Kymlicka An Emergeging Consensus Multicylriralismo Nacionalismo Liberal
Kymlicka An Emergeging Consensus Multicylriralismo Nacionalismo Liberal
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethical
Theory and Moral Practice
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
WILLKYMLICKA
With one exception, the papers in this symposium were originally pre
sented at a Dutch-Israeli colloquium on "Nationalism, Multiculturalism
and Liberal Democracy", held at the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts
and Sciences in November 1997. (Yael Tamir's paper was written after the
symposium, to complete the issue). One goal of the colloquium was to try
to determine whether there is a distinctly liberal-democratic approach to
issues of ethnocultural diversity. How do the claims of ethnic and national
groups relate to the underlying principles of liberal democracy, such as
individual freedom, social equality and democracy? When do these claims
respect or promote liberal values, and when do they conflict with them?
The philosophical debate on these questions is relatively new. Indeed,
for most of this century, issues of ethnicity have been seen as marginal
by political philosophers.1 Much the same can be said of other academic
disciplines, from sociology to geography to history.
Today however, after decades of relative neglect, the question of rights
of minority cultures has moved to the forefront of political theory. There
are a number of reasons for this. Most obviously, the collapse of Commu
nism in 1989 unleashed a wave of ethnic nationalisms in Eastern Europe
which dramatically affected the democratization process. Optimistic as
sumptions that liberal democracy would emerge smoothly from the ashes
1 In his paper in this symposium, Chaim Gans suggests that this is due to the lingering
influence of Enlightenment cosmopolitanism on political philosophers.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
144 WILLKYMLICKA
While this debate is relatively new, I think we can already detect an emerg
ing consensus in the literature. First, there seems to be growing acceptance
of the legitimacy of some or other form of liberal nationalism? According
to liberal nationalism, it is a legitimate function of the state to protect
and promote the national cultures and languages of the nations within its
borders. This can be done by creating public institutions which operate
in these national languages; using national symbols in public life (e.g.,
flag, anthem, public holidays); and allowing self-government for national
groups on issues that are crucial to the reproduction of their language
and culture (e.g., schemes of federalism or consociationalism to enable
national minorities to exercise self-government).
2 See Young, 1990; Buchanan, 1991; Taylor, 1992; Gallenkamp, 1993; Tamir, 1993;
Baubock, 1994; Spinner, 1994; Miller, 1995; Phillips, 1995; Tully, 1995; Kymlicka, 1995a;
Walzer, 1997.1 am not aware of full-length books written by philosophers in English on
any of these topics predating 1990. For collections of recent philosophical articles on these
issues, see McDonald, 1991; Baker, 1994; van Willigenburg et al., 1995; Kymlicka, 1995b;
Raikka, 1996; McMahan and McKim, 1997; Shapiro and Kymlicka, 1997; Lehning, 1998.
3 For recent defenses of liberal nationalism, see Raz and Margalit, 1990; Taylor, 1992,
1997; Tamir, 1993; Spinner, 1994; Miller, 1995; Canovan, 1996; Kymlicka, 1997; Walzer,
1997.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION: AN EMERGING CONSENSUS 145
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
146 WILL KYMLICKA
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION: AN EMERGING CONSENSUS 147
1993). Civic nationalism, on this standard view, defines national membership pur
terms of adherence to democratic principles; whereas ethnic nationalism defines nati
membership in terms of a common language, culture, and ethnic descent. But th
be misleading. Even in the most liberal of democracies, nation-building goes beyon
diffusion of political principles. It also involves the diffusion of a common langua
national culture. What distinguishes liberal nation-building from illiberal national
not the absence of any concern with language, culture and national identity, but rathe
content, scope and inclusiveness of this national culture, and the modes of incorpo
into it. Moreover, there is not one distinction between liberal and illiberal nationa
but several. And each of these distinctions is a matter of degree. We cannot, therefo
vide real-world nationalist movements into two categories: 'liberal' and 'illiberal'. R
nationalist movements will turn out to be more liberal on some scales, and less libe
others. For further discussion, see Kymlicka, 1998.
6 For defenders of liberal multiculturalism, see Young, 1990; Taylor, 1992; Bau
1994; Raz, 1994; Spinner, 1994; Phillips, 1995; Kymlicka, 1997.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
148 WILL KYMLICKA
groups, rather than allowing one group to exercise dominance over other
groups.
We can describe both liberal nationalism and liberal multiculturalism as
forms of 'liberal culturalism'. Liberal culturalism is the view that liberal
democratic states should not only uphold the familiar set of common civil
and political rights of citizenship which are protected in all liberal democ
racies; they must also adopt various group-specific rights or policies which
are intended to recognize and accommodate the distinctive identities and
needs of ethnocultural groups. Such policies range from multicultural ed
ucation policies to language rights to guarantees of political representa
tion to constitutional protections of treaties with indigenous peoples.7 For
liberal culturalists, these various forms of group-specific measures are of
ten required for ethnocultural justice, although to be consistent with lib
eral culturalism they must meet a number of conditions, like those Usted
above.8 In particular, liberal culturalists support policies which make it
possible for members of ethnic and national groups to express and promote
their culture and identity, but reject any policies which impose a duty on
people to do so.
Liberal culturalism has arguably become the dominant position in the
literature today, and most debates are about how to develop and refine
the liberal culturalist position, rather than whether to accept it in the first
place. The five papers presented in this symposium reflect this emerging
consensus.
How has this consensus been achieved so quickly, given that the claim
being defended by liberal culturalists were ignored or decried by most
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION: AN EMERGING CONSENSUS 149
liberals until very recently? One possible explanation is that the arguments
provided by liberal culturalists have been so compelling and convincing
that everyone has been persuaded by them. As a defender of liberal cultur
alism, I wish this were true. But a more plausible explanation, I think, is
that there is no clear alternative position. Liberal culturalism has won by
default, as it were.
Of course, one can imagine alternatives to liberal culturalism, even if
they have not yet been well-developed in the literature. Two broad options
come immediately to mind. One alternative would be to try to show that the
earlier model of a unitary republican citizenship, in which all citizens share
the identical set of common citizenship rights, can be updated to deal with
issues of ethnocultural diversity, even though it was originally developed in
the context of much more homogeneous political communities. One could
argue that the interests we share in common are much more important
than the identities which divide us, and that liberal culturalism is therefore
distracting us from our more important common interests as fellow human
beings. Moreover, one could argue that too great an emphasis on diversity
threatens to undermine the very capacity for democratic deliberation about
the common good.9
This position, however, faces the problem that its traditional pretensions
to ethnocultural neutrality can no longer be sustained. Republicans used to
argue that a regime of common citizenship rights was neutral amongst eth
nocultural groups. By avoiding group-specific rights, the state treated eth
nocultural identities as a matter of individual choice in the private realm,
neither hindering nor helping any particular ethnocultural group.
However, this claim to neutrality has been effectively demolished by
recent writers.10 What appears on the surface to be a neutral system of
common rights turns out, on inspection, to be a system which is heavily
weighted in favour of the majority group. It is the majority's language
which is used in public institutions; the majority's holidays which are
recognized in the public calendar; the majority's history which is taught
in schools; and so on. Moreover, these examples of the privileging of the
majority's language and culture cannot be seen as minor or accidental de
viations from the ideal of ethnocultural neutrality; they help define the very
structure of the liberal state, which in turn shapes the structure of the larger
society. Once the pretence of neutrality has been removed, the republican
commitment to unitary citizenship becomes deeply problematic. It avoids,
9 This is arguably the position of van Gunsteren, 1998. Other republican critics of
liberal culturalism include Ward, 1991; Miller, 1995.
10 For critiques of this neutrality claim, see Tamir, 1993; Spinner, 1994; Kymlicka, 1997.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
150 WILL KYMLICKA
11 See, for example, Spinner, 1994; Phillips, 1995; Young, 1997; Williams, 1998.
12 In his paper for the colloquium, Herman van Gunsteren defended a 'neorepubli
can' model (or a 'republicanism without illusions') which admits that unitary citizenship
is non-neutral while remaining hostile to most forms of group-differentiated citizenship
(particularly to group representation and self-government rights). However, his argument
stayed at such a level of abstraction that it was difficult to tell what concretely it implied for
the sorts of issues about language, education, electoral systems etc., raised in this debate.
See van Gunsteren, "Multiple Belonging in the Community of Fate", unpublished paper
presented at the Netherlands-Israeli colloquium on "Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and
Liberal Democracy" (November 1997).
13 For a classic statement, see Connolly, 1993, 1996.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION: AN EMERGING CONSENSUS 151
the possibility that it will emerge from the contest as the most promising
approach to issues of ethnocultural justice. In any event, I do not think that
postmodernists have provided any compelling reasons for ruling this out.
Indeed, insofar as the postmodernist approach attempts to offer a pos
itive account of ethnocultural justice, it is not clear how it differs from
liberal culturalism.14 Postmodernists are often motivated by (a) a desire to
avoid essentiahzing identities; (b) a desire to avoid Eurocentric cultural
imperialism. How does this differ (except in rhetoric) from the liberal
constraints I discussed above: i.e., (a) that individuals be free to question
and reject ascribed identities; (b) that group-specific policies should aim to
promote equality/non-dominance between groups? How would the post
modernist concern with essentialism and ethnocentrism lead to a different
theory of language rights, say, than the liberal culturalist approach? So far
as I can tell, the postmodernist approach has simply not been developed in
sufficient detail to determine whether and how it differs on concrete issues
from liberal culturalism.
So neither unitary republicanism nor postmodernism provide a clear
alternative to liberal culturalism.15 As a result, the liberal culturalist ap
proach has become dominant by default. The old model of unitary citi
zenship has been exposed as a fraud; and the postmodern alternative is
underdeveloped.
This is arguably the greatest shortcoming in the debate. We simply
need a broader range of approaches to issues of ethnocultural justice. It
is impossible to properly evaluate the strengths and weaknesses of liberal
culturalism until we have a clearer idea of what the alternatives are.
While most authors in the literature are working within the broad camp
of liberal culturalism, this doesn't mean that they are satisfied with the
existing theories of liberal nationalism or of liberal multiculturalism. On
the contrary, many questions have been raised about these theories. These
questions can be organized under two broad headings: methodological and
normative.
14 There is a long-standing dispute about whether postmodernists can endorse any sub
stantive norms of justice or freedom without engaging in a 'performative contradiction' -
i.e., without violating their own metatheoretical critiques of 'reason' and 'truth'. However,
I will set that issue aside.
15 There are other possible approaches (e.g., religious fundamentalism; racialized forms
of nationalism), but these are not likely to win many converts amongst mainstream Western
political theorists.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
152 WELL KYMLICKA
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION: AN EMERGING CONSENSUS 153
16 See also Veit Bader's paper "Unity, Stability and Compliance in Modern Societies
and Recent Political Philosophy", unpublished paper presented at Netherlands-Israeli
colloquium on "Nationalism, Multiculturalism and Liberal Democracy" (November 1997).
17 Indeed, I would argue that the traditional liberal hostility to group-specific rights rests
on a series of selective cases and over-generalizations. For example, models of state/church
relations have been wrongly generalized to other areas of ethnocultural diversity; and ob
jections to segregated institutions for African-Americans have been wrongly generalized
to all forms of 'separate but equal' treatment for ethnic groups.
18 To take one example, compare the discussions of group representation in Phillips,
1995 and Williams, 1998 to those in Young, 1990 or Van Dyke, 1977. I think any im
partial reader would agree that enormous progress has been made in comprehensiveness,
interdisciplinarity, and in institutional specificity.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
154 WILL KYMLICKA
uate all of the arguments which have been advanced for or against these
proposals.
I would like, however, to mention a few more general questions which
have been raised about the moral foundations of liberal culturalism. I noted
earlier that liberal culturalism, in its more general formulation, is the view
that liberal-democratic states should not only uphold the familiar set of
common civil and political rights of citizenship, but should also adopt var
ious group-specific rights or policies which are intended to recognize and
accommodate the distinctive identities and needs of ethnocultural groups.
But why is it so important to recognize and accommodate ethnocultural
identities and practices? Why does it matter whether society is multicul
turalist? Why should we view membership in ethnocultural groups, or the
potential loss of diverse cultures, as a matter of political importance, rather
than simply private lifestyle choices? We can identify at least three distinct
arguments within the liberal culturalist camp:
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION: AN EMERGING CONSENSUS 155
identity argument, but concludes that it works better for some cases of
recognition than for others.
In short, while all of these authors are working within a broadly liberal
culturalist framework, there is no consensus amongst them concerning the
normative foundations of this position. There is no agreement on the rel
ative merits of these three justifications for liberal culturalism, or on what
we should do when these justifications lead in different policy directions.
Several other recent papers have also explored these disputes about the
moral grounding of liberal culturalism.19
It is safe to say, I think, that liberal culturalism has struck an intuitive
chord with many people. And this, combined with the lack of any well
developed alternatives, helps to explain why it has so quickly become the
consensus position in the literature. But as the papers in this symposium
show, much work remains to be done in developing these intuitions into
methodologically sophisticated and philosophically satisfying theories.
References
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
156 WILL KYMLICKA
Kymlicka, W., "Ethnie Relations in Eastern Europe and Western Political Theory", in M.
Opalski (ed.), Managing Diversity in Plural Societies: Minorities, Migration and Nation
building in Post-Communist Europe. Ottawa: Forum Eastern Europe, 1998, pp. 275
322.
Levy, J., "Classifying Cultural Rights", in Shapiro and Kymlicka (eds.), 1997, pp. 22-66.
Lehning, P. (ed.), Theories of Secession. London: Routledge, 1998.
Margalit, A. and M. Halbertal, "Liberalism and the Right to Culture", Social Research,
61(3) (1994), pp. 491-510.
Margalit, A. and J. Raz, "National Self-Determination", Journal of Philosophy, 87(9)
(1990), pp. 439-461.
McMahan, J. and R. McKim (eds.), The Morality of Nationalism. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1997.
Miller, D., On Nationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.
McDonald, M. (ed.), special issue on "Collective Rights", Canadian Journal of Law and
Jurisprudence, 4/2 (1991), pp. 217-419.
Phillips, A., The Politics of Presence: Issues in Democracy and Group Representation.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Raikka, J. (ed.), Do We Need Minority Rights?. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1996.
Raz, J., "Multiculturalism: A Liberal Perspective", Dissent, Winter 1994, pp. 67-79.
Reaume, D., "Justice between Cultures: Autonomy and the Protection of Cultural Affilia
tion", UBC Law Review, Vol. 29(1) (1995), pp. 121.
Shapiro, I. and W. Kymlicka (eds.), Ethnicity and Group Rights. New York: New York
University Press, 1997.
Spinner, J., The Boundaries of Citizenship: Race, Ethnicity and Nationality in the Liberal
State. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994.
Tamir, Y, Liberal Nationalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993.
Taylor, C, "The Politics of Recognition", in A. Gutmann (ed.), Multiculturalism and the
'Politics of Recognition'. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992, pp. 25-73.
Taylor, C, ''Nationalism and Modernity", in J. McMahan and R. McKim (eds.), 1997.
Tomasi, J., "Kymlicka, Liberalism, and Respect for Cultural Minorities", Ethics, 105(3)
(1995), pp. 580-603.
Tully, J., Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1995.
Van Dyke, V, "The Individual, the State, and Ethnic Communities in Political Theory",
World Politics, 29(3) (1977), pp. 343-369.
Waldron, J., "Minority Cultures and the Cosmopolitan Alternative", in Kymlicka, 1995b
(ed.), 1995.
Walzer, M., On Toleration. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997.
Ward, C, "The Limits of 'Liberal Republicanism': Why Group-Based Remedies and
Republican Citizenship Don't Mix", Columbia Law Review, 91(3) (1991), pp.
581-607.
Williams, M., Voice, Trust and Memory: Marginalized Groups and the Failings of Liberal
Representation. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998.
Wllligenburg, Th. van, R. Heeger and W. van den Burg (eds.), Nation, State and the
Coexistence of Different Communities. Kampen: Kok Pharos Publishing, 1995.
Young, I.M., Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1990.
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
INTRODUCTION: AN EMERGING CONSENSUS 157
Department of Philosophy
Queen's University
Kingston, Ontario K7L 3N6
Canada
This content downloaded from 158.170.10.44 on Fri, 08 Mar 2019 22:42:20 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms