Logic Note NoteHeroBot (Chapters 1-6) - 1-90
Logic Note NoteHeroBot (Chapters 1-6) - 1-90
by “NaCl”.
• This passage is not an argument, because it makes no
claim that anything is being proved. The word “thus”
indicates how something is done - namely, how
chemical elements and compounds can be
represented by formulas.
• Illustrations can be taken as arguments. Such arguments are
often called arguments from example. Here is an instance of
one:
– Although most forms of cancer, if untreated, can cause
death, not all cancers are life-threatening. For example,
basal cell carcinoma, the most common of all skin
cancers, can produce disfigurement, but it almost never
results in death.
4. Explanations
• It is an expression that attempts to clarify, or
describe such alike why something is happen that
way or why something is what it is.
• Example:
– Cows digest grass while humans cannot, because their
digestive systems contain enzyme not found in humans.
• Every explanation is composed of two distinct
components:
– Explanandum:- it is the statement that describes the
event or phenomenon to be explained,
– Explanans:- is the statement or group of statements
that purports to do the explaining.
• In the above example, the explanandum is the statement
“Cows digest grass while humans cannot” and the
explanans is “their [cows‟] digestive systems contain
enzyme not found in humans.”
• The purpose of explanans is to show why something is
the case, whereas in an argument, the purpose of the
premises is to prove that something is the case.
• Moreover, in explanation, we precede backward from fact
to the cause whereas in argument we move from premise
to the conclusion.
• Thus, to distinguish explanations from arguments, first
identify the statement that is either the explanandum or the
conclusion
• However, some passages can be interpreted as both
explanations and arguments.
• Example:
– Women become intoxicated by drinking a smaller
amount of alcohol than men because men metabolize
part of the alcohol before it reaches the bloodstream,
whereas women do not.
Conditional Statements
They are an “if . . . then . . .” statements.
Every conditional statement is made up of two component
statements.
antecedent (if-clause), The component statement immediately
following the “if”
consequent (then-clause) the one following the “then”
However, there is an occasion that the order of antecedent
and consequent is reversed.
Conditional statements are not arguments, because in a
conditional statement there is no claim that either the
antecedent or the consequent presents evidence
Also conditional statements are not evaluated as true or
false without separately evaluating the antecedent and the
consequent.
A conditional statement may serve as either the premise
or the conclusion (or both) of an argument. examples:
– If he is selling our national secretes to enemies, then
he is a traitor.
– He is selling our national secretes to enemies.
– Therefore, he is a traitor.
The relation between conditional statements and
arguments may now be summarized as follows:
I. A single conditional statement is not an argument.
II. A conditional statement may serve as either the
premise or the conclusion (or both) of an argument.
III. The inferential content of a conditional statement
may be re-expressed to form an argument.
Conditional statements are especially important in logic
(and many other fields) because they express the
relationship between necessary and sufficient
conditions. example
– If X is a dog, then X is an animal.
– If X is not an animal, then X is not a dog.
The first statement says that being a dog is a sufficient
condition for being an animal, and the second that being
an animal is a necessary condition for being a dog.
However, a little reflection reveals that these two
statements say exactly the same thing.
Generally, non-argumentative passages may contain
components that resemble the premises and conclusions of
arguments, but they do not have an inferential claim.
However, some passages like expository passages,
illustrations, and explanations can be interpreted as
arguments; and the inferential contents of conditional
statements may be re-expressed to form arguments.
Therefore, in deciding whether a passage contains an
argument, you should look for three things:
a) Indicator words such as “therefore,” “since,” “because,”
and so on;
b) An inferential relationship between the statements; and
c) Typical kinds of non-arguments.
But the mere occurrence of an indicator word does
not guarantee the presence of an argument. You must
check that the conclusion is supported by one or
more of the premises.
Also keep in mind that in many arguments that lack
indicator words, the conclusion is the first statement.
Differentiating Deductive and Inductive Arguments
• There are three factors that influence the decision
about the deductiveness or inductiveness of an
argument‘s inferential claim. These are:
1) The occurrence of special indicator words,
2) The actual strength of the inferential link between
premises and conclusion, and
3) The character or form of argumentation the arguers use.
• Words like “certainly", 'necessarily”, “absolutely”,
and “definitely” indicate that the argument should be
taken as deductive.
• words like, “probable”, “improbable” “plausible”
“implausible”, ‘‘likely", “unlikely” and “reasonable to
conclude” suggest that an argument is inductive.
• The occurrence of an indicator word is not a certain
guarantee for the deductiveness or inductiveness of an
argument unless it is supported by the other features
If the conclusion actually does follow with strict necessity
from the premises, the argument is clearly deductive
If the conclusion of an argument does not follow with strict
necessity but does follow probably, it is usually best to
interpret it as inductive argument.
• Example-1:
– All Ethiopian people love their country.
– Debebe is an Ethiopian.
– Therefore, Debebe loves his country
• Example-2:
– The majority of Ethiopian people are poor.
– Alamudin is an Ethiopian.
– Therefore, Alamudin is poor.
The character or form of argumentation the arguers use
refers looking at some deductive or inductive
argumentative forms.
Instances of Deductive Argumentative
Forms
Five examples of such forms or kinds of argumentation
are arguments based on mathematics, arguments from
definition, and syllogisms.
Argument based on mathematics
Arguments in pure mathematics are deductive and
arguments that depend on statistics are usually best
interpreted as inductive.
Statistical arguments are based on random sampling of
data gathering, it is impossible to arrive at absolutely
certain conclusion.
Arguments based on definition
It is an argument in which the conclusion is
claimed to depend merely up on the definition of
some words or phrase used in the premise or
conclusion. example,
Angel is honest; therefore, Angel tells the truth.
Kebede is a physician; therefore, he is a doctor.
Arguments based on Syllogisms
Syllogisms are arguments consisting of exactly
two premises and one conclusion.
Syllogisms can be categorized into three groups;
categorical, hypothetical, and disjunctive
syllogism.
• Categorical syllogism: It is consisting of exactly two
premises and one conclusion and the statement begins with
words like “all”,” “no” and “some”. Example:
• All Egyptians are Muslims.
• No Muslim is a Christian.
• Hence, no Egyptian is a Christian
• Hypothetical syllogism: It has a conditional statement for
one or both of its premises. Example:
– If you study hard, then you will graduate with Distinction .
• Disjunctive syllogism: it is a syllogism having a
disjunctive statement. (i.e. an “either … or” statement.)
• e.g. Rewina is either Ethiopian or Eritrean.
Rewina is not Eritrean.
Therefore, Rewina is Ethiopian.
Instances of Inductive Argumentative Forms
Some examples of such forms or kinds of argumentation are
arguments based on predictions, analogy generalizations ,
authority, signs, and causal inferences
In Prediction the premises deals with some known event in
the present or the past and the conclusions moves beyond
this event to some event to relative future. For example,
Certain clouds develop in the center of the highland,
therefore, rain will fall within twenty-four hours.
An argument from analogy is an argument that depends on
the existence of an analogy or similarity between two
things or state of affairs. Example:
The Encyclopedia Britannica has an article on culture.
The Encyclopedia Americana, like Britannica, is an
excellent work. Therefore, the Americana probably also
has an article on culture.
An inductive generalization (An argument based on
statistics) is an argument that proceeds from the
knowledge of selected sample to some claim about the
whole group. Example:
There are 45 students in this class. I have evaluated
the answer sheets of 20 students and all of them
scored above 85%. It implies that all students of this
class are smart.
An argument from authority is argument based on
citation, interview, or witness of a person who has a
better position or access to the required qualification.
Example:
According to Ato Tewodros who is a lawyer in
Hawassa city, Kebede committed murder because an
eye witness testified to that effect under oath.
An argument based on signs is an argument that proceeds
from the knowledge of a certain sign (may be it is a traffic
sign, a trademark, a cautionary mark, a symbol,) to a
knowledge of the thing or situation symbolized by the
sign. Example:
The package material says that “keep it out of the
reach of children.” Therefore, this package must
consist of some sort of medicine
An argument based on causation is an argument
that proceeds from the knowledge of a cause to
knowledge of the effect, or conversely, from the
knowledge of an effect to the knowledge of a
cause. Example:
The cloud is becoming dark and the thunder is
roaming. So, let us go home quickly, the rain is
inevitable.
From the knowledge that a bottle of water had
been accidentally left in the freezer overnight,
someone might conclude that it had frozen
(cause to effect).
Conversely, after tasting a piece of chicken and
finding it dry and tough, one might conclude
that it had been overcooked (effect to cause).
Because specific instances of cause and effect
can never be known with absolute certainty, one
may usually interpret such an argument as
inductive.
We have to take into consideration that deductive
argument not always proceeds from the general to the
particular and inductive arguments proceed from the
particular to the general.
This is because there are some deductive or inductive
arguments that proceed from the general to the general or
from the particular to the particular or even from the
particular to the general.
For example, here is a deductive argument that proceeds
from the particular to the general:
– Three is a prime number. Five is a prime number.
Seven is a prime number. Therefore, all odd numbers
between two and eight are prime numbers.
Here is an inductive argument that proceeds from
the general to the particular:
All emeralds previously found have been green.
Therefore, the next emerald to be found will be
green.
Here is an deductive argument that proceeds
from particular to general
The members of Mohammed’s family are
Kedija, Kemal and Leyla. Kedija wears glasses.
Kemal wears glasses. Leyla wears glasses.
Therefore, all members of Mohammed’s family
wear glasses.
CHAPTER THREE
LOGIC AND LANGUAGE
Philosophy of Language
• According to Semiotics(the study of sign processes in
communication), language is the manipulation and use
of symbols in order to draw attention to signified content.
• Philosophy of language is the reasoned inquiry into the
nature, origins, and usage of language.
• Philosophy of language has been concerned with four
central problems: the nature of meaning, language use,
language cognition, and the relationship between
language, logic and reality.
• It poses questions like
– What is meaning? How does language refer to the real
world?
– Is language learned or is it innate?
– How does the meaning of a sentence emerge out of its parts?