The Symposium of Plato (1991) - R. E. Allen's Translation.
The Symposium of Plato (1991) - R. E. Allen's Translation.
VO LUME 2
Kylix (wine cup), Attic red-figured, early fifth century B.C. Louvre AGR G. 144.
© Photo R.M.N. Potter: Hieron. Height 0.12 cm, diameter 0.315 cm. Formerly
in Campana Coll. Hoppin, Handbook of Attic Red-Figured Vases, no. 23*. Signature
painted on handle: HIEPON.
TOP: Dionysus between two ithyphallic satyrs with wine pot and flute, and two
maenads with castanets, thyrsus, and cup.
BOTTOM: Satyr with flutes between four maenads, two with thyrsus, one with lyre,
one with mixing bowl. The posture of the last is twisted, in a triumph of com-
position, as though to represent not only motion but the mixing.
Such a cup might have graced Agathon's tables the evening of the banquet. (The
medallion is reproduced on page xii.)
PLATO
THE SYMPOSIUM
Translated with Comment by
R. E. ALLEN
Plato.
[Symposium. English]
The symposium / translated with analysis by
R. E. Allen.
p. cm. — (The Dialogues of Plato ; v. 2)
Includes index.
ISBN 0-300-04874-2 (cloth)
ISBN 978-0-300-05699-0 (pbk.)
PREFACE vii
COMMENT 3
Prologue: Apollodorus to a Companion (ij2a—iJ4a) 3
Aristodemus's Prologue (ijjOr-ijje) 6
Eryximachus Proposes Speeches in Praise of Eros (ij6a—ij8a) 7
The Speech of Phaedrus (i j8a—i Sob) 12
The Speech of Pausanias (iSoc—iSjc) 14
First Interlude: Aristophanes and His Hiccups (i8jc-e) 20
Dionysus 20
The Speech of Eryximachus (i8je—i88e) 26
Eryximachus and Greek Medicine 28
Second Interlude: Aristophanes Recovered from His Hiccups
(i89a-c) 30
The Speech of Aristophanes (iS^c—iy^e) 31
Third Interlude: Socrates and Agathon (iQje—igje) 37
The Speech of Agathon (iqie—iyje) 38
Fourth Interlude: Two Kinds of Encomium (iqSa—iygc) 40
The Speech of Socrates (IQQC—2i2c) 41
The Elenchus of Agathon (i^c—2Oic) 41
The Speech of Diotima (201 d-212a) 46
Eros as Intermediate (2Oid-2O2d) 47
Eros as Daimon (2O2d-2o^a) 48
The Myth of Poros and Penia (2030-6) 49
Plotinus and Ficino 50
Eros as Philosopher (2Oje—2O4c) 53
Eros as Wish for Happiness (2040—205(1) 54
False Consciousness: Plato and Freud 58
Diotima's Definition of Eros (2050-2060) 60
v
Vi CONTENTS
The Symposium is the most widely read of Plato's dialogues with the single
exception of the Republic, and this for good reason. Its literary merit is
unsurpassed, and beneath the shining splendor of its surface it is con-
structed with the precision and something of the intricacy of a Swiss
watch. Its philosophical, psychological, and religious force is revolution-
ary, offering a vision of what it means to live a human life founded on a
transcendent principle of Beauty which, itself intelligible, is the source of
all intelligibility and the ultimate aim of all loving. The Nachleben of the
dialogue, as the Germans call it, its afterlife and influence, is very nearly
as broad as the breadth of humane letters in the West; in the matter of
Quellenstudien, it is not a spring, but a mighty river. Aristotle's theory of
contemplation in the Nicomachean Ethics, as well as his theology in Meta-
physics XII, where God is the primary object of both intellect and desire,
and moves by being loved, is indebted to Diotima. So is Plotinus's account
of beauty. Through Plotinus and, in aftertime, Aristotle, the indirect ef-
fect of the Symposium on medieval philosophy and theology, on Augustine
and Bonaventure and Aquinas, was very great. Ficino picked up Pausan-
ias's muddled distinction between sacred and profane love, which the Sym-
posium clarifies in the contrast between the speeches of Aristophanes and
Alcibiades and the speech of Diotima, and, combining with it much that
is borrowed from Plotinus, forged it into a theory of the relation of art
and beauty which guided the mind of Michelangelo and helped sustain
the Renaissance. In nineteenth-century Germany, Aristophanes and Ro-
manticism triumphed over Diotima's rationalism, and the triumph of the
drunken comedian was ratified by Nietzsche in The Birth of Tragedy, which
presents an incongruous counterpart of the symposium, inverted. After
Nietzsche came Freud, to make the divorce between desire and reason
vii
Vlll PREFACE
final and to proclaim that sacred love is in its inner essence profane, even
as Diotima had proclaimed that profane love is in its inner essence sacred.
An account of the afterlife of the Symposium might easily grow into a
general survey of Western culture—and a very large book. A commen-
tator may properly be excused from such a task. What follows is an in-
troductory account of this singularly powerful dialogue, along with some
cursory remarks on its Nachleben, and a translation meant to allow the
Greekless reader to follow the thought of the dialogue for himself with
some degree of literalness. In making the translation, I have relied on
Burnet's text, occasionally departing from it where variance seemed triv-
ial, or where manuscript readings seemed to me to preserve a satisfactory
sense without emendation. I have constantly consulted R. G. Bury's edi-
tion, which is especially valuable for its insight into structure and its sen-
sitiveness to rhetorical shading, as well as Kenneth Dover's, from whom I
have silently adopted many suggested translations of words and phrases.
Among translators, I have usefully consulted W. R. M. Lamb in the Loeb
Classical Library, Leon Robin in the Bude edition, and the fourth edition
of Jowett, revised by D. J. Allan and H. E. Dale; the version by Alexander
Nehamas and Paul Woodruff, eagerly anticipated, proved unhelpful.1 I
must also acknowledge with gratitude the criticism and suggestions of stu-
dents and friends, Dougal Blyth, now lecturer in classics at Auckland, and
David Ambuel of Northwestern, as well as the helpful comments of such
colleagues as John Anton, Daniel Garrison, David Konstan, Stuart Small,
and David White.
A word needs to be said, I suppose, even in so short a preface as this,
about Platonic love. The late Renaissance made that love a kind of com-
panionship between persons of opposite sex in which there was no ele-
ment of sexual desire, and the notion has stuck. But for Plato, or if you
will, Diotima, love implies active concern for the virtue and goodness of
another soul, founded on the love of Goodness itself; it also implies sex-
uality, since sexuality finds its purpose in the intercourse of man and
woman for the procreation of children and the continuation of the race.
Still, there is an important truth encapsulated in the Renaissance mistake.
Freud, analyzing the neurotics of Vienna at the end of the Victorian era,
concluded that much mental disorder arose from sexual repression. It is
i. R. G. Bury, ed., The Symposium of Plato, 2d ed., Cambridge, 1932 (hereafter cited as
Bury, Symposium). Kenneth Dover, ed., Plato: Symposium, Cambridge, 1980 (hereafter, Dover,
Symposium). Plato: Lysis, Symposium, Gorgias, trans. W. R. M. Lamb, Boston, 1926. Platon: Le
Banquet, trans. L£on Robin, Paris, 1929. Plato: Symposium, trans. Alexander Nehamas and
Paul Woodruff, Indianapolis, 1989. Compare Plato: The Symposium, trans. Walter Hamilton,
New York, 1951.
PREFACE ix
not a cause likely to have troubled an Athenian of the fifth century B.C.,
and the Symposium may be read, at one level at least, as an argument that
a bit more in the way of sexual repression might prove conducive to men-
tal health. The Symposium, indeed, offers an argument for a degree of
abstinence verging on asceticism.
A further word, both literary and logical, about Eros as personified and
as a relation in the speech of Diotima. It may be said that Plato treats Eros
as the domain of a relation, taken distributively. The personification of
Eros in the speech of Diotima is not merely a literary device: Eros is the
lover qua lover, each lover just insofar as he loves. It will be evident that
the lover qua lover cannot be identified with the lover considered apart
from that relation. If the soul is immortal, as Socrates argues in the
Phaedo, then, given Diotima's claim that the lover qua lover lacks immor-
tality and desires to possess it, this must imply that Eros is not Psyche, and
it is a root of error to confound them.
The numbers and letters in the margins of the translation represent a
conventional way of locating and referring to passages in the dialogue.
They derive from the Stephanus edition of 1578, succeeding the Aldine
edition of 1513: Henri Estienne edited and printed, in three volumes, a
folio edition of numbered pages, with columns divided on the page—
whence the letters. The edition is set in type whose design had been com-
missioned by Francis I, king of France. It is a very beautiful book.
Medallion of kylix reproduced as frontispiece: Satyr seizing a maenad. She holds
by the tail a spotted panther who before death was a nursing female: the hunted
hunter, dead mother of life, an iconographic representation of the coincidence
and clash of opposites characteristic of Dionysiac religion. Elsewhere, the spotted
animal becomes a dappled fawn, or a spotted creature ambiguous between a
fawn and a panther.
THE SYMPOSIUM
This page intentionally left blank
COMMENT
2. See E. R. Goodenough, Jewish Symbols in the Greco-Roman Period, vol. 6, Wine, Prince-
ton, N.J., 1956, pp. 9-10.
3
4 COMMENT
rates was then in his mid-fifties and Alcibiades about thirty-four, at the
height of his brilliant career and influence. It was the year before the Si-
cilian Expedition of 415 B.C., which Alcibiades instigated; from it, Athens
lost a fleet and an army and began her long decline.
The narrative date, as distinct from the dramatic date, is less precise,
but determinable. Since Apollodorus checked the accuracy of Aristode-
mus's account with Socrates, it falls before the death of Socrates in
399 B.C., and indeed before the death of Agathon in about 401 B.C.,3 but
some years after Agathon left Athens (i72c), which was after 411 B.C.,
when he heard Antiphon's defense4 and was caricatured in Aristophanes'
Thesmophoriazusae, and probably after 407 B.C., when Agathon went to the
court of Archelaus in Macedonia. So the date of Apollodorus's narrative,
and Aristodemus's, must be over a decade after the banquet, around
402 B.C. The story is fresh in Apollodorus's memory—he told it to Glau-
con only a few days before—and he now agrees to tell it again to an un-
named companion.
Plato's introduction to the Symposium emphasizes the importance of the
speeches to follow, and specifically the accuracy of Apollodorus's account
of the speech of Socrates (i 990-2 i2c). Apollodorus is concerned to learn
and repeat a conversation that took place when he was merely a boy, and
there have been at least two recent reports of the speeches (i72b). 5 That
he has checked Aristodemus's account with Socrates implies the accuracy
of his account so far as the doctrine of Socrates is concerned, though not
(1783) of others.
The Symposium apart, only in the Phaedo and the Parmenides is a dialogue
narrated by someone other than Socrates, and then for the excellent rea-
son that Socrates is dead. He is not dead in the Symposium. But it would
have been impossible to put into Socrates' own mouth the scene with Al-
cibiades at the end, because it is an encomium of Socrates. Plato has at
the very beginning of the Symposium fashioned the narrative structure of
the dialogue around that final scene, which must therefore be important
to its interpretation.
6. Which also strongly suggests that the Symposium was composed after 385, as a terminus
a quo. This conforms to the stylometric evidence, as far as it goes. Aristotle's two references
to the Symposium (Politics 2.12620.12, De anima 2.4153 26) shed no light on the date of com-
position.
7. See Paul Friedlander, Plato, vol. 3, Princeton, 1969, p. 5.
6 COMMENT
Aristodemus's Prologue (
11. Platon: Le Banquet, trans. L£on Robin, Paris, 1929, pp. vii-viii.
COMMENT 9
speakers figure there, and this could scarcely be so had Plato not meant
to recall that dialogue to the minds of his readers.
When Socrates and Hippocrates go to the house of Callias to visit Pro-
tagoras, they find Eryximachus and Phaedrus listening to Hippias of Elis
lecture on nature and astronomy; Pausanias and Agathon are seated with
Prodicus of Ceos (Protagoras 315C—e). Alcibiades is present too, arriving
after Socrates (3 i6a). Prodicus of Ceos was a sophist best known, to Plato's
readers at least, for his genius in distinguishing the meanings of words
and determining the correctness of names;14 his influence is evident in the
speeches of Pausanias and Agathon, whose style, however, is also much
influenced by Gorgias. Hippias was a polymath who put himself forward
at Olympia as willing to answer any question and was never stumped;15
he taught young people calculation and astronomy and geometry and mu-
sic, the "arts" (Protagoras 3i8e), and his influence is present in the wide-
ranging natural history of Eros offered in the speech of Eryximachus. Of
the five initial speakers in the Symposium, four—Phaedrus, Pausanias,
Eryximachus, Agathon—exhibit in marked degree the tropes of sophis-
tical rhetoric. The single exception is Aristophanes, who was not present
in the Protagoras. Socrates in the Protagoras (347c—3483) also exactly an-
ticipates the rules laid down by Eryximachus in the Symposium in respect
to drinking parties, flute-girls, and speeches.
The dramatic date of the Protagoras is nearly twenty years earlier than
that of the Symposium, approximately 435 B.C.; this inference is based on
the youth of Alcibiades, who was just then getting his beard (Protagoras
3oga-b). The relationship between Socrates and Alcibiades is an impor-
tant thematic link between the two dialogues: the Protagoras opens with
Socrates being quizzed by an unnamed companion about his pursuit of
Alcibiades; the nature and consequences of that pursuit are explained by
Alcibiades himself in the Symposium.
There is a further connection between the two dialogues. The central
issue of the Protagoras is the worth of sophistic education, culture, paideia,
and this as represented, not by the likes of Euthydemus and Dionysodo-
rus, but by men of stature such as Hippias and Prodicus and the great
Protagoras himself. Hippocrates comes to Socrates before first light, in
great excitement: Protagoras has come to town, and Hippocrates wants
to study with him for the sake of paideia. Socrates warns him of danger.
Knowledge is the food of the soul,
14. Protagoras 3373, 3403, 3413, 3583, d; cf. Charmides 16301, Laches igyd, Euthydemus
2776, Meno 756.
15. Hippias Minor 3636^.; cf. Protagoras 3150.
COMMENT 11
and we must take care, dear friend, lest the sophist in praising what
he sells deceive us, as grocers and hucksters do with food for the body.
Though they don't at all know which among their wares benefits or
harms the body, they praise everything they sell; and those who buy
of them don't know either, unless they happen to be physicians or
trainers. It's the same with these people who tour our cities peddling
knowledge to whomever desires it; they too praise everything they
sell, but it may be, dear friend, that some of them are ignorant
whether the things they sell are good or bad for the soul. So too for
those who buy from them, unless they happen on the other hand to
be physicians of soul. So if you know what is good and what is bad,
you can buy your knowledge safely from Protagoras or anyone else;
but if you don't, look to it, dear friend, lest you risk and hazard things
of greatest value. For the risk is immensely greater when you pur-
chase knowledge than when you purchase food. You can buy food
and drink from a huckster and carry it away in another container,
and before you take it into your body by eating or drinking, you can
set it aside in your house and summon an expert to consult about
what should be eaten and drunk, and what should not, and how
much, and when; so there's no great risk in the purchase. But knowl-
edge cannot be carried away in another container. Having paid the
price, you must necessarily take what is learned into your very soul,
and depart either benefited or harmed.16
Protagoras will claim to teach virtue, the excellence of a man and a citizen;
the remainder of the Protagoras shows—literally exhibits—that this par-
ticular huckster of learning does not know whether what he sells is good
or bad. The speakers of the Symposium have paid their fees and carried
home the learning of the sophists in their souls. The dialogue not only
provides specimens of rhetoric, but exhibits the effects of rhetorical pai-
deia, culminating in the speech of Alcibiades at the end.
The speeches that follow have a ring structure, a structure peculiarly
suited to combining varied and diverse themes and holding them together
in the mind of the reader: it is a structure Plato repeatedly uses, with
astonishing success, in the Republic. Phaedrus makes Eros a god, and the
eldest; Pausanias makes him two gods; Eryximachus makes him two nat-
ural forces; Aristophanes makes him a single natural force in men; Aga-
thon, returning to Phaedrus, makes him a single god, but the youngest.
This structure is so effective that, though the individual speeches, with
nian coast, at Cytheria (hence her very common title, Kythereia). This
is no doubt the real reason why she is so commonly united with Ares,
who is her cult-partner here and there, and in mythology her lover
and sometimes the father of Eros. . . . To the same desire we may
attribute her mythical position as mother of Eros. This was a respect-
ably old god, worshipped at Thespiai in Boiotia, and at Parion in
Mysaia. Despite the constant association of 'Venus and Cupid' in lit-
erature, Eros has nothing whatever to do with her in anything but
late cult, and little in any literature before the Alexandrian period;
although in Hesiod he attends Aphrodite, he is not her son, but an
ancient cosmogonical power, which indeed he continued to be in theo-
logical and philosophic speculation. In the places where his worship
is of importance, he is quite markedly the deity of the loveliness of
young men and boys, to which, as is well known, the Greeks were
exceedingly susceptible. In Alexandrian times, however, the idea of
romantic love (not mere desire) between the sexes took possession of
literature, which is why most of the famous love-stories date from this
time. Eros therefore became more and more important, at the same
time losing his dignity; for whereas he was previously shown for the
most part as a handsome young athlete — his famous bow dates only
from the fourth century B.C. — he is now generally shown as a pretty
child, a little winged archer, capricious and mischievous, delighting
in working magic (by shooting an invisible arrow at them) on gods
and men alike. In literature, therefore, he appears for the most part
late and in a subordinate part, as part of the divine machinery for
making someone fall in love with someone else.23
Pausanias means to correct Phaedrus, who claimed that Eros is
No action is beautiful or ugly in and of itself, but beautiful if done beau-
tifully, ugly if done shamefully; Eros is beautiful or ugly according to the
kind of love it is. Vulgar Eros is directed toward women and young boys,
and to the body rather than the soul, and it is as inconstant as its objects.
Heavenly Eros is associated with Heavenly Aphrodite, who is motherless,
and directed solely toward the masculine, a principle superior in strength
and intelligence to the feminine. That is, it is directed not toward young
boys but toward adolescents, youths whose intelligence is beginning to
sprout with their beards. Vulgar Eros has brought pederasty into disre-
pute and should be forbidden by law, like adultery.
The v6juo$ — custom or law — concerning pederasty is in most places
23. H. J. Rose, A Handbook of Greek Mythology, New York, 1959, pp. 122—123.
\6 COMMENT
simple. Some Greek cities allow it, others forbid it, especially those in Ionia
under barbarian rule. In Athens, the law or custom is more complicated
and difficult to understand: people generally approve of the lover's suit,
no matter how extreme his importunity, and law permits this to be done
without reproach, its license even extending to the breaking of oaths and
promises, since a sexual vow is not binding as an oath. On the other hand,
parents in Athens prevent their sons from talking with lovers, and boys
are criticized by their contemporaries and their elders for allowing them-
selves to be seduced. So in Athens, pederasty seems to be regarded both
as beautiful and as shameful. But no act is simply beautiful or shameful
in itself, but beautiful if done beautifully, shameful if done shamefully—
Pausanias is a master of the ringing tautology. It is shameful to gratify an
unworthy lover, who is inconstant because he loves the bloom of the body,
which fades; but the worthy lover loves the soul and its virtue, the attri-
butes that constitute the excellence of a man and a citizen, and this love
is permanent and not inconstant.
And so, Pausanias avers, Athenian law provides a test for distinguishing
worthy lovers from those who ought to be shunned: it is the test of time,
which shows whether lover and beloved are moved by love of virtue and
education, naideia. If Eros is good and founded on virtue, it justifies any
action including deception, since it is good to gratify a lover for the sake
of virtue. So Heavenly Eros is of the highest value both to private citizens
and the city, for it compels both lover and beloved to be concerned for
their own virtue.
"Aphrodite," in ordinary Greek usage, meant sex, and the verb d0-
QodiOid^a), used in the active of the man and in the passive of the woman,
meant to have sexual intercourse. One may distinguish Eros from Aph-
rodite as one may distinguish love from sex, as something more than sex
and perhaps other than sex; so there is merit in Pausanias's distinction.
Unfortunately, in his zeal for pederasty, he muddles the distinction be-
tween sex and love by offering two Aphrodites and two Erotes: Vulgar
Eros and Vulgar Aphrodite aim at women and boys for purposes of sexual
intercourse; Heavenly Eros and Heavenly Aphrodite aim only at older
boys for purposes of virtue and education—and sexual intercourse,
"gratification."
Something is lost in all this. Vulgar Aphrodite, "who in her birth par-
takes of both male and female," is treated as Venus Meretrix; but she is
also of course Venus Genetrix, by whom, as Diotima will suggest in the
speech of Socrates, men are able to achieve a kind of vicarious immortality
through their offspring. Heavenly Aphrodite, a goddess, but one who yet
"partakes not of the female but only of the male," is inherently sterile.
COMMENT 17
ment in the matter of homosexuality; but that sentiment was not his own,
any more than it was Socrates', as may be inferred from Alcibiades' failure
to seduce him. In the Symposium, Diotima will treat the intercourse of man
and woman as a divine thing, an immortal element in the mortal living
creature (2o6c); men fertile in body turn to women and are lovers in that
way, aiming at immortality and remembrance and happiness through the
begetting of children (2o8e). Diotima will also recognize a different kind
of pederasty, which is not sexual but aimed solely at education (2ogb-c);
it is a stage in the ascent to Beauty itself (21 ib).
To understand pederasty in Athens, it is perhaps helpful to understand
something of the status of women.28 Pederasty of the sort Pausanias de-
scribes was primarily an upper-class phenomenon, and it was encouraged
by the position of upper-class women, who were in purdah, segregated
from men since childhood. Athens was a great port city and faced toward
Asia; oriental influence may have counted for much in its treatment of
women, which, if we may rely on the example of Homer's Penelope, was
not historically Greek.29 An Athenian aristocrat found in marriage a wife
who would be mistress of his house and mother of his children, but not
an intellectual and moral companion, and marriage was not a matter of
love or romance but of dynastic continuity based on family alliances. It is
an indication of the status of women that, among the citizen class, seduc-
tion was a more serious crime than rape;30 it was plainly not the woman's
interest in personal safety nor the integrity of her body that was protected
by this rule, but the proprietary interest of her husband or guardian, his
interest in stability of possession, legitimacy of offspring, and quiet en-
joyment of title.
So love and marriage had very little to do with each other, though no
28. Helpful, but not dispositive; it may put the cart before the horse. So far from the
position of Athenian women explaining Athenian homosexuality, it may be that Athenian
homosexuality goes some way toward explaining the position of Athenian women. Pausan-
ias's contempt for women and heterosexual intercourse suggests an attitude toward the fe-
male principle that is consistent with, if it does not imply, the subjugation of women, and
may be connected with the worship of Dionysus.
29. Neither was homosexuality, of which there is no trace in Homer. Between the eighth
century and the fifth century something happened—something perhaps associated with the
Thracian Dionysus.
30. A. R. W. Harrison, The Law of Athens: Family and Property, Oxford, 1968, p. 34; cf.
p. 38, summarizing criminal offenses allied to adultery, such as procuring and prostitution:
"Two features of these rules concerned with sexual behavior especially strike us. First, the
woman and her chastity are hardly protected in their own right, but only because she is the
humble but necessary vehicle for carrying on the ofxog. Second, sexual acts of males outside
matrimony are only punished if committed with free-born Athenians; it was not the acts
themselves, but the involvement of two citizens in them which made them sufficiently ab-
horrent to entail legal punishment."
COMMENT 19
ig
rodite, Uranus and Cronus and Zeus, Apollo and the fated musician-hero
Orpheus. And everywhere in the shadows, the flickering, haunted figure
of Dionysus, whose festival it is. In the corners of so large a room, perhaps,
there is darkness—or only so much light as to make darkness visible. Di-
onysus was of fiery origin.
In the Cratylus (4o6b), Socrates makes the name Dionysus mean Wine-
Giver and connects him with Aphrodite, born of the foam. He was in
origin a god of fertility, and chief of his symbols, other than wine, was the
phallus, ritually symbolized as the thyrsus, or wand. His rites were cele-
brated at three main Athenian festivals, the Lenaea in winter and the
Anthesteria32 in spring, festivals of great antiquity whose origins lie
shrouded in the archaic age, and the Greater Dionysia, a civic festival that
perhaps dates from the mid-sixth century, as distinct from the more an-
cient country dionysia held locally around Attica. The Greater Dionysia,
if it was celebrated with a bout of public drunkenness of which Plato heart-
ily disapproved (Laws I 637a-b), was also celebrated by drama, and from
it came not only the comedies of Aristophanes, always in Dionysus's com-
pany (Symposium i77e), but the tragedies of Aeschylus, Sophocles, and
Euripides. The Lenaea was an occasion for drama too, usually comedy,
though Agathon has just won the competition there with a tragedy. Ath-
ens no doubt was the city of Athena, but in the fifth century B.C. Dionysus
was one of its primary gods. One might read long and hard in Plato before
discovering this to be true; yet it is important to the Symposium and, indeed,
to Plato's criticism of the positive morality of his time.
A xcbjuoc; is a revel, and a comedy a revel-song; the revel often ends in
a ydjuog, a union of the sexes, and throughout the classical period the
chorus and actors in comedy wear artificial phalli and sing phallic songs.
Tragedy is a goat-song, and distinctly less jolly; the goat-song may origi-
nally have been sung over a goat as sacrificial victim, torn alive and eaten
raw as a representative of Dionysus himself. Tragedy sends suffering and
32. The Anthesteria was a festival of flowers, at which the jars of new wine were opened;
but it also was a time of exorcising the ghosts of the dead, very like Halloween. This may
explain the connection between Dionysus and Hades in Heraclitus, Fr. 93: "If it were not to
Dionysus that they made procession and sang hymns to the pudenda, they would be doing
most shameful things; Hades and Dionysus, for whom they rave and celebrate the rites of
the winepress, are the same." Aristotle preserves record of a rite of great antiquity still
practiced in his own day: The King Archon, the chief religious magistrate of Athens, had
a building called the Bucoleum, or Bull Stall, near the Prytaneum, where his wife, in an
annual ceremony at the Anthesteria, married and had sexual intercourse (OVJUJUI£IG) with
Dionysus (Athenaion Politeia 3.5). No details of the ceremony are recorded, and it is treated
as a sacred mystery, but if we keep to the name of the building, it suggests ritual intercourse
with a bull, the characteristic bestial form of Dionysus. See, however, H. W. Parke, Festivals
of the Athenians, Ithaca, N.Y., 1977, p. 112.
22 COMMENT
minating ceremony, the tearing apart alive and eating raw, ojtagayjuoc;
and (bjuoQayia, of a sacrificial victim, often a bull or goat in addition to
fawns and small animals and helpless nurslings. In Euripides' Bacchae, the
victim is Pentheus, prince of Thebes; the aytagay^dg ends with Agave, his
own mother, carrying Pentheus's head on a thyrsus, mistaking it for that
of a young lion and exulting in her ability as a huntress. It is, as L. A. Post
remarked, a song of triumph for her own ruin.
Such a state of possession clearly implies extreme pathology, a brief
reactive psychosis involving emotional turmoil, delusions, and hallucina-
tions. In short, these women were temporarily mad. One may well think
of Lucretius on the sacrifice of Iphegenia: "tantum religio potuit suadere
malorum."
We are left with the question of what the Bacchae meant to Euripides,
and to his audience. E. R. Dodds remarks that "as the 'moral' of the Hip-
polytus is that sex is a thing about which you cannot afford to make mis-
takes, so the 'moral' of the Bacchae is that we ignore at our peril the
demand of the human spirit for Dionysiac experience. For those who do
not close their minds against it such experience can be a deep source of
spiritual power and evdai^ovia. But those who repress the demand in
themselves or refuse its satisfaction in others transform it by their act into
a power of disintegration and destruction, a blind natural force that
sweeps away the innocent with the guilty."34 If this trivializes the Hippo-
lytus, its account of the Bacchae, and of evdaijuovia, is decidedly unclear:
what does evdaijuovia consist in? "To resist Dionysus is to repress the el-
emental in one's own nature; the punishment is the sudden collapse of
the inward dykes when the elemental breaks through perforce and civi-
lization vanishes";35 but in the same paragraph Dodds suggests that the
ritual "may have developed out of spontaneous attacks of mass hysteria."
Dodds is able to describe the state of Euripides' mind when he wrote the
Bacchae: "It is as if the renewed contact with nature in the wild country
of Macedonia, and his re-imagining there of the old miracle story, had
released some spring in the aged poet's mind, re-establishing a contact
with hidden sources of power which he had lost in the self-conscious, over-
intellectualized environment of late-fifth-century Athens, and enabling
him to find an outlet for feelings which for years had been pressing on
his consciousness without attaining to complete expression."36 So evdai-
juovia and spiritual power, it seems, are to be identified with the "elemen-
tal" in one's nature as expressed in psychosis—Freud's "primary process."
34. Euripides: Bacchae, 2d ed., Oxford, 1960, p. xlv.
35. Ibid., xvi.
36. Ibid., xlvii.
24 COMMENT
of Agave, and the fact that Pentheus is not a man but a boy with beard
just sprouted. But in an area so socially and psychologically complex as
this, it is perhaps better to think in terms not of linear causation or func-
tional relationships, but of constellations or significant conjunctions of ele-
ments. Dodds remarks that "the (b/LKxpayia and the bestial incarnations
reveal Dionysus as something more significant and much more dangerous
than a wine god. He is the principle of animal life, TCLVQCK; and ravgo-
0dyog, the hunted and the hunter—the unrestrained potency which man
envies in beasts and seeks to assimilate. His cult was originally an attempt
on the part of human beings to achieve communion with this potency.
The psychological effect was to liberate the instinctive life of man from
the bondage imposed on it by reason and social custom: the worshipper
became conscious of a strange new vitality, which he attributed to the god's
presence within him."43
The doctrine of Eros in the Symposium, so far from accepting emotional
ambivalence of the Dionysiac type as an essential characteristic of the hu-
man soul, replaces it with a steadfast and coherent pursuit of goodness
and beauty that culminates in the contemplation of Beauty itself. Ratio-
nality is not psychological bondage imposed on instinctive life. It is the
psychological liberation of instinctive life, as leading to its completion and
fulfillment. Human emotions and desires require peculiarly human ex-
pression, and envy of brute beasts, from Plato's point of view, implies
deep-seated sickness of soul.
45. Gildersleeve claimed that Eryximachus is a pedant and a system-monger "who was
only on sufferance in that brilliant company and whom Plato holds up to ridicule as incor-
porating the worst foibles of the professor of the healing art" (American Journal of Philology
30 [1909], p. 109); this in reply to Sir William Osier's claim that "nowhere in literature do
we have such a charming picture illustrating the position of the cultivated physician in so-
ciety as that given in Plato's dialogue of Eryximachus" (Counsels and Ideals, New York, 1905,
p. 24). It has since been fashionable to see Eryximachus as a caricature, a figure of fun, and
to discount his importance. This is unsupported by the text, and obscures his thematic role
in the dramatic structure of the Symposium. See further Ludwig Edelstein, "The Role of
Eryximachus in Plato's Symposium" Ancient Medicine (ed. Temkin and Temkin), Baltimore,
1967, pp. 153-171. Cf. Phaedrus 268a-b.
46. In treating Eros as a cosmic principle, Eryximachus was anticipated by Phaedrus,
who quoted Hesiod and Parmenides (i78b). In assuming two Erotes as cosmic principles,
he perhaps also draws on Empedocles' cosmic principles of Love and Strife. Aristotle pro-
vides an instructive comment: see Metaphysics I gS^b 23-9853 6.
47. Dover remarks (Symposium, p. 105): "Eryximachus, who feels that the study of med-
icine qualifies him to go beyond what Pausanias has said, runs together (i) the contrast be-
tween good desires or tendencies and bad desires or tendencies, and (2) the contrast between
good consequences of reconciling opposites and the bad consequences of failure to reconcile
them. In (i) he stretches the denotation of the word 'eros' wide enough to diminish its utility
very greatly, and in (2) he stretches it even further by treating an adjustment between two
extremes as creating an eros of the extremes for each other." But (i) scarcely diminishes the
utility of the word; it anticipates the breadth of Diotima's use, while (2) anticipates her con-
nection of desire with friendship, 0tAta. See David Konstan and Elisabeth Young-Bruehl,
"Eryximachus' Speech in the Symposium" Apeiron 1982, pp. 40-46.
28 COMMENT
not those unhealthy desires that constitute the bad Eros. Love has passed
from the gratification of desire to the principle of all desire and gratifi-
cation. In so doing it has become normative, as indeed Pausanias had al-
ready suggested, in that it implies a distinction between desires and what
desires ought to be satisfied.
Eryximachus extends this account to gymnastic and agriculture. Again,
music is knowledge of desires concerning attunement and rhythm, and
the musician must introduce concord among opposites and gratify the
good Eros of the audience; astronomy is knowledge of desires concerning
motions of stars and seasons of years, their mixture and attunement; 77
pavTiwfi, the art of the seer, involves avoiding the impiety that arises if
one does not gratify the orderly and good Eros, and also introduces
friendship between gods and men.
Eryximachus's speech serves an important dramatic function. By ex-
tending Eros beyond sexual desire, it anticipates Diotima's treatment of
Eros as desire in all its forms, one of whose works is friendship. By making
Eros a cosmic principle evinced in medicine, a principle found not only
in opposed desires of the body but in their attunement, it anticipates the
main theme of the speech of Aristophanes: that human love is a healing
power, that Eros is the good physician (i8gd,
Eryximachus and Greek Medicine
48. The brief Hippocratic treatise The Art has been (conjecturally) ascribed to Hippias;
Eryximachus, who is present with Hippias in the Protagoras, here uses the exact phrase
(i86b).
COMMENT 29
who have been both physicians and philosophers, because he was also first
to recognize what Nature effects."49
The Hippocratic corpus as it has come down to us, however, is certainly
not the work of one man or even a committee, but of a tradition extending
over hundreds of years, and, in its theoretical aspects, often at variance
with itself. The tradition is united in its naturalism, its relentless exclusion
of divine intervention as the explanation of disease, including mental dis-
ease. The author of The Sacred Disease—not only epilepsy, but also perhaps
other mental disease including bacchic or corybantic possession—strikes
the tone of the whole: "I am about to discuss the disease called 'sacred.'
It is not, in my opinion, any more divine or more sacred than other dis-
eases, but has a natural cause, and its supposed divine origin is due to
men's inexperience, and to their wonder at its peculiar character."50 Eryxi-
machus as a doctor, asked at a drinking party to praise Eros as a god,
immediately reduces it to a natural power.
Plato attributes to Hippocrates a philosophical concern that is fre-
quently, though by no means universally, exhibited in the Hippocratic cor-
pus. Certainly it is exhibited by Eryximachus, whose claim that dgjtovia,
attunement, is the aim of medicine and the essence of health is strikingly
evident in Regimen I, where health is analyzed in terms of music and, more
specifically, attainment of ratios among the elements of the body of the
octave, the fourth, and the fifth, the perfect consonances of Greek music;
failure to achieve attunement causes disease. Regimen 7, again, holds that
the elements of the body are composed of fire and water, and these,
though opposite, are also treated as complementary: the power of fire is
to cause motion, the power of water to nourish, so that fire and water are
different in power but work together in their use. Eryximachus's criticism
of Heraclitus's doctrine of the warfare of opposites fits with this; the em-
phasis in Regimen I on fire and water is perhaps akin to what Eryximachus
has in mind in suggesting that the aim of medicine is to make inimical
elements—opposites such as cold and hot, bitter and sweet, dry and wet—
friendly by bringing them into attunement. The introduction of these op-
posites, again, perhaps anticipates the doctrine of opposite humors,
phlegm, blood, yellow bile, and black bile, associated with the hot, the
cold, the wet, and the dry, whose proportional mixture or blending pro-
duced health, and disproportion disease and pain.51 If these are philo-
49. On the Natural Faculties I xiii (translation after Brock).
50. The Sacred Disease 1 iff., trans. W. H. S. Jones. The discussion of Greek medicine in
what follows owes much to Jones's magisterial edition of Hippocrates in the Loeb Classical
Library.
51. Cf. Timaeus 8ia-86a, with F. M. Cornford's commentary, in Plato's Cosmology, Lon-
don, 1937, pp. 332—343. Hippocrates, On the Nature of Man, chap. iv.
go COMMENT
30
sophical conjectures, they are also primitive scientific theories, meant to
explain the factual foundation on which Greek medicine was based, de-
rived from accumulated experience and accurate observation, preserved
in clinical histories and accompanied by clear classification of diseases: in
this connection, observe Eryximachus's emphasis on diagnosis.
Did Eryximachus have an art? He did indeed. In surgery, the Greeks
were in many respects ahead of average medical competence in America
at the middle of the last century, specifically in their emphasis on clean-
liness—of hands, of instruments, of dressings and bandages, of the op-
erating room. They were skilled in the treatment and bandaging of
dislocations and fractures, including depression fractures of the skull;
they could trepan the skull to relieve pressure on the brain; they had ex-
cellent knowledge of the treatment and dressing of wounds, and under-
stood the uses of cautery. On the medical side, there was fair knowledge
of the pharmacopia, an astonishing emphasis on the preparation and use
of various kinds of barley water, concern to see that the patient was rested
and kept calm, and a considerable emphasis on diet. Treatment was con-
servative, with trust in the natural recuperative powers of the body—the
vis medicatrix naturae. The Greek doctors were also much concerned with
preventive medicine, and specifically with diet and exercise. They classi-
fied diseases by symptoms rather than causes; they appear not to have
known smallpox, measles, diphtheria, scarlet fever, bubonic plague, or
syphilis; they did know pneumonia, consumption, malaria in manifold
forms, and the common cold. They also knew that medicine was a noble
calling, and their ethical responsibility to their patients, repeatedly in-
sisted upon in the Hippocratic corpus, was of a high order: respect for
their art made them intolerant of apes and clowns, and treatment was
distinguished by humanity to the patient and the curiosity to inquire.
Eryximachus is proud of his art, and with reason. Plato treats the phy-
sician's art as analogous to that of the statesman, as body is analogous to
soul.
resented Plato's own view of love, and that it supported their own spec-
ulation that love is inherently androgynous or bisexual, that is, that all
men and women have in them an impulse toward both homosexual and
heterosexual relations.53 As an interpretation of the Symposium, this is mis-
taken. Aristophanes no more expresses Plato's theory of love than Calli-
cles in the Gorgias expresses Plato's theory of justice; Aristophanes is a
character in a dialogue, and not the leading character. Jung and Freud
also misinterpret Aristophanes, whose story implies that individual hu-
man beings are not inherently bisexual, but inherently either homosexual
or heterosexual; it is the primitive whole, not its halves, which is capable,
on occasion, of being androgynous (i8gd—e, igid—igab). Aristophanes,
after all, wrote the Lysistrata, and only heterosexual love accords with the
purpose of Zeus, who turned the genitals to the front for the purpose of
reproduction (igic); homosexual intercourse is at one point dismissed as
a means of relieving tension and getting back to work (igic; compare
ig3e), and Eros in the speech of Aristophanes is not conceived to be pri-
marily directed toward sexual relations at all (igsc-d).
In the Phaedrus (264c-d), Socrates criticizes the speech of Lysias on
grounds of inconsequence: a discourse should be like a living thing, with
body, head, and foot, the members organized in fitting relation to each
other and to the whole, whereas Lysias's speech can be read in any order,
like the epitaph of Midas the Phrygian. So much might indeed be said,
very nearly, of the speeches of Phaedrus, Pausanias, Eryximachus, and
Agathon. Aristophanes' speech is, on the contrary, well organized and
develops directly to the conclusion at iggb-d. R. G. Bury remarks:
53. C. G. Jung, Psychology and Religion, New Haven, 1938, p. 68, following Freud, Three
Essays on the Theory of Sexuality (1905), Standard Edition, p. 136; cf. Beyond the Pleasure Prin-
ciple (1920), Standard Edition, pp. 57—58; Outline of Psychoanalysis, New York, 1949, p. 6wi.
54. Symposium, p. xxxiv.
COMMENT 33
55. C. S. Lewis in The Allegory of Love (Oxford, 1936, pp. 3-4, 11) argued that romantic
love begins with the troubadours and Provencal love poetry, the tradition of courtly love,
and that it represents a real, and rare, change in erotic sentiment. Its distinguishing marks
are Frauendienst and the idealization of adultery, and the transformation of love and the
beloved into objects of religious awe and worship. In respect to the last point, at least, Lewis
34 COMMENT
later corrected himself: "Years ago when I wrote about medieval love-poetry and described
its strange, half make-believe, 'religion of love,' I was blind enough to treat this as an almost
purely literary phenomenon. I know better now. Eros by his nature invites it. Of all loves he
is, at his height, most god-like; therefore most prone to demand our worship. Of himself
he always tends to turn 'being in love' into a sort of religion" (The Four Loves, p. 154). On
courtly love in its relation to the myth of Tristan and Isolde, one may consult Denis de
Rougemont, Love in the Western World (first published in French under the title L'Amour et
I'Occident), New York, 1956; and M. C. D'Arcy, The Mind and Heart of Love, ad ed., London,
1954. One may also, of course, consult Wagner's Tristan und Isolde, with special attention to
the Liebestod. The Tristan myth is represented in English literature by Thomas Malory,
"The Book of Sir Tristram de Lyones" (ed. Vinaver, Malory: Works, Oxford, 1971), which
puts the original story told in twelfth-century French romances into the framework of the
Arthurian cycle.
COMMENT 35
56. Aristophanes triumphed over Diotima in early German romanticism, and without
comedy. Goethe, in The Sorrows of Young Werther (1774), portrayed suicide as an appropriate
response to frustrated love, with enough conviction to prompt suicides all over Europe, and
in Faust Goethe made knowledge not the salvation of the soul, but the price of its damnation.
The triumph of Aristophanes, drunken comedian and professional servant of Dionysus, was
ratified by Nietzsche in The Birth of Tragedy.
36 COMMENT
wrecks Greek tragedy: "In so far as the struggle was directed against the Dionysian element
in the older tragedy, we may recognize in Socrates the opponent of Dionysus. He is the new
Orpheus who rose against Dionysus, and although he is destined to be torn to pieces by the
Maenads of the Athenian court, he still put to flight the powerful god himself " (sec. 12,
trans. Walter Kaufmann). This is a penetrating estimate of the thematic tension of the Sym-
posium, from which much of its imagery is drawn, and its estimate of Socrates' attitude toward
tragedy is accurate; it is also perhaps worth observing that Euripides is the only poet besides
Homer whom Socrates in the Symposium quotes, and that Apollo is represented by Aristo-
phanes himself as a figure of punishment, carrying out the judgments of Zeus. According
to Kaufmann, the young Nietzsche for years carried a copy of the Symposium in his pocket;
it was his favorite book. But of course, he turned its meaning upside down and perverted
it.
61. See also Phaedrus 237C,
COMMENT 39
between what Eros is and what he causes; Diotima will distinguish Eros
from his works. Agathon makes Eros beautiful and a lover of beauty; Dio-
tima will deny that he is beautiful on the ground that he is a lover of
beauty. Agathon makes Eros happy; Diotima will make Eros the wish for
happiness. Agathon makes Eros a cause of friendship and peace; Diotima
will make Eros desire for knowledge of Beauty itself, and thus implicated
with the common good. Agathon makes Eros delicate, since his home is
in the souls of men; Diotima will exalt beauty of soul above beauty of body.
Agathon makes Eros supple in form; Diotima will define Eros in terms of
its object. Agathon ascribes to Eros the cardinal virtues of justice, tem-
perance, courage, and wisdom; Diotima will make Eros a philosopher, a
lover of wisdom. Agathon makes Eros a poet and creator, responsible for
the generation of animals and a teacher of the arts; Diotima will make
Eros according to the body responsible for generation, and according to
the soul responsible for poetry, law giving, and education.
But in place of Agathon's singing heap of flattering adjectives, meant
to adorn the god and please the audience without regard for truth, Dio-
tima will offer, in dithyrambs, the ascent of the lover to Beauty itself. Both
speeches are rhetorical. But Agathon's rhetoric deals with appearance, as
Socrates' examination of it will show, and Diotima's with reality. The two
speeches exhibit the contrast between sophistic paideia and philosophy.
Diotima's speech, though it contains elements of parody, is in the nature
of a protreptic.
Aristotle in the Poetics64 makes clear that Agathon was one of the leading
playwrights of his time, so skilled at representation that Aristotle com-
pares him to Homer, and an innovator in that he invented his own plots
and did not rely on the traditional stories on which tragedies were based,
which are "only known to a few, though a delight to all."
about Eros in his own way if the company wishes. Phaedrus and the others
urge him to speak.
Socrates distinguishes two kinds of encomium, one concerned to praise
without regard for truth or falsity, the other concerned for truth but pick-
ing out its best features. This recalls the distinction in the Gorgias between
two kinds of rhetoric: the one a species of flattery, concerned with plea-
sure to the hearers and indifferent to truth or the good of the soul; the
other philosophical rhetoric, concerned with truth and the good of the
soul and indifferent to pleasure. The rhetoric Gorgias practices is not
based on knowledge or truth; it is a knack, not an art, of persuasion, al-
lowing the orator to appear to the ignorant to know more than those who
have knowledge (Gorgias 45gc). Socrates here says almost the same thing
of Agathon, Gorgias's follower. Agathon's speech, and by implication the
others, is a specimen of flattery, aiming at pleasure but indifferent to
truth. Socrates will not offer flattery; he will aim to tell the truth about
Eros, while yet, as is proper to an encomium, picking out what is best. If
Eros has also a dark side, Socrates will not directly speak of it here.
So the first act of the Symposium ends. It has been a feast of rhetoric:
five speeches, all pleasing, about Love. Phaedrus led off and treated Love
as an ancient god; he in this way introduced a theme that Pausanias de-
veloped, Prodicus-like, by dividing Love's divinity. Eryximachus followed,
and treated Love as a divided cosmic power. Then Aristophanes, who
treated Love as a healing force whose dwelling place is in the souls of men.
At the end, in a ring structure, Agathon returns to Phaedrus and treats
Eros as a god, but a youthful god. Of these speakers, Aristophanes is a
comic poet, and Agathon a tragedian; the Gorgias (soaa-e; compare Sym-
posium 223d) treats tragedy, and by implication comedy, as rhetoric and
akin to demagoguery: it aims at pleasing the audience without regard to
truth or the good of the soul. As the Symposium makes clear, both comedy
and tragedy are the special province of Dionysus.
Socrates in his own account of Eros will take something from each of
these five speeches, and reject much. It is of the nature of rhetoric, con-
ceived as a species of flattery, that it should consist not in utter falsehood
but in half-truth.
tima will conform to this plan. She will discuss the nature of Eros first,
and arrive at a definition: Eros is desire to possess the good forever (2o6a).
Diotima will then turn to discuss his works (2o6b), which issue in creation
in respect to body and soul.
Socrates' approval of Agathon's distinction suggests, if it does not imply,
that questions about the nature of Eros, of what sort he is, are prior to
questions about his works, what he does: we need to know who, or what,
Eros is (gold). This conforms to Socrates' procedure in other dialogues.
In the Meno (7 ib; compare 87b, loob), for example, one must understand
what virtue is (ri ion) before one can determine what things are true of
it (ojtolov yi n), for example, whether it is taught; in the same way here,
we must understand what love is (onoloc; ng) before we can understand
his works (ra egya avrov).65 Unlike virtue in the Meno, Eros is not a Form
or Idea, but if Socrates is right, it must ultimately be defined in terms of
an Idea, the Idea of Beauty. There is the further point that since the na-
ture of anything, what it is, is universal, a request for definition cannot
be met by mentioning an example of the thing to be defined.
Socrates begins by asking whether Eros is such as to be of some thing or
of nothing. The sense of the question, in Greek as in English, is not trans-
parently clear, and Socrates immediately undertakes to make it more pre-
cise. One cannot say that Eros is of a mother or father, for that would be
absurd (iggd). It is absurd in at least three different senses, all of which
are neatly excluded: the genitive here expresses neither the love felt by a
mother or father, nor the love feltyor a mother or father; Eros, after all,
may mean any sort of love, but especially sexual, not parental or filial love.
Nor is this genitive a special case of the genitive of origin. In Greek, to
be of someone may mean, idiomatically, to be a child of someone;66 Soc-
rates is not asking for the parentage of Eros, which would be a way of
identifying who he is characteristic of an encomium.
It is possible to be more precise. Socrates is not asking about any given
father, but about father by itself (iggd.4), and so similarly about brother,
that which it is by itself (igge.2). That is, he is asking of father qua father,
brother qua brother, whether they are of something or of nothing: asking,
not about any given father or brother or sister, but about all fathers just
insofar as they are fathers. He will similarly inquire of Eros qua Eros.
The of is a genitive of relation: father is father of something, namely, a
65. The Meno contrasts the questions ri eon and 6nol6v u, while in the Symposium, OTTO tog
Tig is equivalent to rig eoriv, and contrasted with rd Egya avrov. Plato is characteristically
disdainful of technical terminology, but the difference in gender also corresponds to the
underlying personification of Eros.
66. As at 204b.6 and 7.
COMMENT 43
assuming things which the respondent agrees that he knows (Meno 7sd),
and eAeyxoc;, refutation, is an important part of dialectic, in the nature of
a reductio ad absurdum: consistency is the first and primary test of truth.
Socrates has relieved Agathon of the false conceit of knowledge, and given
him a motive to inquire into what he once thought he knew and now knows
he did not know (2036-2043); this has also provided Socrates with prem-
ises by which the inquiry can go forward.
Agathon had earlier suggested that he and Socrates would argue their
rival claims to wisdom later, using Dionysus as judge (1756). In this brief
eheyxog, Agathon has begun to learn to judge for himself.
Since Eros is love of what it lacks, it cannot be beautiful or good, and
since the gods possess both attributes, it cannot be divine. It is not, how-
ever, bad or ugly or mortal, but "intermediate" between those attributes
(202a-e).
The logic of the argument seems obscured by the personification of
Eros. Love is a relation. As such, it lacks nothing, and desires nothing. It
implies, however, privation or lack in the lover.68 Socrates has distin-
guished love from its object; but love must also be distinguished from the
lover, and when this is done, the argument to show that Eros is neither
good nor beautiful nor divine is inconclusive. The lover, who lacks and is
by so much imperfect, cannot be divine; it does not follow that love itself
is not divine or good, or for that matter, evil and bad.69 In the Phaedrus,
when Socrates comes to describe the upward passage of Eros to the Place
beyond the Heaven, he describes it as "a god, or something divine" (2426)
because it seeks the divine; but later, when he criticizes the Eros described
in his first speech, a love that seeks unworthy objects and leads to evil
rather than good, he calls it "sinister" or "left-handed," OKaiov nva egcura
(266a), a love of ill omen.
But Socrates and Diotima do not in fact speak of love as a relation con-
sidered apart from its terms, nor of the lover considered apart from that
relation, but of the lover as lover. It is the lover just insofar as he loves who
lacks what he loves and desires to possess it. Diotima will personify Eros,
and that personification is not merely a literary device, lending to airy
nothing a local habitation and a name, but has a logical point: Eros is the
lover qua lover, each lover insofar as he loves (iggd-e, 2Ood-e, 2O4d). It
68. See further "The Elenchus of Agathon: Symposium 1990-2010," The Monist 1966,
pp. 460-463.
69. Agathon, if he is mistaken in describing Eros as beautiful, is surely not making a
linguistic mistake: not only the object of desire but the person desiring could be character-
ized as ttoAog, as Phaedrus and Pausanias make clear. Indeed, desire itself, and specifically
erotic desire, could be so characterized. Cf. E. R. Goodenough, Jewish Symbols in the Greco-
Roman Period, vol. 6, Wine, Princeton, N.J., 1956, pp. 31—32.
COMMENT 45
will be evident that the lover qua lover cannot be identified with the lover
considered apart from that relation. It helps to introduce some elemen-
tary distinctions: between a relation and its terms, between the domain of
a relation and its converse domain or range. If we then bear in mind C. S.
Peirce's further distinction between logica docens and logica utens,70 we may
say, for nutshell effect, that Socrates and Diotima treat Eros as the domain
of a relation, taken distributively.71
If, then, Eros is the domain of a relation, what of its range? We are told
that loving is for what is not at hand and not present and what the lover
has not got, for things of which there is, as it where, an absence of presence
(igge). Furthermore, Eros has as its object, not the things themselves, but
the possession of those things, so that it is always involved not in the pre-
sent but in the future. Socrates assumes, as Diotima will assume after him
(gooa-e), that to love is to desire, and to desire is to wish (iggd). But a
desire, or a wish, must be defined in terms of its objects, that is, in terms
of the various kinds of thing of which it is a desire.72 Thirst, for example,
is simply desire to drink, and distinct from hunger, desire for food; a par-
ticular kind of thirst is desire for a particular kind of drink. By Socrates'
account, one should be even more precise: thirst is not only for drink, but
for possession of what is drinkable. The object of desire is an ideal object,
a future state of affairs.73
Eros is of the beautiful. Socrates is entitled to assume this dialectically,
because Agathon did (igyb), but he plainly supposes it true, and Diotima
too will assume it; they both suppose it to mean that Eros is desire for
possession of the beautiful, or a wish for it (2oob-d), and they also sup-
pose that a desire or wish for the beautiful is a desire or wish for the good.
Beauty is the sensuous aspect of goodness, what is good to look at or good
to hear, and, by an easy extension, goodness in thought or discourse.
70. Or, as Locke remarked, "But God has not been so sparing to men to make them
barely two-legged creatures, and left it to Aristotle to make them rational. God has been
more bountiful to mankind than so. He has given them a mind that can reason, without
being instructed in methods of syllogizing. The understanding is not taught to reason by
these rules: it has a native faculty to perceive the coherence or incoherence of its ideas, and
can range them right, without any such perplexing repetitions." Locke's Human Understand-
ing, ed. Pringle-Pattison, Oxford, 1924, p. 347.
71. This is in general characteristic of Plato's treatment of relations or relatives, and the
source of Aristotle's treatment of relation as a category inhering in primary substance. See
Bertrand Russell, The Philosophy of Leibniz, gd ed., London, 1937, pp. 13, 206.
72. Cf. Republic IV 439^ 438c-d.
73. On the point that desire always looks to the future, one may compare the distinction
taken in the Philebus between true and false pleasures: pleasure is always directed at some-
thing, like opinion, and therefore is true or false in the sense that expectation may be real
or illusory.
46 COMMENT
pare the speech of Socrates in the Apology, or the speech of the Laws of
Athens in the Crito. As the Apology and Crito show, and the Gorgias and
Phaedrus explicitly state, rhetoric and philosophy are not enemies, if rhet-
oric is directed at truth and the goodness of soul of the hearers rather
than flattery and pleasure indifferent to truth. Rhetoric, after all, is power
of persuasion, and persuasion can be guided and controlled by rational
insight. The speech of Diotima, like the speech of the Laws of Athens in
the Crito,78 is an example of implicit dialectic, "dialectic not in dialogue,"79
in which the form of question and answer is used sparingly, but the ar-
gument is developed in a dialectical way. The speech begins with an elen-
chus whereby Socrates, like Agathon before him, is relieved of the false
conceit of knowledge; it proceeds to a definition drawn from agreements
made in the elenchus; that definition is only partial, and various emen-
dations grow from this original starting point, using Socrates' own ad-
missions, until the nature of Eros is more adequately displayed along with
his works.
This dialectical development exhibits three stages. In the first, Diotima
undertakes to define Eros, reaching the conclusion that Eros is of the good
being one's own forever. In the second, she turns to the works of Eros:
Eros aims at immortality, of the body through nutrition and reproduc-
tion, of the soul through fame, to be obtained through poetry, law giving,
and education; because the immortality achieved is vicarious, it is not real
immortality at all, and Eros is in this respect frustrated and vain. The
third stage is the Greater Mysteries of Eros, in which the lover ascends as
by a ladder from bodily beauty, through spiritual and intellectual beauties,
to the contemplation of Beauty itself, and there, if anywhere, becomes
immortal.
which it lacks and desires to possess. All gods are happy and beautiful,
and those who are happy possess beautiful and good things; Eros does
not possess beautiful and good things, because it is desire for them; there-
fore, Eros is not a god and, by implication, Eros is not happy. Eros is not,
however, bad or ugly or mortal; rather, the lover qua lover, the lover just
insofar as he loves, is "intermediate" (juera^v) between these attributes.
Eros will turn out to be the wish for happiness.
Diotima's account seems inconsistent with the Phaedrus, where love is
sometimes good and sometimes bad. But Diotima implies that, contrary
to its usual associations in Greek, Eros is not simply sexual desire but de-
sire in all its forms, and this is later made explicit (2O5a-d). It follows from
this and from its relational character that Eros is to be defined in terms
of its objects, that is, in terms of the various kinds of beautiful things it
seeks. This analysis is developed in the Republic (IV 4^8aff.), where it is
argued that desire, as a relative, is also correlative, and, in F. M. Corn-
ford's brilliant paraphrase, "where there are two correlatives, the one is
qualified if, and only if, the other is so." Thus, "each desire just in itself,
is simply for its own natural object. Where the object is of such and such
a kind, the desire will be correspondingly qualified" (43Qb). Eros as a cor-
relative takes the value of its objects: desire for a good thing is a good
desire, bad if the contrary is true. But if desire is considered in abstraction
from any particular kind of object, it is indeed "intermediate," neither
good nor bad, beautiful nor ugly, divine or mortal. The Symposium and
Phaedrus are not inconsistent on this point.
Eros as Daimon
As intermediate, Eros is also a dafawv, a word for which there is no ad-
equate translation in English — certainly not "demon," whose sense de-
rives, not from etymology, but from the Christian rejection of polytheism.
Socrates in the Apology (syb-e) treats daijuovec; as "either gods or children
of gods." Diotima treats them as intermediate between gods and men,
immortals and mortals. The word is here translated "divinity."80 Diotima's
treatment of Eros as a divinity is a consequence of her personification
of him.
The intermediate mediates. Its function is to bring together, to bind into
a unity, the divine and human realms. In the Phaedrus (244a^.), Eros is
said to be a kind of divine madness that lends wings to the soul of the
80. For a discussion of Plato's "demonology," with comparison of passages, see L£on
Robin, La Theorie platonicienne de I 'amour, Paris, 1908, pp. izqff.
COMMENT 49
of Poros as well, and represents the human capacity for aspiration. As the
comparison of his intermediate character with right opinion foreshad-
owed (2O2a), Eros is also a philosopher, a lover of wisdom; so he is a
hunter, a metaphor traditionally associated with Eros, and one which Plato
elsewhere uses to describe the activity of the philosopher—and the
sophist.
Because Eros is the child of both Poros and Penia, Robin held that the
nature of love is essentially "a synthesis."82 Eros exists in privation, but
desire is not blind, dumb emptiness: to desire is to desire something of a
certain kind, so that desire implies awareness of the kind of thing that will
satisfy it. Desire, that is, implies cognition, and cognition of what is uni-
versal or common to many things.83 Again, it is not without significance
that Eros was conceived on the day of Aphrodite's birth. It is the revelation
of beauty to the bodily senses, the Phaedrus claims, which first awakens
longing for true being. Eros has its being in a synthesis of need and cog-
nition; perhaps, then, there is a sense after all in which Eros is inter-
mediate as being both good and bad, beautiful and ugly, mortal and
immortal.
Plotinus and Ficino
The personification of Eros as child of Poros and Penia is a fiction, its
logical force requiring us to consider Eros as the lover qua lover, the lover
just insofar as he loves. But there is an ancient tradition of interpretation,
descended from Plotinus, which takes it as something more. Plotinus
maintained that Eros is a substance (ovoia), sprung from another sub-
stance but nevertheless a being in its own right, and the cause of the af-
fection of love in the human soul ("On Love," Ennead III 5.3—4). Plotinus
interpreted the myth of Poros and Penia as an allegory meant to represent
metaphysical connections:
But myths, if they are really going to be myths, must separate in time
the things of which they tell, and set apart from each other many
realities which are together, but distinct in rank or powers, at points
where rational discussions, also, make generations of things ungen-
erated, and themselves, too, separate things which are together; the
82. Robin, Theorieplatonicienne, pp. 12iff.
83. It may be observed that this is not the least important of the differences between
Plato and Freud. Freud treats the instincts or drives on the analogy of steam in a boiler,
blind pressures for which an object is afterward supplied by the ego, the managerial or
directive element in the personality, which through secondary process has a grasp of reality;
satisfaction of desire is relaxation of pressure or (to use a different mechanical metaphor)
reduction of tension.
COMMENT 51
myths, when they have taught us as well as they can, allow the man
who has understood them to put together again that which they have
separated. Here is the putting together [of the myth of Eros]: Soul,
which is with Intellect and has come into existence from Intellect, and
then again been filled with rational principles and, itself beautiful,
adorned with beauties and filled with plenitude, so that there are in
it many glories and images of beautiful things, is as a whole Aphro-
dite, and the rational principles in it are all plenitude and Plenty, as
the nectar there flows from regions above; and the glories in it, since
they are set in life, are called the "garden of Zeus," and it is said that
Plenty "sleeps" there, "weighed down" by the principles with which
he was filled. And since life has appeared, and is always there, in the
world of realities, the gods are said to "feast" since they are in a state
of blessedness appropriate to the word. And so this being, Love, has
from everlasting come into existence from the soul's aspiration to-
wards the higher and the good, and he was there always, as long as
Soul, too, existed. And he is a mixed thing, having a part of need, in
that he wishes to be filled, but not without a share of plenitude, in
that he seeks what is wanting to that he already has; for certainly that
which is altogether without a share in the good would not ever seek
the good. So he is said to be born of Plenty and Poverty, in that the
lack and the aspiration and the memory of the rational principles
coming together in the soul, produced the activity directed towards
the good, and this is Love. But his mother is Poverty, because aspi-
ration belongs to that which is in need. And Poverty is matter, because
matter, too, is in every way in need, and because of the indefiniteness
of the desire for the good—for there is no shape or rational forming
principle (logos) in that which desires it—makes the aspiring thing
more like matter in so far as it aspires. But the good, in relation to
that which aspires to it, is form only, remaining in itself; and that
which aspires to receive it prepares its receptive capacity as matter
for the form which is to come upon it. So Love is a material kind of
being, and he is a spirit (daimori) produced from soul in so far as soul
falls short of the good but aspires to it.84
84. Ennead III 5.24-57, trans. A. H. Armstrong. Contrast Dante, Vita nuova 25: "You
may be surprised that I speak of love as if it were a thing that could exist by itself; and not
only as if it were an intelligent substance, but even as if it were a corporeal substance. Now
this, according to the truth, is false. For love has not, like a substance, an existence of its
own, but is only an accident occurring in a substance" (cited and translated by C. S. Lewis,
The Allegory of Lave, Oxford, 1936, p. 47). Dante treats as accident what Plotinus had sub-
stantialized.
52 COMMENT
yourself wise when you are not. In the Lysis (2 i8a—b), those who love wis-
dom are ignorant, but know that they do not know. If someone values
something, he does so by reason of something (dia TL) and for the sake of
something (evexa TOV), as one values a doctor by reason of disease, and
for the sake of health (2i8d-e); disease is bad, but health is good. Put
otherwise, the Lysis distinguishes causa quod and causa ut. So similarly here,
Eros is a philosopher by reason of ignorance, causa quod, and for the sake
of wisdom, which is most beautiful and good, causa ut. In the Lysis, this
pattern of reasoning leads to the claim that there exists something for the
sake of which all other things are loved, itself not loved for the sake of
something else, an ultimate causa ut (2 igb-22ob). In the Symposium (2 loa-
2i2a), it will lead to the Ladder of Love and the ascent to Beauty itself,
by which all other beautiful things are beautiful.
Eros, the desire which has for its object the beautiful, is connected in
the Symposium, as it is in the Phaedrus (24.gbff.) with philosophy, the love
of wisdom and knowledge. The claim is proleptic: it will be explained by
the further claim that Eros implies a wish for happiness, with which wis-
dom is implicated.
hap, happen, and hapless preserves the memory of an earlier force. Like
the word evdaijuovia, and in analogy to health, happiness also has an ob-
jective sense: well-being, the state of affairs in which things are well with
a man, however he feels. In the Republic (X Gaoe), the Fates send with each
soul a daijucov to attend it through life and fulfill for it the destiny it has
chosen, and its destiny is itself described as its daijucov.88 The state of eu-
daimonia is the state of having a good daimon — "good hap," though there
is an irreducible connotation of fortune or luck in the English word that
is not present in the Greek. Happiness conceived as well-being implies
concern for wisdom: Eros is a philosopher.
Diotima treats happiness, which consists in possession of good things,
as the ultimate object of Eros. Socrates offers a similar account in the Meno
(77b-78b). Meno had suggested that men desire evil, some through ig-
norance, believing it good, and some recognizing it for what it is and de-
siring it anyway. He readily agreed that the former really desire the good,
though their desire is misdirected through ignorance; he was then led to
agree that no one can willingly or wittingly desire what is bad, for what is
evil is harmful, and to be harmed is to be made unhappy, and no one
wishes that. It has been claimed that this argument is fallacious, in that it
confuses harm to another with harm to oneself. In fact, the argument is
enthymematic, assuming premises made explicit in the Crito and the Re-
public: to harm another is to act unjustly, and to act unjustly is to harm
oneself, that is to say, one's own soul. Thus, though one may desire to
harm another through ignorance, one cannot voluntarily harm another,
or wish it. This inference is plainly connected with the Socratic paradox
that no one willingly or wittingly does evil, that wrongdoing is involuntary.
The good is "what every soul pursues and for the sake of which it acts in
everything, divining that it is something, but perplexed and unable to
grasp adequately what it is or to form any stable belief about it, as about
other things, and for that reason missing whatever value those other
things may have."89
All men wish for possession of the good and for happiness. But this
raises the issue of mistake: what appears good sometimes isn't — there may
be poison in the cup. The objects of desire, when possessed, have effects
upon the possessor, and it is possible to desire things that are injurious.
Apparent good and real good may coincide, and in the virtuous life usu-
88. Republic X Qiydff., cf. Phaedo loyd—io8c, where the daijucvv functions as an inter-
mediate, conducting the soul to the other world when it finishes its life on earth. Heraclitus
said that, for a man, character is fate—daifiwv (Diels-Kranz, Fragmente der Vorsokratiker B
119)-
89. Republic VI 5O5d; cf. Gorgias 4996, 46721^., 5O$cff.
56 COMMENT
ally do, but they may also differ. So if men do what seems good to them,
they sometimes are mistaken about where their own good lies. Eros, the
lover insofar as he loves, has as its object the beautiful, and yet, as the
Phaedrus claims (266a), may love bad things.90
The distinction between the apparent good and the real good is con-
nected with a perspectival shift. It makes sense to say, "It seems good to
you, or to him, but it isn't"; it does not make sense to say, "It seems good
to me, but it isn't." This shift in perspective, due to difference in the per-
sons of the corresponding verbs, explains a difference in use of nouns for
loving, desiring, and wishing: we may say either that (first person) desire
and wish are always for what is good, or that (second and third person)
desire and wish are sometimes for what is good and sometimes for what
is bad.91 Happiness, which consists in the possession of good things, is the
common term through which first person and third person unite, in that
from both perspectives it is the ultimate object of love, and one cannot be
mistaken in one's belief that it is good.
Plato is entitled to choose between these uses, and does so. In general,
he treats the object of desire, eytidvpia, a denominative noun that suggests
setting one's heart on something, as the apparent good; on occasion—one
must look to context—he treats the object of wish, fiovkrjoic;, a denomi-
native noun that suggests intention, counsel, advice, as the real good.
Since men do what seems good to them, they do what they desire. But
since they are sometimes mistaken about where their own good lies, they
sometimes do not do what they wish. Thus Socrates argues in the Gorgias92
that though the tyrant does what seems best to him, he does not do what
he wishes, and is therefore least of all men free. Socrates uses a similar
argument in the Meno (770-78^ to establish that all men wish for
(fiovfaoOai) the good, that no man willingly or wittingly wishes evil.93 The
nature of BoMrjaig is explained in a single sentence in the Gorgias (467d;
compare Laches i85d): "If a man does something for a purpose, he does
not wish the thing he does, but that for the sake of which he does it."
BovXr]aiq is the rational wish of the self for what is truly as distinct from
apparently good; that is, as Diotima has now made clear, it is wish for
happiness, which consists in possession of good things.94
If Jones believes the world is flat, that it is not flat does not imply that
Jones does not believe it. If Jones desires something because he thinks it
is good, that it is not good does not imply that Jones does not desire it.
But happiness is a common term: from first-person perspective, desire
for the apparent good is desire for the good, and implies wish for hap-
piness and possession of good things. If Eros is desire, and one can desire
bad things in the mistaken belief that they are good, one can love bad
things in fact though not in intention. If Eros is also wish for happiness,
then wish for happiness—and wish to contemplate Beauty itself, in which,
according to Diotima, happiness consists—is implicit in every desire.95 So
if Eros and desire are one, the love of Beauty is implicit in the desire for
a glass of water.
On the other hand, in third-person perspective, one may distinguish
rational wish from desire. If Eros is wish for happiness, and if happiness
consists in possession of what is really good, then, if the proximate object
of desire is not in fact good, one may desire it, but one cannot not ratio-
nally wish it; it will follow that one therefore does not love it. Love is not
a feeling or emotion, or a state of mind that may be introspectively ap-
prehended without considering the value of its object. If one is mistaken
in believing that what one loves is good, one is also mistaken in believing
94. Cf. Definitions 4130: /3ovArjoi£ is "intention with right reason; well-reasoned intention;
desire with reason according to nature." At Symposium 2ooa-e, "to wish" (fiovkeoOai) is not
distinct from "to desire" (emQvjuelv), and this is perhaps also true in the Meno (770-780; cf.
Lysis 207d-e). So there was considerable overlap of meaning in ordinary use, and Dover on
Symposium 2000.4 suggests they are synonymous, "though the former cannot have a sub-
stantive as object." This last, if true (Liddell and Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon, gth ed. [Ox-
ford, 1968], s.v. Povhofiai 1.2), proves that they are not synonymous, and their distinction
is clearly implied at Gorgias 4670! and Symposium 2053. Desire is neutral with respect to the
real as distinct from the apparent worth of its objects, and implies no distinction between
what seems good and what is good. That distinction is less linguistic than conceptual—or
ontological. Happiness is that for the sake of which other things are desired, an ultimate
end.
95. Compare Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics III 11133 15-30 (trans. W. D. Ross): "That
wish is for the end has already been stated (i 11 ib.26); some think it is for the good, others
for the apparent good. Now those who say that the good is the object of wish must admit in
consequence that that which the man who does not choose aright wishes for is not an object
of wish (for if it is to be so, it must also be good; but it was, if it so happened, bad); while
those who say the apparent good is the object of wish must admit that there is no natural
object of wish, but only what seems good to each man. Now different things appear good
to different people, and, if it so happens, even contrary things. If these consequences are
unpleasing, are we to say that absolutely and in truth the good is the object of wish, but for
each person the apparent good; that that which in truth is an object of wish is an object of
wish to the good man, while any chance thing may be so to the bad man . . . ; since the good
man judges each class of things rightly, and in each the truth appears to him?"
58 COMMENT
that one loves it. Love must then imply a kind of infallibility in respect to
judgments of worth or value of a sort given to the wise man; if one loves
x, one is not mistaken in one's judgment that x is good. And if such judg-
ments require knowledge of the essential nature of beauty and goodness,
Eros requires apprehension of Beauty itself. So if Eros and rational wish
are one, the love of Beauty is implicit in the wish for a glass of water.
In her conclusion that Eros is wish for happiness, then, Diotima antic-
ipates the Greater Mysteries of Eros that are to follow, and does so whether
or not we identify desire and rational wish.
False Consciousness: Plato and Freud
The object of desire, insofar as it is desired, is apprehended as beautiful
or good, xaAdg. So in one sense, analytic but not trivial, to be an object
of desire is to be good. Since this sense of good has no contrary—no object
is bad for lack of being desired—this is a derivative sense of goodness.
What is apprehended as good may also be described as indifferent or
as evil. Consider a desire to drink cold water on a warm day after heavy
exercise. No doubt the object of desire, just insofar as it is so, is good. But
there are inconsistent desires: in such a case, the desire for water is in-
compatible with the desire, or wish, not to become ill. Getting the water
is an apparent good but an actual evil. This inconsistency is at the root of
rational choice, which implies ordering or ranking the objects of desire.
Choice is specifically rational in that possession of an object of desire has
effects on the possessor, and the estimate of those effects issues in judg-
ments that are either true or false. The apparent good consists in objects
of desire described as good because they are desired; the real good con-
sists in objects that are truly described as good by reason of the fact that
they coincide with what we wish, that is, what is to our benefit.
Given the dolorous fact that the first thing people want is often the last
thing they need, and that human beings constantly mistake apparent
good for real good, their state may be described as one of ignorance. But
it is not simple ignorance, the bare not knowing of something. It is, on
the contrary, a kind of not knowing of something one knows, a kind of
false consciousness. People, after all, have an awareness not only of what
they desire but of what they wish. If they did not, Socratic dialectic would
have no purchase on them, neither point nor direction; it makes no sense
to question a man in matters of which he is wholly ignorant. Consistency
is a necessary condition not only of truth but of psychological integration,
and Socratic dialectic, directed ultimately toward self-knowledge, is di-
rected proximately toward exposing inconsistencies of belief. False con-
sciousness at a logical level implies contradiction among beliefs; at a
COMMENT 59
96. Belief that there are unconscious mental states is so general that it is possible to forget
there are logical objections to it. It was maintained, before Freud, by Wundt, Hartmann,
and Helmholz, and it led William James to maintain that the assumption of unconscious
mental states "is the sovereign means for believing what one likes in psychology, and of
turning what might become a science into a tumbling-ground for whimsies." James went on
to suggest that arguments to show that unconscious mental states exist involve a variety of
fallacies, including failure to distinguish between having an idea at the moment of its pres-
ence and subsequently knowing all sorts of things about it—the distinction between knowl-
edge by acquaintance and knowledge by description, the basis for his rejection of the
incorrigibility of sense perception, as well as memory. James would specifically have dis-
missed the notion of a dynamic unconscious, on the ground that it involves knowing and
not knowing the same mental fact at the same time: "There is only one 'phase' in which an
idea can be, and that is a fully conscious condition. If it is not in that condition, then it is
not at all. Something else is, in its place. The something else may be a merely physical brain-
process, or it may be another conscious idea. Either of these things may perform much the
same function as the first idea, refer to the same object, and roughly stand in the same re-
lations to the upshot of our thought. But that is no reason why we should throw away the
logical principle of identity in psychology, and say that, however it may fare in the outer
world, the mind at any rate is a place in which a thing can be all kinds of other things without
ceasing to be itself as well." James admitted the distinction between actual and potential
knowledge, but cashed out the notion of potential knowledge in terms of (learned) modi-
fications of the brain; his analysis is inconsistent with dynamic repression (The Principles of
Psychology, Boston, 1890, pp. 163-175). It may be observed that James was familiar with the
phenomena of hypnotism, multiple personality, and hysteria, phenomena which prompted
Freud and others to assume the existence of unconscious mental states, and for which James
provided other explanations.
60 COMMENT
has been treated like JCOITJOK;. There are many kinds of creation: the pro-
ductions of all the arts are creations, and their producers creators, but
the word noirjois has been marked off to stand for a single branch of
creation, that in music and meter, "poetry." The same is true of Eros.
Generically, it is every desire for good things and happiness, but those
who turn to it in ways other than sexual, in money-making, or love of
athletics, or of wisdom, are not said to love or be lovers. Those who as-
siduously pursue one special kind of love obtain the name of the whole.
Since men love the good as kindred to them (oixelov, 2056) rather than
alien (dMorgiov),98 they desire to possess it and possess it forever. So the
object of Eros is to possess the good for oneself always, or forever (dei,
2o6a, b). This is a considerable result; Diotima will infer from it that Eros
is love of immortality (2073).
Diotima here also directly answers Aristophanes (2056; compare 21 id,
2i2c): what lovers seek is not "their other half," reuniting the halves of a
hermaphrodite, but only the good; they will reject what is evil even if it
is as near to them as their hands and feet.
Diotima has denned Eros. Eros, the lover just insofar as he loves, is a
relative term, to be denned by its object; that object is to possess the good
for oneself forever. That the object of Eros is to possess the good for one-
self forever, follows from the analysis of Eros in terms of povArjou;, ratio-
nal wish, whose object is happiness, which consists in the possession of
good things. Since everyone always wishes for happiness, everyone wishes
always to have good things (2O5a) and everyone loves the same things al-
ways (205b). The ultimate object of desire has been identified with the
object of rational wish, and it is common to all mankind. If one always
wishes to possess good things, then, since one can never wish to cease to
be happy, one's wish must be to possess good things always, that is, forever.
If there is an apparent gap between Eros always wishing to possess good
things and Eros wishing to possess good things always, Diotima's analysis
has spanned it."
If Eros, desire, is desire for good things and happiness (2O5d), then the
ultimate object of Eros is not the apparent good but the real good. The
notion of happiness is the key to the inference: for happiness implies well-
98. See Lysis 22 ic, 222C, Charmides i63C-d, Republic IX 5866. See also Aristotle Nicoma-
chean Ethics X 11783 5-8.
99. Dover (Symposium, p. 144) suggests that this conclusion "does not rest on reasoning
at all," and goes on to question Plato's honesty in offering the argument. "Naturally, as long
as the alternative possibilities of having good and having bad exist, we wish to have good,
but it does not follow that we ourselves wish to exist forever." On the contrary, it does follow,
insofar as we love, since the good wished for is happiness, as distinct from the object of some
contingent desire.
62 COMMENT
being. So desire to possess what is really good for oneself implies wish for
continued existence, and Eros, ever wishing to possess the good, wishes
to possess the good forever. One may compare Eros to Spinoza's conatus
esse sui conservandi: "Each thing endeavors, as far as possible, to persist in
its own being,"100 from which conatus both will and appetite spring.
Wish and What Is Primarily Valuable
Desire for a hot drink on a cold day is manifestly not the same as the wish
for happiness, for if it were, then, by transitivity of identity, it would be
the same as desire for a cold drink on a hot day, and a ham sandwich to
go. The desire of a thirsty man for a cup of water, it may be urged, is not
a desire for happiness any more than it is a desire for wisdom: it is a desire
for water. But by Diotima's account the objects of desire are ranked in a
hierarchy of purposes: the desire for water is implicated with the wish for
happiness.
The ranking of purposes is analyzed in the Lysis (2i8d-22od), which
develops a general theory of value, of what is lovable. Medicine is valuable
(0tAog) to the body by reason of (dia n) illness and for the sake of (evexa
TOV) something else, namely, health. Health also is valuable, and if valu-
able, valuable for the sake of something else. We must necessarily go on
proclaiming this, or arrive at a first principle (dg%rj) that no longer refers
to another valuable, but will reach that which is primarily valuable, for
the sake of which we say that all other things are valuable (2 igc-d). This
then is the source of value in other things, which are as it were images
(sidwha) of what is truly valuable, and deceive us in respect to what is
primary and first. Socrates proceeds to illustrate. If a man loves his son
above all else and learns that his son has drunk hemlock, he will value
three gills of wine if he thinks it will save his son, and value a cup if it
contains the wine. It isn't that he thinks the wine and the cup are equal
in value to his son; on the contrary, the wine is valuable for curing the
son, and the cup is valuable for holding the wine:
All such concern as this is directed, not at things provided for the
sake of something, but at that for the sake of which all such things
are provided. We often say, no doubt, that we count silver and gold
of great importance; but it is not true. Rather, we count of utmost
importance that for the sake of which gold and everything is pro-
vided. . . . The same account holds for the valuable: in respect to
everything we say is valuable for the sake of something else which is
neutral, neither good nor bad; they take their value from their object, that
for the sake of which they are done. The Laches suggests that the worth
of a practice such as fighting in armor must be estimated by reference to
the soul and its excellence, and that courage is an excellence of soul. This
is a reason for supposing that courage in souls is prior—ontologically, and
in definition—to the paronymous courageousness of actions. It is mis-
leading to say that courageous men are the kind of men who do coura-
geous actions; on the contrary, courageous actions are the actions of
courageous men. The issue is not one of statement equivalence, but of
ontological and definitional priority. Issues of the value of actions are
founded on moral psychology, and moral terms such as courage and justice
and temperance and virtue are not in any primary sense dispositional pred-
icates. To say that Nicias is courageous is not like saying that salt is soluble.
The claim that when one considers a for the sake of b, the counsel is
about b and not about a, is a claim of priority further considered in the
Gorgias, where fiovkrj, counsel, becomes (tovkrjoic;, rational wish.102 Be-
cause the examples given in the Gorgias include medicine for the sake of
health and sailing for the sake of wealth, it is easy to suppose that it is the
relation of means to ends that is primarily in view. But the Laches implies
that the principle is broader than that: eyes are not the aim or purpose
of salve, nor horses of bits, nor souls of subjects of study, though salve
may benefit the eyes, bits the horse or his rider, and study the soul. In
general, means do not benefit ends, and ends are not benefited by means.
Eyes, horses, and souls are not things at which action aims, but things for
whose benefit action is done; as the Lysis suggests (sigd), they move by
being valued or loved. Aristotle may have had the Lysis in mind when he
wrote, in book XII of the Metaphysics: "That a final cause may exist among
unchangeable entities is shown by the distinction of its meanings. For the
final cause is (a) some being for whose good an action is done, and
(b) something at which the action aims; and of these the latter exists
among unchangeable entities though the former does not" (XII loyab i-
5, trans. Ross). The son poisoned by hemlock is plainly a final cause in
the first sense; the wine as an antidote, and the cup that holds the wine,
are valued for his sake. The Lysis treats the Primary Valuable as a final
cause in an analogous though not thereby an identical way; it is the ulti-
mate source of all goodness.
What are we to understand by the Primary Valuable? If we interpret
the Lysis through the speech of Diotima in the Symposium, the first answer
is that it is happiness, the object of {3ovArjoi<;. If we ask why we do what
103. Republic VIII 558d~55gc; cf. 5543, 57ib, Phaedo 64d-e, Philebus 6ae.
66 COMMENT
than good for oneself, and this we are not constituted to do. This is an
important premise for the Socratic conclusion, or paradox, that no one
willingly does evil. Wrongdoing implies error, and error is involuntary.
This is not meant to deny, but to explain, a familiar fact about human
behavior, namely, that it is often self-destructive. Human bondage is ig-
norance of where one's own good lies. Compare Augustine and the pears:
Your law, O Lord, punishes theft; and this law is so written in the
hearts of men that not even the breaking of it blots it out: for no thief
bears calmly being stolen from—, not even if he is rich and the other
steals through want. Yet I chose to steal, and not because want drove
me to it—unless a want of justice and contempt for it and an excess
of iniquity. For I stole things which I already had in plenty and of
better quality. Nor had I any desire to enjoy the things I stole, but
only the taking of them and the sin. There was a pear tree near our
vineyard, heavy with fruit, but fruit that was not particularly tempt-
ing either to look at or to taste. A group of young blackguards and
I among them, went out to knock down the pears and carry them off
late one night, for it was our bad habit to carry on our games in the
streets till very late. We carried off an immense load of pears, not to
eat—for we barely tasted them before throwing them to the hogs.
Our only pleasure in doing it was that it was forbidden. Such was my
heart, O God, such was my heart: yet in the depth of the abyss You
had pity on it. Let that heart now tell You what it sought when I was
thus evil for no object, having no cause for wrongdoing save my
wrongness. The malice of the act was base and I loved it—that is to
say I loved my own undoing. I loved the evil in me—not the thing for
which I did the evil: my soul was depraved, and hurled itself down
from security in You into utter destruction, seeking no profit from
wickedness but only to be wicked.104
Diotima's reply to Augustine would be, first, "You contradict yourself,"
and second, "You boast." He boasts because he claims to have done what
is impossible: to have loved evil and his own undoing. This false claim is
supposed to follow because he willfully broke the law, a fact that in no way
entails it. He contradicts himself because he claims to have stolen the pears
for no reason, that he was evil for no object, but also claims to have taken
pleasure in doing what was forbidden. In Platonic terms, the case he
makes, at its strongest, is that stealing the pears was an apparent good
that did not accord with the real good, the object of his wish. That is to
104. Confessions III iv, trans. Sheed.
COMMENT 67
chical events either are or are nomologically dependent on physical events, if a thought either
is or is a derivative of an enzyme, if the mind-body problem is to be resolved by monism or
epiphenomenalism, as Freud seems to have supposed, the primary cure for mental disease
or defect is to be sought in the pharmacy; the causal connection to this of induced recol-
lection of putative past events, insight therapy, is conjectural at best.
COMMENT 69
106. Principles I i.
7O COMMENT
Perhaps then one need only distinguish between the object of a desire and
its ownership. If Jones desires that Smith should be fed, feeding Smith sat-
isfies Jones's desire, as it also satisfies Smith's hunger. As there is trivial he-
donism, so there is trivial egoism: in general satisfaction of a desire that
someone else be benefited is, since desire arises out of one's own lack, a bene-
fit to oneself. So in some sense psychological egoism is trivially true.
Diotima, however, is claiming more than this: desire is self-interested
because happiness defines interest, and all men wish to be happy. So the
question, What is in one's own interest? reduces to the question, In what
does happiness consist?
Here the Symposium breaks new ground. Socrates does not in the early
dialogues couch his moral theory in terms of happiness as an ultimate
goal. He speaks rather of that in us which is benefited by justice and
harmed by injustice, the soul, and he offers the Socratic Proportion: that
virtue is to the soul as health is to the body. No doubt in the concept of
psychical health there is an implicit claim about happiness, for happiness
is not a feeling but a state of well-being; the Symposium develops what is
already there. Aristotle, in the Nicomachean Ethics, will make the virtues
means to happiness as an end, but the Symposium, true to its Socratic her-
itage, assumes that happiness consists in virtue and justice: Eros, as love
of beauty, is love of goodness.
Virtue and justice imply concern for the good of others. Diotima will
claim that the works of Eros issue in education; Socrates, in the Euthydemus
(275a), says he desires that Cleinias should become as good as possible,
and this, indeed, defined Socrates' peculiar mission to Athens: "I go about
doing nothing but persuading you, young and told, to care not for the
body or money in place of, or so much as, excellence of soul" (Apology
3oa). If the pursuit of happiness is inherently self-regarding—in one's
own interest—it is also inherently other-regarding—in the interest of oth-
ers: concern for one's own good is implicated, not accidentally but essen-
tially, with the common good. That implication is grounded on the
Primary Valuable of the Lysis, the Form of Beauty in the Symposium, the
Form of the Good in the Republic. Moral psychology has a metaphysical
foundation; self-interest implies community, and community, universal-
ity. Egoism has as its contrast altruism: but that contrast is otiose if the
good of the self is the good of others.
good. It has now become the real good, the object of rational wish. And
it will end as the Idea of Beauty, an ontological first principle of both love
and knowledge.107 Agathon said much more than he knew when he
claimed that Eros is love of the beautiful, and that there is no love of the
ugly-
Diotima has now told who, or what, Eros is. He is an intermediate di-
vinity, a daijucov, the child of Poros and Penia, conceived on the birthday
of Aphrodite; he is not merely sexual desire, nor even desire in all its
forms, but wish for happiness, and therefore wish to possess good things
for oneself forever.
Having said who Eros is, Diotima, following the plan first suggested by
Agathon and ratified by Socrates, now describes his works. If Eros in him-
self is wish to possess good things for oneself forever, the works of Eros
involve begetting or creating in beauty in order to obtain a kind of vicar-
ious immortality. The desire to procreate and give birth is treated as the
product of a desire shared by men with other animals for continued pos-
session of the good.
Diotima's discussion of the works of Eros (2o6b-2oge) is markedly rhe-
torical, sometimes to the point of parody. The style is characterized by
strong and emphatic rhythms, though it avoids the jingles of isology and
assonance (compare iSsc). There is rhetorical use of metonymy, though
now with a purpose (2o6d; compare 1876). There is much imprecision in
the use of words having to do with reproduction: the various stages of
fertility, arousal, intercourse, pregnancy, and birth are mixed together in
a way that cannot be adequately represented in English; sometimes it
seems things are born before they are begotten (2o6d-5, 2ogb.2, c.3).
There is sophistic play at contradiction for the sake of emphasis—the ob-
ject of Eros is now said to be, not the beautiful, but begetting in the beau-
tiful (2o6d-e; compare i8oa, i86a, ig4e-ig5a). There is rhetorical
overstatement, as when Diotima claims that erotic passion causes animals
to sacrifice their lives for their offspring without remarking that it does
not always cause this (2O7b). There is rhetorical overgeneralization, fail-
ure to distinguish cases, as when Diotima explains the fact that Alcestis
died in behalf of Admetus and that Achilles died in addition to Patroclus
as both equally the result of love of honor and remembrance (2o8c-2oga),
contradicting Phaedrus's rhetorical claim that the motive in each case was
the courage born of love. It comes as no surprise when Socrates speaks
107. Cf. AristotleNicomacheanEthics VIII i i55b 23-26 (trans. W. D. Ross): "It is thought
that each loves what is good for himself, and that the good is without qualification lovable,
and what is good for each man is lovable for him; but each man loves not what is good for
him but what seems good."
72 COMMENT
of Diotima as "most wise" and suggests at one point that she replies "as
the accomplished sophists do" (aoSb-c).
The reason is that Diotima's speech is couched in a style suitable for an
encomium. Socrates has already explained that one should tell the truth
about what is praised, selecting what is most beautiful and putting it in
the most suitable way (ig8d). Diotima is telling the truth about Eros, but
in discussing his works she selects her truths and presents them in a style
that imitates a sophistical display, an epideixis.
Imitation runs deeper than style: it is exhibited by content. Diotima's
passage from Eros as desire for beauty to Eros as desire to procreate and
give birth in the beautiful (2o6e) is a radical transition: desire to procreate
is not the same as the rational wish for happiness, and if Eros implies
rational wish for happiness, Eros is most assuredly not found in the animal
kingdom, where Diotima will trace it. The immortality that Diotima claims
to find in procreation is not the continuing existence of what is one and
the same, but reproduction of something of the same kind, and this ac-
cording to body and soul. That is, it is not immortality, but a kind of im-
itation of it. Diotima's sophistical style suits her subject matter.
Eros is love of immortality. We love only what we lack. Therefore, Eros
cannot be immortal. This conclusion seems to contradict the attempts in
the Phaedo, Republic, and Phaedrus to establish the immortality of the soul
by proof, and Hackforth suggested that Plato had "lapsed into skepticism"
on the subject of immortality when he wrote the Symposium.108 The infer-
ence involves a logical mistake. If it is true that Eros is love of immortality,
it is an immortality desired by the lover just insofar as he loves; this does
not imply that the lover does not have an immortal soul, but only that he
does not have it qua lover. Put otherwise, if there is an immortal principle
in the lover, it is not in him by virtue of his love, which derives from his
lack. The immortality that Eros desires is explicitly said to be immortality
of the mortal nature, contrasted to the immortal nature (2o8b.4). Im-
mortality of the mortal nature, procreation, is different in kind from the
immortality of the soul that Plato was concerned to establish by proof. If
the soul is immortal, as Socrates argues in the Phaedo, then, given Dioti-
ma's claim that the lover qua lover lacks immortality and desires to possess
it, this must imply that love, if it is of the essence of the lover, is not of the
essence of his soul. Mortality attaches to the lover, not essentially, but as
a term in a relation. Eros is not Psyche, and it is a root of error to confound
them.
For any living thing which has reached its normal development and
which is unmutilated, and whose mode of generation is not sponta-
neous, the most natural act is the production of another like itself,
an animal producing an animal, a plant a plant, in order that, as far
as its nature allows, it may partake in the eternal and divine. This is
the goal towards which all things strive, that for the sake of which
they do whatsoever their nature renders possible. The phrase "for
the sake of which" is ambiguous; it may mean either (a) the end to
achieve which, or (b) the being in whose interest the act is done. Since
then no living thing is able to partake in what is eternal and divine
by uninterrupted continuance (for nothing perishable can ever re-
main one and the same), it tries to achieve that end in the only way
possible to it, and success is possible in varying degrees; so it remains
not indeed as the self-same individual but continues its existence in
something like itself—not numerically but specifically one.110
Aristotle's analysis is directed toward the nutritive soul, whose functions
are nutrition and reproduction. Diotima's account assimilates nutrition to
reproduction, hunger and thirst to sex.
Her analysis puts sexuality on a new basis; it is found to have a foun-
dation in the life of men and other animals that is broader than itself, in
that desire for sexual intercourse, like hunger and thirst, exists for the
sake of immortality, that is, continued existence in time. It follows that
sexuality is not to be understood primarily in terms of desire for sexual
intercourse, or the emotions that attend on it and constitute romantic love,
but in terms of offspring. Diotima adduces the fact that animals will sac-
rifice their lives for their young: this is not a deduction but a description
of how men and other animals, in some cases, do in fact behave (compare
207c-d, 2o8b, 2o8c-d, 2i2a). So in the mortal nature, Eros, directed to
the continued existence of the individual organism, has as its work the
continued existence of the species, and may require sacrifice of the life of
the individual organism—as is sometimes true not only in men but other
animals. This is a biological image of that wish for happiness which issues
in courage and friendship.
The begetting of children (2o6c) is the natural object of Eros in respect
to the body (2O7C, 2o8b, e), since Eros aims at immortality. It is but a short
step to infer that sexual intercourse that cannot issue in the begetting of
children is unnatural, and Plato in fact reached this result for homosex-
uality in the Republic (III 4O3a-c) and Laws (VIII 8386; compare VIII
no. De anima II 4153 26-b 8 (trans. Smith); cf. De generatione animalium II i. See also
Metaphysics XII io72b iff.
COMMENT 75
84id, 836c-e, I 6366). The seeds of later Natural Law doctrines of sex-
uality, and their implicit asceticism, are found in the Symposium's insistence
that the natural object of sexuality is procreation.
Diotima's description of the mortal nature, in respect to body and soul,
recalls the Cratylus: "Heraclitus says somewhere that all things change and
nothing remains, and he likens things which are to the flow of a river,
saying that you cannot step in the same river twice" (4023). The Cratylus
(33gd~44oc) asserts the existence, among other characters, of Beauty it-
self, and analyzes it very much as Diotima does: it is always (dei) of such
sort as itself, ever the same and unchanging in that it does not depart from
its own form; and the object of knowledge. The Cratylus further argues
that the objects of knowledge must be unchanging. If all things change
and nothing remains the same, there is no knowledge; for if the very char-
acter of knowledge changes, it would change into another character of
knowledge and not be knowledge; there would then neither be knowing
nor anything known. Therefore, if there is knowing, there is also always
what is known—the Beautiful, the Good, and each of the things that are—
and if this account is true, the account of Heraclitus that all things change
must be false. Diotima's treatment of the ways or turnings (rgojtoi) of the
body, of hair, flesh, bone, and blood, and of the soul, its character, habits
and opinions, desires, pleasures, pains and fears, as perpetually coming
to be and passing away, appears to imply that Heraclitus's account is true.
And Heraclitus's account would indeed be true if there were no Ideas:
the samenesses and identities of the mortal world are formal and struc-
tural, products of the presence of common characters. The immortality
achieved by the mortal nature in terms of persistence of species, Diotima
argues, is that of sameness in kind, and this is the only kind of sameness
the mortal nature admits. The very process of begetting cannot be under-
stood without reference to Beauty itself.
Diotima is here speaking of the works of Eros in respect to the mortal
nature, which aims at procreation because it is implicated with lack and
futurity, and therefore with time, becoming new or young as it grows
older.111 Lack of an end in which process can terminate is inherent in an
account of desire that makes its aim immortality in time, an aim that can-
not in principle be attained. Eros, it will be recalled, is the lover qua lover,
who lacks what he desires to possess.
Diotima's conclusion that we are never the same even in what we know
(207e-2o8a) is indeed "much more extraordinary still." The claim is
111. 2oyd 7; cf. 2o8b i. This is a basis for certain arguments in Hypotheses about Unity
in the Parmentdes (I.i.ix, 1.2.x, 1.3). In the Timaeus (383), it is assumed that what moves
becomes older and younger through time.
76 COMMENT
stated with great generality: not only are we not the same in the kinds of
things we know from day to day, but not the same even in each single one
of those things. Our knowledge from day to day is different, and differs
even when it appears to be the same. This is knowledge, of course, which
belongs to the mortal nature (compare 2oga) and is infected with the per-
ishability of its objects. The image or imitation of genuine immortality
produces an image or imitation of genuine knowledge.
that beauty, insofar as it attaches to visible form, is one and the same in—
Diotima actually uses the word em, on—all bodies, and it is therefore
unreasonable to value highly the beauty of any single thing. Socrates is
here speaking of beauty of appearance (2iob.2), the avQoq, or bloom
(compare siob.8); the beauty of this individual beautiful body attaches
to all bodies insofar as they are beautiful, and apprehension of this beauty
is prior to the desire to beget in what is beautiful. The ascent of the lover
begins by detaching Eros from the particular and concrete, so that the
lover comes to recognize and prefer beauty as a universal, present in many
things. Eros is indeed a philosopher; there is a contemplative element, an
apprehension of beauty as a universal, implicit even in sexual passion.
Begetting in the beautiful in respect to the body has been distinguished
from begetting in the beautiful in respect to the soul (2o6b-c, aoyd-e,
2o8e-2oga). The lover in his ascent to Beauty itself will next come to cher-
ish beauty of soul above bodily beauty.114 At this level and its congener,
love of the beauty of laws and institutions, knowledge of Beauty itself has
not yet come.
From beauty of soul it is but a short step to the beauty of laws and
institutions, whose beauty is akin; so in the Republic, the same principles
provide both soul and state with their beauty and proper order.115 Diotima
supposes, as the Greeks did generally, that character and custom insofar
as they are good evince an aesthetic element, an element intensified at the
next level, where the lover comes to contemplate the beauty and order of
the sciences, among them, importantly, we must assume, mathematics and
proportion theory.116
The lover who was drawn to beget in the beautiful according to the soul
became a poet or lawgiver or educator (2oga—e); his attention is now
drawn to that beauty on which education depends. In contemplating the
beauty of the sciences, the lover is impelled toward the ocean of beauty
made manifest in reasoning, that is, in dialectic and philosophy.117 At this
level he must remain until he has gathered strength to attain to the knowl-
edge of Beauty itself, the goal of all his efforts, that for the sake of which
all his former labors exist.
114. This is the level attained by those who have passed through primary education in
the Republic (III 4ozcff.): to them, the most beautiful spectacle is the coincidence of a beau-
tiful body and a noble soul, and this is the object of their love; but it is not beauty of body
they care for so much as beauty of soul.
115. Cf. Republic II 368^., IV 4356^., VIII 544d/f.
116. In the advanced educational program in Republic VII, the sciences are identified as
arithmetic, geometry, stereometry or solid geometry, astronomy, and harmonics. All of these
sciences were unified by proportion theory.
117. Compare the distinction between the sciences and dialectic in Republic VII.
80 COMMENT
118. See Joseph Owens, The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics, zd ed., To-
ronto, 1963, chap. 3: "The Aristotelian Equivocals." See also J. L. Austin, Philosophical Pa-
pers, Oxford, 1963, pp. 37—42. Equivocity by reference is not paronymy, since there need
be no difference in ending; it is not univocity, because definitions are not the same; and it
is only in a qualified sense equivocity, in that the definitions introduce the same form; neither
is it some form of "family resemblance." The phrase "focal meaning" introduces a metaphor,
rather than clarifying the use, which Aristotle supposed had reference to causes: issues of
meaning tack on in complex ways to the structure of the world. G. E. Moore once denied
in conversation that water is wet, and his dialectical instincts were sound. If water is wet,
and goodness is equivocal by reference, the naturalistic fallacy isn't a fallacy.
82 COMMENT
public II, the account of the decline of the just state in Republic VIII and
IX, and the origins of the world order in the Timaeus, presents as a tem-
poral sequence what is in fact an order of natural priority.
The Idea of Beauty
The transcendental Idea of Beauty, knowledge of which is the lover's goal,
is distinct from the things of this world:
First, in respect to changelessness. Beauty itself admits of neither gen-
eration nor destruction, growth nor diminution (2 1 la. 1-2). Since it is not
in anything other than itself (2 1 ia.8), it does not admit of local motion;
since it suffers nothing (2 1 ib-5), it is not affected by what comes to be or
passes away. The analysis here derives directly from the Cratylus (43gd-
44ob): the object of knowledge is unchanging, and it is an Idea. This be-
came the basis of an Academic argument known to Aristotle, that some-
thing is known when particular things have perished.120 Alexander gives
it as follows.121 The "Argument from Thinking" for the existence of Ideas
is the following sort: if when we think man or foot or animal, we both
think something among things that are and nothing among things that
are particular (for the same thought remains when those things have per-
ished), it is clear that there is something besides particulars and sensibles,
which we think when those things both are and are not; for we do not
then think something that is not; but this is the Form and Idea. This is a
variant of the "Argument from the Sciences":122 If medicine is not knowl-
edge of this given health but simply of health, something will be Health
itself; and if geometry is not knowledge of this given equal and that given
diameter, but of what is strictly equal and strictly diameter, something will
be Equal itself and Diameter itself; but those things are Ideas. These ar-
guments, deriving ultimately from the Cratylus and the Symposium itself,
cast their implication backwards: Diotima's earlier claim that in the mortal
nature knowledge comes to be and passes away (2O7e-2o8a) implies that
the object of mortal knowledge is not to be understood to be Ideas, with
their attendant universality and necessity, but particulars and sensibles.
Second, in respect to purity. Beauty itself is in no sense qualified by its
own opposite, ugliness: it is not beautiful at one time or place but ugly at
another, or beautiful relative to one thing but not to another, or beautiful
to one man but not to another (2 1 13.2-5). This is part of what is meant
by saying that it is pure and unalloyed and unmixed (21 le.i). The Sym-
posium here may be compared to the doctrine of the Two Worlds of Knowl-
120. Metaphysics I ggob 14-15, XIII loygb 10-11.
121. In Metaphysics 81.25-82.1, Hayduck. Cf. Asclepius, in Metaphysics, 72.2-7, Hayduck.
122. Alexander, in Metaphysics, 79.11—15.
84 COMMENT
123. Compare Aristotle's description of God as anaQe$ xal dvaAA.oia)Tov, impassive and
unalterable (Metaphysics XII 10733 12).
COMMENT 85
by nature, or present in men in some other way; the Form is here used,
not to identify its instances, but to determine its relation to other attri-
butes, such as teachability.
The Symposium offers still a different function for the Form of Beauty.
First it is a terminus of wish and desire: the whole appetitive life of men,
and their emotional life insofar as it is appetitive, is founded on and rooted
in Beauty itself. But the Form is also a terminus of knowledge: the ascent
to Beauty implies passage through the sciences.
Beauty is treated as equivalent to Goodness, and the ascent passage of
the Symposium looks forward to the Republic and the comparison of the
Good to the Sun in book VI. That the Good is there an Idea or Form is
clear (5086.3, siya.i, 534c.i); as such, it is intelligible and can be known
(5i7c, 5O4d-3, 5180-d, 534C, e), grasped by Adyog (sub, 534c), and dis-
tinguished from other Forms (534b); and as a Form, it is a thing which is
(5°?b; compare 532b), and at the same level as the Beautiful (507^, com-
pare 532b). It is to the intelligible world as the sun is to the sensible world:
as the sun is the source of light by which the eye sees and objects are
visible, so the Good is the source of intelligence and intelligibility. It is a
first principle of the sciences, as Beauty is in the Symposium. Since Beauty
and Goodness are first principles of explanation, it must follow that not
all things that are can be purposively or ideologically explained. That is,
Beauty and Goodness are not equivalent to Being, but beyond Being, sur-
passing it in dignity and power. The Republic and Symposium are on this
point consistent with the doctrine of Necessity in the Timaeus (compare
Republic II 47gb).
The ultimate object of wish and desire in the Symposium is identical with
the ultimate object of knowledge. Beauty as it presents itself to sense, the
av0og or bloom on a lovely body, is the sensuous aspect of goodness.
Contemplation
The guide in the ascent, when he guides rightly, leads the lover to con-
templation of Beauty itself.
The centrality of contemplation in the life of men is probably in origin
a Pythagorean doctrine. There was a tradition, to which Diotima has al-
ready implicitly referred (2O5d), about how Pythagoras,124 when asked
who he was, replied that he was a philosopher, and compared human life
to a festival. Some come to the fair to buy and sell; they are the business-
men, the money-makers. Some come to compete in games that will bring
124. Diogenes Laertius VIII 8, on the authority of Sosicrates, perhaps relying in Hera-
elides of Pontus. See also Cicero Tusculan Disputations V 3 and lamblichus Vita Pythagorae 58.
86 COMMENT
them victory and honor; they are the athletes. But the best come as dearai,
spectators, to watch and contemplate. So similarly in life, some seek gain,
others fame, but philosophers seek truth and reality. Aristotle preserved
the heritage of this tradition in contrasting the three lives of enjoyment,
politics, and contemplation.125
If contemplation is allied to intellectual intuition, the description of Soc-
rates at Potidaea (22oc-d) implies that it also involved hard thought: he
stood for twenty-four hours, from dawn to dawn, "thinking something
over and considering it," and "when he found no solution he didn't leave
but stood there inquiring into it," and then he offered a prayer to the sun
and left. His state of mind is not prayer but explicitly contrasted to
prayer;126 nor is it trance-like, for the verbs used to describe it imply ra-
tiocination. It is well to recall that Pythagoras, if he identified philosophy
with contemplation, included in it the doing of mathematics: the pleas-
antness of contemplation, and its connection with beauty, included the
deductive satisfactions of proof. The upward path to Beauty in the Sym-
posium represents the alternative movement of mind, the ascent to first
principles. If it includes an emotional response that may fairly be called
adoration (2iid-e), its essence is cognition.127
It is possible to supplement this account. Aristotle distinguishes two
125. Nicomachean Ethics I iog5b 17-22. In this he was following the Republic (IX 5810;
cf. Phaedo 68c, 820).
126. Neither is it, at least on this evidence, mystical. The word derives fromjuvco, to shut
the mouth, to shut the eyes—the Indo-European root occurs in English mouse. Slang, as
often, preserves an archaic root in the expression "to keep mum," that is, to keep one's
mouth shut, and in the pleasant oxymoron "mum's the word." Mysticism suggests secret
doctrines, that is, doctrines that ought not or cannot be communicated to others. The speech
of Diotima, on the contrary, is born not of secrecy but of the intent to communicate, and
contemplation involves intellectual apprehension of a first principle that is taken to be ex-
planatory of the structure of the world; it is, that is to say, inherently rational.
It follows that the Symposium provides no evidence of secret or esoteric Platonic doctrines.
To the degree that this claim has ever had a rational as distinct from a cabalistic basis, it
derives from Aristotle, whose testimony about Plato has now been shown to derive primarily
from his own interpretation of Plato's Parmenides. See R. E. Allen, Plato's Parmenides, Min-
neapolis, Minn., 1983.
127. One may recall the remark of that radical empiricist, William James: "Looking back
on my own experiences, they all converge towards a kind of insight to which I cannot help
ascribing some metaphysical significance. The keynote of it is invariably a reconciliation. It
is as if the opposites of the world, whose contradictoriness and conflict make all our diffi-
culties and troubles, were melted into a unity. Not only do they, as contrasted species, belong
to one and the same genus, but one of the species, the nobler and better one, is itself the
genus, and so soaks up and absorbs its opposite into itself. This is a dark saying, I know,
when thus expressed in terms of common logic, but I cannot wholly escape from its au-
thority" (The Varieties of Religious Experience [1902], London, 1952, p. 379).
COMMENT 87
But with regard to incomposites, what is being or not being, and truth
or falsity? A thing of this sort is not composite, so as to 'be' when it
is compounded and not to 'be* if it is separated, like, "that the wood
is white" or "that the diagonal is incommensurable"; nor will truth
and falsity still be present in the same way as in the previous cases.
In fact, as truth is not the same in these cases, so also being is not the
same; but (a) truth or falsity is as follows—contact and assertion are
truth (assertion not being the same as affirmation), and ignorance is
non-contact. For it is not possible to be in error regarding what a thing
is, save in an accidental sense . . . it is not possible to be in error, but
only to know them or not to know them. But we do inquire what they
are, viz. whether they are of such and such a nature or not. (b) As
regards the 'being' that answers to truth and the 'non-being' that an-
swers to falsity, in one case there is truth if the subject and attribute
are really combined, .and falsity if they are not combined; in the other
case, if the object is existent it exists in a particular way, and if it does
not exist in this way it does not exist at all. And truth means knowing
these objects, and falsity does not exist, nor error, but only igno-
rance—and not an ignorance which is like blindness; for blindness is
akin to a total absence of the faculty of thinking.129
The source of this is Republic V: the opposite of truth and reality is not
falsehood but ignorance, and ignorance corresponds to not-being, lack of
any object for the mind to grasp. So in the Parmenides (i32b-<:) it is as-
sumed that a thought, to be a thought, must be of something which is.
Thought, insofar as it is true or false, involves combination and issues in
statements; but combination presupposes contact with the nature of
things that are, and implies intellectual intuition, that intuition which is
of the essence of contemplation, and which must ultimately touch the
principle or principles on which all else depends, Beauty itself and Good-
ness.
Virtue and Contemplation
Perhaps there is a paradox within the structure of Diotima's speech itself.
What is primarily valuable is happiness; happiness consists in living justly
and temperately, but also in the contemplation of a transcendent Idea,
Beauty itself. But living justly and temperately do not seem at all the same
as the contemplation of Beauty.
The paradox is more apparent than real. On the side of objects, justice
and temperance are parts of virtue. Virtue—dgerrj is the abstract noun
of which ayados is the adjective—is goodness; and Beauty and Goodness
are equivalent.
But then, the contemplation of Beauty and Goodness, as distinct from
Beauty and Goodness, is surely a state of mind, whereas the practice of
justice or temperance or courage is a matter of action and conduct. No
doubt it is tempting to think of justice and temperance and courage as
dispositional predicates, as solubility is a dispositional predicate of salt;
Socrates, however, treats the virtues as attributes of soul intimately con-
nected with wisdom. The connection between virtue and contemplation
may be taken as internal, as Aristotle afterward claimed in a passage that
is a precipitate of Diotima's account of the ascent to Beauty:
If happiness is activity in accordance with virtue, it is reasonable that
it should be in accordance with the highest virtue; and this will be
that of the best thing in us. Whether it be reason or something else
that is this element which is thought to be our natural ruler and guide
and to take thought of things noble and divine, whether it be itself
also divine or only the most divine element in us, the activity of this
in accordance with its proper virtue will be perfect happiness. That
this activity is contemplative we have already said.130
And again:
Now he who exercises his reason and cultivates it seems to be both in
the best state of mind and most dear to the gods. For if the gods have
any care for human affairs, as they are thought to have, it would be
reasonable both that they should delight in that which was best and
most akin to them (i.e. reason) and that they should reward those
130. Nicomachean Ethics X i i77a i iff. (trans. W. D. Ross).
COMMENT 89
who love and honour this most, as caring for things that are dear to
them and acting both rightly and nobly. And that all these attributes
belong most of all to the philosopher is manifest. He, therefore, is
dearest to the gods. And he who is that will presumably also be hap-
piest; so that in this way too the philosopher will more than any other
be happy.131
Aristotle, speaking in his own voice, is often Plato's most helpful com-
mentator.
Diotima suggests that the man who has laid hold of or touched (iQdn-
rew) Beauty itself comes to possess true virtue and is beloved of god, and
"he, if any man does, becomes immortal."132 To be immortal is to be di-
vine, and the philosophical life implies an imitation of the divine nature,
so that, as one approximates to the nature of god, one approximates to
the nature of the immortal. The ultimate fulfillment of human nature is
intellectual; human happiness consists in rationality, and it is a law of the
intellect that like knows like.133
Recollection
It may perhaps be asked how the lover, ignorant of beauty, is able to as-
cend, or why he is not satisfied with the state he is in. The Meno, the Phaedo,
and the Phaedrus suppose that knowledge is recollection; but here, in the
ascent passage of the Symposium, there is only reference to a guide (2 loa).
Perhaps that guide is the educator to whom Diotima has already referred
(2ogb-c). But Diotima must ultimately refer to "that by which it is nec-
essary to contemplate" Beauty itself, to "seeing the Beautiful with that by
which it is visible" (212a), that is, to the eye of the soul (compare Republic
VII 533d). We shall then understand that, as in the Phaedo (74d-e, 76d-
e) perception provokes recollection, so the sight of physical beauty re-
minds the lover of the nature of Beauty itself. Diotima, in her account of
Beauty itself, has in fact provided the premise that in the Phaedo (72e—
7gb, 743—773) is understood to imply that knowledge is recollection and
that the soul is immortal.
Given that this is so, Beauty in the Symposium and the Good of Republic
VI may be compared to the God of Augustine's Confessions: "I would not
have sought Thee had I not already found Thee." Aspiration presupposes
implicit knowledge of what is aspired to; what the lover seeks is already
within him, guiding the search, and the guide who leads him upward is
ultimately the active principle of his own rationality. This is a claim in
metaphysics and epistemology, but perhaps it is also a religious claim as
well, one that recalls Augustine: "Our hearts are restless till they rest in
Thee."
The apprehension of Beauty itself presupposes that Beauty itself exists.
If at one level the proton philon of the Lysis, what is primarily valuable,
consists in happiness, and happiness in the contemplation of Beauty itself,
then Beauty itself, that in which all derivative images of beauty partici-
pate, is the ontological condition of all value. In the Lysis (21 ic), Socrates
suggests that "when a cause is destroyed, it is surely impossible for that
of which it is the cause to continue to exist." What is primarily valuable is
a necessary condition for the existence of other things insofar as they are
valuable. One may compare Aristotle (Metaphysics V loiga.i/jf.): "Some
things are called prior and posterior . . . in respect of nature and sub-
stance, that is, those which can be without other things, while the others
cannot be without them—a distinction that Plato first used."
The Descent of Eros
The wish to contemplate beauty is universal among men, but often
thwarted. The failure of most people to attain their own good is the result
of ignorance, and of something more. In the Phaedrus (248a-b), souls in
their passion to attain the heights and follow the gods come into conflict
with one another; their wings are broken in the struggle and they fall to
earth to feed upon the food of semblance.
In his reflections on dialectic in the Phaedrus, Socrates considers the
relationship between the two doctrines of Eros he had earlier explained.
After a recantation of the view of Eros given in his first speech, he turns
to a second.
Socrates' first speech had defined Eros as a species of vfigu;, wanton-
ness: "When irrational desire, pursuing the enjoyment of beauty, had
gained the mastery over judgment that prompts to right conduct, and has
acquired from other desires akin to it fresh strength to strain toward bod-
ily beauty, that very strength provides it with its name: it is the strong
COMMENT 91
passion called Love" (Phaedrus 238b-c). But in his second speech, Socrates
refers to this love as sinister (Phaedrus 266a).
The notion of a sinister love is relevant beyond its immediate applica-
tion. The speech of Lysias (2306-234^, where lust is extolled as a proper
basis for human relationships, is an example of it, and ranging beyond
the Phaedrus, Republic VIII and IX may be taken as a description of the
downward passage of Eros. The progressive perversion and corruption
of the philosophical nature is there analyzed as a social condition, a de-
generacy of constitution; but to each kind of constitution there is a cor-
responding human character.34 Corruption introduces into that character
the seeds of its own destruction, and unless corrected, both state and in-
dividual tend to sink to governance by their lowest elements. In the in-
dividual, this implies the tyranny of a single master passion, a passion that
enslaves other impulses and inverts the natural order of the soul. That
tyrannical master passion is "an Eros" and a kind of madness.135
By contrast with a sinister love, divine love reminds the lover of some-
thing seen before: "When one who is fresh from the mystery (of the vision
of the Ideas), and saw much of the vision, beholds a god-like face or bodily
form that truly expresses beauty, first there comes upon him a shuddering
and a measure of that awe which the vision inspired, and then reverence
as at the sight of a god; and but for fear of being deemed a very madman
he would sacrifice to his beloved, as to a holy image of deity."136 Human
love derives from recollection of the Ideas.
Eros and Psyche
F. M. Cornford supposed that the ascent of the lover from the physical
world to Beauty itself shows that Eros is a spiritual impulse that is one
and continuous throughout the process of ascent, a moving fund of psy-
chical energy operating at a deeper level of the soul than the tripartite
psychology of Republic IV:
We are now to learn that the three impulses which shape three types
of life are not ultimately distinct and irreducible factors, residing in
three separate parts of a composite soul, of some in the soul, some
in the body. They are manifestations of a single force or fund of en-
ergy, called Eros, directed through divergent channels toward var-
ious ends. This conception makes possible a sublimation of desire;
the energy can be redirected from one channel to another. The flow
134. Republic VIII 544^.
135. Republic IX 5726, 573b, d; cf. Laws VIII 8373.
136. Phaedrus 2513 (translation after R. Hackforth).
92 COMMENT
137. "The Doctrine of Eros in Plato's Symposium," The Unwritten Philosophy, Cambridge,
1
952, PP- 70-?1-
138. Ibid., p. 73.
139. See John Gould, The Development of Plato's Ethics, Cambridge, 1955, p. 89.
COMMENT 93
the soul was defined by Plato precisely as the one thing that has the
power of self-motion. The Platonic doctrine of Eros has been com-
pared, and even identified, with modern theories of sublimation. But
the ultimate standpoints of Plato and Freud seem to be diametrically
opposed. Modern science is dominated by the concept of evolution,
the upward development from the rude and primitive instincts of our
alleged animal ancestry to the higher manifestations of rational life.
The conception is not foreign to Greek thought. The earliest philo-
sophical school had taught that man had developed from a fish-like
creature, spawned in the slime warmed by the heat of the sun. But
Plato had deliberately rejected this system of thought. Man is for him
the plant whose roots are not in earth but in the heavens. In the myth
of transmigration the lower animals are deformed and degraded
types, in which the soul which has not been true to its celestial affinity
may be imprisoned to work out the penalty of its fall. The self-moving
energy of the human soul resides properlv in the highest part, the
immortal nature. It does not rise from beneath but rather sinks from
above when the spirit is ensnared in the flesh. So, when the energy
is withdrawn from the lower channels, it is gathered up into its orig-
inal source. This is indeed a conversion or transfiguration; but not a
sublimation of desire that has hitherto existed only in the lower
forms. A force that was in origin spiritual, after an incidental and
temporary declension, becomes purely spiritual again.140
Since Plato believed, at least by the time he wrote the Phaedrus, that soul
is self-moving motion, Cornford is suggesting that Eros and Psyche are
one: "In the Phaedrus . . . the emphasis falls at first on the moving power
of the soul in the living creature. The soul is defined as the only thing
capable of moving itself, and hence the source and fountain of all motion
in the universe. The whole context seems to imply (though this is not ex-
plicitly stated) that the moving force in the soul is desire, Eros; for desire
is the type of motion which reaches forward to its object, and is not pushed
from behind by an antecedent mechanical cause."141 It is perhaps odd to
think of desire being a kind of motion at all, let alone self-moving motion,
but Cornford is drawing on a tradition also represented by L£on Robin:
Love was conceived in the Symposium as an impulse which is always
either in action or ready for action; for love always desires something
other than what it has: it is ceaselessly in chase, ceaselessly moving
140. Cornford, "Doctrine," pp. 78-79.
141. Principium Sapientiae, Cambridge, 1954, p. 80.
94 COMMENT
forward. Thus love is mover and moved; itself, but at the same time
all the rest, soul as well as body, since it is only through love that both
flesh and the spirit have a share in immortality through generation.
Now this double desire is transferred to the soul in the Phaedrus. The
desire to make itself immortal, to perpetuate itself in other souls or
bodies is, according to the Symposium, the fundamental expression of
love; in the Phaedrus it is transformed into an essential immortality
of the soul, without which even love itself would be unintelligible.
Thus it is the soul which moves itself, and everything else. But this
movement is love: the soul loves itself, and it is this which causes it to
accomplish its celestial rotations, moved by the desire to contemplate
those true realities the vision of which provides sustenance for what
is best in it. Again, the soul governs and administers everything de-
prived of soul; it is thus the desire by which it moves everything to
which movement is communicated. . . . Finally, it is this desire which,
awakened in the soul by Anamnesis, arouses an enthusiasm from
which will spring the philosophical love from which the soul will draw
the force that will lead it to its natural place.142
It will be evident that both Cornford and Robin, like Plotinus,143 treat Eros
as a substance in its own right, an ovoia. Once this is done, it is but a short
step to suppose that it is identical with soul, and its identification with self-
moving motion in the Phaedrus appears to follow as of course.
It seems evident that Eros cannot be identified with self-moving motion.
For if Eros were a motion, it could not be self-moving: arising in lack,
ending with fulfillment, the child of both Poros and Penia, it is motion a
quo and ad quern. Eros cannot be identified with soul, conceived as self-
moving motion, because soul is immortal and Eros implies lack of im-
mortality.
Nor can Eros be said to be moved by its objects. Eros involves futurity:
the object of desire is not a presently existing thing, but a future state of
affairs involving possession. The thirsty man desires, not water, but to
possess water. Since desire implies lack of possession, the object of desire
does not exist when desire exists. So the object of desire is peculiarly eva-
nescent: when desire is, it is not; and when desire is not, it is not. Insofar
as desire implies possession of an unpossessed object, its object is, and
is necessarily, nonexistent. What is nonexistent cannot move anything,
either as efficient or as final cause.
If Eros is not a motion, neither is it a "force" nor a "moving fund of
142. Phedre, Paris, 1933, pp. cxxxviii-ix.
143. See The Myth of Poros and Penia (2O3a-€): Plotinus and Ficino, pp. 120-121.
COMMENT 95
144. Church Dogmatics: A Selection, trans. G. W. Bromiley, New York, 1962, p. 173. The
same position is put at greater length by Anders Nygren, Eros and Agape, trans. P. S. Watson,
New York, 1969.
96 COMMENT
cannot pass over or be transformed into the second, nor the second in the
first" (p. 176). Barth proceeds to back this with a philological claim:
It is immediately apparent that the New Testament consistently
avoids the use of the verb Igdv and the substantive egcog—the terms
which in classical Greek plainly describe this other grasping, taking,
possessing and enjoying love. . . . The reader who meets the concept
of love in these pages is obviously not even to be reminded of this
other love. Apart from an occasional use of (fiihelv with its emphasis
on feeling the normal term for love in the New Testament is dyajrdv,
with the substantive dydnr], which is unknown in classical Greek and
only sparing used in Hellenistic. It is only in New Testament usage
that this word has acquired the well-known meaning and content of
a love opposed to egcog. In itself it is rather colorless. It has something
of the sense of the English 'like.'
The noun dydnrj is in fact a late back-formation, first found in the Sep-
tuagint, from the verb dyajtdco, which in classical Greek means to delight
in, to greet with affection, thus making its application to sexual inter-
course in the Septuagint intelligible; it becomes the ordinary word for love
in New Greek.145 Barth is quite right in claiming that egcos and egdv, in
ordinary classical Greek usually used of sexual love, do not occur in the
New Testament; this is a dialect shift characteristic of New Greek. Barth's
inference from it, that "the reader is not even to be reminded of this other
love," is inadequate even as an argument from silence.
The translation offered by the Authorized Version of ayanr], for ex-
ample by St. Paul in I Corinthians xiii, is charity, and charity is not a form
of altruistic desire opposed to selfish desire, but a virtue like faith and
hope.146 Augustine goes to the heart of the matter, with a comment which
shows that Barth's philological misunderstanding is not new:
He who resolves to love God, and to love his neighbor as himself, not
according to man but according to God, is on account of this love said
to be of good will; and this is in Scripture more commonly called
charity, but it is also, even in the same books, called love. . . . Some
are of opinion that charity or regard (dilectio) is one thing, love (amor)
another. They say dilectio is used of a good affection, amor of an evil
one. But it is very certain that even secular literature knows no dis-
tinction.
The right will is, therefore, well-directed love, and the wrong will
is ill-directed love. Love, then, yearning to love what is loved, is desire;
and having and enjoying it, is joy; fleeing what is opposed to it, is
fear; and feeling what is opposed to it, when it has befallen it, is sad-
ness. Now these motions are evil if the love is evil; good if the love is
good.147
Having offered the outlines of a psychology of the emotions based on love
or desire, Augustine goes on to contrast charity with the sin of pride: "For
'pride is the beginning of sin/ And what is pride but the craving for undue
exaltation? And this is undue exaltation, when the soul abandons Him to
whom it ought to cleave as its end, and becomes a kind of end in itself.
This happens when it becomes its own satisfaction. And it does so when
it falls away from the unchangeable good that ought to satisfy it more than
itself."148 Earth in effect makes Eros the sin of pride, "a distinctively un-
critical intensification and strengthening of natural self-assertion." Eros
is the love characteristic of the natural man without the grace of God, the
love characteristic of nothingness and sin.
This account of Eros and Agape is confused at every level. Philologi-
cally, it rests on an argument from silence that ignores dialect changes.
Conceptually, it ignores the fact that Agape has as its classical equivalent
Philia, friendship. As an account of Plato, it neglects the fact that concern
for others is an element in the analysis of Eros itself, insofar as Eros is
directed toward happiness; it makes Eros selfish or self-interested149 at
the expense of ignoring happiness as consisting injustice and friendship,
the works of Eros as issuing in creation not only according to the body
but the soul, and the termination of Eros in contemplation of the summum
bonum. Socrates, on grounds of justice, laid down his life for his city, and
thereby for its citizens: Eros is not distinct from Agape as egoistic desire
is distinct from altruistic, or selfishness from unselfishness, or self-love
from benevolence. To project these distinctions onto Eros is to distort not
only the Symposium but the whole tradition of Socratic and Platonic moral
psychology.
One may also ask whether Earth's concept of Agape, love purely for
the sake of the other without regard to the value or worth of that other,
is not also confused. Theologically, it is based on conviction of man's utter
147. City of God XIV 7 (trans. Dods).
148. Ibid., XIV 13.
149. For Plato's views on selfishness in contrast to justice, see Laws V 73^-7323.
98 COMMENT
Aristophanes Redivivus
The speech of Aristophanes defined Eros in terms of love for unique in-
dividuals, and the speech of Alcibiades, in its praise of Socrates, will pro-
vide an example of that love. Gregory Vlastos reproaches Socrates and
Diotima, whose account he identifies with Plato's, for not agreeing:
We are to love the persons so far, and only insofar, as they are good
and beautiful. Now since all too few human beings are masterworks
of excellence, and not even the best of those we have the chance to
love are wholly free of streaks of the ugly, the mean, the common-
place, the ridiculous, if our love of them is to be only for their virtue,
the individual, in the uniqueness and integrity of his or her individ-
uality, will never be an object of our love. This seems to me the car-
dinal flaw in Plato's theory. It does not provide for love of whole
persons, but only for love of that abstract version of persons which
consists of the complex of their best qualities. This is the reason why
personal affection ranks so low in Plato's scala amoris. . . . The high
climactic moment of fulfillment—the peak achievement for which all
lesser loves are to be 'used as steps'—is the one farthest removed from
affection for concrete human beings.151
Diotima would reply that love of individual human beings, if it is genu-
inely to be love, must be grounded in love of Beauty itself, and that Good-
ness or Beauty is a third term in any love-relation that is real and true.
Martha Nussbaum, repeating Vlastos's words, finds it all a bit myste-
rious—what do uniqueness and individuality come to?—yet decides that
there must be, after all, something in what Vlastos says. She suggests that
while Socrates and Diotima have described one kind of love, Plato, as au-
thor of the Symposium, has described two kinds of love, between which he
means for his readers to choose. There is the love of unique individuals
that Aristophanes has described and Alcibiades will manifest, and on the
151. Platonic Studies, Princeton, N.J., 1973, p. 31. Compare Dover, Symposium, p. 113.
10O COMMENT
other hand the love of Beauty. Plato means for us to understand that to
choose one is to give up the other, so that to choose Beauty is to lose some
beauty. The choice is inherently tragic—or should one say "existential,"
as inherently irrational?—and it is our choice:
But what, then, becomes of us, the audience, when we are confronted
with the illumination of this true tragedy and forced to see every-
thing? We are, Alcibiades tells us, the jury (2igc). And we are also
the accused. As we watch the trial of Socrates for the contemptuous
overweening (huperephanias, 219^5) of reason, which is at the same
time the trial of Alcibiades for the contemptuous overweening of the
body, we see what neither of them fully see—the overweening of both.
And we see that it is the way we must go if we are to follow either one
or the other. But so much light can turn to stone.152
It is flattering to be told that we may see what neither Socrates nor Alci-
biades see, but the account does not inspire confidence by reason of in-
accuracy. It is not we but the company who are addressed as the jury; no
text suggests that we are also the accused; Socrates is not on trial for the
contemptuous overweening of reason, whatever that might be, nor Alci-
biades for the contemptuous overweening of the body either; light does
not turn things to stone.
Inexactness of statement, here and elsewhere, is matched by inexact
analysis. Socrates and Diotima, it will be recalled, argue that the object of
love is the beautiful, and that the lover is not beautiful. One might attempt
to formalize this as: For ally and all x, ify loves x, x is beautiful, and, For
ally and all x, ify loves x, y is not beautiful. To the latter one may object:
"we do not understand how he has reached the conclusion that y lacks
beauty. We thought he was talking about people. We had a situation where
some);—let us say Alcibiades—is in love with beautiful Agathon. He wants
to possess this beautiful person, and yet he is aware that he does not pos-
sess him. . . . So there is a beautiful person whom he both loves and lacks.
This does not, however, show that he himself lacks beauty, even given the
earlier premises of the argument. He may be quite beautiful, for all we
know."153 If Plato were as slipshod in argument as this, why bother to read
him? The gloss confuses Alcibiades as lover, who as such lacks beauty, with
Alcibiades himself, who may be as pretty as you please: Eros is the lover
qua lover, not the lover considered apart from his loving. Confusion over
relative terms leads to further confusion: "So far there is some beauty
152. The Fragility of Goodness, Cambridge, 1986, p. 198.
153. Ibid., p. 178.
COMMENT 101
loved by the lover: Alcibiades loves the beauty of Agathon. From this it
follows only that Alcibiades lacks that beauty—not that he lacks all
beauty. . . : if Alcibiades is kalon in physical appearance, can he not still
love and lack the beautiful soul of Socrates? What we now see is that Soc-
rates' argument depends on a strong hidden assumption: that all beauty,
qua beauty, is uniform. All manifestations of the kalon must be sufficiently
like one another that if you lack one kind it is natural to conclude that
you lack them all."154 That is, if you lack one kind of beauty, you lack all
kinds of beauty, because all kinds of beauty are one kind of beauty: so if
you lack the beauty of a rosebud, you're not a pretty fellow. This is an
astonishing piece of reasoning, a specimen of the here's-your-hat-what's-
your-hurry? school of Plato criticism: it's not supposed to make sense.
Instead of retracing one's steps to see what went wrong, one may rush to
a conclusion:
It is a startling and powerful vision. Just try to think it seriously: this
body of this wonderful beautiful person is exactly the same in quality
as that person's mind and inner life. Both, in turn, the same in quality
as the value of Athenian democracy; of Pythagorean geometry; of
Eudoxian astronomy. What would it be like to look at a body and see
in it exactly the same shade and tone of goodness and beauty as a
mathematical proof—exactly the same, differing only in amount and
in location, so that the choice between making love with a person and
contemplating the proof presented itself as a choice of having n mea-
sures of water and n + 100? . . . These proposals are so bold as to
be pretty well incomprehensible from the ordinary point of view.155
The White Queen, as a result of practice, sometimes believed six im-
possible things before breakfast. Perhaps you can too. While you are
trying, reflect on this implication: "The lover, seeing a flat uniform land-
scape of value, with no jagged promontories or deep valleys, will have few
motivations for moving here rather than there on that landscape. A con-
templative life is a natural choice."156 As natural a choice as any other, no
doubt, for in such a universe any choice would be a matter of indiffer-
ence—if one can still choose when moral nihilism is bounded by ennui.
But one might not seem quite convinced that a contemplative life is a nat-
ural choice even so: "Socrates is put before us as an example of a man in
the process of making himself self-sufficient—put before us, in our still
withdraw, and was murdered in Phrygia in 404 at the behest of the Thirty
Tyrants, Critias and Charmides among them. It was a brilliant, star-
crossed, wasted life, which Plato described in the Republic (VI 494b-d):
immense talents corrupted by boundless ambition to manage affairs, fed
by the flattery of the mob and unaccompanied by the hard work of re-
flection.159
Aristophanes, in introducing his own speech, had said that he would
speak about the human condition, about how human nature is consti-
tuted. The thematic role of Aristophanes, the comic poet whose chief busi-
ness concerns Dionysus and Aphrodite, wine and sex, is now taken over
by Alcibiades—drunk, lascivious, and very funny—and Alcibiades sums
up in his own person the human condition insofar as it is not liberated by
understanding of the aims and purposes of human life. Alcibiades can
represent the human condition because here, at this party, he is a kind of
exemplar of it. He has, or seems to have, everything the human heart
could desire: wealth, noble birth, beauty, political power. And yet, Plato's
readers knew he was not enviable but tragic. He hasn't failed yet, as he
attends this dinner party in the year 416 B.C., but he is going to fail soon,
and the source of his failure, if the Symposium is any guide, is that he values
and passionately loves the wrong things—even in his relation to Socrates.
It is a scene heavy with drunken humor, but Alcibiades is quite serious
in saying he can praise no one, whether god or man, but Socrates; and
Eryximachus, the physician of the body who abhors drunkenness and who
defined the rules by which the previous speeches were conducted, accedes.
Socrates, not Eros, shall be the subject of Alcibiades' praise.160 Socrates,
concerned for truth, is invited to interrupt if Alcibiades says anything
false. He will not interrupt, and by his silence warrants the factual truth
of Alcibiades' account.
159. For Thucydides' comments on the character of Alcibiades, see VI 15—16 (also 89);
on the mutilation of the hermes, VI 27; on Alcibiades accused of parody of the Mysteries,
VI 28; on the politicization of Alcibiades' case, his being refused right of immediate trial
because of his enemies' fear of the army's support for him, VI 29. The Sicilian Expedition
left in midsummer (VI 30), although the Assembly authorizing it met in early spring (para.
8).
Plutarch's Life of Alcibiades also contains useful information. It lays particular emphasis
on Alcibiades' hatred of the flute and contempt for flute players—an interesting gloss on
the emotional ambivalence implied in Alcibiades' comparison of Socrates to Marsyas.
160. R. G. Bury, following Schleiermacher, found in this the key to the meaning of the
Symposium: "It is in the portrait of the ideal Socrates that the main object of the dialogue is
to be sought" (Symposium, p. Ixv). This is exactly wrong: the ultimate object of Eros is the
contemplation of a first principle, and the object of the dialogue is to show it. Alcibiades will
praise Socrates as wise; Socrates, being a philosopher, is not wise but a lover of wisdom, and
Alcibiades therefore confuses love with its object. This is equivalent to confusing Socrates
with Beauty itself, in a manner akin to idolatry.
1O4 COMMENT
the whole of Athens. Agathon replies to Socrates with the exact words
Alcibiades will use: "You are outrageous [vf}QiOTi]$]9 Socrates" (1756), and
suggests that Dionysus will be the judge of their contending claims. That
is, Dionysus will judge between Agathon's claim that Socrates is wiser and
Socrates' claim that Agathon is wiser.
The presence of Dionysus at this drinking party is recalled again with
the introduction of Aristophanes, whose whole business as a comic poet
has to do with wine and sex (1776). But the decision between Agathon
and Socrates is made not by Dionysus, but by the argument begun in the
elenchus of Agathon and carried through in the speech of Diotima: Aga-
thon is not wise because he quite literally, by his own admission, does not
know what he is talking about; Socrates is not wise—as Diotima directly
says (gioa) and Socrates throughout has protested—because he is a phi-
losopher, a lover of wisdom, and can love only what he lacks. Now comes
Alcibiades, a symbolic representation of Dionysus himself, very nearly the
god's epiphany, offering praise of Socrates which from the point of view
of either Dionysus or Aphrodite amounts to condemnation. He loves him,
he has been enslaved by him, he would like to see him dead. The epiphany
of the wine-god is a servant; the surrogate of a chthonian deity has been
bitten by a snake.163
The hubris of Socrates in refusing sexual seduction is something more
than what Alcibiades describes as temperance, self-control. If Eros is wish
for happiness and implies desire for generation according to body or soul,
much sexual desire is not Eros. Specifically, Alcibiades' desire for sexual
intercourse with Socrates was not Eros, because it was sterile. The Eros
praised by the others at the banquet, the Eros of romantic love, is at best
an image, an 8idtokov, of genuine Eros, exemplified in the philosopher
and embodied in Socrates. The hubris of Socrates consists in a principled
disdain. If Eros is wish for what is truly good, then asceticism in respect
to desire and especially sexuality, that most tempting and troubling of all
desires, is implied in the Symposium and at the core of its moral psychology.
Conclusion (223b-d)
Beauty itself had appeared to the soul of the lover suddenly; Alcibiades
had appeared to the company suddenly, and Socrates to Alcibiades sud-
denly, and now a mob of revelers appears at the doors suddenly. Their
arrival marks the end of discourse.
The Symposium ends in impassive calm. Socrates has vanquished the
wine-god.
This page intentionally left blank
TRANSLATION
1723 APOLLODORUS. I think I'm not unprepared in what you ask about.
In fact, I happened to be coming into town the other day from
my home in Phalerum, when someone I know caught sight of me
from behind and called to me at a distance with a playful sum-
mons — "Hey there, you Phalarian," he said, "Apollodorus! Won't
you wait up?" So I stopped and waited.
And he said, "Why really, Apollodorus, I was just looking for
b you a little while ago, because I wish to learn all about the meeting
of Agathon and Socrates and Alcibiades and the others, the time
they were together at the banquet, and what the speeches were
about love. Someone else heard it from Phoenix, son of Philippus,
and related it to me, and he said you knew too; but he had
nothing clear to say. So please relate it to me; for it's very right
of you, after all, to report the discussions of your friend. But
first tell me," he said, "were you present at this gathering your-
self?"
And I said, "It seems he related nothing clear to you at all, if
c you think the meeting occurred so recently that I was present
too."
"Yes, I did think that," he said.
"How so, Glaucon?"164 I said. "Don't you know that Agathon
164. Perhaps Glaucon, son of Ariston, Plato's elder brother and a leading speaker
in the Republic; but if so, and if he, like Apollodorus, was only a child when the
banquet occurred in 416 B.C. (i73a), he must have been very close in age to Plato,
for Plato was then about twelve years old.
II ll ll
112 TRANSLATION
hasn't lived here for many years, whereas it's not even three years
1733 yet that I've associated with Socrates and made it my care each
day to know what he says or does? Before that I ran round every
which way and thought I was doing something when I was more
wretched than anybody, no less than you are right now, thinking
one must do anything else at all except pursue wisdom."
"Don't jest," he said. "Tell me when this meeting took place."
"We were still children," I said. "It was when Agathon won
with his first tragedy, the day after he and his chorus celebrated
their victory feast."
"Quite a while ago, it seems," he said. "But who told you?
Socrates himself?"
b "No indeed," I replied. "It was the same person who told Phoe-
nix, a certain Aristodemus of Cydathenaeum, a little fellow, al-
ways barefoot. He was present at the meeting, and he was I think
one of Socrates' most devoted lovers165 at the time. But of course
I afterwards also asked Socrates about some of the things I heard
from him, and he agreed it was as Aristodemus related it."
"Then why not relate it to me?" he said. "The road into town
is surely well suited for talking and listening."
Well, we walked on together and discussed it, so as I said to
c begin with, I'm not unprepared. If I'm obliged then to relate it
to you as well, it must be done. And anyway, when I talk about
philosophy myself or listen to others do so, quite apart from
thinking I'm benefited, it's extraordinary how much I enjoy it;
but when I hear other kinds of talk, especially from you rich
businessmen, I feel irritation myself and pity for you and your
friends, because you think you're doing something and you're
a accomplishing nothing. On the other hand, maybe you'll believe
I'm unfortunate too, and I think you're right. But I don't just
think it about you, I well know it.
COMPANION. You're always the same, Apollodorus; you're always
speaking ill of yourself and others, and I think you believe that
everyone without exception, beginning with yourself, is wretched
except Socrates. I don't know where you ever got the name of
being soft! For you're always like this in argument, provoked at
yourself and everyone else except Socrates.
165. eQaaTijs, i73b2. Note that there is here no sexual implication in the word,
which might be translated "admirer" or perhaps even "disciple" (cf. 2i8c, 2igc-d),
though its use is proleptic for the discussion of Eros to follow. See also, for example,
Protagoras 317^7, Euthydemus 276d.2.
TRANSLATION 113
After some such discussion as this, he said, off they went. Well,
Socrates turned his thought inward as they proceeded along the
road, and fell behind; when Aristodemus waited for him, he bid
him go on ahead. He found the door open when he reached
e Agathon's house, and he said it put him in a ridiculous position:
for one of the servants inside immediately met him and took him
to where the others were reclining, and he found them just about
to dine. Well, as soon as Agathon saw him, he said, Hello, Aris-
todemus, you're just in time to join us; if you've come for some-
thing else, put it aside for another time, because I looked for you
yesterday to invite you and couldn't find you. But how is it you
don't bring Socrates for us?
I looked around, Aristodemus said, and Socrates was nowhere
to be seen following, so I said that I had myself come with Soc-
rates, because he invited me here to dine.
It's good of you to come, said Agathon. But where is he?
iy5a He was right behind me just now. I wonder where he is myself.
Aristodemus said that Agathon said to a servant, Won't you go
find Socrates and bring him in? And you, Aristodemus, he said,
please recline here by Eryximachus.
He said the servant washed him169 so that he might lie down;
another servant came and announced, Socrates is here. He's with-
drawn to the porch next door, he's standing there, and he won't
come when I call.
That's strange, Agathon said. Keep calling him and don't give
up.
b And Aristodemus said he said, No, let him be. That's his way;
he sometimes stops and stands wherever he happens to be. He'll
be along presently, I think. Don't disturb him, but let him be.
He said that Agathon said, Then we must do so, if you think
it best. But servants, serve dinner to the rest of us. You always
put out whatever you wish in any case, when there's no one su-
pervising you—which I've never yet done—so now assume that
you've invited me with these others to dine as your guests, and
c serve us so that we may praise you.
After this they dined, he said, but Socrates didn't come in.
Well, Agathon several times suggested they send for Socrates, but
Aristodemus wouldn't allow it. Then after a little while Socrates
came, having spent the time in his accustomed way, when they
169. That is, his feet and perhaps his hands, a gesture of customary hospitality.
TRANSLATION 115
heard this, he said, Fine. But I still need to hear from one more
of you: How is Agathon's strength for drinking?
I myself have no strength at all, he replied.
c Well, that's a stroke of luck for the rest us, he said—me and
Aristodemus and Phaedrus and the others here—if you, the most
able drinkers, have now given up; for we're never up to it. I leave
Socrates out of account; he's sufficient either way, so whatever
we do will suit him. Well, since I think no one here is eager to
drink a lot of wine, perhaps I'd be less displeasing in telling you
what sort of thing being drunk is. For I think it has become very
a clear to me from the art of medicine that drunkenness is hard
on people. I would not myself be willing to drink deeply if I could
help it, nor would I advise it for someone else, especially if still
hungover from the previous day.
Aristodemus said that Phaedrus of Myrrhinus interrupted and
said, Why really, I'm accustomed to obey you, especially in what-
ever you say about medicine, and the rest will now do so too, if
they're well advised.
e Hearing this, everyone agreed that the gathering should not
be a drunken affair, but they would drink only for enjoyment.
Then, said Eryximachus, since it's been decided that each of
us should drink only as much as he wishes, nothing compulsory,
I next suggest that the flute-girl who just came in be let go;171
she can play to herself or to the women within the house if she
wishes, while we continue our present gathering through con-
versation. As to the sort of conversation, I'm willing to make a
proposal to you, if you wish.
1773 They all said that they did indeed wish, and bid him make his
proposal.
So Eryximachus said, The beginning of what I have to say fits
Euripides' Melanippe, for "mine is not the tale"172 I'm about to
tell. It belongs to Phaedrus here. Phaedrus often complains to
me and says, "Isn't it terrible, Erixymachus, that the poets make
hymns and paeans for other gods, yet not a single one of them,
b despite their number, has ever offered an encomium to Eros, a
171. The flute, or atUdg (actually, a single- or double-reed instrument and strictly
not a flute but more like a clarinet or an oboe), had a shrill, piercing tone, and was
especially associated with Dionysus, as the lyre was with Apollo. In the Republic (III
3ggd-e; cf. Laws VII 8iac—8133), atUdg-players and atUdg-makers are to be ex-
cluded from the Ideal State: Apollo and his instruments are to be preferred to
Marsyas and his.
172. Euripides, fr. 488 (Nauck): "Mine is not the tale; my mother taught me."
TRANSLATION 117
he did not he would go home and live out a long life, he dared
i8oa choose to help his lover Patroclus and avenge him, not only dying
in behalf of but also in addition to the slain.179 This is why the
gods in high admiration surpassingly honored him, because he
counted his lover so important. Aeschylus talks nonsense in claim-
ing that Achilles was the lover of Patroclus, when he was not only
more beautiful than Patroclus but doubtless than all the other
heroes too, and still beardless, since he was very much younger,
as Homer tells.180 For though the gods really do honor this virtue
b of Eros in highest degree, they marvel and admire and reward
it still more when the beloved cherishes the lover than when the
lover cherishes the beloved. For lover is more divine than beloved:
the god is in him and he is inspired. That is also why they hon-
ored Achilles more than Alcestis, and sent him to the Isles of the
Blest.
Thus then I claim that Eros is eldest and most honored of gods,
and most authoritative in respect to possession of virtue and
happiness for men both living and dead.
185. 0dooo0£ag, 1833.1, obelized by Burnet and excluded by Bury and Dover,
following Schleiermacher, but read by all major manuscripts and supported by
i84C.8-d.i; cf. iSzc.i. The Symposium has been a much emended text, but a con-
servative hand is perhaps more than usually justified; the speakers are sometimes
drunk not only on wine but on their own rhetoric, and this is specifically true of
Pausanias.
124 TRANSLATION
forbid them to talk with their lovers, and the tutor is so ordered,
while companions of his own age also rebuke him if they see
d anything of that sort going on, and their elders do not in turn
prevent the rebuke or criticize it as ill founded—looking to these
things, one might believe again in turn that this sort of thing is
here regarded as most shameful.
But the fact, I think, is this: it is not simply good in and of
itself, nor yet ugly and shameful, but as I said to begin with,
beautiful if done beautifully, shameful if done shamefully. Shame-
fully in gratifying a base lover basely, but beautifully in gratifying
a worthy lover beautifully. The vulgar lover, who loves the body
e more than the soul, is base; he is inconstant because the thing
he loves is inconstant. For as soon as the bloom of the body he
once loved fades, "he takes off and flies," many speeches and
promises disdained. But the lover of a worthy character abides
through life, for he is joined to what is constant.
1843 Our law and custom therefore wishes to test them beautifully
and well, those to be gratified, those to be shunned. For this
reason, then, it commands pursuit to these, flight to those, or-
ganizing a competition to test of which sort the lover is and of
which sort the beloved. It is due to this cause, first, that the law
deems quick capture shameful, in order that time may pass—
which indeed seems to be an excellent test for most things—and
b next deems it shameful to be captured by money or political
power, or if he cowers when ill treated and is not staunch, or if
when offered favors of money or political success he does not
despise them; for none of these seems abiding or constant, quite
apart from the fact that a noble friendship does not naturally
result from them.
One way then is left in our law, if beloved intends to gratify
lover beautifully. For it is law among us that, just as it is not
c flattery or in any way subject to reproach for lovers to be willing
to submit to every kind of slavery for their beloved, so also there
is only one kind of voluntary slavery not subject to reproach: that
involving virtue. For it is held by us that if someone is willing to
serve someone in the belief that through him he will become
better, in respect either to some kind of wisdom or to any other
part of virtue whatever, this voluntary servitude is on the contrary
not shameful, nor is it flattery.186
193. Or perhaps, reading nox; for Badham's JICD, "the twofold Eros is in no sense
there." See David Konstan and Elisabeth Young-Bruehl, "Eryximachus's Speech in
the Symposium" Apeiron 1985, p. 41.
194. A pointless substitution for the Aphrodite Pandemus of Pausanias, as the
"Heavenly Muse" was for the Heavenly Aphrodite: sophistical metonymy.
195. Perhaps an echo of the single surviving fragment of Anaximander, in which
the opposites pay penalty to each other in the cycle of days and seasons, according
to the assessment of Time, for their injustice, that is, their encroachment on the
proper provinces of one another.
TRANSLATION 129
the seasons of the year, it destroys many things and does injustice.
For plagues like to arise from such things as these, and many
other unusual diseases both in beasts and plants; in fact, frost
and hail and blight arise from mutual overreaching and disorder
among things of love such as these, knowledge of which, as it
concerns motions of stars and seasons of years, is called astron-
omy. Still further, all sacrifices and the objects of the seer's art—
that is, the mutual intercourse of gods and men—have to do with
nothing other than protection and cure of Eros. For all kinds of
impiety, concerning parents both living and dead and concerning
the gods, like to arise if one does not gratify the orderly Eros
and honor and revere him in every action, but instead gratifies
the other Eros. The seer's art has therefore been ordained to
oversee these kinds of Eros and heal them, and the seer's art,
again, is a craftsman of friendship between gods and men, by
knowing which things of love among men tend toward piety and
what is religiously right.
So all Eros has, in summary, very great power, or rather all
power, but it is the Eros fulfilled in good things accompanied by
temperance and justice, both among us and among gods, that
has the greatest power and provides all happiness to us and en-
ables us to associate with each other and be friends, even with
the gods, who are stronger than we are.
Well, perhaps I too have left out many things in praising Eros,
but at least not willingly. If I did leave something out, it's your
job, Aristophanes, to fill it in. Or if you intend to offer some
other kind of encomium to the god, please do so, because your
hiccups have stopped.
you don't say something ridiculous, when you could have spoken
in peace.
b Aristophanes laughed and said, You're right, Eryximachus. Let
me unsay what was said. Please relax your guard, because I'm
worried about what I'm going to say, not lest I say something
ridiculous—that would be gain, and native to my Muse—but lest
it make me a butt of ridicule.
Having let fly with this, Aristophanes, he replied, do you think
you'll escape? Pay attention and speak as if you'll be called to
c account for it. Perhaps, however, if I think fit, I'll let you off.
b The reason there were three sexes of this sort was that the male
originally was the offspring of the Sun, the female of the Earth,
and what has a share of both of the Moon, because the Moon also
has share of both. They were spherical both in themselves and in
their gait because they were like their parents. Well, they were
terrible in strength and force, and they had high thoughts and
conspired against the gods, and what Homer told of Ephialtes and
Otus196 is told also of them: they tried to storm Heaven in order
to displace the gods.
c Well, Zeus and the other gods took counsel about what they
ought to do, and were at a loss, for they didn't see how they could
kill them, as they did the Giants, whose race they wiped out with
the thunderbolt—because the honors and sacrifices they received
from human beings would disappear—nor yet could they allow
them to act so outrageously. After thinking about it very hard in-
deed, Zeus said, "I believe I've got a device by which men may
continue to exist and yet stop their intemperance, namely, by be-
d coming weaker. I'll now cut each of them in two," he said, "and
they'll be weaker and at the same time more useful to us by having
increased in number, and they'll walk upright on two legs. But if
they still seem to act so outrageously and are unwilling to keep
quiet," he said, "I'll cut them in two again, so that they'll have to
get around on one leg, hopping."
So saying, he cut human beings in two the way people slice
e serviceberries197 to preserve them by drying, or as they cut eggs
with a hair; he ordered Apollo to turn around the face and the
half-neck of whoever he'd cut to where the cut was made, so that
the man would be more orderly by contemplating his own division,
and he bid Apollo heal the other wounds. Apollo turned the face
around and drew together from all sides the skin on what is now
called the belly, as purses are closed by a drawstring, and, tying it
off in the middle of the belly, he made a single mouth which peo-
igia pie call the navel. And he smoothed out most of the other wrinkles
and carefully shaped the chest with a tool of the sort shoemakers
use to smooth out wrinkles in the leather on a last; but he left a
few wrinkles around the belly and the navel, as a reminder of the
ancient suffering. Now when their nature was divided in two, each
196. Who planned to overthrow the gods by piling Mount Ossa on Olympus and
Pelion on Ossa, to climb the sky (Odyssey xi 307—320). Apollo destroyed them.
197. The European Sorbus domestica, of the apple family; it resembles the moun-
tain ash, but with larger leaves and fruit, which is edible.
132 TRANSLATION
half in longing rushed to the other half of itself and they threw
b their arms around each other and intertwined them, desiring to
grow together into one, dying of hunger and inactivity too because
they were unwilling to do anything apart from one another.
Whenever any of the halves died and the other was left, the one
left sought out another and embraced it, whether it met half of a
whole woman—what we now call a woman—or of a man. And so
they perished.
But Zeus took pity and provided another device, turning their
pudenda to the front—for up till then they had those on the out-
c side too, and they used to beget and bear children not in each
other but in the earth, like locusts—well, he turned them to the
front and so caused them to beget in each other, in the female
through the male, for this reason: so that if male met female, they
might in their embrace beget and their race continue to exist,
while at the same time if male met male, there'd at least be satiety
from their intercourse and they'd be relieved and go back to work
and look after the other concerns of life. So Eros for each other
a is inborn in people from as long ago as that, and he unites their
ancient nature, undertaking to make one from two, and to heal
human nature.
Each of us then is but the token of a human being, sliced like a
flatfish, two from one; each then ever seeks his matching token.198
Men sectioned from the common sex, then called androgynous,
e are woman-lovers; the majority of adulterers are from this sex,
while on the other hand women from this sex are man-lovers and
adulteresses. Women sectioned from a woman pay scant heed to
men, but are turned rather toward women, and lesbians come
from this sex. Those sectioned from a male pursue the masculine;
because they are slices of the male, they like men while still boys,
igaa delighting to lie with men and be embraced by them. These are
the most noble boys and youths because they are by nature most
manly.199 Some say they're most shameless, but they're wrong: they
198. ov{i/3okov. Corresponding pieces of a knucklebone or other object which con-
tracting parties broke between them, each party keeping one piece to match in order
to have proof of the identity of the presenter of the other. The indenture, at common
law, originally an irregularly torn parchment, had an equivalent use.
199. This and what follows is ironical and sarcastic: "Since it is a taunt in Old
Comedy (e.g., Aristophanes Knights 875-880, Plato Comicus, fr. 186) that eminent
politicians in their youth submitted shamelessly (or for money) to homosexual im-
portunities, and this taunt, characteristic of the cynical attitudes of comedy (cf. Dover
Greek Homosexuality, p. 147/.), must have been familiar to Plato, he means Aristo-
phanes to be speaking tongue-in-cheek." Dover, Symposium, on this passage.
TRANSLATION 133
200. Aristotle refers to this passage at Politics II 12620 nff., where he refers to
"the erotic discourses."
134 TRANSLATION
201. The reference is almost certainly to the Spartan dispersion of the Mantineans
in 385 B.C. The city was razed and the inhabitants dispersed to separate villages. Since
the narrative date of the Symposium is before the death of Socrates in 399, this again
(cf. i8ab) is an anachronism.
202. Dice were split as tallies, that is, as av/^ftoAa. Cf. 19id.
203. Since Aristodemus, the narrator, is lying next to Eryximachus (1753), he
would have been next to speak. But he was skipped over when Eryximachus took
Aristophanes' turn, and Aristophanes, following the order originally laid down, now
looks to Eryximachus's right, to Agathon and Socrates.
TRANSLATION 135
Aristodemus said that Eryximachus said, Why, I'll obey you, for
I certainly enjoyed your speech. And if I were not aware that Soc-
rates and Agathon are clever about the things of love, I'd very
much fear they'd be at a loss for words, because of the many and
varied things already said; but as it is, I'm nonetheless confident.
1943 So Socrates said, Yes, Eryximachus, because you yourself com-
peted so well; but if you were where I now am, or rather perhaps
where I'll be once Agathon also speaks, you'd be very afraid and
quite as bewildered as I am now.
You mean to cast a spell on me, Socrates, said Agathon, so that
I'll be thrown into confusion by thinking my theater has great ex-
pectation I'll speak well.
I would be forgetful indeed, Agathon, said Socrates, if, after
b seeing your courage and self-confidence in going up on the stage
with the actors and looking out on so great an audience, about to
exhibit your own play and in no way at all disconcerted, I now
thought you'd be thrown into confusion because of a few people
like us.
Really, Socrates? said Agathon. You surely don't believe I'm so
full of theater that I don't even know that to a person of good
sense, a few intelligent men are more formidable than many
fools?204
c No, Agathon, I said, I'd hardly do well to think you capable of
anything boorish; I well know that if you met someone whom you
believed wise, you'd give heed to them rather than the multitude.
But maybe we're not they — for after all, we were also there, and
among the multitude — but still, if you met others who are wise,
you'd perhaps feel shame before them, if you thought you were
perhaps doing something shameful. Do you agree?
You're right, he said.
d But wouldn't you feel shame before the multitude if you thought
you were doing something shameful?
Aristodemus said Phaedrus interrupted and said, My dear Aga-
204. See Aristotle Eudemian Ethics III i232b tiff, (trans. Solomon): "The magnan-
imous man would consider rather what one good man thinks than many ordinary
men, as Antiphon after his condemnation said to Agathon when he praised his de-
fense of himself."
136 TRANSLATION
truth, have taken place through Necessity and not through Eros;
for there would have been no castrations and fetterings of each
other nor all that other violence if Eros had been present among
them, but friendship and peace, as there now is since Eros rules
the gods as king.
He is young, then, and in addition to being young, delicate,
d There is need of a poet such as Homer to show a god's delicacy.
Homer says that Ate, goddess of delusion, is also delicate—her feet
at any rate are delicate—for he says,206
her feet are delicate; for she steps not
on the ground, but walks upon the heads of men.
So she shows her delicacy, I think, by a pretty proof, because she
walks not on what is hard but on what is soft. But we may also use
e the same proof to show that Eros is delicate: he does not walk on
earth, nor on heads, which are after all not very soft anyway, but
he walks and dwells in the softest things there are. For he makes
his home in the characters and souls of gods and men, though not
in every soul one after another; on the contrary, any soul he comes
upon that is hard in character he leaves, but the soft he dwells in.
So ever touching with his feet and in every way the most soft of
ig6a softest things, he is necessarily most delicate. He is youngest, then,
and most delicate, and in addition his shape is most supple. For
he could not twine himself round in every direction and through
every soul and yet escape notice when first entering and departing,
if he were hard. His gracefulness, which everyone agrees Eros sur-
passingly possesses, is a great proof of his well-proportioned and
supple form, for awkwardness and Eros are ever at war with one
another. The god's dwelling among flowers signifies beauty of
b color, for Eros does not pitch his seat in a body or soul or anything
else from which the bloom is faded and gone. But where a place
is well flowered and fragrant, there he takes his seat and abides.
Concerning the beauty of the god, then, this is sufficient, and
more still remains; but one must next speak about the virtue of
Eros. What is most important is that Eros neither does injustice
to god or man nor suffers injustice from god or man. For if af-
fected by anything, he is himself not affected by violence—vio-
c lence does not touch Eros, nor does he act violently when he acts—
for everyone willingly serves Eros in everything, and what is will-
ingly agreed by willing parties, "the Laws, kings of our city," hold
to be just.207
In addition to justice, he partakes of temperance in fullest mea-
sure. For it is agreed that temperance is mastery of pleasures and
desires, and no pleasure is stronger than Eros; but if weaker, they
are mastered by Eros and he masters them, and, as mastering
pleasures and desires, Eros would be surpassingly temperate.208
a Again, in respect to courage, "not even Ares withstands"209
Eros. For Ares does not possess Eros, but Eros Ares—an Eros for
Aphrodite, as the story goes210—and the possessor is stronger
than the possessed. But, mastering him who is most courageous
among others, he would be most courageous of all.
Let this be said of the justice and temperance and courage of
the god, but it remains to speak of his wisdom: as far as possible,
one must leave nothing out. First of all, then, in order that I may
in turn honor my own art as Eryximachus honored his, the god
e is a poet so wise that he also makes others poets; all whom Eros
touches, at any rate, become poets, "even if he was without music
before."211 So we may fittingly use this as proof that Eros is a poet
who is, in sum, good in respect to all creation over which the Muses
preside; for one could not give someone else or teach another what
one neither has nor knows.
1973 Again, who will deny that the creation of all animals is the wis-
dom of Eros, by whom all animals are born and begotten? But do
we not also know in the craftsmanship of the arts that he of whom
this god becomes teacher turns out to be notable and illustrious,
but he whom Eros leaves untouched remains in the shade? Yes,
and surely Apollo invented the arts of archery and medicine and
prophecy under the guidance of Eros and desire, so that even he
b would be a pupil of Eros, along with the Muses of music and po-
etry, and Hephaestus in metalworking, and Athena in weaving,
and Zeus "in guiding of gods and men." Whence it is then that
207. An early statement of "volunti non fit injuria" as a legal principle—voluntary
assumption of risk.
208. Bury compares Euthydemus zybcff., Aristotle De sophisticis elenchis 1655 §zff.
Having identified Eros as mastery of pleasures and desires, Agathon proceeds to
identify Eros with the strongest desire.
209. Sophocles, fr. 235, said of Necessity, not Eros.
210. Odyssey viii %66ff. Aphrodite and Ares were lovers. Hephaestus, her husband,
set a trap with chains to catch them in bed, and did catch them, and summoned the
other gods to witness their crime. But the gods laughed and envied Ares, chains and
all.
211. From Euripides, fr. 663, also quoted in Aristophanes Wasps 1074.
TRANSLATION 139
the affairs of the gods were arranged when Eros was born among
them, Eros for beauty, obviously—for there is no Eros of ugli-
ness—though before that, as I said to begin with, many terrible
things occurred among the gods, as is told, through the sover-
eignty of Necessity. But since this god was born, all good things
have come to be from love of beautiful things, both for gods and
men.
c So it seems to me, Phaedrus, that Eros, being himself first, as
most beautiful and best, is, next, cause of other such things in
others. I am moved to speak in verse, though it is he who composes
it:
Peace among men, waveless calm at sea,
Rest from winds, slumber for our grief.
a He empties us of estrangement but fills us with kinship, causing
us to come together in all such gatherings as these, in festivals, in
dances, in sacrifices a leader; he introduces gentleness, but ban-
ishes rudeness; giving of goodwill, ungiving of ill will; gracious,
good; gazed upon by the wise, delighted in by the gods; coveted
by those without portion, possessed by those of good fortune; fa-
ther of delicacy, of luxury, of charm, of graciousness, of desire, of
longing; caring for good things, uncaring for bad things; in labor,
e in fear, in longing, in discourse a guide, defender, comrade in arms
and best savior; beauty and good order of all gods and men, leader
most beautiful and best, whom every man must follow chanting
beautifully, sharing the song that he sings, touching with magic
power the thought of all gods and men.212
There is my speech, Phaedrus, he said. Let it be dedicated to
the god. It has a share, some of it, of play, but also of measured
seriousness so far as I can provide it.
212. Dover (Symposium, p. 124) has analyzed the rhythms of this passage and
shown that it consists in metrical units characteristic of Greek lyric poetry.
140 TRANSLATION
"the tongue swore, but not the mind."215 But let it go. For I don't
any longer offer encomium in this manner—indeed, I cannot—
b but I'm nevertheless willing to tell you the truth in my own way if
you wish, though not in competition with your speeches so that I
may not incur your laughter. Consider then, Phaedrus,216 whether
there is really any need for a speech of this kind, to hear the truth
spoken about Eros in such words and arrangement of phrases as
may happen to occur.217
Well, Aristodemus said that Phaedrus and the others bid him
speak in whatever way he thought he should.
Why then, Phaedrus, Socrates said, please let me ask Agathon
just a few small questions still, so that I may speak thus after get-
ting his agreement,
c Why, I do permit it, said Phaedrus. Ask your questions.
So Socrates said, Then this is to love that which is not yet at hand
for him and what he does not yet have, namely, that these things
be preserved and present to him in future,
e Of course, he said.
And so he and everyone else who desires, desires that which is
not at hand and which is not present, and what he does not have,
and what he himself is not, and what he lacks—desire and Eros
are of such things as these.
Of course, he said.
Come then, said Socrates. Let us recapitulate what has been
said. Is it not that Eros in the first place is of something, and next,
of those things of which a lack is present to it?
aoia Yes, he said.
Then next recall of what things you said Eros is in your speech.
If you wish, I'll remind you. I think you said something to the
effect that affairs are arranged by the gods by reason of love of
beautiful things; for there would be no love of the ugly.218 Didn't
you say something like that?
I did, said Agathon.
Yes, my friend, and very properly too, said Socrates. And if this
is so, would Eros be anything except love of beauty, but not of
ugliness?
He agreed,
b Now, it is agreed that he loves what he lacks and does not have?
Yes, he said.
So Eros lacks and does not have beauty.
Necessarily, he said.
Really? Do you say that what lacks beauty and in no way pos-
sesses beauty is beautiful?
Of course not.
Then do you still agree that Eros is beautiful, if these things are
so?
And Agathon said, Very likely I didn't know what I was talking
about then, Socrates.
c And yet you spoke so beautifully, Agathon. But a small point
still: don't you think good things are also beautiful?
I do.
So if Eros is lack of beautiful things, and good things are beau-
tiful, he would also lack good things.
Because then Eros is son of Poros and Penia, this is his fortune:
first, he is ever poor, and far from being delicate and beautiful,
as most people suppose,227 he on the contrary is rough and hard
a and homeless and unshod, ever lying on the ground without bed-
ding, sleeping in doorsteps and beside roads under the open sky.
Because he has his mother's nature, he dwells ever with want. But
on the other hand, by favor of his father, he ever plots for good
and beautiful things, because he is courageous, eager and intense,
and clever hunter ever weaving some new device, desiring under-
standing and capable of it, a lover of wisdom through the whole
of life, clever at enchantment, a sorcerer and a sophist.228 And he
e is by nature neither mortal nor immortal, but sometimes on the
same day he lives and flourishes, whenever he is full of resource,
but then he dies and comes back to life again by reason of the
nature of his father, though what is provided ever slips away so
that Eros is never rich nor at a loss . . .
one loves, if indeed everyone loves the same things, and always,
but we rather say that some love and some do not?
I'm also surprised myself, I said.
Don't be, she said. It is because we subtract a certain species of
eros and name it Eros, applying the name of the whole, but we
use other names for the others.
As what? I said.
As this. You know that making [ poiesis] is something manifold;
for surely the cause of passing from not being into being for any-
c thing whatever is all a making, so that the productions of all the
arts are makings, and the practitioners of them are all makers
[poietai].
True.
But nevertheless, she said, you know that they are not called
makers [ poietai] but have other names, while from all making one
single part has been subtracted, that concerned with music229 and
meter, and given the name of the whole. For this alone is called
poetry [ poiesis], and those who have this part of making are called
poets [poietai].
True, I said.
a So also then for Eros. In general, it is every desire for good
things and happiness, "Eros most great, and wily230 in all"; but
those who turn to him in various other ways, either money-making
or athletics or philosophy, are neither said to love nor to be lovers,
while those who sedulously pursue one single species get the name
of the whole, Eros, and are said to love and be lovers.
Very likely true, I said.
Yes, and a certain story is told, she said, that those in love are
e seeking the other half of themselves. But my account is that love
is of neither half nor whole, my friend, unless it happens to be
actually good, since people are willing to cut off their own hands
and feet if they think these possessions of theirs are bad. For they
each refuse, I think, to cleave even to what is their own, unless
one calls what is good kindred and his own, and what is bad
alien;231 because there is nothing else that men love than the good.
Do you agree?
229. juovoixij (scilicet Tiyyrj) was any art over which the Muses preside, but es-
pecially poetry, which was sung. Cf. Republic II 3766.
230. dohegoc;. The adjective is otherwise rare in Plato, but applied at Hippias Minor
365C to Odysseus. See above, 2O3d.
231. Cf. Lysis 2iob-c, 22id-222e.
150 TRANSLATION
b Then given that Eros is ever this, she said, in what way, and in
what activity, would eagerness and effort among those pursuing
it be called Eros? What does this work happen to be? Can you say?
No, I said. If I could, I would not admire your wisdom so much,
Diotima, and keep coming to you to learn these very things.
But I will tell you, she said: this work is begetting232 in beauty,
in respect to both the body and the soul.
What you say needs divination, I said, and I don't understand.
c Why, 111 put it more clearly, she said. All men are pregnant in
respect to both the body and the soul, Socrates, she said, and when
they reach a certain age, our nature desires to beget.233 It cannot
beget in ugliness, but only in beauty. The intercourse of man and
woman is a begetting. This is a divine thing, and pregnancy and
procreation are an immortal element in the mortal living creature.
a It is impossible for birth to take place in what is discordant. But
ugliness is in discord with all that is divine, and beauty concordant.
So the Goddess of Beauty is at the birth Moira, Fate, and Eilithyia,
She Who Gomes in Time of Need. That is why, when what is preg-
nant draws near to the beautiful, it becomes tender and full of
gladness and pours itself forth and begets and procreates; but
when it draws near to the ugly, it shrivels in sullen grief and turns
away and goes slack and does not beget, but carries with difficulty
232. Or bearing children, roxog.
233. rixTEiv, the verb of which TOUCH; is the corresponding noun.
TRANSLATION 151
246. Or "as being thought beautiful by some but ugly by others." cog with parti-
ciple: Smyth, 2o86b; cf. 2996.
247. In contradiction to Pausanias's sexualized pederasty.
248. Cf. 2ioa, c, e.
249. Diotima directly recalls the speech of Aristophanes, igia, i92b-d.
TRANSLATION 157
2iaa less life, she said, for a man to look there and contemplate that with
that by which one must contemplate it,250 and to be with it? Or are
you not convinced, she said, that there alone it will befall him, in
seeing the Beautiful with that by which it is visible, to beget, not
images of virtue, because he does not touch an image, but true
virtue, because he touches the truth? But in begetting true virtue
and nurturing it, it is given to him to become dear to god, and if
any other among men is immortal, he is too.
252. Ivy was associated with Dionysus, and appropriate to a drunken reveler. Vi-
olets were associated with Aphrodite—fittingly enough, as we shall soon see—but also
with Athens itself, "Violet-Crowned." The violets are Viola hymettia, the blossoms
bright yellow and white against the dark green of the ivy. At present these violets
bloom in March, and it is customary to identify the month Gamelion, on the twelfth
day of which the Lenaea was celebrated, with January—the nights were long (223c).
But the Athenian solar-lunar year made the dates of months in relation to the year
as variable as Easter now is, and the presence of violets in the crown of Alcibiades
indicates the first stirrings of spring.
253. Headbands or ribbons worn in sign of victory or sacrifice to the god.
TRANSLATION 159
scribe for Socrates as you wish, and he for the man on his right,
and so on for the rest.
Why, Eryximachus, said Alcibiades, that's a beautiful sugges-
tion, but perhaps it isn't fair to compare a drunken man to the
speeches of the sober. At the same time, my friend, do you believe
a anything Socrates just now said? Don't you know it's all just the
opposite of what he was saying? Because he's the one who won't
keep his two hands off me if I praise anyone in his presence, either
a god or a man other than him.
What a thing to say! said Socrates.
By Poseidon, said Alcibiades, don't add another word, because
I couldn't praise one other person with you present.
Why, if you wish, do that, said Eryximachus. Praise Socrates,
e Do you mean it? said Alcibiades. Do you think I should, Eryxi-
machus? Should I punish the man and inflict a penalty on him in
front of you?
Whoa! said Socrates. What have you got in mind? To praise me
in order to poke fun at me? Is that what you'll do?
I'll tell the truth. Just see if you allow it.
Why certainly I allow the truth, he said, and I insist you tell it.
I can hardly wait to start, said Alcibiades. But you must do this:
if I say anything untrue, interrupt me right in the middle, if you
wish, and say that I said it falsely; for I won't willingly say anything
2isa false. If, however, in recollecting, I say one thing here and another
there, don't be surprised; because it's no easy thing for someone
in my condition to enumerate your peculiarities fluently and in
good order.
That at least you look like them, Socrates, surely not even you
yourself would dispute.257 But next hear how you're like them in
other ways too. You're outrageous.258 No? Because if you don't
agree I'll offer witnesses. But you're not a flutist? Yes, and one far
c more marvelous than Marsyas. He charmed people by the power
of his mouth, using instruments, and those who play his music do
so even now; for I claim that what Olympus used to play belonged
to Marsyas—Marsyas was his teacher—but whether played by a
good flutist or a worthless flute-girl, his music alone causes pos-
session and reveals, because it is divine, those who need the gods
and rites of initiation.
You differ from him only in this, that you accomplish the same
thing by bare words without instruments. When we hear some
a other speaker, at any rate, even quite a good orator, speaking other
words, it hardly matters to anyone at all; but when someone hears
you or someone else repeating your words, then even if the
speaker is quite worthless and whether it be man, woman, or child
who hears, we are amazed and possessed. At any rate, gentlemen,
if I weren't in danger of seeming completely drunk, I'd state to
you on oath how I've been affected by his words, how I'm still
e affected even now. For when I hear him my heart leaps up, much
more than those affected by the music of the Corybantes,259 and
tears flow at his words—and I see many another affected the same
way too.
I heard Pericles and other good orators and I believe they spoke
well, but I was not affected at all like this, nor was my soul dis-
turbed and angered at my being in the position of a slave; but due
2i6a to this Marsyas here I've often been put in that position, so that
the ears and sometimes the legs and tail of a horse, much given to pursuing nymphs.
He knows important secrets, and if he is caught he can sometimes be forced to tell,
but he was also associated with drunkenness, bestiality, and the worship of Dionysus.
Satyrs are very like silenes, but usually young rather than old, and they took from
Pan the attributes of a goat. By the time they appear in satyr plays, such as Euripides'
Cyclops and Sophocles' Ichneutae, they are clearly human beings, with attributes of
horses or, in Sophocles, perhaps of dogs.
Marsyas was a satyr who in his hubris competed in music with Apollo, and was
worsted and flayed alive for his presumption.
257. Socrates had a snub nose and protruding eyes. Theaetetus 1436.
258. Recalling Agathon's challenge. Agathon had said exactly the same thing
(1756) in suggesting that Dionysus would decide between himself and Socrates. See
also 2 i3c—d, where Socrates in effect brings this charge against Alcibiades, and 2 i4d,
where Alcibiades returns it. But see also 2igc.
259. Cf. Ion 5336-5343, 536c, Euthydemus 277d, Crito 54d, Laws VII 7god.
l62 TRANSLATION
one else has seen the images within when he is in earnest and
opened up, but I saw them once, and I thought they were so divine
2173 and golden, so marvelously beautiful, that whatever Socrates
might bid must, in short, be done.
Believing he was earnestly pursuing my youthful beauty, I
thought it was a stroke of luck and my wonderful good fortune,
because by gratifying Socrates I could learn everything he knew;
for I was amazingly proud of my vernal bloom. So with this in
mind, though previously I wasn't accustomed to be alone with him
unattended, I then dismissed my attendant and was with him
b alone—for I have to tell you the whole truth. Pay attention, Soc-
rates, and if what I say is false, refute me—so we were alone with
each other, gentlemen, one on one, and I thought at that point he
would converse with me as a lover might converse in private with
his beloved, and I rejoiced. But not a bit of it. Instead, he'd con-
verse with me in his usual way, and after spending the day together
he'd get up and go away.
c Next I invited him to exercise with me, and we did; I expected
to accomplish something there. Well, he exercised and wrestled
with me many times when no one was present. And what must I
report? I got no farther.
Since I'd accomplished nothing at all this way, I thought I had
to attack the man directly and not give up, since I'd taken the
matter in hand; at that point I had to know how things stood. So
I invited him to dine, exactly like a lover laying a plan for his be-
loved. Even in this he didn't yield to me quickly, but in time, he
nonetheless obeyed.
d When he came the first time, he wished to leave after dinner.
At that point I was embarrassed and let him go; but I laid plans
for him again, and when we had dined I kept on talking far into
the night, and when he wished to leave I used the excuse that it
was late and made him stay. So he lay down on the couch next to
mine, the couch on which he'd dined, and there was no one else
sleeping in the room except us.
e Well, up to this point it would be fit to tell the story to anyone;
but from here on you wouldn't hear a word from me if it were not
that, first, wine with or without slaves262 is truthful, as the saying
262. Jiaido)v. The word translated "slaves" is also the word for children, and the
underlying proverb probably was "Wine and children are truthful." But slaves, and
perhaps others, are present, and asked not to listen (2i8b). This is dramatic fore-
shadowing: Plato's audience would have recalled that Alcibiades was to be prosecuted
164 TRANSLATION
When he heard this, he said, with the usual sly dishonesty that
is typical of him, My dear Alcibiades, you are really not to be taken
lightly, if indeed what you say about me happens to be true, and
e there is in me some power through which you might become bet-
ter; you would then see inconceivable beauty in me, even sur-
passing your own immense comeliness of form. But if, seeing it,
you are trying to strike a bargain with me to exchange beauty for
beauty, then you intend to take no slight advantage of me: on the
contrary, you are trying to get possession of what is truly beautiful
instead of what merely seems so, and really, you intend to trade
2193 bronze for gold.265 But please, dear friend, give it more thought,
lest it escape your notice that I am nothing. The sight of the mind
begins to see sharply when that of the eyes starts to grow dull; but
you're still a long way from that.
I heard this and said, That's how it is with me; I've only said
what I think. Since that's so, you yourself must consider whatever
you think is best for you and me.
Why, you're right, he replied. We'll in future consider and do
b what appears best to ourselves about these and other things.
In hearing and saying this, I'd loosed my arrows, as it were, and
I thought I'd wounded him; I got up without letting him say an-
other word, and I wrapped my own cloak around him—for it was
winter—and I lay down on his threadbare coat, and I put my two
arms around this genuine divinity, this wonderful man, and lay
c there the whole night through. And again, Socrates, you will not
say I speak falsely. But when I did this, he was so contemptuously
superior to my youthful bloom that he ridiculed and outrageously
insulted it; and in that regard, at least, I thought I was really some-
thing, gentlemen and judges—for you are judges of the arrogance
of Socrates—for know well, by gods and by goddesses, when I
d arose after having slept with Socrates, it was nothing more than
if I'd slept with a father or an elder brother.
Can you imagine my state of mind after that? I considered my-
self affronted, and yet I admired his nature, his temperance and
courage, having met a man of a sort I never thought to meet in
respect to wisdom and fortitude. The result was that I could nei-
ther get angry and be deprived of his company nor yet find a way
e to win him over. For I well knew he was far more invulnerable to
265. Cf. Iliad vi 236, where Glaucus foolishly trades golden armor for bronze.
l66 TRANSLATION
money than Ajax ever was to iron, and he'd escaped me in the
only way I thought he could be caught. So I was at a loss, and I
went around enslaved by this man as no one ever was by any other.
Courage and Contemplation (21^-2210)
All this happened to me before, and afterward we served to-
gether on the campaign to Potidaea,266 and we were messmates
there. Well, first of all, he not only surpassed me but everyone else
2203 in bearing hardship—whenever we got cut off somewhere, as hap-
pens on campaign, and had to go without food, the others were
nothing in respect to fortitude—but again, in times of good cheer,
he alone was able to enjoy them to the full: in particular, though
unwilling to drink, he beat everybody else at it when compelled
to, and what is most remarkable of all, no man has ever seen Soc-
rates drunk. I think that will be tested right now. Then again,
there was his fortitude in winter—the winters there are dreadful.
b He did other amazing things, but one time there was a truly ter-
rible frost and everybody stayed inside and didn't go out, or if they
did they wore an amazing amount of clothes and put on shoes
after wrapping their feet in felt and fleeces, but he went around
outside among them with the same sort of cloak he was accus-
tomed to wear before, and got around on the ice without shoes
more easily than the others did shod. But the soldiers looked
askance at him, thinking he despised them.267
c So much for that. "But here is a task such as that strong man
endured and accomplished,"268 once there on campaign. It's
worth hearing. One time at dawn he began to think something
over and stood in the same spot considering it, and when he found
no solution, he didn't leave but stood there inquiring. It got to be
midday, and people became aware of it, wondering at it among
themselves, saying Socrates had stood there since dawn thinking
about something. Finally some of the lonians, when evening came,
a after they'd eaten—it was then summer—carried their bedding
out to sleep in the cool air and to watch to see if he'd also stand
there all night. He stood until dawn came and the sun ro^e; then
he offered a prayer to the sun, and left.
266. In 432 B.C. Alcibiades would then have been eighteen, Socrates not quite
forty.
267. Some of those soldiers doubtless voted at Socrates' trial; the Symposium, then,
suggests that this was one source of the prejudice against him, one that he himself
could scarcely have mentioned.
268. Odyssey IV 242 (trans. Richmond Lattimore). Cf. IV 271.
TRANSLATION 167
But if you wish, take battles—it is only just to give him this.
Because when the battle occurred after which the generals gave
e me the award for valor, no other man saved me but him; I was
wounded and he refused to leave, but saved both me and my ar-
mor.269 I told the generals even at the time, Socrates, to give the
award to you, and for this you'll surely neither fault me nor say
I'm not telling the truth. But when the generals wished to give me
the prize for valor out of regard for my rank and station, you your-
self were more eager than the generals that I should receive it
instead of you.
Still again, gentlemen, it was worth seeing Socrates when the
22ia army made its disorderly retreat from Delium;270 I happened to
be mounted, but he was in the heavy infantry. Well, as the men
were scattering, he and Laches together gave ground. I happened
to be nearby, and as soon as I saw them I told them to have courage
and said I wouldn't desert them. But here I could watch Socrates
even better than at Potidaea—for I was myself less afraid because
I was on horseback—and first, I saw how much he surpassed even
b Laches in self-possession, and then again, to quote that line of
yours, Aristophanes, I thought that he proceeded there just as he
does here too, "head held high, casting his eyes about,"271 calmly
surveying both friend and foe, making it clear to everyone, and
at quite a distance, that if anybody touched this man he'd defend
himself quite stoutly. That's why he and his comrade got away safe;
they don't usually touch people who defend themselves like that
c in battle, but pursue those who flee headlong.
The Strangeness of Socrates (22ic-222b)
Well, one could praise Socrates for many other remarkable
things; with respect to other activities one might also perhaps say
the same sort of thing about someone else, but unlikeness to any
other man, past or present, is worthy of all wonder. One might
compare the sort of man Achilles was to Brasidas272 and others,
269. Loss of arms in battle was a disgrace. "With your shield or on it" was no light
saying; you could run faster without it.
270. In 424 B.C.
271. Cf. Clouds 362 (not an exact quotation, at least from our present text). Laches
himself, a general, refers to this incident and pays tribute to Socrates' courage at
Delium in the Laches i8ia—b. Socrates mentions his service at Potidaea, Amphipolis,
and Delium as an indication of his faithfulness to duty imposed by Athens, even to
death. Apology 28d-e.
272. A distinguished Spartan general killed at Amphipolis in 422 B.C.
l68 TRANSLATION
and Pericles, again, to Nestor and Antenor, and there are others
a one might compare in the same way. But the sort of man this is
and his strangeness, both himself and his words, one couldn't
come close to finding if one looked, neither among people present
nor past, except perhaps if one were to compare him to those I
mention—not any man, but silenes and satyrs, him and his words.
Actually, I left this out at first, that even his arguments are ex-
e actly like silenes that have been opened. For if one is willing to
listen to Socrates' arguments, they'd appear quite ridiculous at
first; they're wrapped round on the outside with words and
phrases like the hide of an outrageous satyr. He talks about pack-
asses and smiths and cobblers and tanners, and forever appears
to be saying the same things in the same ways, so that an inex-
2223 perienced and unreasonable man might ridicule his arguments.273
But if the arguments are opened, and one sees them from the
inside, he will find first that they are the only arguments with any
sense in them, and next, that they contain within themselves ut-
terly divine and multitudinous images of virtue, and that they are
relevant to most or rather to all things worth considering for one
who intends to be noble and good.
This then, gentlemen, is my praise of Socrates. On the other
hand, I've also mixed in the faults I find in him, and told you of
his outrageous insult to me. It isn't just me he's treated this way,
b however, but also Charmides, son of Glaucon, and Euthydemus,
son of Diocles, and many another as well, whom he seduces as a
lover and ends up himself as beloved instead of lover. I warn you,
Agathon, don't be deceived by him, but learn from our own ex-
periences and watch out, instead of, as the proverb has it, learning
by dumb suffering.274
Conclusion (22%b-d)
But at this point, suddenly, a mob of revelers came to the doors,
and when they found them open because someone was leaving,
they came straight in to us and lay down. Everything was in an
275. Tragic trilogies at the Dionysia closed with a humorous phallic play in which
the chorus dressed as satyrs.
276. The original order of places was Agathon-Socrates (175c-d), and Alcibiades
upon entering seated himself between them (2i3a-b), so that the order became Aga-
thon-Alcibiades—Socrates. Socrates now invites Agathon to change his position so
that the order becomes Alcibiades—Socrates—Agathon.
277. Alcibiades has suggested the order Alcibiades-Agathon-Socrates. Socrates
objects, pleading the rule of procedure suggested by Eryximachus at 2i4b-c (cf.
i?7d).
170 TRANSLATION
uproar, there was no longer any order, and everyone was com-
pelled to drink a great deal of wine.
Aristodemus said that Eryximachus and Phaedrus and some
others got up and left, and he fell asleep and slept quite a while,
c because the nights were long, but he woke up toward daybreak,
at cock-crow, to see some asleep and others gone. Only Agathon
and Aristophanes and Socrates were still awake, drinking from a
large bowl, and passing it from left to right.
Well, Socrates was discussing with them. Aristodemus said he
couldn't remember the other arguments—he wasn't there at the
a beginning, and he was drowsy—but the main point, he said, was
that Socrates was making them agree that the same man knows
how to compose comedy and tragedy, and he who is a tragic poet
by art is a comic poet too.278 Compelled to these admissions, and
not quite following, they drowsed, and Aristophanes fell asleep
first, and then, just as it was becoming light, Agathon.
So after putting them to sleep, Socrates got up and left, and
Aristodemus as usual followed him. He went to the Lyceum and
bathed, passed the rest of the day as he would any other, and after
that he went home in the evening and rested.
278. The argument must have been that tragedy and comedy are opposites; the
same art has knowledge of opposites; therefore, anyone who is by art a tragic poet is
a comic poet too. The conclusion superficially contradicts Ion 5316—5346; but the Ion
denies that the actor, and by implication the poet, has an art.
INDEX
References to author's comments are given according to the pagination of this book. Ref-
erences in italic are to Plato's Symposium, and are given by Stephanus pages in the margin
of the translation; these pages are subdivided according to the letters a, b, c, d, e, answering
to divisions in the original folio page.
Abel, Donald C., 6on tance of speech of, 105-106; life of, 102—
Achilles, 14, 71, 76, 77, 179*, 221c; honored 103; mutilation of the herms and, 26n,
by gods, 180b\ as lover of Patroclus, 180a 102, io2n; prize for valor and, 2 2 0 \ in
Actions: of lovers, 183ar-b\ as neutral, 63- Protagoras, 10; relationship with Socrates,
64, i8ia\ virtue in, 63-64 10, 103, 213-e\ speech of, 104-108,
Acumenus, ij6b 215a—222a; trial of Socrates and, 105,
Acusilaus, 178b 106; wreath crowning, 158n, 212
Admetus, 12, 13, 71, 76, 119, 179b, 208d Ambition, for things beautiful, ij8d
Aeschylus, 180a Amousos, 9
Aesthetic theory, 80 Anachronism, 5, 122n, 134n, 182b, 193a
Agamemnon, 174c Anaximander, 128n
Agape, 95-98 Androgyny, 32, 189e, 191e
Agathon: absence from Athens, 4, 172c; Animals: Dionysiac religion and, 21n, 25,
beauty of, 38; death of, 4; dramatic vic- 26; love of their offspring, 207a—6
tory of, 21, 173a, 194b; importance of Anthesteria festival, 21
speech of, 7; Pausanias as lover of, 17, 38, Aphrodite: Aristophanes as occupied with,
7936; as playwright, 40; in Protagoras, 10; 21, 33, 37, 177e; Dionysus and, 21; Eros
pun on name of, 174e; Socrates' refuta- as companion to, 8, 15, 180d, 181a\ as two
tion of, 7, iggc-2oic\ speech of, 38-40, goddesses, 180d-e\ as Venus Genetrix, 16
1940—1970; youth of, 3, 198a "Aphrodite," as Greek term, 16
Agave, 23, 24, 26 Aphrodite Pandemus. See Aphrodite, as two
Ajax, 219d goddesses
Alcestis, 14, 71, 76, 77, 179b Apollo, 38n, 197a
Alcibiades: Aristodemus compared with, 6; Apollodorus: accuracy of account of, 4; ac-
arrival at Agathon's house, 99, 102-103, quaintance with Socrates, 175a; figure of,
212c—2i$a\ beauty of, 2/70, 2i8e—219a, and double narrative device, 5; as link be-
2i$c\ on courage of Socrates, 219d-221a; tween Symposium and Phaedo, 9; loss of
failed seduction of Socrates by, 18, 216c- wits, 173a; prologue of, 172a—174a; as
2i^d\ human condition and, 103; impor- "soft," 5, 173a*
171
172 INDEX
Apology: Apollodorus and, 5; daimon in, 48; Beauty: account of the Good in Republic
hubris and, 107; language of, 106; por- and, 9; of action, 181a\ of Alcibiades,
trait of Socrates in, 53-54, 105; pursuit 217a, 218e—219a,, 219c; of body vs. soul,
of the good and, 70 80, 2iob-d', as equivalent to the good, 45,
Ares, 15, 196d 54, 70—71, 85, 88, 201c, 204e', in and of
Aristodemus: admirer of Socrates, 6, 173b; itself, 15; ladder of love and, 77—81, 209e—
compared with Alcibiades, 6; in final scene, 210e\ of lover, 14, 20, 43, 44n, 180a\ na-
233d; narration by, 105, 1740-1750; por- ture of Eros and, 42; procreation in, as
trait of Socrates, 6, 104; tolerance for work of Eros, 206b-207a; pursuit of, 26,
drinking, 176c 178d; trial of Socrates and, 106; true vs.
Aristogiton, 182c apparent, 218e0—219a,', as universal, 79,
Aristophanes, 176a, 213c\ arrival of Alci- 80, 2iob-e. See also Good; Idea of Beauty
biades and, 99; Clouds, 36-37, 105, 221a; Bentham, Jeremy, Principles of Morals and
early German romanticism and, 35n; falls Legislation, 68-69
asleep, 223d"; hiccups of, 20, 30, 185c-e, Bisexuality, 32
189a,—b\ importance of speech of, 7, 20, Blest, Isles of the, 178e, 180b
35-36; Lysistrata, 32; not in Protagoras, 10; Body vs. soul: beauty of, 80, 210b-d\ crea-
Nussbaum's analysis and, 99-102; as oc- tion and, 76-77, 79, 208b—209e; love with
cupied with Dionysus, 21, 33, 37, 177e; respect to, 104
quoted by Socrates, 221a; speech of, 31- Brasidas, 221c
37, 189c-193\ theme of speech of, 28; Bury, R. G., 12-13, 19, 32, 103n, 104-05
Thesmophoriazusae, 4
Aristotle, 5n, 21n, 83; De anima, 73—74;
Laws, 17; Metaphysics, 27n, 64, 83, 90, Callias, house of, 10
n8n, 152n; Nicomachean Ethics, 17, 63, Change, and immortality, 75, 207d—208b
88-89; Poetics, 40; Politics, 17; Prior An- Characters, in both Phaedo and Symposium,
alytics, 76-77; Rhetoric, 7n 9-10
Art: as expression of love, 52; invention of, Charmides, 2226
197a-b; knowledge of opposites and, 223a*. Charmides, 17n, 46n
See also Medicine, art of; Music; Seer's art Children: love of, 207a-b; of the mind,
Asceticism, 9, 75, 108 209a-e
Asclepius, 126n, 186e Christian theology, 95-98
Aspasia, 19 Clark, Kenneth, 53
Astronomy, 28, 188b Comedy. See Aristophanes; Drama
Ate, 195a* Comic poet. See Aristophanes
Athena, 197b Contemplation: in ascent to Beauty, 85-89;
Athens: and battle of Delium, 2 2 1 ; and ex- Greek term for, 86n; as natural choice,
pedition to Potidaea, 219e; experience of 101; Socrates and, 6, 220c-d\ virtue and,
war in, 24; the Lyceum in, 223d*; and 88-89, 2I2a
overthrow of tyrants, 182c\ road to, as Cornford, F. M., 8—9, 46, 91-95, 127n
made for conversation, 173a; Sicilian Ex-
pedition and, 4, 103n; sophistical culture Corybantes, 215e
and, 8; status of women in, 18—19 Courage: of Eros, 196d\ Eros as source of,
Atmosphere of Symposium, 9 12, 179b—d; of Socrates, 219d-221a; in
souls vs. actions, 64
Attunement, 28, 29, 187a-d
Courtly love, 34n
Augustine, 66-67, 90» 96—97» 98
Cratylus: changelessness and, 83; Dionysus
in, 21; mortal nature and, 75
Banquet: dining arrangements at, 6; histor-
ical reality of, 4n, 5; light at, 20-21; oc- Creation, and body vs. soul, 76—77, 79,
casion of, 3-4, 173a; order of places at, 208b-209e. See also Procreation
169n; reports of speeches at, 4, 172a (see Crito, 55
also under specific speakers)', ritual character Cronos, 195c;
of, 3 Cupid, 8, 15
Earth, Karl, 95-96, 97 Cynics, 9
INDEX 173