci had used
the concept of “cosmopolitanism” and that of “internationalism” indifferent-
ly.21 In the next draft he abandons the second term definitively, opting for the
notion of “modern cosmopolitanism”. His analysis then culminates in propos-
ing the “nationalization” of the Italian Communist Party in order to “collabo-
rate in the economic rebuilding of the world in a unified way”. The remodeling
of the national function of the working classes into a neo-cosmopolitan per-
spective, passing through the foreseeable supranational stages, projects
Gramsci beyond the intellectual and political horizon of the 1930s.
Bibliography
20 CW: 246–247 (Q 19, § 5: 1988). This reflection immediately precedes a note dedicated to
confuting the justification of the colonial politics of fascism that was searching for inter-
national legitimization citing overpopulation as cause of Italy’s inferiority. Gramsci re-
plied that the “relative poverty” of the Italian people was not derived from the demo-
graphic composition but from the unavailability of the “dominant economic class” to
rationalize the production of the “international wealth” (fspn: 237–239; Q 19, § 6:
1989–1991).
21 Cf. fspn: 238–239 (Q 19, § 6: 1990–1991).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Crisis of European Civilization 37
spn: Hoare, Q., Nowell-Smith, G. (eds.) (1971), Selection from the Prison Notebooks (New
York: International Publishers).
Other Works
Vacca, G. (2017), Modernità alternative. Il Novecento di Antonio Gramsci (Torino:
Einaudi).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 4
In the work program that Gramsci outlined starting from March 1929, one of
the proposed aims was to add to the development of a theory of history and
historiography.1 His intention was to liberate Marxism from a theory of histori-
cal time that was rigid and dominated by the logic of “before-after”: a concept
of time as a homogenous and absolute reality which develops outside of us –
outside of our own will.
The need to reinvent the Marxist theory of history springs from the matur-
ing of cultural orientation (in the post-war period after wwi), which tried to
consider the discontinuity that the war had produced. The conviction that his-
tory proceeds “towards the best” begins to deteriorate. The war itself is a frac-
turing element of history: a dramatic interruption of Time that requires the
reworking of new interpretive categories. This is the negation of every notion
of linearity and rationality in history. It is the affirmation of a temporality with-
out direction – without sense – completely against Newton’s concept of “abso-
lute” time, measured by clocks.
Right in front of him, Gramsci has Croce and not the Croce of Teoria e storia
della storiografia (“Theory and History of Historiography”) where the presence
of “historical naturalism” is still strongly felt (a conception of history marked
by “before-after”), but the Croce that founded a transcendental theory (or eth-
ic) of freedom. He has Croce “the boss of revisionism” staring him in the face so
to speak, as well as being the inspiring force of Bernstein’s Marxism.2 This
obliges him to make a close comparison with the theory of value and, more
generally, with the concept of historical time.
Through Croce, Gramsci tackles, above all, the themes that European cul-
ture was facing in order to rework the interpretative categories of its own time.
1 Cf. Gramsci 1994: 256, Gramsci to Tatiana, 25 March 1929 (LT: 333).
2 That fact that Croce had influenced Bernstein’s research is documented in the letter written
by Sorel to Croce dated September 9, 1899, where he writes: “Bernstein has just written me,
that he indicated in ‘Neue Zeit’ n. 46 that he had been inspired, in a certain way, by your
work” (Sorel 1980: 86).
He confronts the culture of crisis (the finis Europae) that reflects on the decline
of the liberal age, its euro-centric and “Enlightenment” ideology. It is actually
difficult to isolate Gramsci from the debate that developed around the “Euro-
pean crisis of conscience” during the 1920s and 1930s. There are many paths
through which the European philosophical conscience notices that there is no
“history in movement”: a history that develops according to natural laws, that
history does not have its own “immanent logic” and that it is no longer possible
to follow a calm narration of the progressive historical becoming as was fol-
lowed by Ranke or the “early” Meinecke.
There are, however, two moments that explicitly illustrate the changing ho-
rizon of European culture. These are: (a) the debate between Cassirer and Hei-
degger regarding “Kant’s legacy” that took place in Davos in the spring of 1929
(we will return to this later); (b) the lessons held by Kojéve on Hegel’s Phänom-
enologie des Geistes (“Phenomenology of Spirit”), where the theme is the defi-
nition of freedom as the negation of historical determination and, thus, the
positivity of the negative. Gramsci ignores both the first and second moments,
but it is with this “culture of crisis” that he makes an account, when, through
the comment of the conference held by Croce at Oxford in September of 1930,
he describes the process that brings the intellectuals to the point of separating
from the national state in order to assume a supra-national function.3 He sees
all the drama of this separation of the “spiritual” from the “temporal”. And in
this he sees the “disintegration of the modern state” or, more precisely, that
type of administrative and monarchic state structured on the foundation of
political-military and economic control of a determined territory. It is, though,
that process of separation from the intellectuals “from the social grouping to
which they had previously given the highest and most comprehensive form”
that breaks the temporality of modern history and gives birth to the “culture of
crisis”: a culture now deprived of its foundations (the Homeland, the People,
Tradition).
To the necessity of overcoming the “Newtonian” concept of historical time –
the understanding of time as a progressive accumulation of knowledge, re-
sources and civil achievements – Gramsci arrives at another way: the analysis
of Americanism and Fordism.
In an annotation found in Quaderno 10 (“Notebook 10”), Gramsci tells us
that, in order to fight “the law of the falling rate of profit”, Ford “had to get out
of the strictly industrial field of production to organize the transportation and
distribution of his goods”.4 In this way, he changed the relationship between
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
40 Montanari
the spheres of production and consumption. And it is starting from the change
of this relationship that a mass society is created, or more precisely, a democ-
racy of consumption: a society where access to consumption by the subaltern
classes becomes one of the principle criteria for the organization of society.
Inside such a social form, the conflictual participation of the working class in
the government of capitalistic development is plausible and fully justifiable.
But the most relevant fact (and that is why it is so important for the definition
of a theory of history) is that, with the changing relationship between produc-
tion and consumption, the characters of the principal social figures also
change. New and unexpected social figures are formed and grow in this new
environment. Productive activity incorporates and attracts increasingly more
refined forms of knowledge and the relationship between work time and free
time changes to the point that even “free time” (or non-work time) becomes
the moment of the total reproduction of values. The reductio ad unum of the
processing times of goods becomes very unlikely: their measurability accord-
ing to absolute time becomes improbable. It is the same as David Ricardo’s
idea of working time as a measure of the value of the goods to be considered.
Ricardo could imagine measuring the value of goods on the basis of the amount
of work time it took to create them, because it presupposed the existence of
absolute and continuous time. But the multiplication of different types of con-
crete work and the growing diversification of knowledge embedded in them
makes them hardly traceable only to the goods-labor force delivered in the last
phase of the production process. The productive abstract work of value identi-
fies with the entire system of knowledge and with work as together. On the
contrary, it is the different quality and types of knowledge incorporated in the
production process that enhances goods in a differentiated. The result is a de-
cline in the so-called “centrality of the working class” and its “revolutionary”
function.
Changing the relationship between production and consumption and exit-
ing “from the strictly industrial field of production”, one could say that Ford
re-unified capital and knowledge and reduced the role and social impact of
factory work. If the formula of the tendential decline of the rate of profit (pv/
c+v) says that profit decreases with the growth of constant capital, Ford found
the way to contextually devalue the variable capital, in way that the total value
of this formula would remain unchanged. The formula of “tendential decline”
presupposes that variable capital remain invariable with the growth of the
constant capital, but it is exactly this that does not occur because the incorpo-
ration of knowledge into production (establishing a stronger unity between
capital and knowledge or, between “bourgeois” and “intellectuals”) tends to
“devalue” the function of work in the final phase of production and, at the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Notes on Gramsci’s Theory of History 41
same time, render the reproduction of the work force – in virtue of the over-
abundance of goods produced – less onerous for the capital.
What happens, then, is that with Fordism, the value of work time tends to
decrease. And with this decrease, the same centrality of the work time in the
underlining of social processes of accumulation of riches declines. The percep-
tion of the forms of becoming changes; both the perception and the concept of
time change. A new theory of historical becoming becomes indispensable. It is
not by chance that in Quaderno 10 (“Notebook 10”) Gramsci’s notes on Croce
intertwine with those on Ricardo and the notes on the theory of history with
the notes on the theory of value. Ricardo, in fact, is thought of more as a phi-
losopher than as an economist, because, in order to conceptualize work time
in new ways as a measure of labor means to conceptualize the same historical
time in a new way.
In European culture between the two World Wars, the image of absolute
time – homogenous and continuous – is broken (an idea that can be traced to
Ricardo and Newton). It is the sign of the decline of Europe’s faith in itself and
its own history lived and thought of as the journey of the human race towards a
world liberated from darkness – as a progressive “enlightening” or as an unstop-
pable process of the rationalization of human life. One must read Quaderno 10
(“Notebook 10” – the criticism of “the religion of freedom”) and Quaderno 11
(“Notebook 11” – the criticism of historical determinism-naturalism) having
clearly in mind that in these are expressed the awareness that Americanism
had changed the structure of time and that after the Great War, such a struc-
tural change had been intertwined with the crisis of the European historical
conscience. At the center of a new theory of history, there must be then the
idea of a passage from absolute time to “relative” time: from the linearity and
progression of time to an image of time as discontinuous and inhomogeneous
form.
From this point, originates Bukharin’s criticism of “historical materialism”.
A criticism that has two focal points:
a) the concept of objective reality and therefore of the predictability of his-
torical becoming;
b) the idea of the translatability scientific languages.
From the pages that Gramsci dedicates to the criticism of Bukharin’s historical
materialism in Quaderno 11 (“Notebook 11”), clearly emerges that for him “ob-
jective” means humanly objective. “Man – he writes – knows objectively in so
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
42 Montanari
far as knowledge is real for the whole human race historically unified in a single
unitary cultural system. […] There exists therefore a struggle for objectivity […]
and this struggle is the same as the struggle for the cultural unification of the
uman race”.5 The objective knowledge of “reality” (that which is historical or
“natural” and is external to us) is connected to our subjectivity and to our ca-
pacity to communicate with others, through a formal and linguistic system,
which is our perception of reality; the very idea that an external world inde-
pendent from our capacity to formulate cognitive models (knowledge, inter-
pretations, languages) is negated. Objectivity exists in the possibility to com-
municate and therefore to translate logical-linguistic representations into
other languages (the paradigm or algorithm) of the “object of knowledge” that
we construct.
This concept of objectivity excludes the idea that human appropriation of
nature and historical becoming can be indicated by “natural laws” that are pre-
existent to human intentionality. These laws are none other than cognitive
models that enable us to give form and order to the world which surrounds us.
In any case, between our knowledge and our “inner reality” (between the “ob-
ject of knowledge” and the “object in oneself”) there is no difference. It follows
that the two terms of the man-nature relationship (or individual-historical
sphere) reciprocally imply each other. In this relationship, there is nothing that
transcends human intentionality: there is no “nature” or “historical movement”
that have their own temporality and existence beyond knowledge and human
creations. For this reason, one can say that there is nothing mechanical or au-
tomatic in historical becoming. There is nothing “in nature” conceivable as an
absolutely transcendent reality or as an elusive “in one self” with respect to the
practical-cognitive intentionality of humankind.
It is this particular vision of “objectivity” that brings us to the Davos debate
between Cassirer and Heidegger.6 Two different visions of philosophy (and of
the history of philosophy) clash in Davos. A difference that Heidegger makes
explicit, asking the question: “to what extent does philosophy have the task of
freeing ourselves from anguish? Or does it not have the task of radically deliv-
ering the man to it?”.7 The discussion is about Kant. But in the background is
the reading of the crisis of European consciousness. A crisis that, for Heidegger,
indicates the impossibility of man-entity to produce knowledge that per-
mits him to transcend his own finiteness and autonomously handle his own
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Notes on Gramsci’s Theory of History 43
istorical destiny. For Cassirer, it is a crisis that fails to discuss the fundamental
h
principal of Western cultural tradition: the idea that human reason possesses
all the potential to produce knowledge and symbolic forms as well as to govern
his own existence and plan his own future.
What does Heidegger claim at Davos? He affirms that, in the passage from
the first to the second edition of Critique of Pure Reason, Kant theorizes in the
face of the finiteness of man and human knowledge and turns to more accept-
able questions for traditional metaphysics. For this reason, Kant would have
muted the theme of “transcendental imagination” (or “faculty of imagination”)
and would have accepted the finiteness of being and its imperfect capacities
for producing knowledge. He definitely would have accepted to subordinate
“being” to the unspeakable and absolute otherness of being. He would have
resized and closed “being” in its finiteness – in its “being in time”.
Against this interpretation, Cassirer negates Kant’s recession on more or-
thodox and traditional positions and instead affirms that in the Kantian reflec-
tion the “transcendental imagination” (the capacity to imagine and construct
objects of knowledge and/or to produce symbolic forms) assumes a central
function, signaling the passage – realized in the Kritik der praktischen Vernunft
(“Critique of Practical Reason”) – of the search for formal conditions for the
production of knowledge defined as “transcendental freedom” as the capacity
to imagine a “must be”. Cassirer deduces being to its finiteness (to its determi-
nation in space and time) and makes “transcendental freedom” the capacity to
break the determinations of “absolute time”; where Heidegger had reduced
freedom of “being” to the interrogation of the Being.
In Cassirer’s reading of Kant, the idea of objectivity as “humanly objective”
or of knowledge as imagination and as a construction of an “object of knowl-
edge” recurs. The criticism of every naturalism and/or historical determinism
also recurs. “Reality” (both historical and natural) is seen as constructed by our
transcendent faculty of imagining the object of knowledge, as well as by our
faculty of giving material existence to that “must be” that our transcenden-
tal imagination (or cognitive faculty) has allowed us to construct. According
to Cassirer, the fundamental problem of Kant is not the relationship between
Being and Time but between Being and Must Be. Fundamentally, if for Hei-
degger the constitutive element of being is Time (it is thrown into Time; over-
determined by time, dominated and dissolved in absolute Time), for Cassirer
time is subordinate, articulated by our transcendental freedom; by our capac-
ity to construct symbolic forms (languages, knowledge, culture, institutions). In
this way, Heidegger appears to be a pure determinist: nothing happens unless
it was predetermined; nothing happens that was not already placed in abso-
lute, linear and homogeneous temporality that transcends and overwhelms
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
44 Montanari
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Notes on Gramsci’s Theory of History 45
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
46 Montanari
Bibliography
Other Works
Cassirer, E., Heidegger, M. (1990), Disputa sull’eredità kantiana. Due documenti (1928 e
1931) (Milano: Unicopli).
Heidegger, M. (1981), Kant e il problema della metafisica (Bari: Laterza).
Racinaro, R. (1976), Introduzione, in Adler, M., Causalità e teleologia nella disputa sulla
scienza (Bari: De Donato).
Sorel, G. (1980), Lettere a Benedetto Croce (Bari: De Donato).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 5
To speak of “layers of history” in Gramsci, or, in the terms I have given to the
problem in recent years, of “plural temporality”, means confronting one of the
most powerful readings of Gramsci: Althusser’s reading in L’objet du “Capital”
(“The Object of ‘Capital’”), where Gramsci plays the paradigmatic role of abso-
lute historicism, whose fundamental error consists in allowing Marxist history
to lapse into an ideological concept of history that is dominated by the catego-
ries of continuity and contemporaneity, thus flattening the plurality of social
levels into a uniform and homogenous present.1 Of course, Althusser’s reading
of Gramsci has solicited numerous reactions. Among these, two worth remem-
bering are Portantiero’s Los usos de Gramsci,2 and Thomas’ The Gramscian
Moment,3 which have as a common denominator the centrality of the concept
of “conjuncture”. Their critique of Althusser is thus carried out by installing the
concept of “conjuncture” (understood as the intertwining of temporality) at
the heart of Gramscian thought. Whereas the contemporaneity of the present
is what for Althusser renders politics unthinkable as a necessary expression of
that present, it is precisely this intertwining of temporalities that opens onto a
conception of politics as intervention in the conjuncture. In both cases, how-
ever, the concept of “conjuncture” which is wielded as a response to Althusser’s
criticism is precisely an Althusserian one, albeit nuanced, in Portaniero’s case
by the reference to Marx’s 1857 Einleitung, and in Thomas’ by the reference to
Derrida’s Spectres de Marx (“Specters of Marx”). For both authors, “conjunc-
ture” does not signify a superficial variation of a fundamental structural invari-
ance, but rather articulation: a complex intertwining of temporality. On the
basis of these suggestions, it is necessary to return to Gramsci’s text in order to
measure the plausibility of a reading which poses the concept of a multiplicity
of temporality at the center of his thought.
First, however, it will be necessary to consider some passages of Gramscian
thought which explicitly move in the opposite direction, namely, in the direc-
tion of a unilinear, stagist, and progressive history. The influence of the 1859
Vorwort (“Preface”) that Gramsci translated while in prison4 plays a key role in
these texts. This text is extremely important within Marx’s entire theoretical
output, setting out the fundamental concepts of historical materialism (pro-
ductive forces, relations of production, base, superstructure, revolution, and
mode of production) in an extremely concise way. Furthermore, Marx speaks
openly of “progressive Epochen”,5 miming en matérialiste the sequence of
Hegelian kingdoms of spirit. Just as it is in the Manifest der Kommunistischen
Partei (“The Communist Manifesto”) – another text whose first chapter Grams-
ci translated in prison – revolution is the effect of the contradiction between
productive forces and relations of production, and just like the Manifest, Marx
uses the metaphor of pregnancy in order to explain the formation of a society
within the one that precedes it.6 However, two clauses are added which have
the function of explaining the great defeats of 1848, which once again put the
idea of revolution on the agenda in the moment of an ebb:
no social order is ever destroyed before all the productive forces for which
it is sufficient have been developed and new superior relations of produc-
tion never replace older ones before the material conditions for their ex-
istence have matured within the framework of the old society. Mankind
thus inevitably sets itself only such tasks as it is able to solve, since closer
examination will always show that the problem itself arises only when
the material conditions for its solution are already present or at least in
the course of formation.7
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Layers of History and THE Politics in Gramsci 49
of which the necessary and sufficient solutions do not yet e xist” […] and
2) that “no society perishes until it has first developed all the forms of life
implicit in its internal relations”.9
For Gramsci, Marx’s arguments become “the two principles of historical mate-
rialism” whose dialectical mediation resides in the concept of “permanent
revolution”.10 Not only that, but as Gramsci maintains in Q 15, § 17, the concept
of “passive revolution” is also derived from these principles:
9 PN2: 177 (Q 4, § 38: 455). As Frosini notes, Gramsci recalls and cites this passage in several
other places in the Quaderni del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”): PN3: 158 (Q 7, § 4: 855); PN3:
171 (Q 7, § 20: 869); PN3: 346 (Q 8, § 195: 1057); spn: 367 (Q 10ii, § 6: 1244); spn: 432 (Q 11, §
22: 1422); spn: 177 (Q 13, § 17: 1579); spn: 106 (Q 15, § 17: 1774).
10 PN2: 178 (Q 4, § 38: 456–457).
11 spn: 106 (Q 15, § 17: 1774).
12 spn: 106–107 (Q 15, § 17: 1774).
13 Althusser 1978: 47.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
50 Morfino
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Layers of History and THE Politics in Gramsci 51
witches or the minor intellectual soured by his own stupidity and inabil-
ity to act)? Or, on the other hand, is it better to work out consciously and
critically one’s own conception of the world and thus […] take an active
part in the creation of the history of the world, be one’s own guide, refus-
ing to accept passively and supinely from outside the moulding of one’s
personality?16
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
52 Morfino
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Layers of History and THE Politics in Gramsci 53
In Q 27, we then find some interesting reflections on folklore that Gramsci pro-
poses to study as “a ‘conceptions of the world and life’ implicit to a large extent
in determinate (in time and space) strata of society and in opposition […] to
‘official’ conceptions of the world (or, in a broader sense, the conceptions of
the cultured parts of historically determinate societies) that have succeeded
one another in the in historical process”.21 He adds:
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
54 Morfino
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Layers of History and THE Politics in Gramsci 55
Bibliography
Other Works
Althusser, L. (1978), Que faire? (Unpublished mss – Imec archive, ALT2.
A26-05.06/07).
Althusser, L. (2015), The Object of Capital, in Althusser, L., Balibar, É., Establet, R., Mach-
erey, P., Rancière, J., Reading Capital: The Complete Edition (London: Verso),
pp. 215–356.
Frosini, F. (2009), Prefazione del ‘59, in Liguori, G., Voza, P., Dizionario gramsciano 1926–
1937 (Roma: Carocci).
Marx, K., Engels, F. (1959), Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei, in Marx, K., Engels, F.,
Werke (Berlin: Dietz), Bd. 4.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
56 Morfino
Marx, K. (1962), Das Kapital, in Marx, K., Engels, F., Werke (Berlin: Dietz), Bd. 23.
Marx, K. (1974), Vorwort, to Zur Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie, in Marx, K., Engels, F.,
Werke (Berlin: Dietz), Bd. 13.
Portantiero, J.C. (1981), Los usos de Gramsci (México D.F.: Folios Ediciones).
Thomas, P. (2009), The Gramscian Moment (Boston-Leiden: Brill).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Part 3
Communism
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 6
The connecting thread of this contribution is the following question: what are
the distinctive features of the way Gramsci discusses Marx’s thought? And in
which traits does his approach differ from the ones of the many thinkers and
political leaders that, in the twentieth century, accorded to Marx a central
place in their reflections?
The criticisms Gramsci leveled at Marx – that in the fifties Togliatti deemed
as “frankly incorrect”3 – enabled nonetheless Gramsci to approach Marxism
with intellectual freedom: it was unproductive, he thought, to fuel sterile argu-
ments on what is or is not Marxism (“Marxists” and “Marxist” are terms that are
“worn as thin as coins that have passed through too many hands”)4 and in any
case, as he wrote in a famous passage, “Marx is not a Messiah who left a string
of parables laden with categorical imperatives and absolute, unquestionable
norms outside the categories of time and space”.5
Gramsci’s critique of the reduction of Marxism to a positivistic and deter-
ministic doctrine, however, is not only the expression of a heightened cultural
awareness, nourished by the best of the idealistic culture of the nineteenth
and twentieth century; it is also directly linked to political aims. Lenin’s revolu-
tion appeared as a hasty and utopist endeavor to the followers of evolutionary
Marxism, for whom history “non facit saltus” (“does not make jumps”) and the
actualization of communism could only happen through the prior passage
through the purgatory of capitalistic industrialization.
The criticism of the evolutionary corruption of historical materialism is not
pure philosophical analysis; on the contrary, it is also a clear statement of the
possibility and achievability of revolution. It is in considering the October Rev-
olution that Gramsci grasps the weakness of historical materialism when re-
duced to an evolutionary schema. The Marxian doctrine, as Gramsci writes in
an essay titled Utopia, teaches that, “political constitutions are necessarily de-
pendent on economic structure, on forms of production and exchange”.6 If we
take this statement in a mechanical way, then we can also maintain that, “Len-
in is a utopian”, and that, “the unfortunate Russian proletarians are prey to an
utterly utopian illusion, so that a terrible awakening implacably awaits them”.7
But this is not the case, Gramsci writes, and the doctrine must be understood
in a much more elaborate way.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
GRAMSCI’S ANTIDOGMATIC READING OF MARX 61
Those who try to harness history in their preconceived schemas do not under-
stand that history is a “free development – the birth and free integration of free
energies –, which is quite different from natural evolution, just as man and
human associations are different from molecules and molecular aggregates”.9
“Freedom is the inner force in history, exploding every pre-established
schema”.10 Gramsci, in stating these points, finds himself very close to Croce.
He is indeed in good company when criticizing those who use historical
materialism as a comprehensive explanatory schema. Engels had repeatedly
insisted on this point, and his views had later been radicalized by Croce, who
had claimed that the materialistic conception of history was neither a theory
nor a reservoir of predictions; rather, it was only a guideline for historians to
follow. Gramsci, however, did not only aim at understanding complicated his-
torical processes in a more flexible way; he also aimed at assigning a greater
importance to the role of free intellectual activity, to the men who act histori-
cally as “they have a mind, […] they suffer, understand, rejoice, desire and
reject”.11
In the later development of his thought, Gramsci will reconsider this em-
phasis on the creative role of free intellectual activity. Nonetheless, he will
keep himself faithful, over time, to some elements of this first encounter with
Marx: the refusal of dogmatizing Marx’s theories, the criticism of positivistic
degenerations (perhaps, later, attributed more to the followers of Marx than to
Marx himself), and the need to rethink historical materialism so as to over-
come the subordination of intellectual work, and of the active and creative
role of historical subjects, to economic and material forces.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
62 Petrucciani
retracing this discussion, we need however to focus our attention on the ques-
tion of method, or, put more simply, on how Gramsci approaches, and thinks
one should approach, Marx’s texts. From this perspective, the enormous differ-
ence between Gramsci’s approach and fideistic or dogmatic Marxism becomes
immediately apparent.
Gramsci’s awareness of the need of a historically and philologically rigorous
method constitutes the first relevant difference between the two approaches.
This awareness was constitutively part of Gramsci’s intellectual formation, as
he had a strong academic background (although he did not complete his
degree).
If one wishes to study the birth of a conception of the world which has
never been systematically expounded by its founder, some preliminary
detailed philological work has to be done. This has to be carried out with
the most scrupulous accuracy, scientific honesty and intellectual loyalty
and without any preconceptions, apriorism or parti pris.12
It makes no sense, for Gramsci, to approach Marx’s writings without the ut-
most critical rigor: one must carefully distinguish between the works published
by the author himself, those which remained unpublished, and “those which
were published by a friend or disciple, but not without revisions, rewritings,
cuts, etc., or in other words not without the active intervention of a publisher
or editor. It is clear that the content of posthumous works has to be taken with
great discretion and caution”, as it cannot be excluded “the possibility that
these works, particularly if they have been a long time in the making and if the
author never decided to finish them, might have been repudiated or deemed
unsatisfactory in whole or in part by the author”.13
But this is not all. Besides the invitation, when reading Marx, to practice all
the philological rigor required for approaching the works of a great thinker,
Gramsci adds another fundamental methodological warning (which gets him
closer to the approach that will be typical of the so-called “Western Marxism”):
Marx and Engels cannot be considered as they were one and the same, because
“the second is not the first”. It is therefore problematic the fact that (since the
end of the nineteenth century) “[Engels’s] expositions, some of which are rela-
tively systematic”, for example the Antidühring, “have […] been given a position
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
GRAMSCI’S ANTIDOGMATIC READING OF MARX 63
in the front rank as an authentic source, and indeed as the only authentic
source”.14
There is also a second relevant aspect in the way Gramsci approaches Marx-
ism: he highlights how a thought whose aim is to transform the consciousness
and the way of thinking of the less cultured masses, easily ends up resorting to
simplified formulas that betray its authentic content. This was true for the
epigones of Marx, but also for Marx himself.
According to Gramsci, the metaphor according to which the economy con-
stitutes the “anatomy” of civil society is ultimately misleading, but the use of
this metaphor is justified by its ability to speak to those who would find philo-
sophical language inaccessible. However, “the philosophy of praxis, in setting
itself the task of the intellectual and moral reform of culturally backward so-
cial strata, has recourse to metaphors that at times are ‘crude and violent’ in
their popularity”,15 and therefore one needs to interpret it without being mis-
led by these rhetorically effective simplifications.
Simplifications of this kind can be found in Marx, but most of all in his epig-
ones, who show a tendency to “mythicize” the theoretical contents elaborated
by their master (a tendency also motivated by the need to invigorate combat-
iveness and commitment):
But we need to highlight a third aspect of the way Gramsci approaches Marx’s
works, also because this is a point on which many commentators still insist
today: Gramsci’s awareness of the fact that, in Marx, “theoretical and practical
activity are indissolubly intertwined”17 and that, for this reason, in reading his
works one must take into account the contingent political commitment
motivating them (or the “conjuncture”, as today those who refer themselves to
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
64 Petrucciani
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
GRAMSCI’S ANTIDOGMATIC READING OF MARX 65
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
66 Petrucciani
phase, Gramsci writes, is problematic and “cautious”, very different from how
he will be when discussing Marx’s works in later writings. Moreover, in a sar-
castic but fairly sympathetic way, Gramsci overturns the idea of the interpre-
tive canon against Croce himself: first of all, he gives Croce the credit for having
“drawn attention to the study of the factors of culture and ideas as elements of
political domination, to the function of the great intellectuals in state life, to
the moment of hegemony and consent as the necessary form of the concrete
historical bloc”.24 After having sung him high praise, however, Gramsci turns
against Croce the idea of the “canon”, as he writes that, for the philosophy of
praxis, the ethical-political conception of history is “one of the canons of his-
torical interpretation that must always be borne in mind in the study and de-
tailed analysis of history as it unfolds, if the intention is to construct an integral
history rather than partial or extrinsic histories”.25
Hence, just as the first Croce gave credit to Marx for having highlighted the
economic moment, so Gramsci gives credit to Croce for having emphasized
the ethical-political and spiritual moment. To the later Croce, who according
to Gramsci had changed almost all his previous stances, the latter directs in-
stead a harsh critique: of having attributed to Marx, in order to demolish him,
a thesis that did not belong at all to the author of the Manifesto, namely that
superstructures would be “mere appearances and illusions”. This thesis was ab-
solutely extraneous to the young Croce, as well as being, from Gramsci’s point
of view, totally erroneous – since, for the latter, superstructures are an “objec-
tive and operating” reality. And such they were, according to Gramsci, also for
Marx; because it is through them – and here Gramsci broadens to the extreme
the meaning of a famous passage of the Vorwort (“Preface”) of 1859 to Zur Kritik
der politischen Öknomie (“A Contribution to the Critique of Political Econo-
my”) – that individuals and classes “become conscious of their own social be-
ing, their own strength, their own tasks, their own becoming”.26
Leaving aside, however, the emphatic anti-Marxist polemics characterizing,
among Croce’s writings, the ones chronologically closer to the Quaderni del
carcere (“Prison Notebooks”), we can say that Gramsci’s and Croce’s perspec-
tives are not so distant from each other; Gramsci himself goes to show this,
when he observes that the philosophy of praxis does not rule out an “ethico-
political history” at all, since it accords great importance to the moment of
hegemony and of cultural and moral leadership.27
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
GRAMSCI’S ANTIDOGMATIC READING OF MARX 67
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
68 Petrucciani
Bibliography
Other Works
Cospito, G. (2004), Struttura-superstruttura, in Frosini, F., Liguori, G. (eds.), Le parole di
Gramsci (Roma: Carocci).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
GRAMSCI’S ANTIDOGMATIC READING OF MARX 69
Cospito, G. (2009), Struttura, in Liguori, G., Voza, P. (eds.), Dizionario gramsciano 1926–
1937 (Roma: Carocci).
Croce, B. (2001), Materialismo storico ed economia marxistica, in Rascaglia, M., Zoppi,
S. (eds.), Materialismo storico ed economia marxistica (Napoli: Bibliopolis).
Gerratana, V. (1975), Prefazione, in Quaderni del carcere (Torino: Einaudi), i vol.
Marx, K. (1913), A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (Chicago: Charles H.
Kerr and Company).
Togliatti, P. [1958] (1979), Gramsci and Leninism, in Sassoon, D. (ed.), On Gramsci and
Other Writings (London: Lawrence & Wishart).
Tuozzolo, C. (2008), “Marx possibile”. Benedetto Croce teorico marxista 1869–1897 (Mila-
no: Franco Angeli).
Voza, P. (2009), Blocco storico, in Liguori, G., Voza, P. (eds.), Dizionario gramsciano 1926–
1937 (Roma: Carocci).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 7
Guido Liguori
To understand the way in which Antonio Gramsci related to the two Russian
revolutions of 1917, and in particular to the October Revolution, it is necessary
to keep in mind his very particular upbringing.
Already in Sardinia, Gramsci had started to read socialist newspapers and
pamphlets (above all thanks to the influence of his older brother Gennaro, who
was one of the directors of the workers’ union in Cagliari), books and articles
written by the revolutionary Georges Sorel (that influenced him deeply), by
people, like Salvemini, who belonged to the Left (even if he would soon leave
the Socialist Party) and by Antonio Labriola (the first real Italian Marxist).
From the years of his youth in Sardinia, Gramsci was also influenced, per-
haps above all, by the bourgeois culture (opposition to Giolitti and his ideas),
which was the particular field where he was formed. The so-called “Florentine
magazines” like “Il Leonardo” and “La Voce” of Papini and Prezzolini, philoso-
phies such as neo-idealism, pragmatism, and that of Bergson made up a cul-
ture that was almost completely focused on the re-evaluation of the “subject”
against that which had been the dominant philosophy of the second half of
the 1800s and had notably influenced even Marxism and the workers’ move-
ment, with its idea of “objectivism” (epistemological, historical and political):
a vision that still deeply influenced the main currents of the workers’ move-
ment at the beginning of the 1900s.
In 1911, Gramsci moved to Torino to begin his studies at the Faculty of Lit-
erature and Philosophy, thanks to a scholarship that was just enough to sur-
vive on.1 Even before the Great War, he joined the socialist party in Torino.
His Marxism at this time was very particular: because of his cultural forma-
tion, the Marxism of the young Gramsci was against the trend of the time. His
Marxism was subjectivistic, anti-deterministic, anti-economistic, influenced
by neo-idealism and the philosophy of Bergson, mediated in part by Sorel. It
1 Cf. Gramsci 1994: 138, Gramsci to Carlo, September 12th, 1927 (LC2: 117).
was an original but also immature Marxism, centered on (in more than one
passage) the absolute and idealistic supremacy of the will.
In these years, there was no scarcity of important writings with an anti-
deterministic vision, even concerning revolutionary processes. In his 1916
article, Socialismo e cultura (“Socialism and culture”) for example, he put for-
ward a definition of culture as the conquest and valuing of one’s own self and
thus a growth of his own subjectivity.2 It underlined the importance of aware-
ness and of ideas in the processes of change, in the great revolutions. Gramsci
writes:
Starting from the first comments of the February Revolution, Gramsci read the
events in Russia as the revenge of the socialists who had not betrayed the spirit
of the International and who saw a “proletarian revolution”5 in the events of
Petrograd.
He was not completely wrong, as at the beginning of the “first revolution” of
1917, the February Revolution, there had been a workers’ demonstration in
Petrograd as well as the women’s demonstration on March 8th, a day which
corresponded with February 24th in the Julian calendar that was then used in
Russia (14 days behind the Gregorian calendar, used in the West); and, also, the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
72 Liguori
switching of many soldiers to the side of the insurgents (armed peasants) who
instead of shooting rioters, fired at the Tsarist police.
What were the background characteristics of the event, for Gramsci? The
“Russian revolution” for him had “been innocent of Jacobinism”, that is, it “did
not have to crush the majority of the people by the use of violence”.6 (It is no-
table that until 1921 – when his opinion changed on the basis of the work of the
French historian Albert Mathiez, that positively underlines the similarities be-
tween Jacobins and Bolsheviks7 – Gramsci, influenced by Sorel, and ignoring
Lenin and even Marx, was decidedly anti-Jacobin).
For Gramsci, Jacobinism and the Jacobin revolution, were at that time (in
1917), a bourgeois phenomenon: of a minority that “served particular interests,
the interest of its own class”.8 On the other hand, the “Russian revolutionaries”
did not want to substitute one dictatorship for another and – he claimed – they
would have had, through universal suffrage, the support of a huge part of the
“Russian proletariat”, if only they could have expressed themselves freely.
It was a vision that we could say was naive in terms of the revolutionary
process, both for that concerning events in Russia – where the revolutionary
forces were in reality much more internally composite and divided than
Gramsci knew and understood at first –, and in the conviction that universal
suffrage was enough to guarantee the rise of the true will of the proletariat.
Here, Gramsci disregards – contrary to what he would do with great acuity
in his mature writings from prison, but also, partly, in the “Consigli di fabbica”
(factory workers’ councils) period of the journal “L’Ordine Nuovo” (“The New
Order”) and the “biennio rosso” (“Two Red Years”) – the prerequisites of de-
mocracy, from the basically egalitarian elements (in terms of culture, informa-
tion, awareness, freedom from need) that an electoral body should possess to
express themselves without “self-serving ends”.
After a few months, the young socialist will begin the analysis of the internal
distinctions within the great revolutionary event that had archived Tsarist
power, but not the war.
Gramsci’s attention was moving, though not without some understandable
oscillation given the scarcity of information, towards the Bolshevik compo-
nent (a term that was then translated in Italy as “Maximalist”, a category of the
Italian political panorama of the time), identified as the force that did not ac-
cept that the revolution would stop at its bourgeois-democratic stage, and ex-
pected it to continue until the conquest of a socialist society instead: “Lenin
6 Ibid.
7 Cf. Medici 2004: 113 ff.
8 SPW-1: 28 (Gramsci 2017: 35).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci, October Revolution and Its “Translation” in West 73
[…] and his Bolshevik comrades – he wrote – are convinced that socialism can
be achieved at any time. They are nourished on Marxist thought. They are revo-
lutionaries, not evolutionists”.9
Here the polemic is evident against the evolutionism of Kautsky and the
Second International (social-democratic and reformist) represented in Italy by
the moderate socialism of people like Treves and Turati, in the name of that
revolutionary subjectivism that distinguished Gramsci during this period: in
Russia – he added – “the revolution continues”, so that men, all men can be
“the creators of their destiny”.
In the meantime, even before the October Revolution, the enthusiasm for what
had happened in Russia was spreading across Italy and the rest of Europe. The
defeat of Caporetto (which took place in the same days as the capture of the
Winter Palace, between October 24th and November 9th) was just around
the corner, also caused by an increasing amount of criticism against the war
and the inhuman method – that of Cadorna and the other officials on either
side of the trenches – of using soldiers as meat to be slaughtered, with an ease
that also stemmed from a deep-rooted classist attitude.
This same impetus was one of the main causes of the revolution in Russia,
perhaps even the principle one. It is not surprising then, that “do as they do in
Russia” began to be the password that circulated among the popular and sub-
altern classes of a large part of Europe, where the name of “Lenin” was begin-
ning to be largely known and praised.
And Gramsci was no different: the choice is between Kerensky and Lenin,
he wrote in August,10 that is, between the new head of the Russian Provisional
Government formed on August 6th, and the revolutionary leader now being
hunted by the new government’s police and being forced to take refuge in Fin-
land. There he writes Государство и революция (“The State and Revolu-
tion”) in a few weeks until the moment when he must interrupt the draft to
enable his return to Russia to lead the revolution (instead of just theorizing it).
More than a month before the October Revolution, Gramsci warned that
the time was near to decide between liberal revolution and socialist revolu-
tion, measuring “what is the effective force of the socialist revolutionaries and
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
74 Liguori
Between October 24th and 25th according to the Russian calendar (between
November 7th and 8th in the Western calendar), the Winter Palace was occu-
pied and the Soviets (hegemonized by the Bolsheviks) took power.
Gramsci’s comment written at the end of November is famous. For the Sar-
dinian socialist, it was a “revolution against Capital”: Marx’s book, against those
who had given that book and Marxism an economistic and deterministic read-
ing that was “stadial”, in which no socialist revolution would have been possi-
ble in backwards Russia before an adequate development of the “capitalist
stage” of industry and therefore of the Russian working class. Now – wrote
Gramsci – “these maximalists have seized power and established their dicta-
torship, and are creating the socialist framework within which the revolution
will have to settle down”.13
The Marxism of the Bolsheviks was “constructed” by Gramsci in the image
and semblance of his ideas: a historicist Marxism, derived from Hegel and
freed from the slag of positivism. Once again, the will triumphs in Gramsci’s
vision: associated human beings can understand “economic facts, judging
them and adapting them to their will until this becomes the driving force of
the economy and moulds objective reality, which lives and moves and comes
to resemble a current of volcanic lava that can be channeled wherever and in
whatever way the will determines”.14
More than its provocative beginning (the “revolution against Capital” of
Marx), in reality, the article captured one of the deep motivations of the Octo-
ber Revolution: war had made an unprecedented and unexpected event pos-
sible. Marx had “foreseen the foreseeable”, stated the young socialist revolu-
tionary journalist (then only 26 years old), but he could not have foreseen the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci, October Revolution and Its “Translation” in West 75
First World War and its unprecedented character, which “would have aroused
the will of the popular collective in Russia” much faster than normal (“this is
why, under normal conditions – Gramsci added – the canons of Marxist histori-
cal criticism grasp reality”15). He continues: “in Russia the war galvanized the
people’s will. As a result of the sufferings accumulated over three years, their
will became as one almost overnight. Famine was imminent, and hunger,
death from hunger, could claim anyone, could crush tens of millions of men at
one stroke. Mechanically at first, then actively and consciously agter the first
revolution, the people’s will became as one”.16
Today we can affirm that Russia went through its revolution because Lenin
had known how to read the “conjuncture”. He had known how to make “a con-
crete analysis of the concrete situation” (to quote a famous Leninist motto).
Historical events are always individual, politics and history are, for Lenin and
Gramsci, idiographic disciplines: every generalization is a mistake.
5 A Field of Possibilities
The more mature Gramsci would reformulate his vision of the revolutionary
process, arriving at defining it as a relationship of reciprocal influence and
equilibrium between “relationships of force” and revolutionary initiative. From
the October Revolution onwards, in fact, in Gramsci’s writing there begins to
be reasoning and considerations that are more coherent with the Marxist tra-
dition. Gramsci’s Marxism starts to free itself from its idealistic incrustations.
In the article, Il nostro Marx (“Our Marx”), published May 4th, 1918, on the eve
of the centenary of the birth of the German revolutionary, he states that before
Marx, “history was only the domain of ideas” while “with Marx, history contin-
ues to be the domain of the ideas, the spirit, and of the conscious activity of
single or associated individuals”. But, continues Gramsci, thanks to Marx, “the
ideas and the spirit substantiate themselves, losing their arbitrariness” and
“their substance is in economy, in practical activity, in the systems and rela-
tionships of production and exchange”. For this reason, “an idea realizes itself
[…] in that it finds the justification and the way to establish itself in economic
reality”. It follows that, in order to know “what the historical ends of a country,
a society” one must “know first of all what systems and relations of production
and exchange obtain in that country, that society”.17
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
76 Liguori
The vision of the more mature Gramsci will not lose the importance given
to will and subjectivity, but the historical-social reality in the Quaderni del car-
cere (“Prison Notebooks”) will be a field of possibilities, that the objective condi-
tions offer to the subject within which will be determined a certain outcome
rather than another depending on the action and the capabilities of the sub-
ject himself.
Gramsci’s youthful hyper-subjectivism will be surpassed starting from the
new situation that the October Revolution had created and that also reposi-
tioned his vision on a new and more concrete terrain.
It was precisely from Gramsci’s adherence to the international political
movement that was born with the “second Russian revolution”, that his Marx-
ism began to free itself from the idealistic and spiritual incrustations that had
strongly conditioned him in the previous period.
In the following years, Gramsci passes through difficult and crucial experienc-
es. First of all, the “biennio rosso” 1919–1920 (“Two Red Years”) when he became
one of the most unique and important representatives of the “consigli di fab-
brica” (factory workers’ councils) thought in Europe, taking on the leadership
of the movement of the factory councils in Turin and developing an original
concept of self-government for the working classes that was original and also
different from the soviet model in Russia.
The failure of the workers’ movement in Turin, however, opened his eyes to
the complexity and variety of the Italian situation, to the fact that not all of
Italy was like Turin – a modern industrial society, standardized and character-
ized by the “sturdy fortresses and emplacements”18 of “civil society”, as Gramsci
expressed in the Quaderni del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”); but also on the
limits of Italian socialist party that was revolutionary in word but immobile
and confused in reality.
The failure of the workers’ and socialist movement of the “Two Red Years”
also gave birth to the dramatic phase of the Fascist reaction and the historical
defeat suffered by the workers’ movement in Italy. These events provoked a
deep rethinking by Gramsci and induced him to accept Lenin’s teaching on the
conditions of the possibility of a revolution in the West, above all thanks to his
stay in the Soviet capital from June of 1922 until the end of 1923.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci, October Revolution and Its “Translation” in West 77
The lesson that came from Lenin was that of a crisis of capitalism that would
not necessarily immediately turn into a wave of revolution. It was under Len-
in’s influence that Gramsci developed the conviction that the West could not
“do like in Russia” because in the West the “political superstructures” created
by the development of capitalism and by mass society made every possible
revolutionary strategy slower and more complex. Already in 1924, Gramsci had
developed in nuce some of the themes that would be those central to the Quad-
erni del carcere19. The revolution of 1917 needed to be translated into the spe-
cific situation of developed capitalistic societies.
Gramsci therefore arrives at a complete rethinking of his youthful theoreti-
cal baggage. In mature Gramsci, the revolutionary will go side by side with the
most objective knowledge of the situation: a precise social and historical anal-
ysis of the field on which the struggle plays out. Gramsci in prison, arrives at
destroying the morphological difference between East and West, and conse-
quently between war of movement and war of position,20 and comes to the
conclusion that the Russian Revolution had been the last 18th century-style
revolution, the last insurrection-revolution, at least in Europe or in the devel-
oped world.21 In the West, the modern structure of mass society, the new inter-
penetration between state and civil society, the weight and importance of the
mechanisms of the formation of consensus are all factors that bring Gramsci to
a real revolution of the concept of revolution, not only regarding the subjectivis-
tic and idealistic vision of his youthful period, but also regarding the classic
and sometimes stereotyped conception of the Marxist and Leninist tradition.
It is not (as is sometimes argued) because Gramsci emerges from Marxism or
from the revolutionary tradition, with a classically reformist approach. The will
for change does not lose its anchoring in social class, its heart in the economic
world and in social relationships, but sees all the complexity of modern politi-
cal action. It refutes economic conceptions based on the relation between eco-
nomic crisis and revolution; it identifies as fundamental the public and private
structures that form a widespread common sense, and considers it essential to
launch the challenge of conquering the general consensus. In other words, it
underlines the importance of a cultural and ideological reflection that could
offer a new conception of the world and could form a new common sense of
the people.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
78 Liguori
Bibliography
Other Works
Liguori, G. (2015), Teoria e politica nel marxismo di Antonio Gramsci, in Petrucciani, S.
(ed.), Storia del marxismo, vol. 1, Socialdemocrazia, revisionismo, rivoluzione (Roma:
Carocci).
Liguori, G., Voza, P. (eds.) (2009), Dizionario gramsciano 1926–1937 (Roma: Carocci).
Medici, R. (2004), Giacobinismo, in Frosini, F., Liguori, G. (eds.), Le parole di Gramsci
(Roma: Carocci).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 8
Frankreich – “The Civil War in France” – and Kritik des Gothaer Programms –
“Critique of the Gotha Program”) the sequence of process > event is over-
turned, in the way that Marx imagines political events which open the road to
the process of construction in the new social formation, a process which in-
volves “a period of political transition” where the command of the new state is
exercised as “the revolutionary dictatorship of the proletariat”.3
3 mew 19: 28. Cf. mew 4: 481; mew 7: 89; mew 17: 338–339, 342, 349.
4 SPW-1: 34 (Gramsci 1982: 513).
5 SPW-1: 35 (Gramsci 1982: 514).
6 SPW-1: 36 (Gramsci 1982: 515–516).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Transition to Communism 81
Naturally, La rivoluzione contro il “Capitale” was not the only pre-prison text
to deal with the structure of the revolutionary process. Gramsci returns to the
subject in two important articles in particular that appeared within two
months of each other in “Ordine Nuovo” in the summer of 1920. In these arti-
cles he defines the “political power” of the working class as “the defensive orga-
nization and condition of development for a given order in the relations of
production and distribution of wealth”7 (Due rivoluzioni – “Two Revolutions”)
and reiterates that the working class “will achieve its liberation only by passing
through a period of ‘dictatorship’, a period of restrictions, a period character-
ized as a workers’ State”8 (Che cosa intendiamo per “demagogia”? – “What do we
mean by ‘demagogy’?”).
And the mature Gramsci? The Gramsci of the Quaderni (“Prison Note-
books”)? Fashionable today is a vulgar revisionism that aims to rip Gramsci –
especially the imprisoned Gramsci – from the damaged history of 20th century
Communism in order to preserve him in the pantheon of the polite and palat-
able “classics”. A crucial junction in this operation is the pseudo-philology at
the service of the Italian national edition, poised to dismember the body of the
Prison Notebooks in order to inhibit an organic reading; to shatter it by drama-
tizing the question of internal chronology beyond reason (it is strange that the
work of an inmate segregated from the world can no longer be spoken of as a
unified text). But the question of the transition to communism is one that is
not easily tamed. This question is also, for the connections that link it to the
living history of the 20th century (before than to the texts of the top theorists
of revolutionary Marxism), one that ridicules any attempt to pass off the sweet-
ened image of Gramsci the “good democrat”.
The Prison Notebooks deliver a rigorous Leninist theory of the transition to
communism, connected (as is easy to understand) by a series of annotations in
which Gramsci expresses passionately favorable judgments towards the revo-
lutionary experience in progress in the Soviet Union. Let’s consider – with the
necessary speed – at least the principal texts of this theoretical and political
constellation.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
82 Burgio
rocess that (after the conquest of political power by the working class) leads
p
to the construction of a society free from rule:
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Transition to Communism 83
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
84 Burgio
16 Ibid.
17 PN3: 75–76 (Q 6, § 88: 764).
18 Ibid.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Transition to Communism 85
From many pages of the Prison Notebooks emerges the fact that Gramsci’s
theoretical research on the transition to communism intertwines with the
reflection on what happens in these years in the Soviet Union. It is there-
fore worth asking what it represents, or more precisely, how it compares to
the model of the transition to “regulated society” outlined in the Quaderni
del carcere – the ussr between the end of the 1920s and the early 1930s, af-
ter the experience of the nep (New Economic Policy) and the launch of the
first five-year plan. To draft an answer to this question – which goes through
most of the recent critical discussions – it is necessary to study four annota-
tions found in Quaderno 5 (“Notebook 5”), § 127, Quaderno 7 (“Notebook 7”),
§ 43, Quaderno 8 (“Notebook 8”), § 185 and Quaderno 13 (“Notebook 13”),
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
86 Burgio
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Transition to Communism 87
In the end, one could say that Gramsci sees in the Soviet Union at the early
stages (necessarily characterized by the protagonism of coercive power) a real-
ity “in continuous movement” which, precisely by virtue of the use of instru-
ments foreign to bourgeois constitutional law (beyond which, it goes without
saying, because of the inspiring finalities of the Bolshevik revolutionary expe-
rience), conforms to the model of the transition to a “new society” without
classes and free from domination.
Any remaining doubt in this regard is lost when we consider two other texts
that return to these same themes. Gramsci writes that the inaugural phase of
the revolutionary process, inevitably concentrated on the economic dynamic,
will only leave space for a meagre political culture, which will proceed by ne-
cessity with “‘broad outlines’, sketches that could (and should) be changed at
all times in order to be consistent with the structure as it takes shape”.27 Curi-
ously, he concludes:
This, however, did not happen during the period of the communes. In-
stead, culture remained the function of the church; its character was, in-
deed, antieconomic (against the nascent capitalist economy); and its
thrust was to prevent rather than enable the acquisition of hegemony by
the new class. Humanism and the Renaissance were thus reactionary;
they signaled the defeat of the new class, the negation of the economic
world characterized by the new class, etc.28
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
88 Burgio
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Transition to Communism 89
Bibliography
Other Works
Burgio, A. (2003), Gramsci storico. Una lettura dei “Quaderni del carcere” (Roma-Bari:
Laterza).
Burgio, A. (2014), Gramsci. Il sistema in movimento (Roma: DeriveApprodi).
Burgio, A. (2018), Il sogno di una cosa. Per Marx (Roma: DeriveApprodi).
Lenin, V.I. (1974), Staat und Revolution, in Lenin, V.I., Werke, vol. 25 (Berlin: Dietz).
mew: Marx, K., Engels, F., Marx-Engels Werke, 44 vol. (Berlin: Dietz).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Part 4
Hegemony
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 9
figure of the minimal State that monopolizes public goods is thus presented
and this minimal state entrusts the care of the particular interest to the mar-
ket. The moment of the public appears, warns Gramsci, as
The dilation of the distance between private and public, in the name of the
autonomy of the economic calculation, is also the result of a political decision
that designates a particular extension of the relationship between State and
society. Politics is the decision that shortens the gap between State and society
just like politics is also the decision that enlarges the distance between public
and private. Not only liberals, but also Catholics embody an ideological vision
of the relationship between State and society. “They would like to have the in-
terventionist state on their side; failing that, they want a neutral state because
an unfavorable state might support their enemies. In reality, the Catholics
want everything to be in their favor”.2 The State is indifferent or minimal to
others while it is clearly recognizable as a visible hand when it protects certain
interests and values.
Skeptical of the central-bureaucratic State, what is relevant in catholic
thought is the horizontal profile, the relationship supportive neighborhood,
and “the town council was traditionally considered civil society and not state”.3
Civil society becomes the place of exchange and a reticular leading role of as-
sociated worlds: the horizontal link of particularism that creates connections
in an interpenetration between economic-proprietary instances and the cult
of the periphery as a place of communitarian authenticity. A certain combina-
tion of Catholic culture and the exaltation of particularism, Gramsci notes,
1 spn: 261 (Q 26, § 6: 2302). Cf. Poulantzas 1975; Buci-Glucksmann 1976; Carnoy 1984.
2 PN2: 328 (Q 5, § 69: 604). Cf. Bellamy, Schecter 1993.
3 PN1: 215 (Q 1, § 130: 118). Cf. Morera 1990.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: Political Scientist 95
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
96 Prospero
6 spn: 271 (Q 6, § 10: 691). Cf. Tamburrano 1963; Bonetti 1980; Belligni 1981; Martelli 1996; Bella-
my 2013; Rosengarten 2014.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: Political Scientist 97
that the corporate regime might in fact turn out to be a factor of real innova-
tion in the long term. While Americanism implicates the figures of the liberal
state, fascism assumes a closed social and institutional attitude, restrictive to
the point of harnessing competition in order to preserve an authoritarian so-
cial discipline, breaking some basic regularities that seem to pervade the mod-
ern experience.
In the regimes of the masses, the overcoming of the conceptual distinction
between state and society through the one-party government or “bureaucratic
solution” is apparent. For this, the moment of mediation and representation
remains open and not susceptible to mythical solutions. Both change and con-
servation raise the question of political mediation. There exists politics of
management/administration (“this question has to do with the rotation in gov-
ernmental power of different fractions from the same dominant group”) and
politics of change (“the foundation and organization of a new political society,
much less of a new type of civil society”7). Both of these manifestations of poli-
tics lead back to the story of representation and to the institutes of mediation
which seem destined to persist, with adaptations and grafts, until the distinc-
tion between public and private, society and state remains. In the context of a
certain defining oscillation in the use of the principal terms, Gramsci outlines
an open interpretative scheme with three relevant dimensions. The state,
which is not only the state-government that administers the governing force,
but also presents itself as a broad state or community – as a unity with the
characteristics of civil society.
In this sense, the state is not only government or a sanctioning apparatus
that “is commonly understood as the entire state”8 but is also life and society.
In civil society, Gramsci does not only see the signs of economic relationships
but also the typical dynamics of political-cultural character. In the time of the
mobilization of civil society with plural subjects, the State loses its “being for
itself”, which projects it as an abstract dimension of power. It presents an en-
larged political dimension that goes beyond the state. It is a broad layer of civil
society, which goes beyond the economic, to host an organized pluralism. Po-
litical society as state is the law, regulation and the coercive expression of dom-
ination. Civil society, on the other hand, is the way of existing and producing
the objective conditions of living where economic struggles and the conquest
of hegemony are found with the discoveries of politics and culture. Given this
intersection of public and social, Gramsci arrives at the hypothesis that in
statehood, we see actors different than the administration and forms (the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
98 Prospero
arties) and in civil society we do not only trace the footsteps of the economy
p
but also the symbols of subjectivity (parties and unions). In some ways, the
parties introduce social profiles into the political system and impose public
determinations in the private sphere.
Gramsci alludes to a sphere that is larger than the State-administrator of
violence and postulates an opening to the complex superstructure of civil
society.
What we can do, for the moment, is to fix two major superstructural “lev-
els”: the one that can be called “civil society”, that is the ensemble of or-
ganisms commonly called “private”, and that of “political society” or “the
State”. These two levels correspond on the one hand to the function of
“hegemony” which the dominant group exercises throughout society and
on the other hand to that of “direct domination” or command exercised
through the State and “juridical” government.9
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: Political Scientist 99
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
100 Prospero
because the parliamentary group of the strongest party became the “gov-
ernment” or led the government. The fact that, due to parliamentary dis-
integration, the parties have become incapable of carrying out this task
did not cancel the task itself nor did it show a new way towards a solu-
tion: the same thing applies to education and the enhancement of
personalities.16
The crisis of the parliamentary system and of traditional political parties de-
stroys the balancing mechanism of mediation. In the face of the erosion of
political forms, the nostalgic action of mourning the institutional balances
broken by irreversible processes is in vain.
With respect to other organized groups who operate in society and mobilize
themselves in the face of conflict, political parties organize themselves like or-
ganisms that, although established in the social sphere, carry out general tasks
and contribute in the management of the resources of power and coercion.
The ambiguous nature of the political party emerges in this way. As private
organizations, political parties are societies, as government apparatuses, they
are instead like the state or a political society. The party, although it exists in
society, develops public tasks and for this reason it appears to Gramsci as “the
mechanism that carries out in civil society the same function that the state
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: Political Scientist 101
In reality, in certain sense, the “head of state” – that is, the element that
balances the various interests struggling against the predominant but not
absolutely exclusivistic interest – is precisely the “political party”. With
the difference, however, that in terms of traditional constitutional law
the political party juridically neither rules nor governs. It has “de facto
power”, it exercises the hegemonic function, and hence the function of
balancing various interests, in “civil society”; however, “civil society” is in
fact so thoroughly intertwined with political society that all the citizens
fell instead that the party rules and governs.18
After the consolidation of the parties, the changes in the liberal state are not,
according to Gramsci, comprehensible with the traditional models of consti
tutional law anchored in the public-private, legal-factual dualism. The three-
dimensional explanatory diagram sees the interaction between the state
(juridical form, the moment of sovereignty and of organized coercion in a mo-
nopolistic way) civil society (distinct within an area of economy, and in the
levels of action or molecular processes of associative life) and enlarged politi-
cal society (the moment of contention, the competition between many actors
that open channels of intersection between the social and the institutional).
Unions and political parties (that postulate “a strong center of political leader-
ship”) are the components of civil society where Gramsci places that distinc-
tive trait of modernity which separates the functional ambit and abstract from
the particular, while at the same time, demands the presence of the subjects of
pluralism – of actors in a conflict for hegemony that embraces values and in-
terests, economy and cultural politics.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
102 Prospero
In reality, every political movement creates a language of its own, that is,
it participates in the general development of a distinct language, intro-
ducing new terms, enriching existing terms with a new content, creating
metaphors, using historical names to facilitate the comprehension and
the assessment of particular contemporary political situations.19
A political party of the masses does not rest solely on the economic element.
A project in harmony with an epochal change is needed, in the relationship
between the territory of politics (national) and the economic space (global).
Gramsci cautions the “greater autonomy of the national economies from the
economic relations of the world market”.20 This weakening of political sover-
eignty makes it difficult to stage a revolution in a single country, forced to live
with a world economy dominated by trade and by the regime of capital. But also
the fate of the war of position is consigned to a strategic asymmetry between
the profile of sovereignty (limited in the national dimension) and the degree of
interdependence imposed by the elusive dynamics of the world market.
19 PN1: 126 (Q 2, § 43: 31). Cf. Ives 2004; Boothman 2011; Carlucci 2013.
20 spn: 243 (Q 13, § 7: 1566). Cf. Cox 1993; Ayers 2008.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Gramsci: Political Scientist 103
Bibliography
Other Works
Ayers, A.J. (ed.) (2008), Gramsci, Political Economy, and International Relations Theory
(New York: Palgrave Macmillan).
Bellamy, R. (1994), Introduction, in A. Gramsci, Pre-Prison Writings (New York: Cam-
bridge University Press).
Bellamy, R. (2013), Croce, Gramsci, Bobbio and the Italian Political Tradition (Lanham:
Rowman & Littlefield).
Bellamy, R., Schecter, D. (1993), Gramsci and the Italian State (Manchester: Manchester
University Press).
Belligni, S. (1981), Egemonia, in N. Bobbio, N. Matteucci (ed.) Dizionario di politica (To-
rino: Utet).
Bobbio, N. (1978), Stato, governo, società (Torino: Einaudi).
Bobbio, N. (1990), Saggi su Gramsci (Milano: Feltrinelli).
Bonetti, P. (1980), Gramsci e la società liberaldemocratica (Roma-Bari: Laterza).
Boothman, D. (2013), The Sources for Gramsci’s Concept of Hegemony, in Green, M.E.
(ed.), Rethinking Gramsci (London: Routledge).
Buci-Glucksmann, C. (1976), Gramsci e lo Stato (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Carlucci, A. (2013), Gramsci and Languages (Boston-Leiden: Brill).
Carnoy, M. (1984), The State and Political Theory (Princeton: Princeton University
Press).
Coutinho, C.N. (2012), Gramsci’s Political Thought (Boston-Leiden: Brill).
Cox, R.W. (1993), Gramsci, Hegemony and International Relations, in Gill, S. (ed.),
Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
De Rosa, G. (1978), Gramsci e la questione cattolica, in Ferri, F. (ed.), Politica e storia in
Gramsci (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Femia, J.V. (2002), Hegemony and Consciousness in the Thought of Antonio Gramsci, in
Martin, J. (ed.), Gramsci. Critical Assessments of Leading Political Philosophers (Lon-
don: Routledge).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
104 Prospero
Finocchiaro, M.A. (1988), Gramsci and the History of Dialectical Thought (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press).
Haugaard, M., Lentner, H.H. (2006), Hegemony and Power (Oxford: Lexington Books).
Ives, P. (2004), Gramsci’s Politics of Language (Toronto: University of Toronto Press).
Liguori, G. (2019), Gramsci e il populismo (Milano: Unicopli).
Martelli, M. (1996), Gramsci filosofo della politica (Milano: Unicopli).
Martin, J. (2015), Morbid Symptoms: Gramsci and the Crisis of Liberalism, in McNally, M.,
Antonio Gramsci (London: Palgrave MacMillan).
Mastellone, S., Sola, G. (eds.) (2001), Gramsci: il partito politico nei “Quaderni” (Firenze:
CET).
Morera, E. (1990), Gramsci’s Historicism. A Realist Interpretation (London: Routledge).
Paggi, L. (1970), Gramsci e il moderno principe (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Poulantzas, N. (1975), Potere politico e classi sociali (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Rosengarten, F. (2014), The Revolutionary Marxism of Antonio Gramsci (Boston-Leiden:
Brill).
Tamburrano, G. (1963), Antonio Gramsci (Manduria: Lacaita Editore).
Texier, J. (1968), Gramsci teorico delle sovrastrutture e il concetto di società civile, in “Crit-
ica marxista”, 3, pp. 71–99.
von Beyme, K. (2013), Sozialismus (Berlin: Springer).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 10
Giuseppe Cospito
Going back even further, if not the term hegemony, that in the writings preced-
ing his stay in Moscow (May 1922-November 1923) appears exclusively as in the
then currently accepted meaning of supremacy, the concept is at least implic-
itly present from the period of the “Ordine Nuovo” (“New Order”). Gramsci re-
calls the concept in the essay on the Quistione meridionale (“Southern ques-
tion”) left unpublished at the time of his arrest, writing that:
The Turin communists had concretely posed the question of the “hege-
mony of the proletariat”, that is, the question of the social base of the
proletarian dictatorship and the workers’ state. The proletariat can be-
come the ruling class and dominant in the way in which it manages to
create a system of class alliances that allows it to mobilize the majority of
the working population against capitalism and the bourgeois state, which
means, in the existing class relations in Italy, to the extent that it is able to
obtain the consent of the large peasant masses.5
Gramsci would resume his theoretical writings more than two years later, at
the end of a long judicial procedure (arrest, confinement, preventive incar-
ceration, prosecution and conviction of more than 20 years in prison, request
to obtain the permission to write while imprisoned). The Quaderno 1 (“Note-
book 1”) bears the date of February 8th, 1929, but for a whole year the prisoner
merely formulates some work plans and drafts a handful of annotations of bib-
liographical nature, dedicating the rest of his time to reading and above all,
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The “Prison Notebooks”: Hegemony and Civil Society 107
This formulation, and others similar to it, on one hand, sometimes take on al-
most literal expressions used by Gramsci in the last phase of his active political
militancy and in particular in the essay on the Quistione meridionale (“South-
ern question”), while on the other hand introduces a series of innovations des-
tined to connote the prison reflections in a different way. First of all, consistent
with the forcefully für ewig character of Gramsi’s writing in those years, what
was a political strategy in a certain phase, later becomes a political-historical
criterion; consequently, it is not only the question of the hegemony of the pro-
letariat that is at stake here, but of any social class – in the second draft of the
Notebook 19, § 24, Gramsci will say social group – that tries to conquer and
conserve power. Furthermore, already at this point there is an apparent oscil-
lation between a narrow sense of hegemony intended as rule based on consen-
sus and a broader definition: hegemony understood as rule and domination –
consent that is not opposed to force. That which seems to be one of the
6 Cf. Genesi e svolgimento del lavoro in carcere in Cospito, Frosini 2017: xx et seq.
7 PN1: 136–137 (Q 1, § 44: 41). Since the new critical edition of Gramsci’s Quaderni (Prison Note-
books) referred to in the previous note, is still in the finishing stages, from now on the refer-
ence to the prison manuscripts will be in the order of the notebooks and paragraphs pro-
posed in V. Gerratana (ed.) (1975), Quaderni del carcere (Turin: Einaudi) even where this does
not correspond to that of the new edition. For the dates of single prison notes cf. Cospito 2011:
896–904.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
108 Cospito
8 The reference is obviously to Anderson 2017 which confirms the thesis of the first edition
of the essay (1976), despite the theoretical and philological refutation in the second part
of Francioni 1984.
9 PN1: 155–156 (Q 1, § 48: 59).
10 PN1: 169 (Q 1, § 61: 72).
11 PN3: 342 (Q 8, § 185: 1053).
12 NM: 172.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The “Prison Notebooks”: Hegemony and Civil Society 109
Real Italy and legal Italy. The formula contrived by the clericals after 1870
to direct attention to the national political uneasiness: contradiction
between legal Italy and real Italy. […] Generally speaking, it is felicitous
because there existed a clear disjunction between the state (legality) and
civil society (reality) – but did this civil society exist completely and exclu-
sively within “clericalism”? Meanwhile, this same civil society was some-
thing shapeless and chaotic and remained so for many decades; it was
therefore possible for the state to dominate it, overcoming each time the
contradictions that presented themselves in a sporadic, localized form,
without any national nexus.14
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
110 Cospito
notes (that is, in the sense of the political and cultural hegemony of a
social group over the whole society; as the ethical content fo the state)
from the sense given to it by Catholics, for whom civil society is, instead,
political society or the state, as opposed to the society of the family and
of the church.16
This and other notes from Notebook 6, spanning from the end of 1930 until the
summer of 1931, represent the first point of arrival of a reflection that began
in Notebook 3 and 5, but most of all in Notebook 4, both in the first series of
“Philosophical Notes” (with particular regard to the notes on the relationships
between structure and superstructure) and in the miscellaneous notes on the
intellectuals (destined to converge in Notebook 12). In these notes, Gramsci out-
lined in particular the connection between hegemony and civil society, con-
sistent in the fact that the second constitutes the privileged battleground and
therefore is the exercise of the first. This connection appears implicitly starting
from § 47 of Notebook 1, where Gramsci discusses from “Hegel’s doctrine of par-
ties and associations as the ‘private’ fabric of the state” that presuppose a “gov-
ernment by consent of the governed, but an organized consent, not the vague
and generic kind which is declared at the time of elections: the state has and de-
mands consent, but it also ‘educates’ this consent through political and trade-
union associations which, however, are private organisms, left to the private
initiative of the ruling class”.17 The link between the two concepts is made ex-
plicit in § 81 of Notebook 6 – Hegemony (civil society) and separation of powers –
where there appears a reference to “the hegemonic apparatus” which also re-
calls the material character of the exercise of hegemony.
In § 52 of Quaderno 8 (“Notebook 8”, February 1932), dedicated to the Mod-
erno Principe (“the Modern Prince”), recurs the expression (that constitutes a
hapax legomenon in Gramsci’s work) of “civil hegemony”, presented as a com-
position and surmounting of the concept of “permanent revolution”, that in
turn is assimilated into the strategy of the war of movement, that according to
Gramsci will become obsolete in the modern world, at least in the West. Vice
versa, “in politics, the war of position is the concept of hegemony that can only
come into existence after certain things are already in place, namely, the
large popular organizations of the modern type that represent, as it were,
the ‘trenches’ and the permanent fortifications of the war of position”.18 The
military metaphor – that continuously permeates the Marxist tradition (from
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The “Prison Notebooks”: Hegemony and Civil Society 111
among the many meanings of democracy, the most realistic anc concrete
one, in my view, is that which can brought into relief through the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
112 Cospito
The reflections of the following years up until the abrupt interruption because
of Gramsci’s failing psychological and physical conditions towards the middle
of 1935, are dedicated to, on one hand, the reorganization of at least a part of
the material gathered until this point (with the introduction of significant revi-
sions, especially at the beginning) and on the other hand, the drafting of new
miscellaneous notes in Notebooks 9, 14, 15 and 17. For what regards our specific
theme, we must again examine the dynamism of the hegemony/civil society
nexus in relation to, above all, a series of events that contribute to Gramsci’s
rethinking of the Marxist doctrine – taken from the orthodoxy of the Third
International as a type of fideistic dogma – in terms of philosophy of praxis: on
one hand the first signs of regression in Stalinist ussr, and on the other the
strengthening of Western capitalist regimes, both of the liberal-democratic
type – exemplified by Roosevelt’s New Deal in the usa – and the authoritarian
type – fascism elected as “Europe’s ideological representation” of the “passive
revolution” (Notebook 10, §9, April-May 1932)24 and Hitlerism with its “manifes-
tation of brutality and monstrous ignominy” (Notebook 28, § 1, first months of
1935).25 These are all themes that require separate and individual treatment.
For obvious reasons of space, we cannot dwell upon each of them here.
Bibliography
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The “Prison Notebooks”: Hegemony and Civil Society 113
PN: Buttigieg, J.A. (ed.) (1992, 1996, 2007), Prison Notebooks (New York: Columbia Uni-
versity Press), 3 vols.
Q: Gerratana, V. (ed.) (1975), Quaderni del carcere (Torino: Einaudi), 4 vols.
spn: Hoare, Q., Nowell-Smith, G. (eds.) (1971), Selection from the Prison Notebooks (New
York: International Publishers).
SPW-1: Hoare, Q., Nowell Smith, G. (eds.) (1977), Selections from Political Writings, 1910–
1920 (London: Lawrence & Wishart; New York: International Publisher).
Other Works
Anderson, P. (2017), The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci (London: Verso).
Cospito, G. (2011), Verso l’edizione critica e integrale dei “Quaderni del carcere”, in “Studi
Storici”, 4, pp. 881–904.
Cospito, G. (2016), The Rhythm of Thought in Gramsci: A Diachronic Interpretation of
Prison Notebooks (Boston, Leiden: Brill).
Cospito, G., Frosini, F. (2017), Introduzione, in Gramsci, A., Quaderni del carcere, critical
edition directed by Francioni, G., vol. 2, Quaderni miscellanei (1929–1935) (Roma: Is-
tituto della Enciclopedia Italiana).
Francioni, G. (1984), L’officina gramsciana. Ipotesi sulla struttura dei “Quaderni del car-
cere” (Napoli: Bibliopolis).
Pala, M. (ed.) (2014), Narrazioni egemoniche. Gramsci, letteratura e società civile (Bolo-
gna: il Mulino).
Vacca, G. (2017), Modernità alternative. Il Novecento di Antonio Gramsci (Torino:
Einaudi).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 11
Michele Filippini
1 Gramsci Provincialized
1 Given the amount of references it is impossible to present a short bibliography on the suc-
cess of this concept. Please refer to the Gramscian bibliography online (http://bg.fondazi-
onegramsci.org/biblio-gramsci), where one can search by theme or by the language of the
contribution.
2 Cf. Filippini 2016.
3 Cf. Mezzadra, Capuzzo 2012.
4 Cf. Chakrabarty 2000.
5 Chakrabarty 2000: 16.
6 Ibid.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
116 Filippini
way uncentered with respect to its principle axis. The figure of Niccolò Machia-
velli for example, in being the first modern thinker in a country without any of
the political conditions of modernity, represents this eccentricity well, indi-
cated by Gramsci himself.7
Gramscian thought is a full-fledged part of this eccentric theoretical pro-
duction. How else could we define his reflection on the peasantry – the central
element of every backward country – but within the context of a West armored
by the “fortresses and emplacements” of a modern civil society?8 How could
we not consider oxymoronic the concepts of passive revolution or revolution/
restoration, used to account for modern transformations but guided from
above by conservative forces? And why should we try to logically compose the
contradiction between the State as a “political society + civil society”9 and the
State as the sole “political society”10 opposed to civil society, when it precisely
expresses the two sides of a spurious condition that today is more globally
widespread that ever?11
The list could continue. What interests me is to show how the Gramsci’s
legacy is fully part of the modern political conceptualization developed on a
spurious, secondary and peripheral track, but still within European modernity,
and how it lends itself in a particular mode to the appropriation of different
contexts, an appropriation that never configures itself in the terms of faithful
translation or emulation, but always in that of appropriation and reuse.
The journey that the concept completed in this first displacement has as its
starting point Gramsci’s Italy of the 1930s, makes a stop at the Peronist move-
ment in Argentina in the 1960s and 1970s, only to return to the other side of the
Atlantic in the second decade of the 21st century, in particular in the countries
7 “It is impossible to understand Machiavelli without taking into account the fact that with
the European (international, for his times) experience he went beyond the Italian experi-
ence; without the European experience, his ‘will’ would have been utopian” (PN3: 72; Q 6,
§ 86: 760). Cf. also Althusser 1999.
8 PN3: 169 (Q 7, § 16: 866). Cf. ppw: 313–337 (SP3: 243–265).
9 PN3: 75 (Q 6, § 88: 764).
10 spn: 12 (Q 12, § 1: 1518).
11 This is one of the ambivalences that leads Perry Anderson to see Gramsci’s position as
inconsistent and incoherent; not realizing that this ambivalence is actually constitutive
of the hegemonic reality of many social and state formations (cf. Anderson 1976). For a
different critique of Anderson’s thesis, cf. Thomas 2009: 93–95.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Productive Use of Hegemony (Laclau, Hall, Chatterjee) 117
For Gramsci, even though the diverse social elements have a merely
relational identity – achieved through articulatory practices – there must
always be a single unifying principle in every hegemonic formation, and
this can only be a fundamental class […]. This is the inner essentialist
core which continues to be present in Gramsci’s thought, setting a limit
to the deconstructive logic of hegemony.15
Laclau intends to break down this last limit, formulating a theory of hegemony
that expunges every residue of necessity that is fully contingent and discur-
sively structured.16 Recovering the arsenal of Gramscian concepts listed above
is rightfully a part of this operation which permits Laclau to recover all the
richness of a Marxist theory formulated under exceptional conditions, decen-
tralized, and thus more suited to the politics of contingent articulations. It is
therefore starting from Gramsci, in Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, that a
hegemonic-discoursive theory is constructed that will support all of Laclau’s
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
118 Filippini
subsequent works where the theme of hegemony works side by side with
(partly overlying and partly substituting) the theme of populism as in On Popu-
list Reason.17 This book has had an undeniable impact in Europe, particularly
on the political strategy of emerging leftist forces that are alternatives to social-
ist parties (Podemos in Spain, Syriza in Greece, La France Insoumise in France
and also the Labour in England). The Italian anomaly that, reformulated on the
margins through populist (Peronist) Argentinian categories, comes back to Eu-
rope as the ideological base of the new Left, is an explanatory image of a suc-
cessful provincialization.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Productive Use of Hegemony (Laclau, Hall, Chatterjee) 119
compromise between workers and capital, that from the 1940s in England had
been tacitly accepted by all governments. Thatcherism, therefore, should not
be understood as a pathology of the British political system, but as one of the
best bets ever wagered inside of it. Not by chance, Thatcherism has a history of
hard struggle within its political field, in order to impose itself on the other
rightwing factions of the Conservative Party. Thatcher’s masterpiece was to
build an autonomous and hegemonic narration and to have understood the
political nature of the cultural framework.
In this context, Hall uses the reference to Gramscian concepts like theoreti-
cal picklock – allowing him to overcome the impasse of the English “left” in the
face of changes that they do not seem to fully understand. The problem of
ideology returns to the centre stage of the discourse in the sense of “the lan-
guages, the concepts, categories, imagery of thought, and the systems of
representation”.21 In this case, Gramsci is important because:
Compared to the Left, Thatcherism first understood the multifaceted and he-
gemonic nature of contemporary society. Against class reductionism, Gramsci
thus becomes useful once again with his concepts of hegemony, historical bloc
or war of position, which manage to extract from the core of Marxist thought a
mediated concept of determination, not formulated in a economic manner
but instead based on “relations of force”.23
To stress once again the role played by Gramsci as a link, it is interesting to
note how Laclau, coming from a Marxist background, puts himself beyond
Gramsci criticizing his essentialist residuals, and how Hall, on the contrary,
coming from a structuralist background, thinks of Gramsci like an embank-
ment on the opposing front: “Gramsci is where I stopped in the headlong rush
into structuralism and theoreticism. At a certain point I stumbled over Grams-
ci, and I said, ‘Here and no further!’”24
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
120 Filippini
The last voyage departs from the old continent bringing the concept to India,
and then returns home, as is usual, enriched with the nuances and innovations
that make Gramsci’s provincialization a political-theoretical weapon. Partha
Chatterjee, an Indian intellectual who is a member of the second generation of
the subaltern studies group, wrote two books of interest: Nationalist Thought
and the Colonial World and The Politics of the Governed.
The first book reconstructs the history of Indian nationalism by retracing
three different phases. In the first phase, nationalism is the pre-conceived
knowledge that colonial domination imposes on local elites. It is a “theoretical
tool” that is derived from the experiences, the concepts, and the history of the
colonizers. This nationalism, writes Chatterjee, is at the same time “imitative
and hostile to the models it imitates”.25 This ambiguity is first cause responsi-
ble for the separation between elite and subalterns in India. It is here that the
Gramscian “toolbox” comes into play:
25 Chatterjee 1986: 2.
26 Chatterjee 1986: 29–30.
27 spn: 105–106 (Q 15, § 59: 1823).
28 Cf. Guha 1997.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Productive Use of Hegemony (Laclau, Hall, Chatterjee) 121
Here Chatterjee suggests the parallelism with the history of the Italian Risorgi-
mento just as Gramsci had suggested it through the concept of passive revolu-
tion: as Gandhi is to Mazzini and Garibaldi, so Nehru is to Cavour.
The failure to include subalterns, or more precisely, the lack of the “classical”
forms of their inclusion into the national state, remains a defining characteris-
tic of the Indian state even in its postcolonial history. The Politics of the Gov-
erned begins exactly from this dyscrasia between the liberal-constitutional
discourse (according to which all citizens are equal bearer of rights) and the
Indian reality (where these principles are actually more nuanced – they de-
pend on the context and form an overall tenuous belonging to civil society).
Through a compelling reconstruction of the political battles of the inhabitants
of an informal settlement in Calcutta, Chatterjee tells us how a large sector of
the population finds themselves outside of the rational and “geometrical”
structure of the rule of law, but how not for this reason should its presence be
considered irrelevant. The external nature of this population and the impossi-
bility of its complete internalization make it an internal problem of the state.
Relations that are established between state power and these “populations” are
therefore of a governmental nature, based on bargaining and fighting, objec-
tively outside the frame of liberal-democratic citizenship.
Chatterjee chooses a Gramscian concept – that of political society – to iden-
tify this place of conflict, negotiation and production of subjectivity that be-
comes a space of action for the subalterns. The groups that make up this politi-
cal society operate through an informal yet dense network of relations often
using the vote as a bargaining chip or political activism as a weapon of black-
mail. Through these instrumental uses of the classic channels of democratic
participation, the dimensions of citizenship and governmentality intersect.
What Chatterjee says concerning the concept of political society therefore
is that there exists a political nature that expresses itself outside of the classical
coordinates of the constitutional state and that its exponential growth repre-
sents one of the major challenges for the state. It is superfluous to note how
such externality/internality and such an unrecognized but active political na-
ture, such decomposition and pluralization of forms of citizenship, investigat-
ed in the slums of Calcutta, in reality tells us a lot about our contemporary
developments in “the West”.
5 Conclusion
For a partial conclusion of this brief overview of the uses of Gramsci’s concept
of hegemony it is perhaps appropriate to go back and ask how much this spe-
cific provincialization has to do with Gramsci himself: if not with his personal
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
122 Filippini
history then at least with the political inheritance of his legacy. On this front,
there are many opinions that tend to define their eccentric uses as simple
wordplay or forced interpretations. I believe instead that these productive read-
ings of the concept of hegemony support at least two fundamental character-
istics of Gramsci’s work. On one hand, the attempt to learn conceptually and to
politically propose a way out of the Marxian thesis of the increasing simplifica-
tion (polarization and proletarianization) of capitalist society; on the other
hand, to politically pose the problem of how one builds the strength of eman-
cipation given the different types of work, forms of life and social identities.
Tracing this type of continuity, however, also responds to another Gramscian
statement: that of reconstructing a theoretical tradition of the oppressed that
ensures that the “history of subaltern social groups” will no longer be “neces-
sarily fragmented and episodic”.29
Bibliography
Other Works
Althusser, L. (1999), Machiavelli and us (London: Verso).
Anderson, P. (1976), The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci, in “New Left Review”, 100,
pp. 12–34.
Chakrabarty, D. (2000), Provincializing Europe. Postcolonial Thought and Historical Dif-
ference (Princeton: Princeton University Press).
Chatterjee, P. (1986), Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse
(London: Zed Books).
Filippini, M. (2016), Using Gramsci. A New Approach (London: Pluto Press).
Guha, R. (1997), Dominance without Hegemony: History and Power in Colonial India
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
On the Productive Use of Hegemony (Laclau, Hall, Chatterjee) 123
Hall, S. (1979), The Great Moving Right Show, in “Marxism Today”, January.
Hall, S. (1986), Gramsci’s Relevance for the Study of Race and Ethnicity, in “Journal of
Communication Inquiry”, 10, pp. 5–27.
Hall, S. (1986), The Problem of Ideology: Marxism without Guarantees, in “Journal of
Communication Inquiry”, 10, pp. 28–44.
Hall, S. (1988), The Hard Road to Renewal. Thatcherism and the Crisis of the Left (Lon-
don: Verso).
Hall, S. (1988), The Toad in the Garden: Thatcherism among the Theorists, in Nelson, C.,
Grossberg, L. (eds.), Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture (Champaign: Univer-
sity of Illinois Press).
Laclau, E. (1990), New Reflections on the Revolution of our Time (London: Verso).
Laclau, E. (1996), Emancipation(s) (London: Verso).
Laclau, E. (2005), On Populist Reason (London: Verso).
Laclau, E. (2014), The Rhetorical Foundations of Society (London: Verso).
Laclau, E., Mouffe, C. [1985] (2001), Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical
Democratic Politics (London: Verso).
Mezzadra, S., Capuzzo, P. (2012), Provincializing the Italian Reading of Gramsci, in Bhat-
tacharya, B., Srivastava, N. (eds.), The Postcolonial Gramsci (London: Routledge),
pp. 34–54.
Thomas, P. (2009), The Gramscian Moment: Philosophy, Hegemony, and Marxism
(Leiden, Boston: Brill).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Part 5
Historiography
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 12
Marzio Zanantoni
The interpretations, debates and polemics that concern the figure of Antonio
Gramsci and his intellectual output in Italy (starting from his incarceration in
November of 1926) have been reconstructed several times and in various ways.
Throughout the succession of its various editions, Guido Liguori’s Gramsci
conteso,1 has been and still is for all, an essential point of reference for those
who want to travel through the story of the interpretations and discussions
had about Gramsci over the last three decades in Italy.
I will therefore try to follow a different path, one which puts historiographi-
cal aim on the diversified influences and legacy of Gramsci in Italian culture,
more than on the “dispute” between opposing and incompatible interpreta-
tions. In short, I will focus more on the conscious or unconscious use (both not
so political and not only political) of the Gramscian lesson, than on the judg-
ments (instrumental or not) of opposing factions.
Immediately after Gramsci’s death on April 27th, 1937, the imminent and
emerging problem in a large part of the writings, articles and testimonies that
the Italian and international press dedicated to the Sardinian politician, was
that of placing Gramsci in the history of Italy – within the events of the work-
ers’ movement and in political struggle. In some ways it was the moment of the
first “dispute” concerning the figure of Gramsci by the differing ideologies and
forces, despite them being in this moment essentially unanimous in the cele-
bration of a “martyr” of the fascist prisons and “one of the best leaders, one of
the most loyal fighters for the cause of the liberation of humanity”, according
to the converging words of Ercoli and Dimitrov, Nenni and Buozzi, as well as
Carlo Rosselli and Camillo Berneri.
As it is noted, in Italy it was Palmiro Togliatti, the man who more than any-
one else was able to claim to have shared such a closely shared path with
Gramsci, who shaped the contours of Gramsci’s image. For 37 years, from 1927
to 1964, through 14 writings and speeches, Togliatti gives shape to the profile, or
better said, to the profiles of his friend and companion, keeping in mind that
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 129
humus (fertile ground) necessary for the overthrow of an abstract dialectic for
a realistic and materialistic vision of reality, conflict and class struggle in I taly.15
It is also relevant to note that Togliatti’s preoccupation with reminding “us
Communists” of Gramsci’s Italianness so that “we do not believe that the pat-
rimony of Antonio Gramsci is only ours […] this patrimony belongs to all Sar-
dinians, all Italians, all workers who fight for their emancipation, whether it be
for their religious faith or their political beliefs […] he thought for all of us, he
spoke for all of us, he suffered for all of us”.16 Thus, Gramsci’s image changes
and grows over the course of one decade: it is molded with moral, intellectual
and political features, whose alignments change significantly by being condi-
tioned by two disputes – on one side with the composite constellation of so-
cialists, liberals and catholics that thought of Gramsci increasingly as a politi-
cian and nothing more than one of the many anti-fascist intellectuals17 and on
the other side, with the resistance of the Communist world, reluctant to imag-
ine the Sardinian thinker as a “national” man and not only as the “leader” of the
international working class. What are evident here are the solicitations dictat-
ed by the current political struggle: from the initial development of a national
way of constructing democracy in our country, to the need for a strategy of
moral and intellectual alliances designed to give definite closure to the fascist
experience. The last features that Togliatti wanted to model, have a reference
from behind the scenes that was then unknown but would become public
knowledge shortly thereafter: Gramsci’s writings from prison. While Togliatti
recalled the strong image of Gramsci’s Italianness from the balcony of the Pala-
zzo Civico of Cagliari on April 27th, 1947, in those same days bookstores were
receiving printed copies of Lettere dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”).18 The im-
pact of Gramsci’s Letters is enormous and the dispute surrounding the most
correct interpretation of those written and the image to offer in the form of a
political and intellectual legacy in reality occurs several months earlier and in
a place that was certainly not neutral: Elio Vittorini’s “Il Politecnico”.19 Publish-
ing “courtesy of the Casa Editrice Einaudi (Einaudi publishing house)”, a group
of 13 letters written by Gramsci at the Turi prison between 1928 and 1932 and
addressed to his wife, his sister-in-law and his son Delio, Vittorini outlined
explicitly in his brief introduction, in certain passages extrapolated from the
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
130 Zanantoni
c ontext and isolated as quotations. “His Gramsci”, was certainly very different
than Togliatti’s description. Vittorini writes, Gramsci:
appears to us today like a man of politics that could be more sharply po-
litical thanks to his capacity to find the cultural reasons for every issue.
[…] He claimed the importance of the aesthetic evaluation of art along-
side the historical evaluation, more than any other great revolutionary.
[…] For us, in any case, in many problems the last word belongs to him,
for the Communists and for all the Italian intellectuals.20
Vittorini adds a distinctive passage, causing not only tensions within the
communist movement, but uses Gramsci in the same issue of the magazine
in which the famous text of Togliatti is published,21 reinforcing his struggle
with the problem of the relations between politics and culture, configuring
the image of the Sardinian thinker as a Marxist politician whose quality of
his Marxist political being was the intellectual capacity to recognize the aes-
thetic autonomy of the artistic fact (art, poetry, art literature) “alongside his-
torical evaluation”. This is a use of Gramsci that will permeate the left-wing
intellectual.
The debate surrounding the figure of Gramsci exploded when he was award-
ed the Viareggio Prize in August 1947. Meanwhile, it should be noted that Togli-
atti’s idea of publishing the Lettere dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”) before
the Quaderni del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”)22 in which Gramsci’s thought
was most widely expressed, represented a significant anomaly in the Commu-
nist tradition.23 In the history of the workers’ movement, letter correspon-
dence had a certain importance, but usually consisted of political and ideo-
logical letters – very rarely personal letters. Just think of the correspondence of
Marx and Engels with various exponents of the German Social Democrats such
as Bernstein, Bebel and Kautsky. Correspondence was essential both as a tool
and as useful documents for understanding the theoretical structuring of both
sender and recipient. In the case of Gramsci, the Lettere dal carcere (“Letters
from Prison”), published before the contemporaneously written and more the-
oretical Prison Notebooks, still posed a problem for the Communist community
that was negatively sensitive to intrusions of the “private” into the presentation
20 Gramsci 1946: 5. About this Gramscian reading of “Politecnico” cf. Liguori 2012: 81–82,
Luperini 1971: 124–125.
21 Togliatti 1946: 3–4.
22 Cf. Daniele 2005: 76, letter from Felice Platone to Giulio Einaudi, November 4, 1946.
23 Cf. several references in Hobsbawm 1978: 367.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 131
of a public figure of absolute moral intransigence who was also leader of the
party. To the consciously defined features that Togliatti gradually outlined, the
Lettere added another extraordinarily effective feature to the figure of Gramsci
even with the possibility of a risky reception: “the world of feelings and the
most fundamental affections”.24
Here is the sentimental key that could predispose the hearts and souls of
Italian intellectuals and militants alike to the reception of Gramsci not only as
leader of the working class, anti-fascist intellectual, “scholar” and the “writer”
but also as an intellectual and militant revolutionary whose letters reveal to all
his “vast and profound humanity”.25 Togliatti’s “reading” of Gramsci was so de-
cisive that, from the reasons for the Viareggio award read by Leonida Repaci
the evening of August 16th to the numerous reviews and comments that fol-
lowed, it was Gramsci’s humanity that was emphasized as one of his most clas-
sic traits. The Communist community and the varied constellation of Italian
culture seemed to have overcome their perplexities and divergences in order
to unanimously recognize the figure of the Sardinian politician as a “man, rev-
olutionary, thinker, husband and father through and through”,26 discovering
the Lettere dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”) as a “monument of life and of
indestructible moral teaching” and “Gramsci the narrator and artist as equal to
the moralist, philosopher and historian”.27 As Calvino wrote: “an exemplary fig-
ure of the modern Italian” who “knew how to graft to the trunk of the most
rigorously traditional Italian culture, the biting historicity of dialectic
materialism”.28 Some voices were displeased, uttered with a mix of envy and
political irritation29 against that “simple follower of Croce” – as written for ex-
ample by Alberto Savinio to his editor Bompiani commenting on that “almost
idiotic and immoral thing” of the Viareggio Prize,30 in relation to the dispute
surrounding the Gramscian legacy to appropriate that body and mind which
for ten years had suffered and worked in fascist prisons and which had written
celebrated pages, such as those on Benedetto Croce. In reality, these were some
of the most equivocal words, with those references (often evoked in ways that
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
132 Zanantoni
were not exact)31 to the Lettere dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”), which would
belong “even to one who is of another or opposing political party”,32 because,
“as a thinker, Gramsci, was one of us, one of those who in the first decades of
the 20th century in Italy formed a philosophical and historical mind able to
deal with the problems of the present”33 – a group in which Croce naturally
included himself. In fact, Croce’s review of the Lettere is just another opportu-
nity to talk more about himself than about the reviewed book and to attack the
most orthodox Marxist doctrine – attributed to Togliatti and the Italian Com-
munists “armed with a philosophical catechism written by Stalin” – through
the example of Gramsci and his presumed difference. Croce emphasized the
Gramscian ability to interpret the specificity of literary and poetic phenomena
“for their aesthetic values alone and not to love them for their ideological
content”34 – with an implicit reference to what Vittorini had observed (with
quite a different intent) and the attempt to bring the Communist doctrine to
the stature and tradition of the great Italian philosophers: from Bruno to Cam-
panella to Vico. An interpretation that would soon turn out to be instrumental
when shortly thereafter the first volume of the Quaderni del carcere (“Prison
Notebooks”) would be published and dedicated the philosophy of Benedetto
Croce. This time, the review35 would have another tone, when the philosopher
from Abruzzo realized how much Gramsci’s “philosophy of praxis” was strong-
ly characterized by its profound critical autonomy and philosophical original-
ity and to what heights of elaboration Gramsci had achieved while in prison.
Certainly, the Viareggio Prize and the almost unanimous chorus of praise that
arrived above all from the liberal and actionist area, that maybe had too conve-
niently interpreted “Gramsci is for all”, could not help but arouse some con-
cerns within the Communist community. Carlo Muscetta hastened to warn
against Croce’s subtle game of an illegitimate appropriation, almost an “ideo-
logical kidnapping” of Gramsci and to reject (with the pen of Lucio Lombardo
Radice), the efforts of the “traditional culture to liquidate Gramsci by
assimilation”.36
In the context of the readings and interpretations of these months between
1947 and 1948, the position of another actionist, Luigi Russo (who was then the
31 Cf. for example the memorial speech given by Giorgio Napolitano to the Camera dei Dep-
utati on April 27th, 2017 (Napolitano 2017).
32 Croce 1947: 86–88. Croce’s review was anticipated on July 6th by four newspapers (see
D’Anna 1988: 289).
33 Croce 1947: 86.
34 Croce 1947: 87.
35 Croce 1948: 78–79.
36 Cf. Ajello 1979: 109–112. For Radice’s position on Gramsci cf. Ragazzini 2002: 122–155.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 133
director of the Scuola Normale of Pisa), stands out. It was at this school (the
Scuola Normale of Pisa) on April 27th, 1947, on the occasion of the 10th anni-
versary of Gramsci’s death, as requested by Togliatti, that Russo gave an impor-
tant speech taking into account not only Gramsci’s recently published Lettere
dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”), but also a manuscript copy of the Quaderni
del carcere (“Prison Notebooks”) before their publication37 made available to
him with keen foresight by Togliatti. The profile of Gramsci that Russo outlined
was one that, at least in those first moments, was better able to give back to
that name, to that memory, the face of a man: a complete moral and intellec-
tual physiognomy in a sufficiently determined place in history. His profile, de-
scribed with non-rhetorical38 words, seemed like that of a rediscovered friend,
but even more that of “our brother in work”39 who from the depths of a prison
“was so close to us and remembered all of our writings in a friendly way and
with genuine warmth”.40 Included in that “us” were names and books that first
Russo, and soon after the entire Italian culture discovered with stupefied admi-
ration: “Croce, De Ruggiero Omodeo, Salvatorelli, Matteo Bartoli, Umberto
Cosmo”. They discovered the subjects that Gramsci studied in prison: from the
Risorgimento to grammar; from Machiavelli to literature; from Dante to Piran-
dello, demonstrating a “vast culture, knowledge of foreign languages and liter-
atures, an encyclopedic interest in literature and history, critique, linguistics
and finally political thought”.41 It was as though Russo could not wait to write
to Togliatti the day after the memorial at the Scuola Normale, “for me, Gramsci
was a revelation”.42 But one wonders, “And Gramsci the politician?”. Russo, as
he himself point out to Togliatti, is “not a Communist but not anti-Communist”43
and it is in this view that he interprets Gramsci in whose writings “after 1921
one rarely finds the words dictatorship of the proletariat, instead he talks about
democratic conquest and democratic education of the proletariat”.44 In this
way, where Communism appears to him like “a starting point for democratic
education”,45 for the first time, Russo emphatically and decisively underlines
the role of the intellectual as educator on the political path towards d emocracy.
37 Cf. Chiarotto 2011: 52–53; D’Anna 1988: 301–302; Togliatti 2014b: 95–97.
38 Russo 1947: 395–411 (later reprinted with the title Scoperta di Antonio Gramsci, cf. Santar-
elli 1991: 225–240).
39 Santarelli 1991: 228.
40 Ibid.
41 Santarelli 1991: 229.
42 Togliatti 2014b: 95.
43 Ibid.
44 Santarelli 1991: 231.
45 Togliatti 2014b: 90.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
134 Zanantoni
We are still in 1947, where the role of the proletariat, even from its perspective
of “non-anticommunist and sincere and loyal democratic” is fundamental.
Togliatti can only rejoice: the director of the Scuola Normale knew how to of-
fer, so to speak, the “correct understanding” of Gramsci. He is no longer just a
politician and scholar “impregnated with the Western spirit” and “essentially
rooted in the Italian tradition”,46 but a “fighting partner” that progressive men
of culture feel close to, by having indicated (as no one else did before now) the
problem of the education of intellectuals as necessary allies of workers and
peasants instead of lofty, unreachable teachers. Luigi Russo’s interpretation of
the organic intellectual was the most lucid and conscious, and, through deci-
sive Gramscian guidance, undoubtedly shifted the commitment of democratic
men of culture.
Russo had outlined the most empathetic image of Gramsci, one that was
heartfelt and not just intellectualized by men of culture of the time. In con-
trast, Giacomo Debenedetti (another literary critic) developed the most inno-
vative and penetrating reading of Lettere dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”)
that had been written up until those first months of 1947. From that moment,
this reading traced a profile of Gramsci that would become indelible: the clas-
sicism of Gramsci. Debenedetti, who had personally known Gramsci in Torino
in the 1920s, joined the pci (the Italian Communist Party) in 1944 and was also
a member of the jury for the Viareggio Prize. Close to the time of publication
of Gramsci’s Lettere, he wrote few dozen pages of notes that remained unedit-
ed until 1972 and were then gathered by Ottavio Cecchi with the title Il metodo
umano di Antonio Gramsci, appunti del 1947 per un saggio sulle “Lettere dal car-
cere” (“The human method of Antonio Gramsci, notes from 1947 for an essay
on the Letters from Prison”)47 as well as an article-review published on May
22nd, 1947 in the Roman edition of “l’Unità” and on June 1st, 1947 in the Mila-
nese edition48 with the title Gramsci, uomo classico (Gramsci: classical man).
There is an obvious connection between the notes and the article appearing in
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 135
the Communist newspaper. In the latter, almost all the complexity of Debene-
detti’s considerations and his ingenious path towards a penetrating view of
Gramsci’s thought disappears. Even more brilliant if we think that such a read-
ing came about for Debenedetti without having the complete edition of the
Lettere at his disposition (among these, the dramatic letter to Tania of March 6,
1933, not included in the 1947 edition) and without having read in the Quaderni
those problematically and temporally connected “Note autobiografiche” (“au-
tobiographical notes”) included in Quaderno 15 (“Notebook 15”) (a text that was
also excluded from the first edition of the Quaderni del carcere).49 The reading
of Lettere dal carcere (“Letters from Prison”) that Debenedetti offers is in fact
thought of as a kind of exploration of Gramsci’s self-analysis and revolves
around a conclusion that turns out to be “between the words that most fre-
quently recur, […] those of molecule, molecular”.50 Availing of the complicity
of Leopardi and De Sanctis, the critic from Turin reads the Lettere like a “story
of a soul”,51 an “autobiography of Gramsci’s last ten years”,52 where plots are
outlined, in the literary form of storytelling and diary – “a human method”.53
Closed in a prison cell, writes Debenedetti, conscious of his physical and psy-
chological changes, time was the only direction in which Gramsci could still
move. “But it is exactly that, through which man proceeds to discover and ana-
lyze himself”.54 It is a procession of memories, emotions and sentiments. To
arrive at an understanding of things in their “entirety” and complexity, Grams-
ci carries out an analysis of time lived, memories, “sensazioni molecolari”
(“molecular sensations”) through that which Debenedetti identifies as “meto-
do umano” (“human method”). “The human method that Gramsci proposes is
nothing else but philological method, spread across the whole experience of
living”. It is philology applied to oneself. According to Debenedetti’s reading,
Gramsci seems to say, “Nothing that is human is foreign to me”. This expresses
“the classical ideal of man”,55 where every factor on the intimate and individual
plane must be taken into account. I cannot allow myself to go on about all the
49 On the close link, both problematic and temporal, between the letter to Tania and the
paragraph in Quaderno 15 (“Notebook 15”) cf. in particular Gerratana 1990: 189–202. Re-
garding the editorial details surrounding Tania’s letter and the publication of Gramsci’s
“Note autobiografiche” (“Autobiographical notes”) and the political implications of De-
benedetti’s reading cf. Forenza 2013, pp. 123–136.
50 Debenedetti 1972: 16. The same theme is also taken up in the article for “l’Unità”, in Santar-
elli 1991: 265.
51 Santarelli 1991: 264.
52 Ibid.
53 Ibid.
54 Santarelli 1991: 265.
55 Santarelli 1991: 267.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
136 Zanantoni
56 Cf. especially the two texts already cited by Gerratana and Ragazzini.
57 Cf. Gramsci 1962. Following Gramsci’s texts is Dibattito per un’antologia di Gramsci, in-
cluding selections by Mario Alicata, Giacomo Debenedetti, Giansiro Ferrata, Franco Ferri,
Niccolò Gallo, Giancarlo Vigorelli, Gramsci 1962: 14–30 (cf. in particular Forenza 2013:
131–132).
58 Gramsci 1964.
59 Togliatti 1964 (cf. it also in Togliatti 2014a: 1186–1189).
60 Togliatti 1964: 1187.
61 Togliatti 1964: 1187–1188.
62 Togliatti 1964: 1189.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 137
intensify, developing on its three main fronts: the history of intellectuals and
literary criticism, the history of Italy and the anti-Croce philosophical project.
Even in the field of philosophical studies, Togliatti’s elaboration was deci-
sive in defining the traits of Gramsci’s legacy. His interpretation was focused, as
it is known, on two central aspects: the affirmation of the absolute historicity
of social and political reality and therefore the definition of Marxism as “abso-
lute historicism”63 and on the other side, the value of Italian cultural tradition,
an underscoring that also involved a reflection on the relationship between
Gramsci and the tradition of idealism.64 It was Eugenio Garin who best and
most profoundly delved into this work. In Cronache di filosofia italiana (“Chron-
icles of Italian Philosophy”) conceived and published between 1951 and 1953
and then gathered in to a volume in 1955,65 Garin represents a moment of rup-
ture and contention in the historiographical debate, precisely in reference to
the Gramscian lesson. The Cronache, conceived around the same time as the
publication of the thematic edition of the Quaderni, had Gramsci’s thought at
their center, read in terms of “historicism” and “national tradition”, integrating
themselves in those same years with Tolgliatti’s formulation. But what Garin
highlighted in his research was the attempt to write, in line with Gramsci’s
direction, a history of Italian philosophy that was the history of Italian
intellectuals – an expression of their era and not the story of a purely specula-
tive vision of events and ideas. Following Gramsci’s formula, he reconfirmed
the historical task of Italian culture: the construction of Anti-Croce as a con-
struction of another type of hegemony – a task that, in his opinion, had not yet
been completed. Together with 1956 and his political-cultural reflections, even
the reading of Gramsci lived through disputes and defenses. The migration of
Communist intellectuals into other fields, and the modification of interpretive
categories created a strong discontinuity regarding substantial aspects of “his-
toricism” and the idea of translating Marxism into nationalist terms. In light of
this, the collective editorial operation of La città futura (“The City of the Fu-
ture”), the anthology of essays published by Feltrinelli66 seems almost specular
in comparison to Garin’s Cronache. La città futura aims at a reading of Grams-
cian thought that is completely opposed to Togliatti’s line of thought and con-
firms that of Eugenio Garin. In this anthology, two authors take up Gramscian
thought in a philosophical scope: Mario Tronti and Emilio Agazzi, intellectuals
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
138 Zanantoni
that were in different ways outside of and distant from the militant nature of
the pci (Italian Communist Party) and of “official Marxism”.
Through Gramsci, read and used in different ways by the historicist culture
prevalent in the pci, these two presented a theoretical program having as a
goal the elaboration of an Italian Marxism described as the philosophy of the
praxis and scientific methodology of political action. Their principal thesis
was that before the establishment of Marxism in Italy could take place, the
ideology of Benedetto Croce (an anti-Marxist cultural hegemony) had to be
demolished.
At the same time, such an establishment of Italian Marxism could not do
without the energizing sap of the one who, towards Croce, had begun the work
of demolition, that is, Antonio Gramsci and his conception of Marxism as a
philosophy of praxis. The establishment of Italian Marxism during the 1960s,
however, needed to demolish Croce’s thought in a way that was different from
Gramsci’s and to liberate itself from every influence of Gentile. It could occur
only through a more “genuine” re-reading of Marx’s teachings. It was the con-
sequence of this line that exactly 20 years later, another collective volume
(even this an expression of a “new Left” more radically opposed to the official
Left) resumed a reading of Gramsci that was in many ways analogous to the
theses of La città futura, analogous even in the interpreters of the time, with
the philosopher Emilio Agazzi who in the new anthology Gramsci. Una eredità
contrastata, published in 1979,67 in underlining what was “acceptable” about
Gramsci’s legacy, confirmed and highlighted its point of view regarding Grams-
ci’s unfinished Anti-Croce operation and the necessity to finish it through a
rethinking of Marx that was indispensable in order to overcome that “specula-
tive residue” of Gramsci and to reconnect that “dialectical melding of theory
and praxis in the structural moment of the economy that is the central point of
Marxim”.68
If, as we have previously seen, the Cronache of Garin constituted (in the
light of a convinced adhesion to Gramcian thought) the attempt of a history of
Italian intellectuals from the point of view of a history of philosophy, Alberto
Asor Rosa represents, in my opinion, one who like no other, successfully at-
tempted in the same timeframe, to write an analogous history of Italian intel-
lectuals in the view of literary culture. While in fact maintaining some of the
negative criticisms of Gramsci’s thought expressed in his famous 1965 book,
Scrittori e popolo69 (“Writers and People”), – an illusory ideology of progress, an
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 139
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
140 Zanantoni
76 For the “revolutionary” discovery of Gramsci by Giuseppe Petronio cf. Paladini Musitelli
2003: 76.
77 Cf. Gatto 2016: 81–83. Gatto’s book constitutes one of the few recent positive additions to
the field of contemporary Gramscian criticism (and not only in the literary field) noted
for its wealth of analysis and information.
78 Gatto 2016: 162–164.
79 Cecchi 1974.
80 Ragionieri, in Cecchi 1974: 58.
81 Togliatti, in Daniele 2005: 17.
82 Candeloro 1956–1986.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 141
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
142 Zanantoni
or limits.89 These limits were more strongly highlighted by those who intended
to re-read Italian history from the point of view of the working class. Such was
the case of historian Stefano Merli who, albeit very critical towards the tradi-
tion of Gramscian historiography, nevertheless in his introduction to his un-
surpassed and weighty volume on the formation of the industrial proletariat in
the last two decades of the 1800s,90 warned against the Manichean vision of
history that a working class reading produced. That type of reading that had
produced its own paradigmatic text: Proletari senza rivoluzione (“Proletariats
Without Revolution”) by Renzo Del Carria, edited in 1966 and well known be-
tween 1968 and the early 1970s. Del Carria, who put a group of Gramsci’s writ-
ings in the final Bibliography, recalled the Sardinian thinker, in a line of conti-
nuity from Marx and Lenin, as a discoverer of the study of the autonomous
protest of the subaltern classes and of their becoming revolutionary classes.91
Del Carria was the most ideologically extreme manifestation of a certain read-
ing of Gramsci: the Gramsci who in the political battles of 1968 and in the ex-
pressions of the “new Left” of those years, became the only theorist and orga-
nizer of factory councils, the journalist of the new order, the revolutionary that
changed the perspective from party to class, the theorist of hegemony of the
war of position read as a search for dominion and for the violent and revolu-
tionary act, the young Gramsci against the imprisoned Gramsci, expression of
Togliatti’s opportunism and of the revisionism and reformism of the pci.
The convention in Florence in December 1977 was the last moment for a
lively debate surrounding Gramsci’s legacy: a debate in which the political and
cultural polemics between the supporters of the pci and its opposers found
(through Gramsci and his use) the reasons for a bitter confrontation. But the
convention also brought deeper theoretical and political understanding.
The last two decades of the 1900s (especially the 1980s) were the years of
Gramsci’s oblivion, or better, of a debate surrounding the Sardinian thinker,
especially in Italy. On the one hand, they were years of expansion in the world
of Gramsci’s thought and on the other hand, a time of pointing out the herme-
neutics as well as the terminological and conceptual clarification of Gramsci’s
work produced during his time in prison. This operation, which had and has in
Gianni Francioni one of the most constant scholars of Gramscian philology,
however, was the indispensable premise, together with the discovery and ac-
quisition of new documentation, to add to that innovative season of Grams-
cian studies that had definitively overpassed – as Giuseppe Vacca wrote well,
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 143
“the most serious distortion of both recent and past Gramscian studies: the
dissociation of his life from his thought”.92 The two works of scholars that are
decidedly different are the 2012 volume written by Vacca93 and the new biogra-
phy of Gramsci by Angelo d’Orsi:94 the most recent expressions albeit in differ-
ent languages and with different intentions.
The national edition of the writings and letters of Antonio Gramsci, now in
progress, will surely offer new perspective and stimuli. It will be up to the new
generations of researchers to understand how to grasp them. But this is the
history of the future.
Bibliography
Gramsci’s Works
Gramsci, A. (1946), Lettere dal carcere, in “Il Politecnico”, 33–34, September–December.
Gramsci, A. (1962), Carte inedite di Antonio Gramsci, in “L’Europa Letteraria”, ii, 13–14,
February–April.
Gramsci, A. (1964), 2000 pagine di Gramsci, (Milano: Il Saggiatore).
Gramsci, A. (1947), Lettere dal carcere (Torino: Einaudi).
Other Works
Agazzi, E. et al. (1979), Gramsci. Un’eredità contrastata. La nuova sinistra rilegge Grams-
ci (Milano: Ed. Ottiaviano).
Ajello, N. (1979), Intellettuali e PCI. 1944–1958 (Bari: Laterza).
Albertini, M. (1947), Un Gramsci edificante, in “Lo Stato moderno”, 17, September 5th.
Asor Rosa, A. (1965), Scrittori e popolo. Saggio sulla letteratura populista in Italia (Roma:
Samonà e Savelli).
Asor Rosa, A. (1976), Storia d’Italia. Dall’Unità ad oggi, iv/2 (Torino: Einaudi).
Asor Rosa, A. (1972), Sintesi di storia della letteratura italiana (Firenze: La Nuova Italia).
Asor Rosa, A. (1978), Una risposta, in Macry, P., Palermo, A. (eds.), Società e cultura
dell’Italia unita (Napoli: Guida).
Berlinguer, M. (1945), in “Mercurio”, 11, July, pp. 27–31.
Calvino, I. (1947), Antonio Gramsci. Lettere dal carcere, in “L’Amico del popolo”, May 1st.
Candeloro, G. (1956–1986), Storia dell’Italia moderna (Milano: Feltrinelli).
Caracciolo, A., Scalia, G. (eds.) (1959), La città futura. Saggi sulla figura e il pensiero di
Antonio Gramsci (Milano: Feltrinelli).
92 Vacca 2017: 4.
93 Vacca 2012.
94 d’Orsi 2017.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
144 Zanantoni
Cecchi, O. (ed.) (1974), La ricerca storica marxista in Italia (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Chiarotto, F. (2011), Operazione Gramsci. Alla conquista degli intellettuali nell’Italia del
dopoguerra (Milano: Mondadori).
Croce, B. (1947), Lettere dal carcere di Antonio Gramsci, in “Quaderni della Critica”, iii, 8.
Croce, B. (1948), Il materialismo storico e la filosofia di Benedetto Croce, in “Quaderni
della Critica”, iv, 10.
D’Anna, G. (1988), La “scoperta” di Antonio Gramsci. Le “Lettere” e i “Quaderni del car-
cere” nel dibattito italiano 1944–1952, in “Italia contemporanea”, 211.
D’Ina, G., Zaccaria, G. (eds.) (2007), Caro Bompiani. Lettere con l’editore (Milano:
Bompiani).
d’Orsi, A. (2017), Gramsci. Una nuova biografia (Milano: Feltrinelli).
Daniele, C. (ed.) (2005), Togliatti editore di Gramsci (Roma: Carocci).
Debenedetti, G. (1947a), Gramsci, uomo classico, in “l’Unità” (Roma), May 22.
Debenedetti, G. (1947b), Gramsci uomo classico, in “l’Unità” (Milano), June 1.
Debenedetti, G. (1972), Il metodo umano di Antonio Gramsci. Appunti del 1947 per un
saggio sulle “Lettere dal carcere”, in “Rinascita”, 39.
Del Carria, R. [1966] (1970), Proletari senza rivoluzione. Storia delle classi subalterne ital-
iane dal 1860 al 1950 (Milano: Oriente).
Diaz, F. (1980), Gli intellettuali dall’Unità alla Grande Guerra, in Tranfaglia, N. (ed.),
L’Italia unita nella storiografia del secondo dopoguerra (Milano: Feltrinelli).
Forenza, E. (2013), Il Gramsci “molecolare” di Giacomo Debenedetti: il problema politico
dell’autobiografia, in “Historia Magistra”, 13.
Garin, E. (1975), Cronache di filosofia italiana 1900–1943 (Roma-Bari: Laterza).
Gatto, M. (2016), Nonostante Gramsci. Marxismo e critica letteraria nell’Italia del
Novecento (Macerata: Quodlibet).
Gerratana, V. (1990), Unità della persona e dissoluzione del soggetto, in Muscatello, B.
(ed.), Gramsci e il marxismo contemporaneo (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Hobsbawm, E.J. (1978), La fortuna delle edizioni di Marx ed Engels, in AA.VV. Storia del
marxismo, 1, Il marxismo ai tempi di Marx (Torino: Einaudi).
Liguori, G. (1996), Gramsci conteso. Storia di un dibattito 1922–1996 (Roma: Editori
Riuniti).
Liguori, G. (2012), Gramsci conteso. Interpretazioni, dibattiti e polemiche 1922–2012
(Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Liguori, G., Meta, C. (2005), Gramsci. Guida alla lettura (Milano: Unicopli).
Luperini, R. (1971), Gli intellettuali di sinistra e l’ideologia della ricostruzione nel dopogu-
erra (ii), in “Ideologie”, 15.
Mangoni, L. (1999), Pensare i libri. La casa editrice Einaudi dagli anni trenta agli anni
settanta (Torino: Bollati Boringhieri).
Merli, S. (1972–1973), Proletariato di fabbrica e capitalismo industriale. Il caso italiano:
1880–1900, 2 vol. (Firenze: La Nuova Italia).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The Influence and Legacy of Antonio Gramsci 145
Mustè, M. (2017), La presenza di Gramsci nella storiografia filosofica e nella storia della
cultura, in “Filosofia Italiana”, special issue L’influenza di Gramsci in Italia e nel mon-
do, 2.
Napolitano, G. (2017), Memorial speech for Gramsci, in “l’Unità”, 28th April.
Paladini Musitelli, M. (2003), Ricordo di Giuseppe Petronio, in “Critica Marxista”, 1.
Pane, A. (2017), Debenedetti e “l’Unità”: la ‘Verticale’ del 1946–47, in “Prassi Ecdotiche
della Modernità letteraria”, 2.
Ragazzini, D. (2002), Leonardo nella società di massa. Teoria della personalità in Grams-
ci (Bergamo: Moretti Honegger).
Ragionieri, E. (1976), La storia politica e sociale, in Storia d’Italia. Dall’Unità ad oggi, iv/3
(Torino: Einaudi).
Russo, L. (1947), Antonio Gramsci e l’educazione democratica in Italia, in “Belfagor”, 4.
Santarelli, E. (1991), Gramsci ritrovato 1937–1947 (Catanzaro: Abramo).
Sereni, E. (1962), Mercato nazionale e accumulazione capitalistica nell’unità italiana, in
Problemi dell’Unità d’Italia (Roma: Editori Riuniti).
Sereni, E. (1972), Agricoltura e mondo rurale, in “I caratteri originali”, Storia d’Italia,
vol. i, (Torino: Einaudi).
Togliatti, P. (1946), Politica e cultura. Una lettera di Palmiro Togliatti, in “Il Politecnico”.
Togliatti, P. (1949), Gramsci (Milano: Milano-sera Editrice).
Togliatti, P. (1964), Gramsci, un uomo, in “Paese sera”, June 19th.
Togliatti, P. (2014a), La politica nel pensiero e nell’azione. Scritti e discorsi 1917–1964, Cili-
berto, M., Vacca, G. (eds.) (Milano: Bompiani).
Togliatti, P. (2014b), La guerra di posizione in Italia. Epistolario 1944–1964 (Torino:
Einaudi).
Vacca, G. (2012), Vita e pensieri di Antonio Gramsci 1926–1937 (Torino: Einaudi).
Vacca, G. (2017), Modernità alternative. Il Novecento di Antonio Gramsci (Torino:
Einaudi).
Vicario, G. (ed.) (1984), Gli scrittori e l’Unità. Antologia di racconti 1945–1980 (Roma:
l’Unità).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Chapter 13
Davide Cadeddu
1 Cf. Ferri 1977; in specific, for the English context, cf. Showstack Sassoon 1980.
2 Cf. spn, Gramsci 1973, SPW-1, SPW-2.
3 Cf, for example, Aricó 1988.
4 Cf. Williams 1980; Hall 1987, Said 1993; Guha 1983.
5 Cf. Q.
6 Cf. Gramsci 1978–1996; Gramsci 1981; Gramsci 1981–2000; Gramsci 1999–2002; Gramsci 1991–
2002; Gramsci 1992–2011.
7 For the most recently updated description see Bibliografia gramsciana: http://bg.fondazion
egramsci.org/biblio-gramsci.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
148 Cadeddu
Francesco Giasi and Maria Luisa Righi with the collaboration of the Interna-
tional Gramsci Society.13
Once we find our bearings inside of a cultural production whose value is as
vast as it is inhomogeneous, we can identify which works deserve to be in-
cluded in a general historiographical analysis and which others have little to do
with historiography (being more appropriately placed in the area of political
and social theory or directly in the arena of political and cultural struggle with
its consequent ideological uses). From the historiographical point of view, An-
tonio Gramsci clearly emerges as a completely complex and rare case, precise-
ly in relation to his worldwide diffusion and to his “global” being in almost all
the meanings this adjective could assume. The complexity of the situation fac-
ing us therefore suggests that we must identify some categories and, without
being overwhelmed by an infinite mass of information, bring ourselves to be
able to discern.
First of all, we must have a clear idea of what we mean by historiography. If
everything is history, “nothing else but history”,14 certainly not everything is
historiographical production, at least not in its narrow, specialized and scien-
tific meaning. Historiographical analysis involves the historical reconstruction
of past events or the historicized interpretation of an expression of human
creativity, which in our case could be either political thought or the general
thought of an author. The production of political theories or other various
theories certainly does not belong to historiography, because they draw liber-
ally on suggestions offered by the past, with the scope of interpreting (with
some well-defined or less well-defined categories, more or less adherent to the
original formulation) questions and realities that are contemporary to us or at
least not contemporary to the original formulation of that thought and those
categories. We were taught that historiography always springs from a present
interest,15 but must avoid the danger of falling into the temptation of allowing
a commingling of past and present, with the possible consequence of an
anachronistic reading of both past and present.16
The international fame of Antonio Gramsci, as evidenced by the production
of the historiography of international relations, subaltern studies and cultural
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The International Historiography on Gramsci 149
17 See Schirru 2009. For a concise view, see Vacca, Capuzzo, Schirru 2008 and Manduchi,
Marchi, Vacca 2017. See also Filippini 2017.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
150 Cadeddu
facing two obstacles directly connected to his global being and to the effects
that globalization has produced around him as a subject of study.18
Undoubtedly, the first obstacle impeding historiographic dialogue is of a
quantitative type. Scanning the aforementioned Bibliografia gramsciana, one
understands the material impossibility of a single human being able cope
with the overflowing mass of essays and volumes published every year. This
problem is certainly a characteristic of our times where with the ease of self-
publishing, there is a greater certainty of making one’s own writing public (at
least on the web page of a private blog) and a smaller chance of actually being
read. The sheer quantity of words that hit each of us every day is simply too
overwhelming.
As if anything more was needed, the second obstacle, making a complete
historiographical mastery of our theme impossible is of a linguistic type. As
already mentioned, talking about it in positive terms, the fact that translations
of Gramsci’s writings exist in more than forty languages and that about half of
the literature dedicated to him, produced every year, is written in languages
other than Italian.19 Clearly, this aspect also constitutes a limit to the circula-
tion of ideas and to the complexity and completeness of the historiographical
debate.
Even in recently published works by authoritative scholars, the references
to studies by authors not belonging to the world of linguistics in bibliographies
(or in footnotes) is relatively scarce, when compared to the richness of inter-
national production.20 Certainly, the relevance is often connected to the place
and modality of cultural expression (publishing house, journal and diffusion
of the language used), but we also are well aware that this is not always the case
and illuminating passages may also be found in the so-called minor scientific
literature. What is beginning to be seen as true in many historiographic areas is
even macroscopic in Gramsci. International historiography in the 21st century
seems to be almost devoid of dialogue or, more precisely, this historiographi-
cal dialogue seems to be very limited, even despite the continuous and Pro-
methean efforts of both the Fondazione Gramsci onlus (Gramsci F oundation
18 For a “more balanced history of political thought”, from a global view, see Babb 2018,
where the goal is “to identify the key political thinkers throughout world history”, who
“have had influence, substance and relevance”. On this theme in general, see Middell,
Hadler 2007.
19 Cf. Lussana, Pissarello 2008.
20 Cf., for instance, the recent study by Grelle (2017), which mentions only studies in
English.
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The International Historiography on Gramsci 151
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
152 Cadeddu
Bibliography
Other Works
Aricó, J. (1988), La cola del diablo. Itinerario de Gramsci en America Latina (Buenos Ai-
res: Puntosur).
Babb, J. (2018), A World History of Political Thought (Cheltenham, UK-Northampton,
usa: Edward Elgar).
Buttigieg, J.A. (1992), Editorial, in “International Gramsci Society Newsletter”, 1, http://
www.internationalgramscisociety.org/igsn/index.html.
Carlucci, A. (2013), Gramsci and Languages. Unification, Diversity, Hegemony (Leiden-
Boston: Brill).
Cospito, G. (2016), The Rhythm of Thought in Gramsci. A Diachronic Interpretation of
Prison Notebooks (Leiden-Boston: Brill).
Coutinho, C.N. (1999), Gramsci: Um estudo sobre seu pensamento político (Rio de Ja-
neiro: Civilização Brasileira); Italian version (2006), Il pensiero politico di Gramsci
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
The International Historiography on Gramsci 153
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
154 Cadeddu
Lussana, F., Pissarello, G. (eds.) (2008), La lingua/le lingue di Gramsci e delle sue opere.
Scrittura, riscritture, letture in Italia e nel mondo. Atti del Convegno internazionale di
studi, Sassari, 24–26 ottobre 2007, with an introductory essay by Vacca, G. (Soveria
Mannelli: Rubbettino).
Manduchi, P., Marchi, A., Vacca, G. (eds.) (2017), Studi gramsciani nel mondo. Gramsci
nel mondo arabo (Bologna: il Mulino).
Middell, M., Hadler, F. (2007), Challenges to the History of Historiography in an Age
of Globalization, in Wang, Q.E., Fillafer, F.L. (eds.), The Many Faces of Clio. Cross-
Cultural Approaches to Historiography. Essays in Honor of Georg G. Iggers (New York-
Oxford: Berghahn Books), pp. 293–306.
Righi, M.L. (1995), Gramsci nel mondo. Atti del convegno internazionale di studi grams-
ciani (Formia, 25–28 ottobre 1989) (Roma: Editori Riuniti-Fondazione Istituto
Gramsci).
Said, E. (1993), Culture and Imperialism (New York: Knopf).
Schirru, G. (ed.) (2009), Gramsci, le culture e il mondo (Roma: Viella).
Showstack Sassoon, A. (1980), The “Gramsci Boom”: A Reflection on the Present Crisis?, in
“Politics & Power”, 1, pp. 203–211.
Thomas, P.D. (2008), The Gramscian Moment: Philosophy, Hegemony and Marxism
(Leiden: Brill).
Vacca, G. (2017), Introduzione. Gli studi gramsciani oggi in Italia, in Vacca, G., Modernità
alternative. Il Novecento di Antonio Gramsci (Torino: Einaudi, 2017).
Vacca, G., Capuzzo, P., Schirru, G. (eds.) (2008), Studi gramsciani nel mondo. Gli studi
culturali (Bologna: il Mulino).
Williams, R. (1980), Problems in Materialism and Culture: Selected Essays (London:
Verso).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Bibliographic Abbreviations
agr: Forgacs, D. (ed.) (2000), The Gramsci Reader. Selected Writings 1916–1935 (New
York: NYU Press).
CW: Forgacs, D., Nowell-Smith, G. (eds.) (1985), Selections from Cultural Writings (Cam-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
fspn: Boothman, D. (ed.) (1995), Further Selections from the Prison Notebooks (Minne-
apolis: Minnesota University Press).
hpc: Cavalcanti, P., Piccone, P. (eds.) (1975), History, Philosophy and Culture in the
Young Gramsci (St. Louis: Telos Press).
LC: Caprioglio, S., Fubini, E. (eds.) (1965), Lettere dal carcere (Torino: Einaudi).
LC2: Santucci, A. (ed.) (1996), Lettere dal carcere. 1926–1937 (Palermo: Sellerio).
LT: Natoli, A., Daniele, C. (eds.) (1997), A. Gramsci, T. Schucht, Lettere. 1926–1935 (Tori-
no: Einaudi).
NM: Capioglio, S. (ed.) (1984), Il nostro Marx (1918–1919) (Torino: Einaudi).
PN: Buttigieg, J.A. (ed.) (1992, 1996, 2007), Prison Notebooks (New York: Columbia Uni-
versity Press), 3 vols.
ppw: Bellamy, R. (ed.) (1994), Pre-Prison Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press).
Q: Gerratana, V. (ed.) (1975), Quaderni del carcere (Torino: Einaudi), 4 vols.
spi: Spriano, P. (ed.), (1973), Scritti politici (Roma: Editori Riuniti), 3 vols.
spn: Hoare, Q., Nowell-Smith, G. (eds.) (1971), Selection from the Prison Notebooks (New
York: International Publishers).
SPW-1: Hoare, Q., Nowell Smith, G. (eds.) (1977), Selections from Political Writings, 1910–
1920 (London: Lawrence & Wishart; New York: International Publisher).
SPW-2: Hoare, Q. (ed.) (1978), Selections from Political Writings (1921–1926) (New York:
International Publishers; London: Lawrence and Wishart).
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Index
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Index 157
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
158 Index
base 48, 65, 68, 140 Liguori, Guido 55, 68, 69, 77n19, 78, 104, 127,
mode of production 48, 65, 84, 120 130n20, 139n70, 144, 147, 148n13, 153
relations of production 48, 75, 81 Litri, Marina 153
structure 48, 54, 60, 65, 67, 68, 77, 79, 83, Lukács, György 67
85, 87, 98, 108, 110, 139 Luperini, Romano 130n20, 140, 144
superstructure 48, 54, 65–68, 77, 83, 98, Lussana, Fiamma 150n19, 154
110, 139
historicism 44, 47, 104, 137 Macherey, Pierre 55
absolute historicism 47, 137 Machiavelli, Niccolò , viii 21, 111, 116,
anti-historicism 44 122, 133
Hoare, Quintin 25, 37, 46, 55, 68, 78, 89, 103, Macis, Enrico 17
113, 122, 152, 155 Manduchi, Patrizia 149n17, 154
Hobsbawm, Eric John Ernest 130n23, 144 Mangoni, Luisa 129n18, 144
Marchi, Alessandra 149n17, 154
idealism 8, 9, 59, 70, 137 Martelli, Michele 96n6, 104
neo-idealism 70 Martin, James 95n5, 100n15, 103, 104
ideology 39, 54, 88, 93, 119, 123, 138, 153 Martinelli, Renzo 4n5, 11
Igger, Georg 148n16, 153, 154 Marx, Karl 8, 9, 22, 47–49, 53–56, 59–81,
Il Grido del popolo 6, 11 83, 85, 89, 106, 109, 111, 130, 138, 142,
imperialism 7, 33, 154 144, 155
intellectuals 23, 32, 33, 34n17, 35, 39, 40, 52, Marxism 8, 9, 38, 44, 60, 62, 63, 64, 67, 70, 71,
55, 66, 110, 115, 129, 130, 131, 134, 137–140, 74–77, 81, 117, 137, 138, 140, 146
146, 149 Mastellone, Salvo 100n15, 104
organic intellectuals 23, 115, 134 Mathiez, Albert 72
internationalism 4, 31, 35, 36 Mazzini, Giuseppe 18, 99, 121
Ives, Peter 102n19, 104 McNally, Mark 104
Medici, Rita 72n7, 78
Jacobinism 72, 139 Mensheviks 80
Jacobin revolution 72 Merli, Stefano 142, 144
Jacobins 72 Mezzadra, Sandro 114n3, 123
Jehle, Peter 152 Michels, Robert 6
Middell, Matthias 150n18, 154
Kant, Immanuel 39, 42, 43, 44, 46 Monticone, Alberto 6n7, 11
Kautsky, Karl 73, 130 Morera, Esteve 94n3, 104
Kerenskij, Aleksandr Fëdorovič 73 Mouffe, Chantal 117, 123
Kojéve, Alexandre 39 Mukherjee, Supriya 148n16, 153
Kuck, Gerhard 152 Muscetta, Carlo 132
Mussolini, Benito 3
L’Ordine Nuovo 10–12, 29, 36, 72, 89, 112 Musté, Marcello 137n64–65, 145
Labriola, Antonio 70, 128, 149
Laclau, Ernesto 114–119, 121, 123 Napolitano, Giorgio 132n31, 145
Lange, Friedrich-Albert Lange 65 nation-state 7, 54, 120
Lassalle, Ferdinand 84 central-bureaucratic state 94
Le Trosne, Guillaume 108 coercive state 82, 84
Lenin, Vladimir Il’ič 60, 72, 73, 75–77, 80, night-watchman state 82, 84
83, 85, 89, 111, 117, 142 national-popular 18, 23
Lentner, Howard H. 95n5, 98n10, 99n12, 104 nationalism 4, 31, 33, 35, 120
Leopardi, Giacomo 135 Natoli, Aldo 25, 46, 155
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
Index 159
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University
160 Index
- 978-90-04-42651-1
Downloaded from Brill.com03/20/2023 10:32:30PM
via Western University