David Shoemaker - Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility - Volume 1-Oxford University Press (2013)
David Shoemaker - Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility - Volume 1-Oxford University Press (2013)
RESPONSIBILITY VOLUME 1
This page intentionally left blank
Oxford Studies
in Agency and
Responsibility
Volume 1
Edited by
DAVID SHOEMAKER
1
3
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP,
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
# the several contributors 2013
The moral rights of the author have been asserted
First Edition published in 2013
Impression: 1
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics
rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
ISBN 978–0–19–969485–3 (Hbk)
ISBN 978–0–19–969486–0 (Pbk)
Printed in Great Britain by
CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY
Contents
Introduction 1
David Shoemaker
1. The Possibility of Action as the Impossibility of Certain
Forms of Self-Alienation 12
Sarah Buss
2. The Fecundity of Planning Agency 47
Michael E. Bratman
3. Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? Intentions and the
Own Action Condition 70
Luca Ferrero
4. Regret, Agency, and Error 95
Daniel Jacobson
5. Phenomenal Abilities: Incompatibilism and the Experience
of Agency 126
Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
6. Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 151
Michael McKenna
7. Responsibility, Naturalism, and “The Morality System” 184
Paul Russell
8. The Three-Fold Significance of the Blaming Emotions 205
Zac Cogley
9. Unwitting Wrongdoers and the Role of Moral
Disagreement in Blame 225
Matthew Talbert
10. Partial Desert 246
Tamler Sommers
11. Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 263
Heidi L. Maibom
12. Fairness and the Architecture of Responsibility 284
David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
Index 315
This page intentionally left blank
Notes on Contributors
Work on these questions, while more or less having an uneasy home base in the
world of moral philosophy, draws from a diverse range of cross-disciplinary
2 David Shoemaker
attempts to find a way to give reason a greater role in determining the goals
we pursue, so that it is already, in a way, built into the motivational part.
But this kind of solution is problematic, argues Buss, insofar as its advocates
do not build enough into the motivational part. We are left with a real
challenge to agency theorists: how might we understand how the goal-
directed behavior of creatures like us is transformed into behavior we cause
in pursuing those goals? Buss urges that this challenge cannot be met absent
metaethical vexation about the nature of reasons.
Michael Bratman’s essay, “The Fecundity of Planning Agency,” may
be construed as an attempt to answer this challenge (although that is not
how it is explicitly framed). As agents, we are capable of (1) acting—and
organizing our actions—across time; (2) joint action (or shared intention-
ality); and (3) self-governance. A theory of rational agency will gain in
plausibility to the extent that it can provide a unified account of these three
remarkable capacities. Bratman’s conjecture, fleshed out in insightful ways
here, is that these three capacities are grounded in our core capacity for
planning agency. The issue engaging most directly with Buss is that of self-
governance. Bratman attempts to avoid worrisome homuncular models of
the self by locating it (or at least locating its representative voice) in the
agent’s plan-like commitments to what matters (such that they carry weight
in our deliberative thought). As Bratman puts it, “[W]hen these plan states
guide, the agent governs.” And such commitments obviously build on the
agent’s planning agency. The question, then, is to what extent locating the
agent (or the agent’s voice) in such commitments can avoid the worries
articulated by Buss.
Luca Ferrero is also interested in an important aspect of attributability,
of what is involved in an attitude’s being mine. In particular, Ferrero is
interested in one sort of attitude—intention—which is commonly thought
to take as its proper object only the intender’s own action. Call this the
“own action” condition. Ferrero’s aim in “Can I Only Intend My Own
Actions? Intentions and the Own Action Condition,” is to show that the
“own action” condition is false. The relevant aspects of agency deemed
necessary to intention may actually be met without restricting the objects of
the agent’s intention to her own actions. He arrives at this conclusion by
first considering “aimings,” a simpler kind of practical attitude, and he
attempts to show that the own action condition isn’t necessary to aimings,
and to the extent that intentions are not relevantly different in key aspects,
the own action condition isn’t necessary to them either. This conclusion
bears significance for several skirmishes in the field of agency, including
how to properly characterize the relation between intentions and actions,
the fate of the causal action theory, and the nature of joint, or shared,
intention and agency. This last, of course, is one of the three agential
4 David Shoemaker
particular, they say, we experience ourselves from the inside as having the
ability to do otherwise when engaged in moral deliberation and/or action,
an ability that is incompatible with determinism and so provides some
evidence for our incompatibilist freedom. Compatibilists, in return, may
grant that we have some such experience, but deny that it implicates any
sort of incompatibilist ability; rather, they say, the experience we have of
being able to do otherwise is simply of being able to do otherwise if the
circumstances had been different. But if this is all my experience is of, then it
merely implicates an ability that is perfectly compatible with determinism.
Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols take this to be an empir-
ical dispute and so ripe for the methods of experimental psychology. In
their paper “Phenomenal Abilities: Incompatibilism and the Experience of
Agency,” they discuss a series of experiments they performed investigating
how people actually regard what is going on in their experiences of moral
deliberation and decision-making. As it turns out, they found remarkably
consistent results: people across the board overwhelmingly (a) view them-
selves as having the ability to do otherwise in a variety of practical (includ-
ing moral) circumstances, and (b) regard this ability explicitly in
incompatibilist terms. When testing various compatibilist reinterpret-
ations, the authors found that they just weren’t what subjects meant by
their experienced ability to do otherwise, an experience that remained
firmly incompatibilist. This paper is a model of experimental philosophy,
for it identifies an empirical matter on which a certain aspect of a long-
standing philosophical dispute hangs and subjects it to scientific scrutiny. It
then discusses the findings in distinctly (and insightful) philosophical
terms. If we accept the authors’ findings, we must move on from wrangling
over the interpretation of our phenomenal ability to do otherwise to the
role the phenomenology ostensibly plays in support of libertarianism: is it
really evidence for the view?
Alternatively, perhaps the ability to do otherwise isn’t necessary for
freedom at all. This is the course taken by many compatibilists who have
become convinced by the so-called “Frankfurt cases,” scenarios in which a
counterfactual intervener stands at the ready to ensure that some agent
decides as he (the intervener) wants her to (and so removes her ability to do/
decide otherwise) but never does a thing, as she decides all on her own to do
the hoped-for action. But if PAP is false, what does the sort of control
implicit in freedom and responsibility require? One popular move has been
to view free agents as those who are reasons-responsive. The problem with
doing so is that it looks as if agents in Frankfurt cases actually aren’t
reasons-responsive, as they wouldn’t have been sensitive to the reasons
not to perform the hoped-for action. In responding to this worry, Fischer
and Ravizza (1998) have argued that their favored notion of guidance
6 David Shoemaker
control over some action consists in its issuing from the agent’s own
reasons-responsive mechanism, something which can be sensitive to
reasons to do otherwise in Frankfurt cases, even if the agent herself isn’t.
Michael McKenna, in his intricate paper, “Reasons-Responsiveness,
Agents and Mechanisms,” traces this dialectic with great care before discuss-
ing some serious problems with a mechanism-based approach to the nature of
compatibilist control, in particular the problem of individuating the specific
mechanisms operative in cases of free action. This problem, McKenna argues,
is really symptomatic of a deeper, structural problem with mechanistic
theories generally: if (as seems plausible) we allow that various sub-mechan-
isms clearly interact with one another to issue in different types of action, we
seem driven to attribute actions to “the mechanism” that can somehow
include all such simultaneously-operating sub-mechanisms, but then this
mechanism looks an awful lot like a full-fledged agent once more. So if we
are forced back to an agent-based reasons-responsive view, are we also back to
accepting PAP (given that it seems these types of views give the wrong answer
in Frankfurt cases)? No, argues McKenna: it is possible for an agent to be
reasons-responsive in the Frankfurt case without being able to react to reasons
to do otherwise when given sufficient reason to do so. Developing and
defending this intriguing proposal takes up the remainder of his essay.
possibility that opens the door again to deep skepticism about responsibility
generally. Russell, in the remainder of his essay, tries to close this door by
offering a middle-path naturalism about our ethical reactive attitudes—
motivated by Bernard Williams’s critique of “the morality system”—one
that charts a path between Strawson’s own overly wide approach (given his
inclusion of too many emotional reactions as ostensibly relevant to moral
responsibility, e.g. love and friendly feeling) and R. Jay Wallace’s overly
narrow one (which distorts our understanding of human ethical life and
looks conceptually imperialistic).
One of the many innovations of Strawson’s approach was to view being
morally responsible as somehow a function of being regarded as morally
responsible, where to be regarded as such is just to be the target of various
sorts of reactive emotions (although there are significantly different ways to
interpret this view; see Brink and Nelkin’s paper for a realist—in contrast
to a response-dependent—understanding of Strawsonian responsibility).
Strawson divided the sorts of pleas that get one off the hook as a target of
such reactions into two groups, what Watson (1987) has helpfully called
“excusing” and “exempting” pleas. Excusing pleas—“It was an accident”;
“I didn’t know”—are those that get the agent off the hook for a particular
action but continue to leave her vulnerable to reactive emotions generally.
Exempting pleas—“She’s only a child”; “He’s a hopeless schizophrenic”—
remove the offender from the community of morally responsible agents
altogether. What Strawsonian theorists have searched for, then, are ways of
theoretically unifying these categories. In other words, is there any unified
grounding for the inappropriateness of resentment for accidents, ignorance,
insanity, and the like? Some have thought there is theoretical unity given
the sanctioning aspect of (negative) reactive attitudes, where the unity
conditions are grounded in the fairness of such sanctions. Others have
sought the appropriateness conditions in the expressive nature of the
reactive emotions (such that some emotions are unfitting in virtue of their
failure to meet the felicity conditions of certain forms of communication).
Others have found unifying ground by focusing on how the reactive
emotions target certain qualities of will.
If Zac Cogley, in “The Three-Fold Significance of the Blaming Emo-
tions,” is right, this search for a unified treatment may be quixotic. Cogley
first draws from recent psychological research to articulate three distinct
functions of the (negative) reactive emotions: appraisal, communication,
and sanction. Second, Cogley shows that each of these three functions
imports its own distinct set of appropriateness conditions: while a blaming
emotion may meet the conditions rendering it an accurate or fitting
appraisal of responsibility, say, it may not meet the conditions rendering
it a fair or deserved sanction. This point leads to a third: different (unifying)
8 David Shoemaker
down by the father of the girl, who shoots him. In both cases, the driver
dies, but only in the second might we think he deserved his fate. This
reaction, Sommers argues, reveals our commitment to there being facts
external to the punished agent and what he knew or did that are relevant
to assessments of desert. In particular, it matters whether the offended
parties carry out (or at least contribute to a determination of) the punish-
ment. His defense of this proposal carries him into interesting territory,
including an important exploration of whether the proportionality
required for just legal sentencing and moral sanctioning must be ordinal
as well as cardinal, i.e. an exploration of whether like cases really must be
treated alike.
While Sommers exclusively focuses on moral desert and responsibility,
some have thought that we can achieve real insight into features of moral
responsibility by thinking about criminal responsibility. There are, for
instance, several explicitly articulated aspects of criminal responsibility—
excuse, justification, mens rea, fault, and liability—that seem to play an
analogous and important role in moral responsibility too (for doubts
about this ostensible relation, however, see Shoemaker Forthcoming).
Susan Wolf, for example, has famously appealed to the legal notion of
insanity to ground a normative competence condition for moral responsi-
bility. She discusses the case of JoJo, the son of an evil dictator, who
soaks up his daddy’s values and, when grown, treats the peasants in the
same horrible ways as dad. Wolf ’s thought is that, insofar as JoJo isn’t
viewed as morally responsible (a dubious finding, however; see Faraci
and Shoemaker 2010), it is because his deep self (his reflecting, valuing
self) isn’t normatively sane, i.e. he is unable to recognize the correct
moral values. Insofar as previous compatibilist theories hadn’t taken this
fundamental orientation to the good as necessary to moral responsibility,
they were incomplete.
Heidi Maibom, in “Values, Sanity, and Responsibility,” sees the Wolfian
position as dilemmatic: either this understanding of insanity is supposed to
capture the legal notion or it is not. If it is supposed to do so, then it
overreaches, insofar as legal insanity typically incorporates only those
suffering from delusions and hallucinations, and not those who merely
have different values than ours; indeed, the legally insane usually com-
pletely share our values. If, on the other hand, the Wolfian view advances a
different understanding of moral insanity, then it is wrong-headed, as it
would require us to cease regarding as responsible those we clearly do,
namely, those who are merely intransigent in holding different values than
ours. As long as there is an available inferential route for them from their
own values to beliefs about wrongness we can share, they are eligible for
responsibility assessments for failing to do so. If we didn’t allow for this
10 David Shoemaker
In each case above, I have only skimmed the surface of these rich essays. But
what I have said should be sufficient to reveal both the variety of topics
falling under the rubric of “agency and responsibility” as well as their
interesting and variegated relations to one another. While most writing
on responsibility focuses solely on the negative, blaming, reactions to the
deeds of others, my reaction to the contributions of the authors herein is
nothing but philosophical and personal gratitude.1
1 My thanks to all of the authors, both for their contributions to this volume and for
their comments on an earlier draft of these introductory remarks. I am also deeply
grateful to Steve Sheffrin and the Murphy Institute at Tulane University for financing
the first workshop on agency and responsibility in November 2011, and to Nathan
Stout, Jason Tyndal, and Frankie Worrell for compiling the index. Finally, thanks to
Peter Momtchiloff at Oxford University Press for his early and enthusiastic support of
this new series.
Introduction 11
REFERENCES
Faraci, David, and Shoemaker, David. (2010). “Insanity, Deep Selves, and Moral
Responsibility: The Case of JoJo.” Review of Philosophy & Psychology 1: 319–32.
Fischer, John Martin, and Ravizza, Mark. (1998). Responsibility and Control.
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Frankfurt, Harry G. (1988). The Importance of What We Care About. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press).
—— (1999). Necessity, Volition, and Love. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Shoemaker, David. Forthcoming. “On Criminal and Moral Responsibility.” In
Mark Timmons, ed., Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, Volume 3 (Oxford:
Oxford University Press).
Strawson, P. F. (1962). “Freedom and Resentment.” Proceedings of the British
Academy 48: 1–25.
Watson, Gary. (1987). “Responsibility and the Limits of Evil: Variations on a
Strawsonian Theme.” In Ferdinand Schoeman, ed., Responsibility, Character, and
the Emotions: New Essays in Moral Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1987): 256–86.
1
The Possibility of Action as the
Impossibility of Certain Forms
of Self-Alienation
Sarah Buss
a being can be self-alienated in the relevant way, then the fact that she
engages in instrumentally rational, goal-directed behavior does not suffice
to ensure that the goals she pursues are her own. The fact that she behaves
in a way that would qualify as an action if she were not a rational being is
compatible with the fact that she is alienated from her behavior; and so, it is
compatible with the fact that her behavior does not qualify as her action;
and so, an adequate account of what is required in order for her to act will
have to be an account of the conditions under which she is not alienated
from herself in the relevant way.1
In the first half of this paper, I will press the case against the assumption that
rational beings succeed in acting as long as they engage in instrumentally
1
The point is not, as Jennifer Hornsby puts it, that we are under “pressure to add an
extra ingredient in order to reveal [a rational agent] as a more or less reasonable,
conscious being” (Hornsby 2004: 185). The point, rather, is that we are under
pressure to identify the extra ingredient that is present when a rational being does not
dissociate herself from her motives. It is perhaps worth noting at the outset some of the
ways in which my critique of the standard picture of action is at once similar to and
different from the sort of challenges that target what Hornsby calls “the naturalistic
assumptions” at the heart of this picture. Like Hornsby, I will be arguing that there is a
form of self-alienation which is a threat to even less-than-“robust” agency. More
particularly, I share the concern that insofar as one relates to oneself as a feature of the
world, one is a bystander to one’s own motives, and so one is not the direct cause of
anything that is directly caused by these motives; i.e. their causal efficacy is not an
instance of one’s own agency. Whereas, however, Hornsby and others who challenge so-
called “causal” accounts of action think it is a mistake to characterize bodily actions as
events caused by agents, I do not challenge this assumption. (This assumption, it is
important to stress, is not the assumption that “an action . . . is something on the physical
side of a supposed mental/physical divide and called a bodily movement.”(180) Rather,
the claim is that bodily actions are bodily movements insofar as they have a certain
nonphysical status—which includes, but (as the requirement of instrumental
rationality makes clear) is not exhausted by, their status as the effects of mental causes.
Note that, Hornsby’s suggestion to the contrary notwithstanding, the same story applies
to actions that consist of an agent’s intentionally refraining from moving her body in
various ways.)
In addition to these respects in which my criticism resembles and differs from the
typical challenges to causal theories of action, there are others. Whereas Hornsby thinks
that the problems with the standard conception reveal the misguidedness of any attempt
to account for action in terms of the “mental states” of the agent, I think that we can offer
a diagnosis of what has gone wrong without ruling out the possibility of such a reduction.
In other words, it seems to me that taking an “external perspective” on oneself can “pose
a genuine threat to our agency,” even if our actions can be “unproblematically accom-
modated in the naturalistic explanatory order” (181). (This is true, even if, as I suggest, to
do something for a reason, one must take oneself to be responsive to reasons, and even if
it is a mistake to offer a “naturalistic” account of reasons.) Finally, as I hope to make
clear, one can claim that “X’s desiring something and believing something [can be]
translated into talk of items with causal potential” without claiming that “X’s having a
reason is . . . a matter of the existence of a pair of states” (180). Indeed, as far as I can tell,
very few advocates of the standard conception endorse the latter claim.
14 Sarah Buss
2
This is a point Aristotle makes in the Nicomachean Ethics: “In the soul too there is
something contrary to the rational principle, resisting and opposing it. . . . Now even this
seems to have a share in a rational principle, as we said; at any rate in the continent man it
obeys the rational principle—and presumably in the temperate and brave man it is still
more obedient; for in him it speaks on all matters, with the same voice as the rational
principle. Therefore the irrational element also appears to be twofold. For the vegetative
element in no way shares in a rational principle, but the appetitive, and in general the
desiring element in a sense shares in it, in so far as it listens to and obeys it; this is the
The Possibility of Action 15
Most people who think about what is involved in doing something volun-
tarily assume that an adequate account of action will apply equally to
(i) those, like squirrels, to whom it is a mistake to attribute any opinions
about what they have reason to do and (ii) healthy, mature human beings
who form such opinions quite frequently, even though they rarely do so
self-consciously. According to this widespread assumption, when it comes
to plain old acting, a rational being need not satisfy any conditions other
than those that suffice for the action of a nonrational being.
But this assumption is false. For it overlooks the fact that the capacity to
reason is the capacity to dissociate oneself from the very sort of psychic
forces whose causal role would yield an action if they were attributable to a
nonrational being. Whereas having a behavior-determining impulse to
bury a nut is all that it takes for a squirrel to have the goal of burying a
nut, a rational being need not share the goal of her desire at a given moment
in time, no matter how powerful this desire may be, no matter how nicely it
sense in which we speak of ‘taking account‘ of one’s father or one’s friends, not that in
which we speak of ‘accounting’ for a mathematical property. That the irrational element
is in some sense persuaded by a rational principle is indicated also by the giving of advice
and by all reproof and exhortation. And if this element also must be said to have a
rational principle, that which has a rational principle (as well as that which has not) will
be twofold, one subdivision having it in the strict sense and in itself, and the other having
a tendency to obey as one does one’s father.” (Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, Bk. 1, ch.
12, 1102b25–1103a3)
16 Sarah Buss
may cohere with her other desires and commitments, and no matter how
confident she may be that some considerations do count in favor of the
goal-directed behavior. Any conception of agency that suggests otherwise is
thus inadequate. It is inadequate because it implies that a form of self-
alienation is compatible with agency, even though in relating to one’s
behavior in this way, one would be no less passive than one is when one
suffers a blow.
So, at any rate, I hope to show. I will argue, first, that it is not possible to
act if one dissociates oneself from the motivating force of whatever psychic
condition directly causes one’s behavior. I will then point out what this
implies: in order for a rational being to act, it is not enough that she engages
in instrumentally rational, goal-directed behavior.
Let me begin by calling attention to a metaphor. Most philosophers
seem to agree that the paradigm case of an agent who is not responsible for
what she does is someone who is, as Harry Frankfurt puts it in characteriz-
ing the “unwilling” addict, a “passive bystander” to her own motives
(Frankfurt 1988). But the metaphor of the “passive bystander” reveals a
problem: if there is anything that being an agent is not, being an agent is not
being a “passive bystander” to the direct mental causes of one’s behavior.
Insofar as one is a passive bystander to an event, this event is not one’s own
doing. It is not one’s own action.
Of course, it is possible for me to reflect on my actions even as I am
engaged in them: here I am, typing away at my keyboard, even as I am
observing the movements of my own fingers. But, as this example makes
clear, the point of the metaphor is not simply that we can take a detached
stance toward our own actions, but that we can be opposed to what we
ourselves do, even as we are doing it for a reason. Indeed, there is more to it
than this. Even if we very much wished that we had better alternatives, and
even if we keenly appreciated what compelling reasons we have to act
otherwise, we would not necessarily be opposed to our behavior in the
relevant sense. The point of the metaphor is that—with eyes wide open, as
they say—we can prefer to do one thing under the circumstances, even as we
are intentionally doing another. We can do this, moreover, in cases where
the action is not merely “reflexive”—cases, that is, in which what we do is
not a spontaneous response to a sudden change in our circumstances.3
Since, as Frankfurt reminds us, it would be possible to satisfy the
stipulated conditions only if it were possible for the forces that move us
to render us passive bystanders to their motivating power, and since insofar
3
For an example of a reflexive movement, think of a case in which one quickly moves
one’s hand in front of one’s face when a baseball suddenly appears in close proximity to
one’s head.
The Possibility of Action 17
4
For a discussion of the principle of instrumental rationality in which I argue that it is
not possible to wittingly will to do what is incompatible with achieving one’s end under
this description, see Buss, “Norms of Rationality and the Superficial Unity of the Mind,”
Unpublished Manuscript.
18 Sarah Buss
5
Buridan’s ass choices are a special instance of this phenomenon.
6
For an account of weakness of will that does justice to this relationship between
practical reason and the will, see Buss 1997.
The Possibility of Action 19
Interestingly, support for this thesis can be found in the testimony of people
who are widely agreed to be the paradigm examples of agents overpowered by
inclinations they wish they could resist: those suffering from obsessive-com-
pulsive disorder (OCD). Consider, for example, the anguished testimony of a
man who could not overcome his powerful compulsion to return, over and
over, to the place where he thought he might have hit someone with his car:
The pain is a terrible guilt, that I have committed an unthinkable, negligent act.
At one level, I know this is ridiculous, but there’s a terrible pain in my stomach
telling me something quite different. . . . The anxious pain says to me, “You Really
Did Hit Someone.” The attack is now in full control. Reality no longer has meaning.
My sensory system is distorted. I have to get rid of the pain. Checking out this
fantasy is the only way I know how.
I start ruminating, “Maybe I did hit someone and didn’t realize it. . . . Oh my
God! I might have killed somebody! I have to go back and check.” Checking is the
only way to calm the anxiety. It brings me closer to truth somehow. I can’t live with
the thought that I actually may have killed someon—I have to check it out.
My fantasies run wild. I desperately hope the jury will be merciful. I’m particu-
larly concerned about whether my parents will be understanding. After all, I’m now
a criminal. I must control the anxiety by checking it out. Did it really happen?
I think to myself, “Rush to check it out. Get rid of the hurt by checking it out.”
I’m now close to hysteria because I honestly believe someone is lying in the brush
bleeding to death. Yes,.. the pain makes me believe this. (Rapoport 1991: 24)
In short, even though there is an obvious sense in which someone responding
to the characteristic obsessions and compulsions of OCD wishes that she did
not behave as she did (and even though there is usually “a part of [her] psyche
[that] keeps telling [her] that this checking behavior is ridiculous” (Rapoport
1991: 26)), there is an equally obvious sense in which, at the moment
of action, she is convinced that she has no better alternative, under the
circumstances. She believes that nothing is more important than behaving
as she does; and her understanding of why it is important incorporates
both the irrational “fantasies” and the very real pain that accompanies the
fantasies. Most importantly for our purposes here, her experience as of being
overpowered by her compulsion is not the experience of being passive in
relation to her behavior. To be sure, she is passive in relation to the pain and
anxiety. But her response to her agony is the response of someone who is
absolutely (and not unreasonably, given the intensity of the pain, and given
that nothing else is likely to stop it) convinced that she really has no viable
alternative. Her compulsion dominates her by determining her point of view.
Her problem is precisely that she cannot dismiss her fantasies as alien to her
own beliefs and concerns.7
7
For a development of this account of how “compulsions” prevent agents from being
accountable for their actions, see Buss 2012.
20 Sarah Buss
8
The image of “the will as a muscle” is misleading, at best. “Will power” is not
analogous to the power we manifest when we hold on for dear life; it is not the power of
“the will.” Rather, it is the very sort of power we manifest when we hang on for dear life.
The difference simply has to do with what is being resisted, and—as I will soon have
occasion to stress—with what form it is possible for defeat to take.
The Possibility of Action 21
9
This is a point that Gary Watson stresses in his more recent work. (See Watson
2004) There he rejects the model of unfree action I am criticizing here. For an alternative
account of the distinction between self- and other-determined action that is key to
assessments of moral responsibility, see Buss 2012.
10
Note what this implies about cases in which our demands on ourselves are not met
with obedience: the defiance necessarily takes the form of forcing a reappraisal of our
options—even if (as in the case of akrasia) we are unpleasantly aware that this reappraisal
is a mere rationalization.
22 Sarah Buss
the power to act? Or should we concede, instead, that when its hands
move in order to indicate that the time is now five past midnight, and
when this happens despite its conviction that it has overriding reason to
do otherwise, these movements no more qualify as its actions than do the
hand movements of an ordinary clock?
Of course, in the case as described, the clock’s opinions about “its”
behavior are so causally isolated from this behavior as to disqualify the
behavior from being its own. But this is just the point. Nothing of
significance would change, moreover, if many of its opinions did have an
effect on its behavior. As long as its judgment regarding the all-things-
considered desirability of the two-handed choreography was inefficacious,
the regular movements of (what we can now safely call) its hands would not
be its doings. They would not be its actions.
This situation resembles a case in which a person’s body drags her
around, or does other things, “against her will.” Apparently, something
like this does sometimes happen. When a person suffers from anarchic
or alien hand syndrome, for example, one of her hands may undo the
buttons of her shirt, without her having any intention of doing this.11
So as to contrast this behavior with a mere spasm, we could refer to it as
an “action.” Since, however, the goal being pursued is not a goal that
anyone “has in mind,” it is not anyone’s intentional action. And in any
case—and this is what matters to me here—it is not an action
attributable to the person herself. A person is passive in relation to
what her anarchic fingers are doing to the buttons of her shirt—no
less passive than she would be if these fingers were on somebody else’s
hand.12
[Thought Experiment 2] Consider a second goal-seeker. Call him
A. A has no capacity whatsoever to reason. He has no capacity to ask
himself whether anything is worth doing. Nonetheless, he has dispositions
11
People suffering from anarchic or alien hand syndrome “lose the ‘sense of
agency’ associated with the purposeful movement of the limb while retaining a
sense of ‘ownership’ of the limb. They feel that they have no control over the
movements of the ‘alien’ hand, but that, instead, the hand has the capability of
acting . . . independent of their voluntary control. The hand effectively has a ‘will of
its own.’ ” “The alien hand is directed toward goals of which the patient is not
consciously aware.” (“Alien Hand Syndrome,” Wikipedia <http://en.wikipedia.org/
wiki/Alien_hand_syndrome>)
12
“Sufferers of alien hand will often personify the rogue limb, for example believing
it to be ‘possessed’ by some intelligent or alien spirit or an entity that they may name or
identify.” (“Alien Hand Syndrome,” Wikipedia <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Alien_
hand_syndrome>)
The Possibility of Action 25
to pursue various goals. And he also has the disposition to be guided by B’s
theoretical reasoning about what it would take in order to satisfy these
goals. When B is aware of a goal A has, she engages her reason in the task of
understanding what it would take to achieve this goal. And when she
reaches a conclusion on this point, A—who also has a special capacity to
read her mind!—adjusts his goal-pursuing accordingly.
By stipulation, this story contains two distinct individuals: one (A)
disposed to pursue goals in an instrumentally rational way, despite having
no opinion whatsoever about the desirability of doing so; the other (B)
disposed to employ reason to determine which events are likely to give rise
to which other events. Is A an agent? In contemplating this question, we can
consider some others: Would it make a difference if B deliberately “fed”
A the results of her reasoning—because (motivated, perhaps, by the interest
in understanding things) she was curious to see what he would do? Would
it matter if we implanted B inside A—so that they now shared a single
body? Perhaps this would suffice to render B an agent—if we also gave her
the higher-order goal of achieving A’s goals. Note, however, that in this
case, B’s goal-seeking behavior would constitute an action only because
B would endorse this behavior; the fact that it was instrumentally rational
goal-seeking behavior would not suffice.
This point is even more obvious if we stipulate that B strongly repudiates
the goals pursued by the body she now shares with A. Under these
circumstances, who is the agent of the resulting behavior? Should we not
concede that no one is, and that, accordingly, the behavior does not qualify
as an action, despite satisfying Smith’s conditions?
We cannot solve the problem revealed by these examples by simply
introducing more complex causal feedback mechanisms. As long as, despite
these greater complexities, the explanation thereby provided does not rule
out the possibility that the behavior is unresponsive to the contempor-
aneous normative judgments of the rational being whose action it would
otherwise unproblematically be, it will not qualify as an action. I thus
conclude that we must reject the standard conception of agency.
Before turning to consider an alternative conception, I want to warn
against reading too much into this conclusion. I am not claiming that
acting always requires reviewing the considerations pro and con. I am not
claiming that when we do things for reasons, we generally have a vivid,
determinate conception of why what we are doing is really worth doing.
I am sure that neither of these claims is true. Though, as Talbot Brewer
eloquently reminds us, we can, and often do, make a point of pursuing
certain activities with the aim of gaining an ever-greater appreciation of
their value (Brewer 2009), for the most part, our actions involve relatively
unreflective attempts to continue the activities we have already initiated,
26 Sarah Buss
often without ever having given the matter much thought. As Hilary Bok
points out in discussing the Milgram experiments, our capacity to act
without regarding every change in our circumstances as a new occasion for
deliberation and choice makes it possible for us to become accomplices to evil
without endorsing any evil ends: if we don’t pay attention—and, again, we
often don’t—continuing on the path we have set ourselves can lead us to a
place we did not know we were headed (Bok 1996). Less dramatically,
philosophers of action are surely right to stress the extent to which we are
inclined to give ourselves permission to act “from habit”; and David
Velleman and Peter Railton (among others) are right, too, to note that
even instrumental reasoning is often superfluous: our habits of response
include dispositions to adjust our means to our immediate ends without
engaging in any more “reasoning” than occurs when the average backyard
squirrel scampers from branch to branch (Velleman 2009 and Railton 2011).
We can concede each of these points, however, while insisting that even
the most ho-hum instances of agency are incompatible with the sort of self-
alienation I have here been exploring. Insofar as (however unconsciously)
we—we reasoning beings—take a stance on what we are doing (insofar as
we take ourselves to have sufficient reason for what we are doing), we endorse
what we are doing—not in the sense that we think especially well of
ourselves, or are especially pleased with the options we face—but in the
sense that we—the ones who bother forming an opinion about whether
what we are doing makes sense—accept the goals of our behavior as our
own. An adequate account of rational agency will thus be an account of this
self-relation, and of the normative judgment that is inseparable from it.13
13
There is a vast philosophical literature devoted to making sense of the fact that
rational agents “identify with” their motives. Some philosophers appeal to higher-order
desires. (For the classic defense of this approach, see Frankfurt 1971 and Frankfurt
1977.) Others appeal to evaluative judgments (for the classic defense of this approach, see
Watson 1975. Others appeal to hierarchies and intentions, or other “plan-like” states.
(See Bratman 2002.) By the end of this paper, I hope it will be clear why my sympathies
lie with Watson’s approach, even though I do not endorse his account.
The Possibility of Action 27
14
It is important to distinguish this point from the claim that agents must reflect on
(“foreground”) their desires. The point is that they can reflect on—and call into ques-
tion—what these desires represent as to-be-done. (For a defense of the thesis that desires
are not typically among the things agents take into account, See Pettit and Smith 1990.
28 Sarah Buss
15
Korsgaard is quite explicit about this: “I am going to argue that in the relevant sense
there is no you prior to your choices and actions, because your identity is in a quite literal
way constituted by your choices and actions (Korsgaard 2009: 19).
The Possibility of Action 29
which ensures that the ends associated with our practical impulses are truly
our own. According to the first of the two accounts that endorse this
conception of practical reasons, this means that the criteria for what counts
as a reason for action are the necessary conditions of self-determined
behavior. According to the second account, the criteria are the necessary
conditions of nonobservational knowledge of one’s behavior. If, as I will argue,
we must reject these accounts, then we must reconsider the premises that
appear to support them. We must reconsider the assumption that action is
possible if agents endorse the conception of practical reasons these premises
express.
obligations can figure among their reasons for action. So, too, even if we
less-than-divine rational beings can be divided from ourselves in a way that
enables us to give and take the same orders, most of us are usually
sufficiently identified with the verdicts of our own reason—i.e., these
verdicts are usually sufficiently motivating—to make such assertions of
authority superfluous. For us, too, the thought that our reason permits or
requires a certain course of action is usually one thought too many.
This is, I think, an important objection to the conception of rational
agency as the product of an intrapersonal authority relation. I want, how-
ever, to focus on a deeper problem with what we can call the “authority-
based” conception. To put it bluntly, on this conception of rational agency,
insofar as we are desiring beings, we could not care less about whether the
motivating force of these desires can be attributed to an agent. And so we
could not care less about the fact that in defying the demands of our reason,
we would be sabotaging our agency. And so, we have no motive to obey
these demands. And so, we cannot obey them.
Of course, in describing the possibility of “sabotaging our agency,”
I have been forced to speak about what we would do, and so I have been
forced to imagine a situation in which we are sufficiently unified to perform
various agent-sabotaging acts. But this merely brings home the point that it
is not possible to make sense of action if we posit the division of labor that is
essential to the authority-based account. If, as the authority-based concep-
tion assumes, the laws of our reason and the ends of our desires stand in no
internal relation to each other, then there is no possible way for us to
exercise authority over our desiring selves.
The argument for this claim went by very quickly. I want to rehearse it
again more slowly, beginning with an observation by the person who has
done more than any other philosopher working today to develop and
defend the authority-based account. “If I am to govern myself,” Korsgaard
tells us, “there must be two parts of me, one that is my governing self, my
will, and one that must be governed and is capable of resisting my will”
(Korsgaard 2008: 60). According to this division of labor, the governing
self is the agent insofar as she is identified with her reason, and more
specifically, with whatever formal principles of rationality impose
constraints on which desires she has reason to satisfy. Accordingly, the
governed self—the self on the receiving end of reason’s “laws”—must be the
agent insofar as she is identified with motives that are not grounded in this
commitment.16 And here is where things get tricky. As we have learned
16
Note that these motives could nonetheless be responsive to reasons. Indeed, this
could well be true of even our deepest instinctual desires.
32 Sarah Buss
17
Can my thinking self be alienated from itself? Not in the sense that matters here.
No sooner do I call my contemporaneous normative judgment into question, than it
ceases to be my judgment. No sooner do I disavow a given assessment of the consider-
ations for and against a given action than I endorse a different assessment—if only one
that can be expressed in terms of the disavowal. This having been said, it does seem
possible to be alienated from one’s normative judgments in a different way: one can call
their legitimacy into question, not on normative, but on metaphysical, grounds. This is
the sort of self-alienation familiar from discussions in metaethics.
34 Sarah Buss
18
It is interesting to compare my answer to this question—and, more generally, my
critique of Korsgaard’s account of action as self-constitution—with Tamar Schapiro’s
attempt to make sense of the Kantian thesis that when someone does something
intentionally, she “incorporates” her desire (“inclination”) into her action-guiding
principle. Schapiro notes that insofar as I have an inclination that is not grounded in
my reason, “part of me sees the world through [the] eyes of [this inclination] and
responds to the world [accordingly], and part of me is aware of itself as not being the
source of this way of seeing and responding” (Schapiro 2011: 164). So far, so good. My
point, however, is that if an inclination really is internal to my point of view, then even
though “it has no capacity to demand reason or justification for its way of seeing and
responding to the world” (156), I cannot be indifferent to such demands insofar as I am
the subject of this desire.
The Possibility of Action 35
grounded.19 I am not sure whether this is the only way things could work.
I want, however, to explain what I have in mind in suggesting that
satisfying this condition would suffice to make an intrapersonal authority
relation possible. In so doing, I hope to reinforce the two related lessons
I have just drawn from my discussion of Korsgaard: (1) a genuine
intrapersonal authority relation presupposes that there are facts about
what we have reason to do that are not grounded in our commitment to
acting; and (2) a genuine intrapersonal authority relation requires that in
our capacity as the one who is governed, we are not so alienated from our
governing self that we cannot appreciate any reason for regarding the
demands of the governing self as authoritatively binding.
Suppose, then, that I have reached the conclusion that I have overriding
reason not to eat that second piece of pie. And suppose that I would not
have bothered to employ my reason on this occasion if I had not assumed
that its verdicts would have a greater epistemic authority with respect to
what is really to-be-done than any desire prompted by the close proximity
of the pie. Alas, I might nonetheless persist in desiring to eat that second
piece of pie, and this desire might be stronger than any others. If to be in
this state is to represent the pie as to-be-eaten, then when I am in this state,
I am opposed to being guided by the verdict of my reason(ing). Insofar,
however, as I represent the pie in this way, I cannot dismiss as irrelevant the
belief that it is not to-be-eaten-by-me. And so, I cannot be indifferent to
which of these representations has greater epistemic authority. If, moreover,
I believe that the verdicts of my reason have greater epistemic authority,
then even as I am disposed to act contrary to these verdicts, I am also
disposed to acknowledge the authority of the demand to act otherwise. In
short, precisely because, qua pie-desirer, I am not wholly identified with my
reason, I am in a position to regard the epistemic authority of my own
normative judgments as a distinct reason to grant practical authority to
whatever demands reflect these judgments.
Under the stipulated circumstances, my desire to eat the pie puts me at
odds with myself; it moves me to defy the verdicts of my own reason. To
this extent, I regard the directives that are grounded in these verdicts as
external constraints—even as I am the one who is imposing them. At the
same time, however, since I also regard the directives as coming from a
source that has epistemic authority with respect to the very point at issue
between me and myself (since—rightly or wrongly—even as I desire the
pie, I regard the contemporaneous verdicts of my reason as more likely to
19
I agree with those who reject Raz’s appeal to epistemic authority to account for
relations of practical authority between agents. My suggestion here is that intrapersonal
authority relations are importantly different.
36 Sarah Buss
track the reasons I really have than are any pie-related desires that are not
grounded in my reason20), I assume that I (the person I am insofar as
I employ my reason to figure out what to do) am justified in asserting
practical authority over myself (the person I am insofar as I am not identified
with my reason). And so I regard the directives as authoritatively binding.
I regard these orders as authoritatively binding because I regard them as
reflecting my own superior epistemic position with respect to the very issue
my desire represents as being at stake when it represents the piece of pie as
really, really, really to-be-eaten-by-me.
20
It is important to stress that I could be mistaken about this: sometimes one’s reason
leads one astray. The important point here is that insofar as I am the subject of a certain
normative judgment, I take myself to have reason to rely on it. If I did not believe that the
judgment was reliable, then I would see things differently.
The Possibility of Action 37
21
For the classic discussion of our special epistemic relation to our own actions, See
Anscombe 1957. See also Moran 2001.
40 Sarah Buss
But perhaps this line of questioning misses the point. After all, Velleman’s
comment suggests that what matters is not that we will better understand our
behavior if we understand it in the way that we do when we understand it as
our action. What matters is that we are in a privileged position to ensure that
our behavior will not surprise us. According to Velleman, our beliefs about
what we will do are based on what we know about our behavioral dispos-
itions. Given our desire to understand our behavior, these beliefs will
generally be responsive to what we are motivated to do; and for the same
reason, they will generally be sufficiently motivating for the resulting behav-
ior to make them true. When this happens, it is we who are the behavior’s
determining cause. We are the cause of our behavior because the desire that
causes it would not do so if we thought that this made no sense in light of
everything else we believe and desire. Because the motivating force of the
desire is constrained by our desire for self-understanding, the aim it moves us
to seek is our aim too.
But something still seems missing from this account. In particular: why
would the aspect of myself that is indifferent to reasons be moved to
“accommodate” the “naturally inquisitive” aspect of myself “by enacting
ideas of what it would be intelligible for [me] to do”? (Velleman 2009: 18)
The problem identified here is evident when we take a careful look at
Velleman’s most recent attempt to explain his conception of action as the
product of a cooperative relationship between a rational being (qua
rational) and certain reason-independent behavioral dispositions. In
particular, his use of pronouns reveals that, on his account, it is not
possible for this relationship to qualify as the reflexive self-relation that
only genuine unity/identity will support. Here is a representative passage:
The cognizable object [i.e. the person of whom someone ( = the inquirer) is aware in
being aware of himself and his dispositions] is disposed to instantiate what the
inquirer already understands: it is so disposed because it consists in the inquirer
himself, with his drive toward self-understanding. The inquirer learns that he can make
sense of himself by [his] making sense to himself — that is, by [his] doing what makes
sense to him. (Velleman 2009: 17; the underlined words reflect Velleman’s emphasis)
In this passage, I have used bold type for those pronouns that refer to the
aspect of the person constituted by the contingent behavioral dispositions
that are the objects of the person’s reflection. And I have used italics for
those pronouns that refer to the person insofar as he is the subject of this
reflection, motivated by the desire to understand his behavior. Velleman
asks us to think of the relationship between these two aspects of the pre-
agent as analogous to the relationship between an improvising actor and the
character whose responses to the circumstances the actor is improvising.
Because, he argues, the character and the improviser are one and the same
The Possibility of Action 41
struggling with her groceries; and so, given my desire to find my behavior
intelligible, I will be moved to help her. (Alternatively, the desire for self-
understanding will directly generate the belief that I will help this person,
and this will then generate the desire to help her.)
On this account, action does not require a pre-agent’s nonrational self to
cooperate with her rational self. Accordingly, it does not require the pre-
agent to overcome her alienation from the practical impulses she finds
herself with. No such self-integration is necessary because, on this account,
the aspect of the self from which the subject of self-reflection is alienated is
relegated to the status of a very special feature of her circumstances: it is the
feature of her circumstances that shares with her the power to directly affect
the movements of her body, the feature that shares a body with her. On this
account, integrating oneself with one’s reason-independent practical
impulses is not essential to one’s identity as an agent. So, the self-alienation
that persists is not an impediment to one’s agency (provided, of course, that
one’s beliefs about one’s reason-independent impulses are sufficiently on
target to generate reason-dependent motivations that can exert a decisive
influence on the movements of one’s body). Nonetheless, the fact that, on
this account, every agent is necessarily alienated from herself in this way
seems to be a defect. (Is it really essential to rational agency that a rational
being’s understanding of why her action makes sense is completely inde-
pendent of the way she represents this action to herself insofar as she is the
subject of desires that are not grounded in her reason?)
More importantly, it seems to me that this account is plausible only
insofar as it attributes to rational agents a substantive assumption about
what is really worth doing, independent of their commitment to acting, or
any other commitments they may have. Insofar as my desire to help the
person struggling with her groceries is a response to my desire to under-
stand myself, it is not simply one more disposition I find myself with when
I reflect on the reason-independent constituents of my mind; it is not just
one more mental state for me to take into account in deciding how it would
be intelligible for me to behave. Nor is it simply the disposition to regard
intelligibility as the key to what it is for a fact to be a reason for action. Nor
is it simply the effect of such a disposition. As I have described the case, the
desire to help the person struggling with her groceries is grounded in my
belief that I desire to help people, together with my disposition to regard
the intelligibility of my helping her as a reason to help her—a distinct,
substantive consideration in favor of helping. As far as I can tell, unless my
motivation can be construed in this way, my identity as a rational being
cannot be unified with my identity as the subject of practical impulses in
the way these two identities must be unified if the motivating force of my
impulses is to be attributable to me—the one who is committed to acting
The Possibility of Action 43
The idea that the necessary conditions of action are the ultimate criteria of
practical reasons is a very intriguing one. I have chosen to discuss two
fascinating developments of this idea not only because they are fascinating
(though this certainly played a part in my choice), but, more importantly,
because they represent proposals regarding what rational agency could be if
we assume both that (i) no rational agent qualifies as acting intentionally
simply in virtue of engaging in instrumentally rational, goal-directed
behavior, and that (ii) our reason is not a capacity for discovering mind-
independent facts regarding which substantive goals we have reason to
pursue. I do not know whether there are any alternative accounts of the
source of normativity that are compatible with these conceptual commit-
ments—any alternatives, that is, to (i) an account according to which practical
reasons are grounded in laws whose practical authority is itself grounded in
nothing but the fact that no one can coherently challenge this authority if she is
committed to being the author of her behavior, or (ii) an account according to
which practical reasons are grounded in the constitutive aim of theoretical
reason, and the more specific aim of not being perplexed about why one is
being moved to satisfy a given desire. I strongly suspect, however, that whatever
other options there may be, they will have the same structural defects. They will
presuppose that our identity as rational beings is distinct from our identity as
beings with noninstrumental practical goals. And so they will lack the resources
necessary to make sense of the possibility of rational agency.
Something has gone seriously wrong if agency itself (“constituting one-
self as an agent”) is conceived as the goal of every being with practical
impulses—not, to be sure, a goal that such pre-agents conceive under the
44 Sarah Buss
That is, there must be something about us in our nonrational capacity that
inclines us to cooperate with, or obey, the interests, or demands, that define
us as “rational.” It also means that (6) we cannot be so alienated from
ourselves that the conditions necessary for unifying our normative verdicts
and our nonrational dispositions—the conditions necessary for being an
agent—determine what we have reason to do. In particular, (7) insofar as
our point of view is not constituted by our normative verdicts, we must take
ourselves to have reason to accommodate ourselves to these verdicts, and so
we must take there to be reasons for action that are not grounded in the
conditions necessary for agency.
REFERENCES
Anscombe, G.E. (1957). Intention, 2nd edn. (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press).
Bok, Hilary (1996). “Acting Without Choosing.” Noûs 30 (2): 174–96.
Bratman, Michael (2002). “Hierarchy, Circularity, and Double Reduction.” In
Sarah Buss and Lee Overton (eds.), The Contours of Agency (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press), 65–85.
Brewer, Talbot (2009). The Retrieval of Ethics. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Buss, Sarah (1997). “Weakness of Will.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78: 13–44.
—— (2012). “Autonomous Action: Self-Determination in the Passive Mode.”
Ethics 122: 647–91.
—— “Norms of Rationality and the Superficial Unity of the Mind” (Unpublished
manuscript).
Frankfurt, Harry. (1971). “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” The
Journal of Philosophy LXVIII: 5–20. Reprinted in Frankfurt 1988, 11–25.
—— (1977). “Identification and Externality.” In Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.),
The Identities of Persons (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press). Reprinted
in Frankfurt 1988, 58–68.
—— (1988). The Importance of What We Care About. (New York: Cambridge
University Press).
Hornsby, Jennifer (2004). “Agency and Alienation.” In Mario De Caro and David
Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism in Question (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press), 173–87.
Kant, Immanuel (1956). The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans..
H. J. Paton. (London: Hutchinson & Co).
Korsgaard, Christine (1996). The Sources of Normativity. (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
—— (2007). “Autonomy and the Second Person Within: A Commentary on
Stephen Darwall’s the Second-Person Standpoint.” Ethics 118 (1): 8–23.
—— (2008). “The Normativity of Instrumental Reason.” In The Constitution of
Agency. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 27–68.
46 Sarah Buss
Not all agents are planning agents. There can be goal-directed agents who
do not structure their thought and action over time by way of planning.
Dogs and very young human children are likely examples. Such agents
engage in goal-directed activity in which their behavior tracks a goal—say,
getting a drink of water. And this may involve complex plasticity of
response—a thirsty dog may respond sensibly to your moving the bowl
of water. But it seems unlikely that the dog, or the fifteen-month human,
settles on plans for a temporally extended period, and thinks about and
3 Allan Gibbard sees our capacity for planning agency as at the bottom of normative
thinking (Gibbard 2003). And Scott Shapiro sees law as grounded in our planning
capacities (Shapiro 2011). In these ways both Gibbard and Shapiro aim to extend the
fecundity of planning agency.
4 Bratman 2010. What is central is the claim to provide sufficient conditons for
central cases of these forms of human agency. The conjecture of the fecundity of agency
leaves open the possiblity of multiple such sufficient conditions.
The Fecundity of Planning Agency 49
guides his behavior over time in the light of those plans. Of course, whether
the dog, or the young child, does or does not guide his thought and action
in this plan-infused way is an empirical issue; perhaps psychological
research on these matters will surprise us. But the central point here is
the distinction between, on the one hand, temporally local goal-directed
agency and, on the other hand, plan-guided diachronic agency.5
In planning we take seriously what to do later, as well as what to do now.
But why worry about what to do later? Why not just worry about what to
do now and cross your bridges when you come to them later? The
commonsense answer is that we need to figure out what to do later in
order to figure out what to do now and to coordinate our earlier with our
later activities. Once I settle on going to New Orleans next month it is clear
that I need soon to get an airline ticket. In contrast, if I just ask right now
“should I right now get a ticket to New Orleans for next month?”
I normally cannot sensibly answer without settling on whether to go
there then. In the interest of cross-temporal coordination, I need many
times to settle now what I will do later, and then plan accordingly about
what to do now. In settling now to go to New Orleans next month I come
to be in a plan state that is future-directed. And we understand what such a
plan state is by explaining its role in the rational dynamics of planning
agency.
This pressure in the direction of future-directed planning is especially
acute for resource-limited agents like us.6 We frequently need to settle now
what to do later in part because we cannot reasonably trust that when the
later time arrives we will be able, given the pressures of action, to sort out all
the complexities efficiently and reach a sensible decision from scratch.
In developing this idea of the cross-temporal coordinating role of plan-
ning we need also to do justice to two further, commonsense ideas. The first
is the idea of choice among alternative options each of which would be
sensible—one aspect of, as we might say, the idea of “will.”7 We make such
choices all the time, from different routes to a destination, to different
careers, to the choice made by Sartre’s young man between aiding his
mother and fighting with the Free French.8 And these choices, while
underdetermined by the agent’s view of her reasons, nevertheless settle
relevant practical matters and play central, forward-looking roles in cross-
5 For the idea of planning agency as a species of agency, see my use of Paul Grice’s
strategy of “creature construction.” Grice 1974–5 in Bratman 2007 f.
6 Simon 1983.
7 A second aspect is the idea of willpower. See Holton 2009. And here too, as Holton
argues, the planning theory can be of use.
8 Sartre 1975, 354–6.
50 Michael E. Bratman
temporal coordination. The ability to make choices and settle such matters
seems a basic feature of human agency, one that helps explain why we are not
constantly suffering the plight of Buridan’s ass. This is an ability to make a
transition from a state of indecision between several alternatives, each of
which seems sensible, to a state of being settled on one of those alternatives in
particular. We shed light on this ability by saying more about the output state
of being settled on one of those alternatives in particular. And we understand
this output state in large part in terms of its role in planning agency: to be
settled on an option is, or anyway is closely related to,9 being in a plan state,
where, again, we understand what a plan state is by explaining its role in the
rational dynamics of planning agency. In this way we resist an overly simple
time-slice conception of the will by embedding our account of the will within
a larger model of diachronic planning agency.
There is, second, the very idea of intention. Here we need to be careful to
distinguish adverbial forms—as in “he did it intentionally”—from the verb
“to intend.” The idea that is central here concerns the latter, and the
corresponding phenomenon of intending; and we can allow for a more or
less complex relation between X-ing intentionally and intending to X.10
The central thought here is that to intend to do something is to be in a plan
state, where—again—we understand what a plan state is by explaining its
role in the rational dynamics of planning agency. Intending leads to action
in ways that normally involve diachronic planning structures.
So a model of the rational dynamics, and the associated cross-temporal
coordinating roles, of planning agency would also be a theory of the will and a
theory of intending.11 This promises a deeper understanding of the forward-
looking nature of the will, and of the complex diachronic interconnections
between our thought and our action. And the conjecture of the fecundity of
planning agency is that such a planning model sheds light on the trio of
agential capacities with which we began.
9 This qualification is needed to allow for the complex relation between choice and
intention that I discuss in Bratman 1987, ch. 10.
10 This is where I have argued against the “Simple View” according to which it is
always true that in intentionally A-ing one intends to A. (Bratman 1987, ch. 8). In that
discussion I also considered the “single phenomenon view” according to which when one
intentionally A’s one intends something, though perhaps not, in particular, A. I said that
something like this will be true in “the vast majority of cases,” but I left it open that there
might be marginal cases in which one acts intentionally and yet there is no intention—no
plan-state—involved. (pp. 126–7.) What is important here is the conjecture, built into
the planning theory, that cases of intentional action in which relevant plan states are
completely absent, if such there be, are theoretically marginal for our understanding of
our adult human agency. For a challenge to this conjecture See Velleman 2007.
11 Holton 2009, 5, argues that “there is solid psychological evidence that we have
intentions along something like these lines.”
The Fecundity of Planning Agency 51
3. PLANNING AGENCY
Let me now sketch a model of our individual planning agency that I have
discussed elsewhere.12 We begin with plans of action. Such a plan specifies
ways of acting now and into the future. It ties these ways of acting, together
with what one believes about the world, into a more or less consistent and
coherent web, though a web that will normally be both partial in important
ways and to some extent conditional in structure. To plan to do something
is to be appropriately committed—committed in a distinctive, practical
way—to a plan of action that says to do that. Planning agents are
systematically involved in such commitments to relevant plans, and these
commitments shape their practical thought and action over time.
Intending to do something is, I have said, being committed in the
relevant way to a plan that says to do that (perhaps conditionally). We try
to explain this idea of being appropriately committed to such a plan of
action by appeal to two general ideas. First: we try to characterize the
normal roles—the normal ways of functioning—that are characteristic of
such plan states; and second we try to articulate basic planning norms,
the at-least-implicit acceptance of which by the agent is involved in those
roles.
Begin with these planning norms. Intentions—that is, plan states—are
subject to a characteristic quartet of norms. Intentions are to be internally
consistent and consistent with the agent’s beliefs. It needs to be possible to
agglomerate one’s various intentions together into an overall intention that
is itself consistent and consistent with one’s beliefs. Intentions in favor of
ends engage demands of means-end coherence in the direction of filling
in one’s—normally, partial—plans appropriately, and as time goes by, with
means and preliminary steps.13 And structures of plan states, though
potentially a target of reconsideration, are subject to a norm of stability
over time: there is some sort of defeasible presumption in favor of
one’s prior plan states. In short, there are planning norms of consistency,
agglomeration, means-end coherence, and stability. A planning agent will
at least implicitly accept these norms and this will tend to guide that agent’s
thought and action in ways that support conformity to these norms.
To accept these norms is not simply to be disposed to conform to them.
One is also set to see divergence from these norms as breakdowns, and so to
respond to such cases with a kind of “Darn it!” reaction. One is thereby set
to be guided in the direction of conformity with the norm.14
This norm-guidance is part of the explanation of characteristic roles that
such plan states play. Given the pressure from an accepted planning norm
to avoid means-end incoherence, prior, partial plan states pose problems
about means; and the agent will be set to fill in her plans accordingly. This
will normally induce end-means reasoning that is structured by prior,
partial plans. Given the pressure from accepted planning norms in favor
of agglomeration and consistency, plan states will tend to filter out from
deliberation options intending which would introduce new plan inconsist-
encies. And given the pressure from an accepted planning norm of stability,
a prior intention will tend to persist, other things equal. This persistence
is sometimes a result of the snowball effect: once one begins acting on a
prior plan one changes the world in ways that tend to support continuing
with that plan.15 And sometimes this is because the costs of reconsidering
prior plans—and/or the risks that reconsideration poses of undermining
important coordination previously forged—are too high in the absence of
recognized reasons for change; and a prior plan will tend to persist unless it
is reconsidered.16 But our planning agency also involves, I think, a
distinctive norm of stability that directly says to treat one’s prior plans as
a defeasible default.17
So we have a package of characteristic roles together with associated
norms that are at least implicitly accepted. Such a planning psychology
induces and supports complex forms of temporal organization of thought
and action. And a plan state in this planning psychology can favor a specific
option despite known underdetermination by prior reasons. Once Sartre’s
young man settles, say, on a plan to work with the Free French, demands of
consistency and means-end coherence come to bear and support corres-
ponding forms of temporally downstream functioning. This is true even
though his decision in favor of the Free French was, by his own lights,
underdetermined by his prior reasons. And we can make a similar point
about less dramatic examples of career decisions, or even of different routes
to an intended destination.
If all goes well, planning structures induce cross-temporal referential
connections that are both forward and backward looking. My present
14 For discussion of norm acceptance See Gibbard 1990. See also Railton 2006.
15 See Bratman 1987, 82, where I note that I owe to John Etchemendy the label
“snowball effect.”
16 Yet another potential explanation of this persistence is that we are frequently
guided by habits of nondeliberative nonreconsideration, habits that are, in general,
useful to us.
17 Bratman 2010, 2012.
The Fecundity of Planning Agency 53
plan to paint the house this week at least implicitly refers to my later, then-
present-directed intention to put on the final coat of paint; and that later
intention at least implicitly refers back to my earlier intention. And the
stability of my intention in favor of painting this week helps support a
coordinated flow of activity over time. These cross-temporal referential
interconnections and constancies help support an effective temporally
extended structure of partial plans. These partial plans provide a back-
ground framework for further deliberation about means, deliberation
shaped by accepted norms of coherence, consistency, and agglomeration.
This idea of cross-temporally stable and referentially interlocking atti-
tudes is familiar from the Lockean tradition of understanding personal
identity over time—or, at least, “what matters” in such identity18—by
appeal to overlapping strands of continuities of attitude and referential
connections across attitudes.19 The standard functioning of plan states in
our planning agency involves such broadly Lockean cross-temporal ties.20
Now, in speaking of accepted planning norms I have so far not raised the
question whether these norms do indeed have normative force or signifi-
cance. I have, up till now, only appealed to the explanatory role of their
acceptance in a planning psychology.21 But I do not think we should rest
content simply with such a “positivist” theory of planning agency. There
are two reasons for this. The first is that we ourselves are planning agents:
our theory of planning agency is a theory of our agency. So the question
whether these norms have normative force is one we face in such theorizing.
After all, there are likely many patterns of thought that are pervasive in
human agency as we know it, but which we would not, on reflection,
endorse.22 So we will want to know whether, and if so why, these planning
norms do pass reflective muster. Second, it would be an important
theoretical fact about planning agency if these structures of agency were
indeed robust in the face of reflection on its basic principles. One important
way to ascertain whether our planning agency has such robustness is
directly to ask whether these planning norms really do have normative
force.23 And a positive answer would defuse a concern that the planning
4 . T E M P O R A LL Y E X T E N D E D A G E N C Y
cultivating the garden; one recognizes that this needs to involve relevant
means such as planting the seeds and watering; and so one includes those
means within the plan to which one is practically committed. One’s
practical commitment to this plan involves one’s being set intentionally
to act in these specified ways in the course of following through with one’s
overall plan. In this way our temporally extended intentional activity is an
exercise of our planning capacities.
Michael Thompson has criticized what he calls “the tendency of students
of practical philosophy to view individual human actions as discrete or
atomic or point-like or eye-blink-like units.”27 Now, I think that the
planning theory in my 1987 book is not guilty of this purported tendency:
a central concern of that book was, after all, to understand how planning
rationally supports our temporally extended agency. In the present context
the point is that the first dimension of the fecundity of planning agency—its
support of our capacity for temporally extended intentional agency—
continues to avoid an atomistic tendency that, as I agree with Thompson,
we should avoid.28
5. SHARED AGENCY
Turn now to our capacity for shared intentional activity. The proposal here
is that our capacity for shared intentional activity is grounded in our
individual planning capacities in the sense that the proper functioning of
those planning capacities, given relevant special contents of the plans,
contexts of the plans, and interrelations among the participating planning
agents, would constitute a basic case of shared intentional activity.
As anticipated, this does not mean that simply by having the capacity for
planning agency one thereby has the capacity for shared intentionality. To
get from planning capacities to the capacity for shared intentionality we
need further resources in the form of distinctive contents, contexts, and
interrelations. So there remains the possibility of planning agents who are
not capable of shared intentionality. Indeed, it is some such gap between
planning agency and shared intentionality that Michael Tomasello and his
colleagues have highlighted as a potential key to a fundamental difference
between humans and the great apes.29 Nevertheless, the further resources—
conceptual, metaphysical, and normative—involved in the step from
32 In putting the idea in this way I am signaling an asymmetry. In the individual case
the basic explanation of conformity to the individualistic rationality norms involves the
at-least-implicit acceptance of those very norms by the relevant individuals. In the shared
case, in contrast, the initial explanation of conformity to the cited social norms appeals to
the at-least-implicit acceptance of the norms of individual plan rationality by the relevant
individuals. However, once these interconnected planning structures are on board it may
well be that the individual participants also accept, and are guided by, the social norms
themselves. I discuss these matters in Bratman forthcoming a.
33 Though in special cases there will also be a sense in which the participants
themselves construct the sharing. The theoretical construction I am envisaging would
be a part of a larger strategy of Gricean creature construction.
34 See e.g. the quartet of essays on this subject in Bratman 1999a, Bratman 2009c,
and Bratman forthcoming a.
35 I also think we need the idea that each intends that we paint by way of his own
intention that we paint. But to keep things more manageable I put aside here this
condition of reflexivity.
58 Michael E. Bratman
each intends that the joint activity proceed by way of the relevant intention
of the other participant, and by way of associated mutual responsiveness
between the intentions and actions of the participants. And this intended
mutual responsiveness will need to involve mesh between the relevant sub-
plans of each.
A fourth observation concerns the condition that all this is out in the
open.39 A central reason for this condition is that we want to model a kind
of shared reasoning that is characteristic of shared intention, namely: shared
reasoning about how to carry out our shared intention to paint the house
together.
I leave it as an open question whether the relevant idea of “out in the
open” goes somewhat beyond the conceptual resources of our theory of
individual planning agency. Except for that possible qualification, however,
I think that the conceptual, metaphysical, and normative resources at work
in this proposed construction are within the domain of the resources of our
theory of individual planning agents: the construction is conceptually,
metaphysically, and normatively conservative.
The basic conjecture, then, is that these interdependent and interlocking
intentions of each, taken together with the cited beliefs and in a public
context, will, in responding to the rational pressures associated with indi-
vidual planning agency, function in ways that constitute the social-norm-
conforming social functioning of shared intention. So this structure of
interdependent and interlocking intentions constitutes at least one central
form of shared intention.
In partial support of this basic conjecture, note that we are supposing
that each intends the joint painting by way of the other’s intention, mutual
responsiveness, and meshing sub-plans. It is not just that each intends his
part and merely expects the other to play her part.40 This means that the
rational pressure on each to make her own plans coherent and consistent
ensures rational pressure on each to support the success of the joint activity
and the meshing role of the other in that activity. Given my intention that
we paint by way of your intention, mutual responsiveness, and meshing
sub-plans, I am under rational pressure to coordinate with you, to support
your role—perhaps by way of helping actions—and to avoid ways of acting
39 It is here that talk of common knowledge and/or mutual belief is potentially apt.
40 This contrasts with a case in which each only intends his own activity while
expecting the others to perform their part, and the social organization is out-sourced
to some external managerial group. In such a case the participants will not each be
committed to the joint activity in a way that is normally involved in shared deliberation
about how to proceed. (Scott Shapiro discusses large-scale versions of this latter sort of
case in Shapiro forthcoming.)
60 Michael E. Bratman
that are incompatible with all that. And given your analogous intention,
you too are under analogous rational pressures. These rational pressures on
each, given these distinctive contents and interrelations, induce pressures
in the direction of social coherence and consistency, and associated
coordination and effectiveness, pressures that are characteristic of shared
intentionality.
This approach to shared intentionality highlights conceptual, metaphys-
ical and normative continuities with individual planning agency. This
contrasts with views that see the step to shared intentionality as necessarily
involving a basic new conceptual and/or metaphysical and/or normative
resource. For example, John Searle thinks that shared intentionality
involves a special kind of “we-intention” in the heads of the individual
participants. We-intentions, on Searle’s view, are distinctive attitudes, not
to be identified with ordinary intentions that concern our own activity.41
Again, Margaret Gilbert thinks that shared intentionality involves a
primitive interrelation of “joint commitment” between the participants,
an interrelation that essentially involves distinctive nonmoral obligations.42
Without pausing to examine the details of either of these views, we can say
that if the plan-theoretic model I have proposed does succeed in providing
sufficient conditions for shared intentionality,43 then the burden of proof
is on both Searle and Gilbert to explain why we also need these new
primitives.44
6 . SE LF - GO V E R N AN C E
41 Searle 1990.
42 Gilbert 2009.
43 What about the obligations that are commonly present in cases of shared intention
and shared intentional action? On the plan-theoretic model these will normally be
familiar moral obligations, such as an obligation to follow through with an assurance,
or in accordance with reliance that is intentionally induced.
44 As Michael Smith noted in conversation.
45 I put to one side other possible ways in which certain considerations can matter.
The Fecundity of Planning Agency 61
46 Bratman 2007b. This general approach—though not the details—is in the spirit of
work of Harry Frankfurt. See Frankfurt 1988a and 1999a. (An important difference is
my emphasis on the role of these commitments to weights in deliberation.) Concerning
the agent’s guidance, see Velleman 1992.
47 Bratman 2007e, 151–4.
48 Velleman 1992, 472.
49 Bennett 1974, Arpaly and Schroeder 1999, and Driver, 2001, ch. 3.
50 Gibbard, 1990, ch. 4. The example to follow comes from Gibbard’s discussion.
51 See Harman 2000b, 129.
62 Michael E. Bratman
52 Frankfurt 2006.
53 Bratman 2007b, 233–8.
54 Bratman 2007e, 153. Since these plan-like commitments to weights will normally
have an important generality, I have called them self-governing policies; and I have also
emphasized that they will include policies about the significance of one’s own desires
and/or what those desires are for. See Bratman 2007b and, 2007c. There are important
similarities between my appeal to policies about weights and Alan Gibbard’s appeal to
plans “of ‘treating R as weighing in favor of doing X’,” in Gibbard 2003, 189. Gibbard’s
main concern is his metaethical proposal that judgments about normative reasons are
expressions of such plans. My main concern is with the role of such plan states in self-
governance.
The Fecundity of Planning Agency 63
What explains why such plan-like commitments speak for the agent55
and are such that when they guide the agent governs? I have said that the
agent’s practical standpoint serves as an anchor for deliberation, and so
guidance by this standpoint is a form of governance. But I have also alluded
to other roles of that standpoint, roles that help support the idea that when
it guides the agent governs. What roles are these?
Here my proposal is to embed the role of anchor in deliberation within
the overall role of knitting together in distinctive ways the agent’s practical
thought and action, both synchronically and diachronically. What ways?
Well, what we learn from broadly Lockean approaches to personal identity
over time is that there is a close connection between such personal iden-
tity—or, anyway, “what matters” in such identity—and overlapping
strands of continuities of attitudes at different times, and cross-reference
among attitudes at different times. If certain attitudes that anchor delibera-
tive thought had the role of knitting together thought and action in these
broadly Lockean ways—in ways that essentially involve such diachronic
continuities and cross-references—these attitudes would organize that
agent’s life over time and thereby help constitute the cross-temporal iden-
tity56 of the agent whose life thereby has this organization. And my
proposal is that it is in playing this role of anchoring deliberation in ways
that constitute and support such broadly Lockean cross-temporal
organization of one’s thought and action that, in the absence of relevant
conflicts,57 an attitude speaks for that agent.58
And now the point is that plan-like commitments to weights do indeed
realize these “design specifications”: they anchor deliberation in ways that
involve these broadly Lockean roles in the diachronic organization of the
agent’s practical life. This follows from the content of these commit-
ments—namely, what is to have weight in deliberation—together with
the general theory of the nature of plan states. Given their distinctive
contents these plan-like commitments can provide premises about weights,
premises that shape deliberation. And plan states organize our thought and
action over time in Lockean ways. So there is a case for the idea that these
plan-like commitments to weights, in the absence of relevant conflicts, do
indeed speak for the agent. When plan-like commitments to weights
function properly, they weave together the agent’s practical thought and
55 As I once put it, why do these commitments have “agential authority”? See
Bratman 2007d.
56 Or anyway, “what matters” in such identity.
57 This appeal to the absence of relevant conflict draws on Harry Frankfurt’s idea of
satisfaction in Frankfurt 1999b; and See Bratman 2007c, esp. 34–5, 44.
58 A related idea is in Yaffe 2000, ch. 3.
64 Michael E. Bratman
Return now to the norms of individual plan rationality. Let’s focus on the
synchronic norms of consistency, agglomeration, and means-end coher-
ence. And here reflection on the fecundity of planning agency gives us
something to say about the force of these norms. After all, accepting and
being guided by these norms is, on the theory, part and parcel of being a
planning agent. Planning agency is fecund in the sense that it helps support,
inter alia, important forms of temporally extended, shared, and self-
governed agency. And, I take it that we sensibly value these forms of agency:
they significantly enrich our lives. This means that we have good reason to
value being a planning agent, and so to value our continued acceptance of
these norms. Giving up these planning structures, if we could, would
cascade through our lives and come at a high price.
This is a broadly pragmatic rationale for continuing to be a planning
agent, and so for continuing to accept these synchronic norms—in a sense
of “pragmatic” that includes both instrumental and noninstrumental rela-
tions between such planning agency and what we sensibly value. This
pragmatic support for our continued acceptance of these planning norms
does draw on a form of instrumental reasoning; but it need not draw
specifically on the norm of means-end coherence of intentions that is
among the norms it seeks to support. So there need be no circle.
There remains, however, a problem, one familiar from J. J. C. Smart’s
concerns about “rule worship.”60 Even if there are significant advantages
that accrue to the acceptance of these general synchronic norms, it seems
that there can still be particular occasions in which one does better—better
as judged by the very values to which our pragmatic argument appeals—by
65 This is not to say that ought works this way. Nevertheless, there are hard issues that
I cannot discuss here about this proposed principle.
66 Bratman 2009b. Compare David Copp’s thought that “rationality is in the service
of self-government” (Copp 2007, 351), and Kenneth Stalzer’s thought that means-end
incoherence is a failure of “self-fidelity.” (Stalzer 2004, ch. 5).
67 I discuss a related idea of self-reinforcement, in the context of a discussion of views
of David Gauthier, in Bratman forthcoming b.
68 Thanks to the participants at the 2011 New Orleans Workshop on Agency and
Responsibility. Special thanks to David Shoemaker both for his deft organization of the
workshop and for his helpful comments on an earlier draft.
The Fecundity of Planning Agency 67
REFERENCES
Arpaly, Nomy and Schroeder, Timothy (1999). “Praise, Blame and the Whole
Self,” Philosophical Studies 93, 161–88.
Bennett, Jonathan (1974). “The Conscience of Huckleberry Finn.” Philosophy 49,
123–34.
Bratman, Michael E. (1987). Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press; reissued 1999 by CSLI Publications).
—— (1999a). Faces of Intention (New York: Cambridge University Press).
—— (1999b). “I Intend that We J.” In Bratman, 1999a, 142–61.
—— (2007a). Structures of Agency: Essays (New York: Oxford University Press).
—— (2007b). “Three Theories of Self-Governance.” In Bratman, 2007a,. 222–53.
—— (2007c). “Reflection, Planning, and Temporally Extended Agency.” In
Bratman, 2007a, 21–46.
—— (2007d). “Two Problems About Human Agency.” In Bratman, 2007a,.
89–105.
—— (2007e). “A Desire of One’s Own.” In Bratman, 2007a, 137–61.
—— (2007f). “Valuing and the Will.” In Bratman, 2007a, 47–67.
—— (2009a). “Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical.” In Robertson (ed.), 2009,
29–61.
—— (2009b). “Intention, Practical Rationality, and Self-Governance.” Ethics 119,
411–43.
—— (2009c). “Modest Sociality and the Distinctiveness of Intention.” Philosophical
Studies 144, 149–65.
—— (2010). “Agency, Time, and Sociality,” Proceedings and Addresses of the
American Philosophical Association 84, 7–26.
—— (2012). “Time, Rationality, and Self-Governance,” Philosophical Issues
(Action Theory) 22.
—— (Forthcoming a). Shared Agency (New York: Oxford University Press).
—— (Forthcoming b). “The Interplay of Intention and Reason,” Ethics.
Broome, John (2007). “Is Rationality Normative?” Disputatio 2, 161–78.
Cohen, Philip R., Morgan, Jerry, and Pollack, Martha E. (eds.) (1990). Intentions in
Communication (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Copp, David (2007). Morality in a Natural World (New York: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press).
Davis, Wayne (1984). “A Causal Theory of Intending.” American Philosophical
Quarterly 21, 43–54.
Driver, Julia (2001). Uneasy Virtue (New York: Cambridge University Press).
Ferrero, Luca (2009). “What Good is a Diachronic Will?” Philosophical Studies 144,
403–30.
Foot, Philippa (ed.) (1967). Theories of Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press).
Frankfurt, Harry G. (1988a). The Importance of What We Care About (New York:
Cambridge University Press).
68 Michael E. Bratman
Luca Ferrero
1. INTRODUCTION
1.1
The possible objects of one’s desires and wishes seem to be virtually
unlimited: one might desire unattainable states of affairs including,
perhaps, even known logical impossibilities. By contrast, the proper
objects of one’s intentions appear to be much more limited. As Baier
(1976: 214) writes: “My intentions must not only be ‘made’ by me, when
I make up my mind, they must be directed upon, they must concern,
my own future actions.” It seems that the agent can only intend to do
something herself : intentions appear to be necessarily de actu suo (Wilson
1989).
This restriction on the proper object of intentions is reflected in the
grammar of attributions of intention: an agent is usually said “to intend to
do such-and-such.” The syntactical complement of attributions of
intention is usually an infinitival verb phrase whose subject is implicitly
understood to be the very agent of that intention. Although it is not
ungrammatical to say that an agent S intends that p be the case, it seems
that the propositional complement “that p” should be interpreted as
making implicit reference to the agent’s own action. That is, “S intends
that p” is elliptical for “S intends to do what it takes for her to bring about
that p.”
This restriction on the admissible objects of intentions—which some-
times goes under the name of the “own action condition”—suggests
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 71
that there is a special relationship between an agent, her intentions, and her
own actions.1 The own action condition (OAC, hereafter) might strike the
reader as trivial, in the sense of both obviously true and uninteresting.
Nonetheless, this thesis has not gone utterly uncontested.2 In addition,
many philosophers claim that the status of OAC bears on important issues
in the philosophy of agency. For instance, according to both Thompson
(2008) and Setiya (2011) a proper characterization of the relation between
intentions and actions depends on the fate of OAC. Boyle and Lavin
(2010) defend OAC as central to their rejection of causal theories of
action and their defense of the “guise of the good” thesis. Finally, OAC
matters for the characterization of shared intentions in joint agency (See
Bratman 1997 and Stoutland 2002).
Hence, in spite of its apparent triviality, OAC is worth a closer look. In
fact, in this paper I will argue against it: the genuine object of intentions is
neither necessarily nor primarily restricted to the agent’s own actions.
Although the agent’s own agency plays a necessary role in carrying out her
intentions, this role is not reflected in the restriction of the intention’s objects
to her own actions. The object of an intention is not necessarily cast in the
infinitival/agential form—“I intend to do so-and-so.” The more inclusive
propositional clause—“I intend that such-and-such”—is actually the proper
characterization of the logical form of intentions. Or so I will argue.3
1.2
I will begin with some preliminary considerations on the notion of the
object of an attitude in general (Section 2). I will then discuss how to
characterize the content of a simpler kind of practical attitude, which
I call “aiming.” I will argue that OAC does not hold of aimings (Section 3).
Then I will move to intentions and show that the features that make them
different from aimings are not sufficient to support the application of OAC
to intentions (Section 4). I will then consider whether one’s own actions
might still be taken to be the standard although not necessary object of
1
OAC is defended by Baier (1970: 650), Meiland (1970), Castañeda (1972: 140),
Castañeda (1975: 25, 169–75), Baier (1976: 214), Searle (1983: 100, 105), Gustafson
(1986: 104, 121, 204), Wilson (1989), Perloff (1991: 403), Velleman (1997), Stoutland
(2002), Thompson (2008: 120–3, 127–8, 130–1), Moran and Stone (2009: 143, 147).
2
See Bratman (1997), Tuomela (2005), Setiya (2011).
3
In this paper, I use “propositional” as an umbrella term that covers various possible
characterizations of content—whether in terms of propositions, sentences, states of
affairs, and the like. For present purposes, what matters is only the contrast between
the characterization in broadly conceived propositional terms and the one in the agential/
infinitival form.
72 Luca Ferrero
intention. I will argue that although one’s own actions might play a
prominent role they do not do so as distinct pieces of conduct and separate
targets of one’s intentions (Section 5). Finally, I will consider the different
degrees to which one’s own agency might be involved in intentions. I will
claim that one’s own agency is necessarily involved but in a way that is
formal and generic, and as such lends no support to OAC (Section 6).
Space constraints prevent me from discussing how my conclusions bear on
the various philosophical disputes that invoke the fate of OAC but for the
discussion of the distinction between intending and acting. I will argue that
my rejection of OAC puts pressure on the tenability of a stark distinction
between intending and acting. This is a somewhat surprising development
of the standard dialectic, since this substantive claim is usually supported
on the basis of the acceptance of OAC (5.8).
2.1
Talk of the “object” or “content” of an intention is not as straightforward as
it might appear. Grammatically speaking, the object is the syntactic com-
plement of expressions of intention, but what we are interested in here is
rather the object as the complement of the logical form of intentions.
Before investigating this logical form, however, we need to make some
preliminary considerations about the notion of the content of attitudes in
general and various notions of the conditions of satisfaction or success of an
attitude.
Let’s begin with the simpler case of belief. Take the belief that p. The
content of this belief—the proposition p—individuates the attitude. It
differentiates this particular belief from other beliefs, such as the belief
that q. (This individuating content is also something that can be “shared”
with attitudes of a different kind, for instance, the desire that p, the
assumption that p, etc.) The individuating content of a belief also seems
to indicate its conditions of success: the belief that p succeeds as a belief when
p obtains.
At first, it seems that the same holds true of practical attitudes. Consider
the desire that p. The proposition p individuates it by differentiating from
other particular desires. In addition, a desire that p is satisfied—succeeds as
a desire—only when p obtains. Likewise for intentions. The object of the
intention (whether characterized in infinitival or propositional terms)
seems to both individuate a particular intention and indicate its conditions
of success.
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 73
These considerations, however, are too hasty since they do not pay
attention to the different senses in which an attitude can be successful.
First, an attitude is constitutively successful when it meets the standards
that govern the acquisition, retention, and abandonment of attitudes of its
kind. For instance, beliefs are regulated by the standards of veridicality: the
belief that p is constitutively successful when p is true. This explains why
the obtaining of the conditions of individuation of a belief coincides with
the obtaining of its conditions of “constitutive” success.
This coincidence, however, might not hold of other attitudes: conditions
of constitutive success need not be the same as the attitude’s individuating
content. For instance, assumptions are not regulated by veridicality: the
assumption that p is individuated by p but, unlike the belief that p, it might
be constitutively successful even if p is false.
Something similar holds of desires. The constitutive standards of desires
are those of “desirability”: one is supposed to acquire, retain, and abandon a
desire in light of the “desirability” of its content—whatever that turns out
to be according to the substantive accounts of the nature of desires. The
desire that p can be constitutively successful even if p does not obtain and
never will. The obtaining of p, however, matters for a different kind of
success, the desire’s fulfillment or satisfaction.
2.2
The satisfaction of a desire is a form of success distinctive of practical attitudes,
but it is not to be confused with another kind of practical success, the
“achievement” as the success of executive attitudes. An executive attitude, such
as an intention, is an attitude that moves the agent toward a goal. When the
agent has an executive attitude aimed at the state of affairs g, the mere obtaining
of g is not sufficient for the attitude’s executive success. The obtaining of g does
not count as an achievement if g comes about independently of the attitude or
via its deviant operation (although the agent’s non-executive desire that g,
which might accompany the executive attitude toward g, can still be success-
ful—in the sense of “satisfied”—no matter how g comes about).
Thus, for executive attitudes like intentions, there are three kinds of
conditions: (i) of individuation (formulated in terms of the goal g ), (ii) of
constitutive success (to be met in order for the agent to be correct in having
that attitude), (iii) of executive success (the non-deviant obtaining of g by
way of the proper operation of the executive attitude). The distinction is
not simply between these notions but also between the substantive condi-
tions: the goal g might individuate the attitude, but its obtaining is neither
necessary for constitutive success nor sufficient for the executive one.
74 Luca Ferrero
The difference between these conditions matters for the attitude’s logical
form. Talk of its “object” should be cast in terms of individuating content.
The conditions of individuation are those that matter for the discussion of
restrictions on the proper objects of an attitude. Considerations about
constitutive and executive success pertain instead to discussions about
kinds of attitudes. They matter for the understanding of the distinctive
operation of attitude-types—their distinctive mode or force—rather than
the content of their tokens.
It can be quite tempting to conflate the different conditions, especially
when talking about the objects of attitudes. Particularly dangerous is the
nowadays common philosophical talk of the attitudes’ aims. This expres-
sion when properly used indicates what regulates attitudes as a matter of
their constitutive conditions (for instance, to say that beliefs aim at truth is
to single out veridicality as their constitutive standard). This “constitutive
aim,” however, should not be confused with the “individuating aim” of
particular executive attitudes, that is, with the particular goal g that the
agent has when she is set on a particular pursuit. Only executive attitudes
have individuating aims, since having aims in this sense is what makes them
executive. (Additionally, executive attitudes are also under conditions of
executive success and, as a result, there might be a sense in which they “aim”
at achievement but the target of this aiming is not to be confused with the
substantive goal that provides their individuating content—see 5.7.)
3. AIMING
3.1
Before discussing whether OAC holds of intentions, let’s consider whether
it is true of a simpler kind of executive attitude, which I call “aiming.”
Aiming is the distinctive attitude of the basic form of representational
agency. When an agent aims at a state of affairs g, she has g as her goal,
that is, she is set on making g true in light of her representation of it.
The pursuit of g by aiming at it consists of the combined exercise of
several executive powers.
1. Power of self-motion. The subject as a whole is the source of its conduct
(the conduct is not the mere product of external forces or uncoordinated
operations of the subject’s subsystems).4
4
See Frankfurt (1978), Burge (2009).
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 75
2. Power to represent the goal and orient one’s conduct in view of it.5
3. Power to respond to interferences by (i) adjusting conduct in the face of
perturbations and (ii) persisting in the pursuit in the face of some
setbacks.
4. Practical ingenuity and opportunism: the ability to take advantage of
favorable conditions, including: (a) refraining from interfering with
advantageous courses of events, (b) reliance on other agents, (c) explor-
ation of novel ways to progress toward the goal.
5. Two-way powers. The exercise of executive powers might not be merely
reactive : the subject might not simply react automatically and in fixed
ways. It might respond to circumstances in light of its perception of or
belief about the fit between its response and the circumstances, rather
than being simply triggered by them (See Kenny 1992: 70).
Some of these powers might be exercised in isolation from each other and,
as such, underpin even simpler forms of agency. In addition, agents might
have these powers in domain-specific forms and exert them with different
degrees (if any) of conceptual sophistication and reflection. Nonetheless,
I contend that some combination of these powers, even if in the absence of
conceptual sophistication and reflection, is constitutive of basic goal-
directed agency, of the agency exhibited in “aiming.”
3.2
A particular aiming is individuated in terms of its goal g, the state of
affairs toward which the aiming is executively directed. When g obtains
nondeviantly by way of the combined operation of executive powers
constitutive of aiming, the aiming at g is executively successful—it achieves g.
The conditions of executive success are not part of the individuating
content, of the goal g: when one aims at g, one is orienting the executive
capacities toward making the states of affairs g obtain. One is not orienting
them toward “the bringing about of g in a nondeviant manner and by way
of this very aiming.” The nondeviant bringing about of g is not the
individuating goal of the attitude. Rather it spells out what aiming consists
in as an attitude kind. Hence, it needs to be spelled out only when
articulating the characteristic force of aiming as a kind, rather than the
distinction between token aimings.
5
The orientation might be minimal: it requires neither a plan toward g, nor the
representation of g as a goal. At bottom, it amounts to the capacity of taking instrumental
steps and registering one’s progress toward g (at least, registering when g obtains so as to
stop its pursuit).
76 Luca Ferrero
3.3
Limiting the content of the simpler form of goal-directed agency to one’s
own actions is overly restrictive. Although it is possible to aim just at one’s
own actions, this restriction does not seem supported by reflection on the
operation of goal-directed agency. Executive capacities can be oriented
toward goals quite remote from the agent’s own actions, that is, from the
agent’s exercises of these capacities. As long as the cognitive and concep-
tual abilities allow for it, the agent’s goals can extend as far as the remote
consequences of her actions, including the results of her omissions, the
actions of other agents, and the effects of other agents’ actions. That a
state of affairs g might obtain either by omission or the mediation of
others’ actions does not make it illegitimate as a goal.
A state of affairs qualifies as a goal as long as it can provide suitable
orientation for the exercise of executive capacities. There might be limita-
tions on how remote the object might be to qualify as a goal rather than the
object of a wish. But this is a concern with the upper boundary of aiming’s
possible objects, which puts no pressure on restricting acceptable goals to
the lower boundary of the agent’s own actions.
These considerations rule out OAC for aimings. If, as I maintain, talk of
the object of an attitude should be interpreted in terms of individuating
content, and an aiming’s individuating content is its goal, then the object of
aimings cannot be restricted to the agent’s own actions.
One might try to reject this conclusion by interpreting talk of the aiming’s
“object” in terms of what is especially relevant in the attitude’s psychological
operation rather than in its individuating content. For instance, one might
argue that the main focus of the exercise of one’s executive capacities in the
aiming at g is not the (explicit) representation of g but of the instrumental
actions to be taken toward it. And one might continue with the claim that the
object of an attitude is to be equated with the content of this focus. But this
suggestion is problematic. It is not sufficiently systematic and comprehensive.
First, the focus of the psychological operation of aimings might vary widely;
second, oftentimes the remote goal rather than the means seems to be at the
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 77
center of one’s attention (this is especially so, I surmise, for the simpler
executive attitudes like aimings).6 In addition, even if the goal is not the
focus of orientation, it is hard to deny that it plays some role in the actual
psychological operation of aimings.
3.4
To reject OAC for aimings is not to deny that they display important de se
features: these features can be found both (i) in the ownership and exercise
of executive capacities, and (ii) in the path toward the achievement of g.
First, the immediate exercise of the executive powers that underpins the
agent’s aiming cannot but be the agent’s own. For it is constitutive of the
subject’s identity as an agent that she is the locus of this immediate exercise.
This is an instance of a more general phenomenon: the fundamental de se
involvement that characterizes the existence and identity of subjects as
separate loci of individual psychologies. A subject is none other than the
locus of the unmediated exercise of psychological powers, including the
executive ones (See Burge 2000).
Second, the path toward achievement originates in the agent. Execution
originates in the agent and proceeds from her: from her specific location
in space and time and from her point of view on her surroundings. In
addition, execution is subjected to the limitations imposed by the agent’s
present executive powers and circumstances. In this sense, execution is
always ego-centered and perspectival.
These features do not entail that the object of one’s aiming should be
restricted to the exercise of one’s executive capacities. Execution is neces-
sarily ab se, but its object/target need not be de se.
The psychological work is, ultimately, always of one’s own. For the
subject of this working is nothing other than the locus of the unmediated
psychological operations. This is not to say that one’s executive attitudes
are either exclusively or primarily oriented toward these operations or
their immediate effects. The distal and outward-looking orientation of
aiming is rather a manifestation of the proper operation of goal-directed
agency.
The ab se character of execution does not bear directly on the object of
executive attitudes, but it matters for determining the conditions of both
executive and constitutive success. First, executive success can only be
secured via the initial and unmediated exercise of one’s executive capacities.
6
The focus of the psychological operation on instrumental steps might affect the
content of intentions as more complex executive attitudes; see plans-as-recipes in 4.5.
78 Luca Ferrero
3.5
To sum up: the discussion of aiming shows that there are fundamental de se
elements in the location and working of executive attitudes. But these elem-
ents do not necessarily make the content of these attitudes to be exclusively
or primarily about one’s own actions: the admissible goals of aimings are
7
My claims concern the logical form not the metaphysics of executive attitudes. It might
well be that possessing an executive attitude amounts to nothing more than a disposition to
or the actual exercise of certain immediate executive capacities.
8
Compare the case of the driver going downhill in Frankfurt (1988).
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 79
4. INTENTION
4.1
Let’s return to intentions. Intentions are executive attitudes. They are
considerably more complex than aimings, but does this difference affect
their logical form and support OAC?
Intentions differ from aimings in four ways:
1. Intentions are under distinctive rational pressures for stability and
agglomeration, whereas aimings are not rationally criticizable when
unstable or unagglomerable (See Bratman 1987).
2. Intentions extend the temporal reach of agency, by allowing the pursuit
of very distal goals and engagement in temporally extended and
“unified” activities (See Ferrero 2009b).
3. Full-fledged intentional agency usually goes together with more sophis-
ticated conceptual capacities. It is the agency characteristic of agents
who are (a) able to articulate their goals and their plans to reach them,
(b) in the business of both offering and asking for folk-psychological
explanations, and (c) capable of at least some reflection about their
agency and psychology.
4. Intentions are planning attitudes (Bratman 1987): (a) they frame further
deliberation and help coordinate conduct over time (in part by fixing
expectations about future conduct); (b) they often come with plans as
(partial and hierarchical) recipes that list some of the steps to be taken
toward one’s goal.
None of these distinctive features of intentions support OAC. This is easy to
show for the first two features. First, the rational pressures on the intention
do not concern the form of their individuating content. Likewise for the
temporal reach of agency. It does not affect the content’s form, although it
allows for the pursuit of more complex and distal substantive goals.
4.2
Perhaps, one might devise a way to support OAC starting from the de se
character of the alleged self-referential nature of intentions, which relates to
the third feature of intentions, their alleged conceptual sophistication.
80 Luca Ferrero
9
See Searle (1983: 85), Harman (1986: 86), Harman (1993: 141).
10
This confusion underlies the “content satisfaction view” used by Searle (1983) to
support self-referentiality. According to him, the content of an attitude should be
equated with its conditions of satisfaction. But as shown above (2.2), the idea of
satisfaction/success is ambiguous. The content satisfaction view seems to work for
some attitudes, such as beliefs and (nonexecutive) desires—the content of beliefs
happens to correspond to the conditions of their constitutive success; the content of
desires happens to correspond to the conditions of their success as satisfaction. But this
equivalence is accidental; there is no principled reason to think that it holds of attitudes
in general, let alone of executive attitudes given that the conditions of constitutive and
executive success of executive attitudes are much more complex than their individuating
content. (My point here is stronger than the one made by Mele (1987: 316–17), who
only claims that the content satisfaction view does not hold of intentions but might be
fine for beliefs and desires.)
11
See the criticisms of Mele (1992: 204–6), Kapitan (1995: 154, fn. 8), Roth (2000),
and Harman’s (1993: 145) acknowledgment of the problem. In addition, Kapitan
(1995: 163) correctly remarks that the efficacy of intending does not seem to depend
on the representation in its content of the conditions of its success.
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 81
4.3
Consider now the last distinctive feature: the planning character of inten-
tions. Their role in framing and coordinating deliberation and conduct
does not concern their content. But the plan-as-recipe component does. An
agent might not simply intend to pursue a goal g but to pursue it by way of
a plan-as-recipe r ; that is, she might pursue g guided by a specification of
some of the steps that she expects to take toward it. The intention with a
plan-as-recipe plays a somewhat different role in organizing the agent’s
deliberation and conduct than an intention directed at the same goal
without a plan or via a different one. To this extent, the recipe is part of
the individuating content of the intention.
However, this qualification of the content does not support OAC. First,
the change does not restrict the goal, which still needs not to be formulated
in terms of one’s own actions. Second, a recipe need not be formulated in
terms of the agent’s own actions. Sometimes it only specifies intermediate
nonagential goals on the way to g.
4.4
Putting these considerations together, we might conclude that none of the
ways in which intentions differ from aimings make a difference to the
12
A conceptually sophisticated agent might have second-order intentions about the
efficacy of her first-order intentions. For instance, she might become aware of failures of
her executive capacities and address them by intending to improve her rate of executive
success. By engaging in the self-policing of her executive capacities, she acquires new
goals that make reference to the role of her intentions in securing executive success. But
she does not thereby change the content of her first-order intentions. In addition, the
second-order intentions about the success of one’s first-order intention do not have as a
goal the securing of their own conditions of executive success (if not in the indirect sense
in which they themselves might benefit from the self-policing of executive capacities that
the second-order intentions might put in place).
82 Luca Ferrero
4.5
The only modification to the logical form warranted by the distinctive
features of intentions is the introduction of a recipe component. Some
intentions have the following form:
(I+r) S intends that: (by way of r) g
where r stands for a plan-as-recipe, the specification of some of the instru-
mental steps that the agent expects to take in the pursuit of g.13
The recipe’s instrumental character is indicated by the parenthesis.
Unless r is entirely composed of necessary means to g, it is possible
genuinely to achieve g even if the agent does not follow the recipe (not to
be confused with the accidental or deviant obtaining of g, which does not
count as an achievement). In this sense, the agent might be executively
13
For a similar suggestion about the role of plan components in the content of
intentions, see Mele (1987: 326).
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 83
successful in carrying out the more generic intention (I) directed at the
same goal but without the specification of a plan of action. (For recipes that
are partly constitutive of the goal and incorporated into it, see 5.4.)
4.6
To sum up, in this section, I argued that there are no differences in logical
form and the de se involvement between simpler aimings and intentions.
Aimings and intentions share these features in virtue of their common
executive character. Their only differences concern (a) the rational norms
that govern them and the specific ways in which the executive powers are
called upon to meet these norms; (b) the possible presence of the recipe
component in intentions. None of these differences, however, support
OAC for intentions.
5.1
Rejecting OAC does not imply that one’s own actions might not be the
object of one’s intentions. One might actually argue that they are the
paradigmatic objects at least of future-directed intentions, which ordinarily
seem directed at one’s own future actions. A future-directed intention to ç
at f seems to have as its genuine object the action of ç-ing, which is to be
initiated at the future time f and whose inception marks the transition
from the mere intending to ç to the actual ç-ing.
This reading might seem obvious at first, but it needs to be handled
carefully since it might induce a misleading picture of the relation between
intending and acting, a picture that exaggerates their differences by taking
the intention to be directed at the action as a truly distinct piece of conduct.
This distinction is perfectly in order when an agent intends that another
agent does something. For one intends that the other agent acquires a
separate intention and carries it out successfully as a matter of a separate
course of action. But as I am going to argue, a similar distinction is
problematic for ordinary intentions directed at one’s own actions.
In this section, I will discuss how best to understand the relation between
an intention to ç and one’s ç-ing. This discussion will reinforce my case
against the OAC but also offer a diagnosis of its intuitive appeal. In
addition, it will allow a more fine-grained characterization of the de se
elements of intention.
84 Luca Ferrero
5.2
As soon as one acquires the intention that g, one puts oneself under various
rational pressures, including the continuous demand to secure the possibil-
ity of eventual success and, when appropriate, to make actual progress
toward it. What is specifically required to meet these demands depends
on one’s particular circumstances (including one’s present and expected
skills, opportunities, and information). At times, one has to take specific
steps, including making particular bodily movements and using specific
tools; at other times, one might simply take advantage of favorable condi-
tions and let the natural course of events unfold unperturbed. At times, one
might have to engage in particular deliberations about implementation and
coordination; at other times, one might automatically implement prior
plans and policies, or let habits determine one’s conduct. Discharging the
rational pressures of intention is a matter of the agent’s continuous “intelli-
gent guidance” toward g, which requires a mix of antagonistic interven-
tions, nonantagonistic monitoring, and the management of attention and
deliberation. This mix of bodily and mental events is what I will call a
Course of Active Intelligent Guidance (CrAIG, henceforth) directed at g.
Responding to the rational pressures of the intention that g is thus a matter
of engaging in the appropriate CrAIG.
Although a CrAIG is produced by exercising one’s executive powers, not
all portions of the CrAIG need to be “actions” in the sense of antagonistic
bodily interventions. In the limiting case, an agent might secure that g
simply by monitoring the favorable unfolding of a natural course of events
that eventuates in g without requiring any antagonistic intervention. In
this case, there is no action in the narrow sense of some antagonistic
intervention, but the achievement is still the agent’s doing.
5.3
Imagine that I intend that I be at a party tonight but I don’t care about how
I get there (this includes not caring about getting there by antagonistic
interventions of mine; it would be fine, say, if someone were to take me
there while I am asleep). However, given my circumstances, it is reasonable
to expect that some antagonistic intervention of mine is required. Yet, I do
not need to commit to any specific implementation. My intention only
commits me to exercising my executive powers toward g, i.e. to engage in a
CrAIG directed at g—whatever shape this CrAIG might take in response to
the specific demands imposed by my present and future circumstances until
the goal is either achieved or abandoned.
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 85
Imagine now that my goal is still simply to be at the party, but I also plan
on driving there as the most reasonable or likely means to my goal. Not
only does my intention include a recipe (my driving) but it might also be
expressed in its terms as “I intend to drive to the party,” even if the driving
is only instrumental to my goal (that is, “I intend that: (by way of my
driving) I be at the party”). The driving-as-recipe provides the default focus
for the organization of my executive capacities. As I embark in the CrAIG
directed at g, I exert these capacities toward g in large part by being oriented
toward my driving. As a result, I am going to engage in an episode of
“driving” as a course of action with a characteristic mix of antagonistic
interventions (including the use of various tools and the performance of
distinctive bodily movements), nonantagonistic monitoring, and correlated
management of deliberation and attention.
A plan-as-recipe offers a default yet revisable orientation for especially
salient albeit instrumental stages of an otherwise continuous CrAIG
directed at g. The CrAIG does not necessarily consist only of my driving,
nor does it necessarily start or end with my driving. My actual driving
should not be equated with the executive success of the intention. But my
starting to drive marks the point where the progress toward g begins to
unfold as “intended” in the sense of “according to the plan-as-recipe;” the
point where the course of active intelligent guidance directed at my being at
the party begins to take its expected shape.
5.4
There are cases where the recipe becomes part of the goal. For instance,
I intend to be at the party only by my driving (maybe, I want to impress the
partygoers by showing off my new car and I do not care to be at the party
otherwise). In these cases, the intention takes this form:
(I+gr) I intend that: g-by-way-of-r
Although g might be a goal by itself, here it is only a portion of the goal,
which now also includes some of the means to g—the recipe r. When so,
the inception of r marks a more momentous transition in the CrAIG:
when r begins, the achievement of the intention begins as well. From that
moment on, the intention is “in achievement,” so to say. But this
transition does not mark the acquisition of a new intention or the
inception of a novel CrAIG. It is not a transition between the intention
and a genuinely separate action. Rather, the transition is only the
beginning of the internal culmination of the original CrAIG, the incep-
tion of its finale.
86 Luca Ferrero
Oftentimes, the recipes that are part of the goal are what might be called
“performances”: specific and characteristic combinations of mostly antag-
onistic interventions in the form of certain bodily movements and the
distinctive uses of specific tools—for instance, playing a piano sonata or
dancing the tango. The beginning of the performance marks the inception
of the achievement but it is still a transition internal to the CrAIG that
began when the intention was first acquired (which might occur well in
advance of the performance’s inception).
Whenever the execution of a recipe begins (whether it is instrumental to
or constitutive of the goal), there is no break in the continuity of the agent’s
active guidance toward the goal. The execution of any of the actions
included in the recipe does not mark the termination of the intending
and the inception of a distinct piece of conduct, the acting. It is only an
internal transformation of the CrAIG’s shape, as required by the dynamics
of intentional progress toward g.
To claim that there is a single course of active intelligent guidance that
begins with the acquisition of the intention and continues until the inten-
tion is given up, voided, or carried out is not to deny that this course of
guidance has distinct stages. These stages might be quite different from
each other given that the specific demands on the agent’s executive capaci-
ties might vary widely as she progresses toward g. For instance, if she uses
her planning abilities well, earlier stages of a CrAIG tend to demand few, if
any, antagonistic interventions. At the outset, many well-planned projects
require minimal, if any, interference with the natural course of events. The
agent might only need to monitor for the persistence of currently favorable
circumstances. At the earlier stages, the specific effects of the intention tend
to be limited to the framing and organization of further practical deliber-
ation rather than antagonistic interventions in the outer world. Conversely,
later stages tend to keep the agent busier with antagonistic interventions
since more interference is usually needed at the later stages to secure that the
course of events eventuates in the intended state of affairs. But this is only a
simplified illustration of a typical but not necessary progression of the
demands imposed by an intention. The distribution of these demands
can differ widely (for instance, the agent might be kept busier earlier rather
than later, or cycle through the different stages).
The transitions between the stages can vary from the smooth and subtle
to the abrupt and sudden, depending on the changes in the demands
imposed by the circumstances. In any event, these transitions do not
mark a hard and fast metaphysical boundary between two utterly distinct
kinds of practical engagement with the world—intending vs. acting. When
describing the unfolding of an intentional pursuit, the distinction between
merely intending and actually acting is between two stages of an underlying
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 87
5.5
The temptation to think of the acting stage as a distinct item to which the
intention is directed might arise from the possibility of engaging in the
same kind of conduct independently of the future-directed intention. It is
often possible to imagine circumstances where one might initiate the action
of ç-ing without any prior intention directed at it. But from this it does not
follow that in acquiring a prospective intention to ç at f one aims at
initiating a distinct piece of conduct in the future. The prospective inten-
tion and its correlated CrAIG are not successfully carried out by “passing
the baton” to another intention and its correlated CrAIG at f. What occurs
at f is rather a transition to a different stage within the same intention
and CrAIG. It is a matter of internal transformation dictated by the
dynamic unfolding of the pursuit of the goal g to which the ç-ing is directed.
When one acquires the prospective intention to ç at f one is—so to say—
“stretching over time” the pursuit of g by bringing its inception forward in
time. One is not preparing in advance for a distinct future undertaking.
Rather, one is advancing the time when one first acquires the goal g
and, thereby, puts oneself under the rational pressures distinctive of that
particular intentional pursuit. In turn, if one is rational, this is also the time
when one begins discharging these pressures by engaging in a CrAIG
directed at g.
5.6
We are now in a position to better appreciate what it means for an intention
to be directed at an action as a genuinely distinct item, as it happens when
one intends the action of another agent. The latter intention is directed at
the initiation of a separate course of active guidance. The target of my
intention that you ç is the success of your distinct CrAIG directed at your
goal. Your ç-ing is not a stage of my CrAIG. When an action is a genuinely
distinct goal, the inception of the action marks a break in the continuity of
intentional guidance rather than a transformation induced by its internal
dynamics.
14
One might think of the two stages of intending and acting as akin to phase-sortals,
and to their transitions as akin to metamorphosis (See McDowell (2010)).
88 Luca Ferrero
5.7
Let’s consider one last attempt at defending OAC. One might concede all
the points I made but claim that there is still a sense in which the object of
intention is necessarily one’s own action. The argument would revolve
around the necessary ab se character of executive success. As argued above
(3.4), executive success can be secured only via the agent’s exercise of her
own executive capacities: achievement is necessarily ab executione sua, so to
say. Hence, any achievement amounts to the culmination of an actual doing
on the agent’s part, that is, the culmination of a CrAIG directed at g (i.e. of
a sequence of exercises of the agent’s own executive capacities that eventu-
ates in the nondeviant obtaining of g ). Why can’t we claim that the object
of the agent’s intending is necessarily this CrAIG, which is by its very
15
There are some special cases in which one might genuinely intend to pursue a goal
g and yet hope, without any paradox, that one will never be in a position to actually
succeed at carrying it out. For instance, I am fully committed to go the hospital if I get a
life-threatening injury but also hope that I will never have to carry out this precautionary
conditional intention. If I can have some control on the antecedent, I might even intend
to avoid that it ever comes true (that I ever get a life-threatening injury), see Ferrero
(2009a).
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 89
nature always of her own? In other words, according to this suggestion, the
object of intentions is necessarily the agent’s own doing, in the broad sense
of “doing” that encompasses the various modes of intelligent guidance.
The problem with this suggestion is that it indicates as the object a formal
and generic target. The course of action that leads to the achievement is not
something to which one can aim in the substantive and specific way in
which one aims at a particular goal g. As the necessary object of the
intention, the CrAIG in question is nothing other than the very operation
of an executively successful intention; it is the same as the successfully
completed process that constitutes the “perfection” of one’s intending that
g. A formal target cannot be the individuating goal of an intention, since
there is nothing specific to it. The executive capacities are oriented toward
substantive targets, not toward executive success as such. In intending that g
one necessarily “aims” at the formal target as well, at the achievement as the
successful culmination of one’s own doing. But in this purely formal sense
of aiming, it is uncontroversial but also uninformative to claim that in
intending one aims necessarily at the doing of one’s own that would
amount to the executive success of that intention.
5.8
Time to take stock. In the first part of the paper, I discussed whether OAC
could be supported on the basis of considerations on the individuating
content of intentions and their conditions of success. I started by consider-
ing whether OAC might hold of the simpler kind of executive intentions—
aiming. I argued that it doesn’t. Intentions are a special kind of aiming. Their
distinctive features, however, do not make a difference to the structure of
their individuating content. Hence, I argued that OAC does not hold
of intentions either.
I then moved to a distinct but related question. Could action at least be
the paradigmatic target of future-directed intentions? I argued that this is
not so, if the action is understood to be the separate target of the intending.
The actions of other agents are genuinely distinct pieces of conduct that can
be made into the proper object of one’s intentions. But one’s own actions
do not normally play this role. In the first person mode of full temporal
identification, there is a deeper continuity between intending and acting.
This continuity is deeper than it might appear at first, especially if one were
to read the logical structure of intentions out of the grammatical structure
of ordinary expressions of intentions with their infinitival complement,
since the latter seems to suggest that one is targeting one’s actions as distinct
pieces of conduct.
90 Luca Ferrero
6 . D E G R E E S O F D E S E I N V O LV E M E N T
6.1
Although I have argued that the content of intentions is neither necessarily
nor paradigmatically cast in terms of one’s own actions, I do not deny that
intending necessarily involves one’s own agency. This necessary involvement
is a matter of the metaphysics of executive attitudes, which are necessarily of
their own agent, both in ownership and exercise. Any executive attitude is
necessarily (but also trivially) de executione sua: possession of an executive
attitude is a matter of the agent’s exercise of her relevant executive powers.
This de se involvement of agency is fundamental but also unspecific. This is
just the ab se dimension of execution (see 3.4), a dimension that does not
impose any formal restriction on the objects of executive attitudes.
This fundamental but generic degree of de se involvement of agency is
not reflected in the individuating content. It is rather implicit in the
reference to the subject of the executive attitude: in a first-person attribu-
tion of intention, we might say that it is implicit in the “I” of the “I intend.”
There are two other degrees of involvement of one’s agency in intending.
They concern the role that the agent might play in the individuating
content of her intentions. The agent might plan on playing an instrumental
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 91
role in the pursuit of g. That is, she plans on relying on her taking certain
specific steps (say, her ç-ing) toward g but she is open to the possibility that
someone else might take her place in promoting g. Alternatively, an agent
might take specific exercises of her own agency to be constitutive of her
goal—putting herself under a rational pressure to prevent anyone else from
taking those steps instead.
Here is how the three degrees of de se involvement of agency appear (in
boldface) in the logical form of intentions as formulated in the first person:
(1st) I intend that: g
(2nd) I intend that: (by way of my ç-ing) g
(3rd) I intend that: g-by-way-of-my-ç-ing
It is only in the first degree that one’s own agency is necessarily involved,
although in the form of the generic exercise of one’s executive capacities. By
contrast, one’s specific agential involvement in the recipes and goals of
one’s intentions is not required. These goals or recipes might actually
involve other agents, both instrumentally and constitutively (for instance,
I might intend that: (by way of your ç-ing) g; or I might intend that: g-by-
way-of-your-ç-ing).
6.2
One might be involved to the second and third degree in a temporally
“alienated” form. Let’s imagine that, out of a concern for my own health,
I intend to work out tomorrow. My intention is that my body undergoes
the strenuous exercise. However, the satisfaction of my desire to be healthy
does not require that I work out directly out of my prior intention rather
than just as a result of it. Given that I expect that tomorrow I will be so lazy
that I might irrationally abandon my intention, I can still carry out my
intention by setting up a pre-commitment device that manipulates me into
working out tomorrow in spite of my reluctance to do so at that time.
In this case, my intention involves me to the third degree (the goal is my
performance rather than someone else’s) even if tomorrow I need not
endorse the considerations that supported my original intention. I might
act in response to that intention in the same way as another agent might be
cajoled by it. If so, my lack of full identification with myself in the past
makes my working out a distinct action, which is the genuine object of my
prior intention. This action is the culmination of a separate CrAIG guided
by a new intention, the intention to work out that I acquire tomorrow as a
result of the manipulating effect of my prior intention.
Standard intentions are not of this alienated kind. We ordinarily take
ourselves to continue to identify over time, to continue to embrace and
92 Luca Ferrero
sustain the same intention throughout its unfolding and, thereby, to engage
in a single continuous CrAIG without self-directed goading, cajoling, or
manipulating. Hence the strongest degree of de se involvement is that of full
temporal identification rather than that of mere (and potentially alienated)
temporal identity.16
6.3
Although the second and third degrees of de se involvement are not necessary,
it is very common for ordinary intentions to take these forms.17 Hence, many
of our recipes and goals are formulated in terms of specific manifestations of
our own agency (usually in the nonalienated form). I surmise that this
explains why ordinary expressions of intention usually take the infinitival
form. For two reasons:
First, verbal expressions help characterize the specific ways in which the
agent’s executive capacities are involved in pursuing her goals. Nongeneric
verbs of action describe distinct and characteristic patterns of bodily move-
ment, tool-use, monitoring, attention management, and appreciation of
the situation. Ordinary expressions usually make explicit the communi-
catively most salient elements of the intention, in terms of (some aspects) of
its recipe and/or goal. But we should not expect these expressions necessar-
ily and fully to articulate the content of the attitude.
Second, usually the intention’s most salient elements concern the agent’s
exercise of her executive capacities in the mode of full temporal identification.
Hence it is often pleonastic to make explicit the subject of the infinitival
16
To mark this stronger form of first-personal transtemporal relation, one might
introduce an augmented quasi-indicator, S**. Hence, “S intends that: S* works out
tomorrow,” leaves it open that one might manipulate one’s future self, whereas “S
intends that: S** works out tomorrow” doesn’t.
17
The existence of the various degrees of de se involvement raises one important
question. Even if many of our ordinary projects involve by default the agent to the third
degree, should this involvement matter to us? Are there intrinsically personal projects—
projects that cannot be pursued but de se to the strongest degree? And if there are, should
we care about them? (See Perry 1976, Whiting 1986.) Reflection on the nature of the
fundamental first-degree of de se involvement does not seem to help with these questions.
The fundamental form of de se involvement makes it metaphysically impossible for the
source of agency to be but particular agents involved in the immediate exercise of their own
executive capacities. What does it take for this involvement to extend over time? That is, to
extend over its immediate and momentary exercises? Is some temporal extension
metaphysically required by the nature of agency itself ? (See Burge (2004).) And if not,
what does it take to secure this extension? And is it worth it? These questions cannot be
addressed in this paper, but the discussion of the object of intentions and their relations to
the first person makes them particularly vivid. (For some initial considerations about what
makes extended intentional agency valuable to us, see Ferrero 2009b.)
Can I Only Intend My Own Actions? 93
REFERENCES
Baier, Annette (1970). “Act and Intent.” Journal of Philosophy 67: 648–58.
—— (1976). “Mixing Memory and Desire.” American Philosophical Quarterly 13:
213–20.
Boyle, Matt and Lavin, Doug (2010). “Goodness and Desire.” In Sergio Tenenbaum
(ed.), Desire, Good, and Practical Reason. (Oxford: Oxford University Press),
171–91.
Bratman, Michael (1987). Intentions, Plans, and Practical Reason. (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press).
—— (1997). “I intend that We J.” In R. Tuomela and G. Holmstrom-Hintikka
(eds.), Contemporary Action Theory, Volume 2 (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 49–63.
Burge, Tyler (2000). “Reason and the First Person,” In C. Wright, B. Smith, and
C. Macdonald (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds. (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
—— (2004). “Memory and Persons.” Philosophical Review 112: 289–337.
—— (2009). “Primitive Agency and Natural Norms.” Philosophy and Phenomeno-
logical Research 79: 251–78.
Castañeda, Hector-Neri (1972). “Intentions and Intending.” American Philosophical
Quarterly 9: 139–49.
—— (1975). Thinking and Doing. (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Ferrero, Luca. (2009a). “Conditional Intentions.” Noûs 43: 700–41.
—— (2009b). “What Good is a Diachronic Will?” Philosophical Studies 144: 403–30.
Frankfurt, Harry (1978). “The Problem of Action,” In Harry Frankfurt, The
Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press),
69–79.
Gustafson, D. F. (1986). Intention and Agency. (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Harman, Gilbert (1986). Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press).
18
Thanks to Michael Bratman, Rahul Kumar, Matthias Haase, David Shoemaker,
the audience at the NOWAR meeting in 2011, and two anonymous referees.
94 Luca Ferrero
* This paper issues from an ongoing collaborative project undertaken with Justin
D’Arms. Many of its arguments were developed in discussion with him, though respon-
sibility for the paper’s faults falls to me alone. I am grateful to Bruce Brower, Sarah Buss,
Rae Langton, Michael McKenna, Peter Railton, Tim Scanlon, David Shoemaker, two
anonymous referees, and audiences at the New Orleans Workshop on Agency and
Responsibility, Syracuse University, and the University of Michigan for helpful com-
ments on previous drafts. My greatest debt is to Bernard Williams and Michael Stocker
whose work not only inspired this paper but sparked much of my interest in moral
philosophy. This paper was supported by a grant from the John Templeton Foundation.
1
It should be noted that Williams’ primary concern is with the narrower notion of
agent-regret. The problems I will raise concern agent-regret too, but this initial com-
plaint reflects mostly a semantic (and hence superficial) difference with Williams: we are
working with different conceptions of regret. But it should become clear that we are not
merely fighting over words.
96 Daniel Jacobson
think for instance that Neville Chamberlain, the architect of the 1938
appeasement of Hitler in Munich, who returned to England triumph-
antly declaring “peace with honour,” was peculiarly well situated to
regret that policy in light of the German blitzkrieg of Poland in 1939.
By contrast, Winston Churchill famously announced, on Chamberlain’s
return from Munich: “You were given the choice between war and
dishonour . . . you chose dishonour and you will have war.” Obviously
Churchill thought it would have been much better had Britain con-
fronted Hitler earlier and under more favorable conditions. As Williams
understands regret, Churchill and Chamberlain both have reason to
regret the Munich agreement—but this seems odd. Indeed, Williams
can hardly claim that Chamberlain has more reason to regret than does
Churchill, and hence that his feelings should be more intense, since even
in retrospect it was surely Churchill who believed more strongly that
another course of action would have been preferable. Yet agent-regret
might seem to solve this problem on the cheap, since, by definition, it is
an emotion that Chamberlain but not Churchill could feel about the
Munich appeasement.
However, I will argue that the deep worries in this neighborhood cannot
be met in this way, by designing new emotions to meet a philosophical job
description. In particular, I reject the method Williams employs in charac-
terizing generic regret and then constructing agent-regret out of it. This
method of type-identifying emotions is characteristic of the cognitivist
theory of the emotions, which identifies a constitutive thought, belief (or
perhaps some weaker propositional attitude) in which is a necessary condi-
tion for having any given emotion.2 Williams does just this by explicitly
identifying a constitutive thought of regret and implicitly suggesting
another for agent-regret. Perhaps having this thought isn’t sufficient for
being in a state of regret, since it might need to be accompanied by the right
sort of feeling. Nevertheless, Williams (1976: 27) expressly claims that “in
principle” anyone who can make the judgment can have the emotion
and—since the judgment he associates with regret expressly pertains to
states of affairs—“anyone who knows of them” can make the relevant
judgment. While I will not argue directly against cognitivism here, I do
want to use this discussion to illustrate two serious problems with the
2
Such cognitivist theories come in several varieties, most notably neo-stoicism
(Solomon 1988, Nussbaum 2001), judgmentalism (Taylor 1985), and quasi-
judgmentalism (Greenspan 1988, Roberts 1988). These theories share the defining
propositions methodology of type-identifying the emotions, though they differ on
whether the thought must be accepted or merely entertained, and whether it is wholly
or only partly constitutive of the emotion.
Regret, Agency, Error 97
3
The issue of what is meant by calling an emotion rational will be taken up presently.
In order to follow the literature under discussion, I will use the term “rational” to refer to
what D’Arms and I elsewhere called its fittingness, in order to disambiguate this
judgment from other kinds of assessment of the appropriateness of emotions.
98 Daniel Jacobson
with both Williams and Michael Stocker concerns whether one can
rationally regret taking (what one considers) the best option available.
Nevertheless, their discussion of regret and its cognates exhibits
an important virtue, which I greatly respect and wish to maintain: its
psychological realism. Since I find this one of the characteristic virtues in
the work of both Williams and Stocker, my two principal foils here,
I should begin by noting my admiration for the psychological insight
that informs their moral philosophy. Two facets of this realism are
particularly significant for present purposes, what I’ll call the agency
principle and the residue principle, both of which concern the relationship
between acting and feeling. These two principles are illustrated respect-
ively by Williams’s two paradigms of agent-regret: the lorry driver who
blamelessly kills a child, and Agamemnon who chooses to sacrifice his
daughter in order to save his becalmed fleet.4
Consider first the agency principle: the claim that we are connected,
through our feelings, to even the involuntary aspects of what we do—as
opposed to what simply happens around us. Williams has in mind things
for which we are merely causally responsible, but in virtue of what we
intentionally did. He illustrates this insight with his famous lorry driver
case. The driver who blamelessly kills a child can surely be expected to feel
something different than does a mere spectator to the accident, though
neither is culpable for the tragedy. This core insight is one of his primary
motivations for differentiating the “regret of the agent” from that of a mere
spectator. Whereas Williams insists that the lorry driver feels rational agent-
regret, I will argue that he can be expected to feel irrational but praise-
worthy guilt. This is not to deny that the driver might have another bad
feeling, directed at the state of affairs or even his role in bringing it about;
but this emotion should not be considered a form of regret either. Although
I thus reject both Williams’s claim that the driver feels regret and that this
emotion is rational, I think he grasps an important kernel of truth. The
agency principle, understood as an empirical rather than a normative claim,
is a psychological insight with profound philosophical implications. But
the further claim that such predictable feelings are rational needs to be
considered separately, as does the question of exactly what emotion we
should expect from the driver in this scenario.
4
Before considering these scenarios, however, it’s worth noting that they are chosen
for their philosophical interest. This strategy proves double-edged. In trying to gloss an
emotion—that is, to understand its distinctive concern—I contend that one should look
first to commonplace rather than novel cases. Though philosophers tend to focus on
philosophically interesting examples, the more mundane cases are also more perspicuous,
and unusual cases can be misleading—often for the very reason that they’re interesting.
Regret, Agency, Error 99
Second, both Williams and Stocker observe that sometimes when we face
conflicting values or obligations, which cannot be jointly satisfied, some
residue of bad feeling (or emotional “remainder”) can be expected even
when we have done the best we could.5 This residue principle contains a
crucial psychological insight as well, though I will describe it differently
and draw different conclusions from it than do Williams and Stocker.
Williams (1965: 181) adduces as an example Agamemnon, who “ought to
discharge his responsibilities as a commander, further the expedition, and so
forth . . . [but] ought not to kill his daughter.” We are of course to imagine
that he can satisfy either obligation but not both. Williams insists further that
both incompatible obligations bind Agamemnon, and that therefore it is
rational for him to regret whatever he does, despite thinking he has most
reason to do it. In fact, Williams and Stocker go so far as to claim that
anything Agamemnon may be able to do in this tragic situation would be
wrong.
While I do not accept this conclusion, the cases on which I will focus
concern conflicts of value rather than obligation, so as to avoid issues of
guilt and wrongness. The problematic claim here, developed most per-
spicuously by Stocker, is that in some such conflicts of value it will be
rational to regret choosing what one knows is the better option: the greater
good or the lesser evil. Let us call this residual regret. As with the agency
principle, one can accept the residue principle as an empirical insight
without granting the rationality of residual regret. I will argue, analogously,
that some of these cases don’t involve regret but another emotion, which
may or may not be rational; and others are cases of irrational regret that is
nevertheless, in a different sense, an appropriate emotional response. This
normative corollary to the residue principle, concerning the putative
rationality of residual regret, plays a crucial role in a recent debate over
conflicts of value, to be discussed later. But this argument obscures the
insight at the heart of the residue principle: the phenomenon of loss. I grant
that something significant can be lost in making the better choice, and that
this loss can indeed justify residual bad feeling in various respects.
A similar problem plagues discussion of both the agency and residue
principles. The problem lies not in the principles themselves but with the
5
Sometimes this remainder is supposed to be a new obligation arising out of the old
(forsaken) one. But that kind of remainder poses no problem to those who think that the
lesser of two conflicting (prima facie) obligations does not bind, and hence that violating
it would not be wrong. It is easy to grant that when I miss our lunch date for some
obviously good reason, I incur an obligation to explain myself to you, to reschedule at
your convenience, or even to pick up the tab. But these new obligations can be seen as
issuing from the inconvenience I’ve caused you, however justifiably, rather than from any
wrongdoing on my part.
100 Daniel Jacobson
1 . R E G R E T A S A SE N T I M E N T
As a purely semantic point, it must be granted that the word “regret” can be
used extremely broadly. However strange it sounds for a present-day histor-
ian to say that she regrets the Munich agreement, she could make use of
what Williams elsewhere calls the thoroughly adverbial sense of the word to
say: “The Allies regrettably chose appeasement at Munich.”6 Even if any
unfortunate situation can be called regrettable, though, should we really
conclude that everyone has equal standing to regret it? It will be more
perspicuous to focus on when it is apt to ascribe regret to an agent, rather
than on what could be called regrettable but might just as well be called
unfortunate. Indeed, if “regrettable” and “unfortunate” are not synonymous,
when used in this broadest sense, then it is because regret involves someone’s
agency or choice, whereas misfortune need not. This linguistic observation
suggests that Williams’s notion of generic regret, which is directed at states
of affairs rather than actions, is a misnomer. The fact that the storm did
so much damage is more felicitously termed unfortunate than regrettable.
Although in my view all regret is agential, one can certainly judge another
person’s action regrettable, meaning thereby that the agent should
(rationally) regret it.
Perhaps the best lesson to draw from these reflections is that ordinary
language is especially misleading with respect to emotion terms. Even if the
adverbial usage counts as a literal ascription of regret, certain familiar
6
Williams (1973b: 112, fn. 1) writes of the “thoroughly adverbial” account of
pleasure, on which anything that can be done pleasurably counts as a form of pleasure.
Regret, Agency, Error 101
7
My favorite example comes from a postcard used by a famous scholar to reply to
requests which begins, “Edmund Wilson regrets that it is impossible for him to: Read
manuscripts . . . ,” and then goes on to list some twenty other scholarly tasks that he
was, regrettably, unable to perform. We should all be so fortunate as to have such regrets.
8
But cf. Deigh (2000) who suggests that this assertion must issue from a Humean
theory of mind on which only passions and not judgments can motivate. On the
contrary, this is a commonsense observation about specific cases. Indeed, I claim to
make the relevant judgment about Munich myself, without affect. It seems ad hoc to
deny that I make this judgment sincerely.
102 Daniel Jacobson
might instead say that Churchill felt dismay over the Munich agreement (in
addition to whatever else he may have felt, such as anger at Chamberlain’s
self-righteousness, contempt for his naivety, fear for England’s future, and
so forth). Whereas the historian’s judgment that things would have been
better otherwise is simply an evaluation, dismay and regret are emotions
because they are ways of feeling. The question is whether they are the same
emotion. Is the regret that Chamberlain can be supposed to have felt, in
retrospect, about his decision to appease Hitler at Munich simply a “par-
ticularly important species” of the same emotion Churchill felt about what
happened despite his objections, as Williams implies? More abstractly, is
this question a matter of psychological fact, as it purports to be, or simply
linguistic stipulation about “regret” and “dismay”?
At this point I need to broach two additional claims, one general and the
other more specific, for which I cannot yet argue. These are substantial
claims, open to falsification, and ultimately in need of elaboration and
defense. The first concerns a distinction between emotions and sentiments.
Although the disparate class of states called emotions have little in common
(compare approval and surprise, for example), my focus here will be on a
core group I’ll term sentiments, each of which constitutes a natural psycho-
logical kind of state whose nature can be discovered empirically rather than
stipulated semantically.9 The second claim specifically concerns regret:
that it is a sentiment concerned with the agent’s own errors. If this gloss is
correct, then the reason it would be odd to attribute regret over Munich to
Churchill is simply that he didn’t make the mistake of trying to appease
Hitler—Chamberlain did. But since both Williams and Stocker’s central
claims about regret are inconsistent with my gloss, it would beg the
question against them to assume it. For now I simply aspire to make
these two claims plausible: that regret is a sentiment, and that it is best
glossed as being about one’s own error.
What am I claiming by calling regret a sentiment? Like other emotions,
sentiments are syndromes of thought, feeling, and motivation; but unlike
some members of the disparate class of emotional states, the sentiments
play a distinctive role in the human mental economy.10 Sentiments are
discrete sources of motivation, which can be in tension with our overall
9
Philosophers of the emotions as disparate as Amélie Rorty (1978: 104) and Paul
Griffiths (2004) doubt that emotion counts as a natural kind. Although I agree,
I contend both that the sentiments as a group, and each individual sentiment such as
regret, forms a natural psychological kind. In part, this claim amounts to adopting a
broad construal of the emotions and a narrow, more technical notion of the sentiments.
Cf. Frank (1988), Frijda (1986).
10
See D’Arms and Jacobson (2003, 2006). Note the unfortunate change of terminology:
what we call natural emotions in (2003) become the sentiments in (2006).
Regret, Agency, Error 103
beliefs and desires. For this reason, two related features distinguish the
sentiments from mere emotions: they are prone to stable recalcitrance, and
they issue in acting without thinking in a sense to be explicated. First,
whereas emotions that are not sentiments evaporate when one disbelieves
their associated judgment, the sentiments can be recalcitrant, in that an
agent can be in the grip of a sentiment contrary to his better judgment.11
Those who are afraid of flying despite knowing that their flight is safer than
the drive to the airport, which does not frighten them, are prone to stably
recalcitrant fear. By contrast, the emotion of resentment, understood as a
form of anger that involves a critical moral judgment, cannot coexist with
the belief that no wrong was done; what can persist recalcitrantly is just
anger.
The phenomenon of recalcitrance reflects the epistemic aspect of the
sentiments’ partial encapsulation from our beliefs and desires; whereas
acting without thinking reflects the motivational aspect. For instance, the
sentiment of anger is notoriously insensitive to whether the behavior it
motivates coheres with our overall ends. This gives anger and the other
sentiments an essential role in psychological explanation of behavior that
would otherwise be mysterious. These explanations are obvious, not espe-
cially insightful. They might be called shallow (as opposed to depth)
psychological explanations, so long as this isn’t taken pejoratively. Obvious
explanations need not be false.
Consider for example the behavior of the French footballer Zidane,
perhaps the greatest player of his era, in his final match: the 2006 World
Cup Final. This was not only the most important match of Zidane’s career,
it was his last, and the hopes of the French side depended almost entirely on
him. Yet when an Italian player taunted him, Zidane responded with a
flagrant and illegal head-butt, certain to get him thrown out of the match,
thus ending his career in selfishness and disgrace. He thereby ruined any
chance of attaining what had to be his greatest desire: leading France to a
World Cup victory in the final match of his spectacular career. Instead he
got the immediate gratification of revenge at the cost of defeat and igno-
miny. Why would anyone behave so irrationally—that is, so contrary to his
overall beliefs and values? The answer should be obvious: he was in a rage
and acted on the characteristic motivation of anger, namely retaliation.
Sentiments thus explain the phenomenon of acting without thinking in this
11
See D’Arms and Jacobson (2003) for discussion of recalcitrance and why there isn’t
recalcitrant “fear of flying,” understood as an emotion, only recalcitrant fear. The crucial
claim here is that whenever an emotion figures in such an explanation, some underlying
sentiment does the real explanatory work.
104 Daniel Jacobson
specific sense: the agent does not consider how his action coheres with his
aims.12
In short, the sentiments are a core class of emotions that can be found
across cultures and times, albeit with some variation in their eliciting
conditions, which have some characteristic motivational tendency.13
We can thus say, with Aristotle, that anger is about undeserved slights—
even though what counted as a slight for Aristotle differs from what a
modern youth would consider a diss (i.e. show of disrespect). Whereas any
combination of thought, feeling, and motivation counts as an emotion, the
sentiments figure essentially in psychological explanations and predictions
of behavior. Only some of the varied states that get called emotions will
count as sentiments, while others cut across different sentiments. For
example, we have stipulated that one can be dismayed in various ways, all
of which can be expressed by a thought such as, “How much better if it had
been otherwise”; but sometimes such dismay will involve sorrow, anger, or
shame rather than regret. Although we can say that dismay is an emotion
that includes various sentiments expressed by that constitutive thought, this
way of speaking can be treacherous. Each of these sentiments has distinctive
content and issues in different characteristic behavior. Hence what explains
why Jack lashed out in his dismay, while Jill tried to make amends and Jan
withdrew completely, is that Jack’s dismay was a form of anger, Jill’s of
guilt, and Jan’s of shame. What I’m calling dismay resembles the emotional
manifestations of Williams’s notion of generic regret, but I contend that
regret is best understood as a sentiment.
Whatever Chamberlain actually felt after the blitzkrieg shattered the
illusion of “peace in our time,” there is a familiar psychological syndrome
that he might have suffered but Churchill could not. Only Chamberlain
could have had a bout of the sentiment I will hereafter simply call regret:
the syndrome of painful feelings of self-reproach focused on his blunder
and its disastrous consequences, accompanied by the wish to undo the error
and the intention to act differently next time. Part of the regret syndrome
thus involves a motivation toward what might loosely be called policy
change, although in this case there could be no question of Chamberlain
getting another chance. (Indeed, the motivation should be expected even
when it is futile and manifests itself only in symbolic gestures and fantasy;
12
This is not always to condemn such action, even when it conflicts with considered
judgment, much less to bemoan the fact that we humans have such discrete, fast-and-frugal
motivational systems in addition to slower and more deliberative ways of thinking (Gigerenzer
and Todd 1999).
13
See Ekman (2003) on the universality of facial expression of the sentiments (or
basic emotions).
Regret, Agency, Error 105
this partly explains the social importance of such gestures and the psycho-
logical importance of such fantasy.) This characterization is loose because
in some cases the regretted act does not accord with any previous policy:
either it was done without thinking; or not as an expression of a general
policy; or even, in cases of weakness of will, contrary to one’s policy. In
all these cases, though, regret has a motivational component concerning
one’s intentions for future action. The lessons learned from regret involve
dwelling painfully, perhaps obsessively, on some (putative) mistake and the
decision leading up to it.14 In sum, our historian makes a dispassionate
evaluative judgment, and Churchill’s painful dismay is an emotion, but
only Chamberlain’s hypothesized regret counts as a sentiment. Moreover,
agent-regret will prove to be chimerical because it manifests itself in
disparate sentiments, which can be in tension both with Williams’s
characterization of the state and with his paradigm cases: the lorry driver
and Agamemnon.
2. WHAT IS AGENT-REGRET?
14
The word “putative” does important work here, since there is no guarantee that the
action genuinely regretted was really mistaken. Indeed, when things go badly, one can
expect that the reasons against doing what was done will become especially salient, and
the reasons in favor will appear correspondingly diminished.
106 Daniel Jacobson
one acted otherwise. When this is really regret about the choice rather than
dismay about the outcome, however, I hold that it is recalcitrant regret,
which is irrational by the agent’s own lights. Hence the criterion for the
rationality of regret is whether or not one erred. That is one of my central
disagreements with Williams and Stocker.
Recall that Williams coins agent-regret out of his capacious conception
of regret in general, with the additional restriction that it must focus on the
agent’s own actions and their consequences, and the insistence that this
need not be an all-things-considered wish. He thus implies that agent-
regret has a constitutive thought along the lines, “How much better, in some
respect, if I had done otherwise.” Moreover, he (1976: 27–8) writes:
The sentiment of agent-regret is by no means restricted to voluntary agency. It can
extend far beyond what one intentionally did to almost anything for which one was
causally responsible in virtue of something one intentionally did. Yet even at deeply
accidental or non-voluntary levels of agency, sentiments of agent-regret are different
from regret in general, such as might be felt by a spectator, and are acknowledged in
our practice as being different. The lorry driver who, through no fault of his, runs
over a child, will feel differently from any spectator, even a spectator next to him in
the cab, except perhaps to the extent that the spectator takes on the thought that he
himself might have prevented it, an agent’s thought.
Here Williams seems to be making a psychological claim about what we
can expect an ordinary, decent person in the unfortunate driver’s position
to feel: something different from what a mere spectator would feel. He also
claims, plausibly, that we would expect the driver’s bad feelings to move
him to make some gesture of reparation to the victim. As Williams (1976:
28) notes, “The lorry-driver may act in some way which he hopes will
constitute or at least symbolize some kind of recompense or restitution, and
this will be an expression of his agent-regret.” While a spectator would
likely be moved to console the victim’s parents, it would be strange for her
to offer restitution for the accident.
Moreover, although Williams grants that people are prone to “irrational
and self-punitive excess” in this area, he insists on the propriety of some
such expression from the driver. Despite the driver’s (stipulated) blameless-
ness, he claims that such a response would not only be normal but proper,
indeed rational. “[I]t would be a kind of insanity never to experience
sentiments of this kind toward anyone,” Williams (1976: 29) writes,
“and it would be an insane conception of rationality which insisted that a
rational person never would.” Thus the leading thought of his discussion of
the lorry driver case—with which he introduces the notion of agent-
regret—is what I’ve called the agency principle. As he (1993: 92) notes
elsewhere, it is an “utterly familiar fact that what happened to others
Regret, Agency, Error 107
through our own agency can have its own authority over our feelings, even
though we brought it about involuntarily.” This seems especially likely
when the outcome is negative.
Williams moves quickly from the predictability of such a response to the
insanity of being entirely immune to it, and then to the rejection of any
conception of rationality on which a rational person would be so immune.
Surely “insanity” is hyperbole, and what he really means is something more
like inhumanity. Any decent person will display such tendencies. Thus
Williams commits himself to the rationality of the lorry driver’s regret
(which I will deny), on the grounds that it would be unacceptable to adopt
standards of rationality for the emotions that fail to cohere with human
psychology (which I accept). One issue between us concerns the specific
respect in which one should endorse this regret. This will be the topic of
Section 3. Another question, to which I will now turn, is whether we should
accommodate the agency principle by positing a novel emotion, namely
agent-regret.
Williams’ notion of agent-regret seems to differ from guilt, which is
typically taken to be rationally restricted to the voluntary—or, at any rate,
the blameworthy.15 As Williams (1993: 89) himself observes, “What
arouses guilt in an agent is an act or omission of a sort that typically
elicits from other people anger, resentment, or indignation.” This is just
what distinguishes the blameless driver from the negligent or malicious
one: no one has any justified complaint against him. Although Williams
(1976: 27) considers agent-regret to be a species of the more capacious bad
feeling he calls regret in general, he also claims that it “is not distinguished
from regret in general solely or simply in virtue of its subject-matter,”
namely one’s own action, but is also characterized by a different form
of expression in motivation: the desire to make reparations. But note
that this is exactly the motivation characteristic of guilt.16 In the throes of
guilt, one feels like one owes a debt, and that discomforting feeling issues in
the desire to make reparations. Thus Williams’s notion of agent-regret
seems precariously placed between (generic) regret and guilt. What then
is the point of giving the emotion we can expect from the lorry driver a
distinct name? And why call it agent-regret?
15
It is worth noting that, years later, Williams (1993: 93) tosses off the remark that
the lorry driver’s agent-regret is “psychologically and structurally a manifestation of
guilt.” On one hand, this suggests that my treatment of the case does not differ as
much from Williams as first appears; on the other, this seems an admission that even his
restricted notion of agent-regret conflates cases of regret with those of guilt.
16
See, e.g. Gibbard (1990), Tangney and Dearing (2002), Baumeister et al. (1994,
1995).
108 Daniel Jacobson
This question becomes even more puzzling when we consider what some
other philosophers have written about the lorry driver case. Gabrielle
Taylor describes the driver’s emotion simply as guilt and concludes that
guilt concerns causal rather than moral responsibility. “Causal responsi-
bility is the type that is sufficient for guilt, and that much is also necessary,”
Taylor (1985: 91) writes; hence, guilt “cannot be vicarious, and feelings of
guilt similarly cannot arise from the deeds or omissions of others,” not even
one’s children or compatriots. But almost no one else agrees with her, and
for good reason: counterexamples seem rampant.17 Taylor’s gloss of guilt
forces her to hold that vicarious guilt is not merely irrational but impossible,
which would make survivor guilt and liberal guilt into counterexamples
to her theory—if they are indeed forms of guilt, not just states casually
called by that name.18 Of course, she could always posit another emotion
to accommodate these phenomena rather than denying their possibility
outright. But to posit something like “liberal compunction” to cover cases
of vicarious guilt is an ad hoc maneuver designed to salvage the theory by
stipulation. Worse, she would no longer be talking about guilt, the natural
kind of psychological state, but a subset of its instances chosen precisely to fit
her claims. This renders tautological a claim—that guilt cannot be
vicarious—which seems to be put forward as an empirical observation. It
would be better to advance a claim that is neither empirical nor semantic but
normative: that causal responsibility is necessary for guilt to be rational. This
would make survivor guilt possible, even explicable, but not rational; and
that combination of claims seems quite plausible. Moreover, Taylor’s
implicit suggestion that we should expect the lorry driver to feel guilt
rather than some variety of regret is exactly right.
Though we can evaluate claims about the sentiments, those about
constructed emotions are much more difficult to assess, because they
seem precariously placed between empirical hypothesis and semantic stipu-
lation. Consider Marcia Baron’s (1988) discussion of agent-regret and the
lorry driver, in which she claims to detect a difference between regret and
agent-regret that Williams fails to note. Baron (1988: 262) writes: “Agent-
regret has an ethical dimension which plain regret lacks. Agent-regret is felt
toward the sorts of things which, if done deliberately, would properly
occasion guilt.” Baron clearly means to be talking about the same state as
17
See Greenspan (1992) for counterargument. When Taylor is being more careful
she allows that the requirement is, rather, that an agent must believe himself causally
responsible for something in order to feel guilty over it. Even so, many counterexamples
arise.
18
The fact that these states motivate apology and attempts at reparation, even where
there is no causal responsibility, is a reason to think that they are indeed forms of guilt.
Regret, Agency, Error 109
19
This point illustrates another infelicity of ordinary language: some words do have
connotations of great significance, such as “remorse” and “misery,” both of which suggest
great intensity. But surely this is just a semantic point and, what is more, it does not hold
about “regret.”
110 Daniel Jacobson
20
When one makes the right decision but it turns out badly, one loses out on
something genuinely valuable, with only the cold comfort of having chosen correctly.
And when one makes a hard choice, where there are different reasons on both sides of the
question—even if the reasons for one choice clearly outweigh the other—then we often
do painfully feel the loss of the goods rationally forgone.
Regret, Agency, Error 111
21
I think guilt should instead be given a dual aspect interpretation, as about either
impersonal wrongness or personal betrayal. This dual-aspect view can explain the
rationality of guilt in situations like Agamemnon’s, where the demands of duty conflict
intractably with our deepest personal commitments and relationships. See D’Arms and
Jacobson (1994), Baumeister et al. (1994, 1995), Tangney and Dearing (2002).
22
While some of these cases call for depth psychological explanation, such as when
the confession is best seen as a further act of hostility rather than atonement, surely this is
not always the case.
112 Daniel Jacobson
One reason why guilt and regret are so often confused—or conflated by
way of an artificially constructed emotion like agent-regret—is that typically
when one feels guilty, one will also feel regret (though not vice versa). That
is to say, painful thoughts of having done wrong, which motivate the desire
to make reparations and thereby placate the anger of others, tend to be
accompanied by painful thoughts that one has made a mistake, which issue
in repudiation of the action and resolve to act differently in the future.
Nevertheless, guilt need not be accompanied by regret, since it seems
psychologically possible to think that one acted immorally without repudi-
ating what one did.
Because agent-regret conflates two distinct sentiments, it is a misleading
emotion category that obscures more than it illuminates. However, its
construction is not a mere mistake; it is motivated by the insights of the
agency and residue principles. Yet Williams’s attribution of agent-regret to
the lorry driver carries some tacit normative implications which, when
made fully explicit, point in a different direction than he suggests. He
aims to find an emotion that it would be rational for the lorry driver to feel,
but which cannot rationally be felt by a mere spectator to the event. I’ve
already granted the plausibility of Williams’s agency principle, which holds
that the driver can be expected to have bad feelings disproportionate to
those of a mere spectator. If we assume, further, that the difference between
agent and spectator is not merely a matter of degree but of what kind of
emotion they can be expected to feel—as Williams clearly implies by
contrasting agent-regret with the regret of the spectator—then his motiv-
ation for coining agent-regret becomes clear.
Calling the lorry driver’s emotion agent-regret suggests that he need not
be blameworthy in order to feel it rationally. According to Williams, one
can feel rational regret over actions with bad outcomes for which one is
merely causally responsible, in virtue of what one intentionally did—such
as driving the lorry blamelessly. And calling it agent-regret suggests that a
mere spectator cannot feel it rationally, since he could feel that only if he
thought himself to be a participant in the action (which really would be
insane). Agent-regret thus seems to fit the job description perfectly. Yet
I will argue in the following section that this is a specious victory. Nothing
important is gained by attributing agent-regret rather than guilt or dismay
to the lorry driver, and Williams’s (hedged) commitment to defending the
rationality of the lorry driver’s emotion is understandable and plausible but
ultimately proves misguided.
Regret, Agency, Error 113
Williams does not argue for the rationality of the lorry driver’s regret so
much as peremptorily reject any conception of rationality that denies it.
Since there are several different respects in which philosophers have claimed
emotions to be appropriate—as rational, admirable, fitting, and so forth—
it isn’t immediately obvious what Williams thereby rejects. We might
differentiate between these forms of criticism by saying that an emotion
is unreasonable whenever there is most reason not to feel it, that it is not
admirable when it conflicts with what a virtuous person would feel under
the circumstances, and that it is unfitting when it misrepresents its object. It
is possible that an emotion could be fitting, in this sense, despite neither
being what a virtuous person would feel nor what one has most reason to
feel. Because cognitivist theories of the emotions posit a constitutive
thought to each, they have an obvious affinity for accounts of fittingness
in terms of the truth of that proposition. Although I here follow Williams
and Stocker in speaking of the rationality of emotions such as regret, I take
them to be talking about fittingness. And I understand them to hold that an
emotion is irrational when its (supposedly) constitutive thought is false.23
Williams suggests that there would be something wrong with the lorry
driver if he felt merely what a spectator could feel over the tragedy for which
he was causally responsible. While acknowledging the likelihood of exces-
sive self-reproach in such situations, he insists that a driver should be prone
to an initial bout of bad feeling that expresses itself in the impulse to make
(even symbolic) reparations. But he also expresses some proper caution
about this conclusion. Williams (1976: 28) writes:
Doubtless, and rightly, people will try, in comforting him, to move the driver from
this state of feeling . . . to something more like the place of a spectator, but it is
important that this is seen as something that should need to be done, and indeed
some doubt would be felt about a driver who too blandly or readily moved to that
position.
I can accommodate Williams’s leading thought about this case, which
corresponds to the modest, empirical version of the agency principle
alongside an ethical norm endorsing those feelings. We can expect even
the blameless driver to feel worse than a spectator, and to want to make
some kind of restitution; moreover, in some sense he should have such
23
See D’Arms and Jacobson (2000). An additional reason not to use “rational” in this
sense arises from cases of misleading evidence, where the epistemic flavor of that term is
inapt. But we will not be considering such cases here.
114 Daniel Jacobson
24
I take this to be the leading thought of Rosebury (1995) on moral luck.
Regret, Agency, Error 115
Moreover, if this is what decent people feel, then any notion of what an
admirable agent will feel cannot deviate too far, on pain of becoming overly
idealized and unrealistic. As Williams (1965: 175) holds about cases of
conflicts of obligation,
A tendency to feel regrets . . . at having broken a promise even in the course of acting
for the best might well be considered a reassuring sign that an agent took his
promises seriously. At this point, the objector might say that he still thinks the
regrets irrational, but that he does not intend ‘irrational’ pejoratively: we must
rather admit that an admirable moral agent is one who on occasion is irrational.
This, of course, is a new position: it may well be correct.
But this is precisely my view of the lorry driver scenario. It is admirable for
the driver to feel guilt about the accident that is, strictly speaking, irrational.
The driver’s guilt attributes some grounds for blame to himself that are not
present, by stipulation—a stipulation to which the driver cannot help
himself. The driver’s initial tendency should be considered, to paraphrase
Williams, as a reassuring sign that he takes his agency seriously.25
This solution will remain elusive, however, so long as the different forms
of normative assessment are conflated with the term “rational” (or any
other word). Only by differentiating between the rational and the admir-
able can we explicate what Williams calls the non-pejorative sense of
irrationality. Moreover, once this distinction is made, it no longer seems
necessary to coin an emotion that the driver can rationally feel; hence there
is no need to coin agent-regret to do that job. And this, in turn, would
allow Williams to acknowledge that it is irrational guilt that we can expect
the driver to feel, not rational agent-regret. It also solves the problem noted
earlier, that his catch-all notion of agent-regret makes it mysterious why
that emotion has such disparate forms of expression in action: it sometimes
issues in the motive to make reparations, sometimes to change policy, and
other times to do neither. That can be easily explained once we notice that
the emotion is sometimes guilt and sometimes regret, and that it is not
always rational even when it is predictable, and indeed admirable, to feel.
Even if guilt can be rationally felt only over actions for which we
are responsible, it can be reliably predicted in other circumstances as well.
The most admirable sort of person—within the constraints imposed by a
realistic moral psychology—will initially be prone to unjustified guilt when
he is an innocent causal agent of disaster; but he will also be “moveable”
25
I want to thank Michael McKenna for pressing the point that the agency principle
does not operate solely under conditions of uncertainty. In my view, uncertainty is
sufficient for justifying some such feelings, but I do not hold that it is necessary. Much
will depend upon the context, and people can disagree about what virtue demands.
116 Daniel Jacobson
26
I am indebted to Tim Scanlon for this way of putting the worry, which I find
particularly challenging. It has been extremely helpful to me to think through my
response to this challenge.
Regret, Agency, Error 117
emotion that you can feel rationally but the mere spectator cannot. Yet this
constructed emotion explicates nothing. We might just as well have said
that although both you and the spectator can be dismayed at this terrible
event, only you can (rationally) be dismayed while having the thought that
it would have been better had you parked elsewhere.
Contrast dismay with regret. Dismay has no coherent motivational
component; there is no characteristic action-tendency common to its
disparate instances. One can be dismayed about all sorts of misfortune,
and one will act and express such dismay very differently depending on the
context. These actions and expressions will be explicable in terms of the
underlying sentiment producing them: if I feel guilty, I will act on my
dismay in one way; if I am ashamed, in another; and if I am angry, in an
altogether different manner. Moreover, when dismay is recalcitrant, it will
be recalcitrant as a sentiment: as regret, guilt, shame, or anger. And when it
issues in acting without thinking, the action motivated will again be the
characteristic motivation of some particular sentiment. Of course what
I have been calling agent-dismay is precisely Williams’s notion of agent-
regret. But the dispute over what to call this emotion is not mere semantics,
because calling it regret obscures what is distinctive about regret as a
sentiment: that it focuses on our errors and motivates policy change.
This discussion has also aimed to illuminate why, although it is cheap to
construct new emotions by their constitutive thoughts, that approach does
not advance our understanding.
greater, which gives an evaluative reason to do the lesser rather than the
greater.”27 This suggests a gloss of regret in terms of the thought, “How
much better, in some respect, if I had done otherwise”—which is exactly
the constitutive thought of agent-regret according to Williams.
We should not accept an account of regret that marginalizes the central
scenario in order to capture the peripheral, even if the latter are more
philosophically interesting. The gloss of regret in terms of this thought
threatens to do just that. Since the thought is true both when the agent errs
and when he makes the right choice in a hard case, the account assimilates
error and loss. This threatens the idea that regret serves as a sentiment
whose function involves learning from one’s mistakes, because cases of loss
without error should not motivate any change of policy. However we use
the term regret, we must not lose sight of this sentiment or fail to notice its
importance. Even in difficult choice situations, where we will be emotion-
ally conflicted no matter what we do, our aim is surely to make the right
decision. In deliberation we seek to avoid error and the sentiment con-
cerned with sanctioning errors, even if a painful emotion concerned with
loss is unavoidable.
Like Williams’s agency principle and the lorry driver, Stocker’s argument
moves very quickly and with great rhetorical insistence from the predictabil-
ity of an emotion to its rationality. Indeed, we ordinarily grant a presumption
of warrant to our actual feelings and, especially, to what we are stably prone
to feel. Hence the burden lies with those arguing against the rationality of
feelings to which almost everyone would be prone. Yet recall the lesson of the
lorry driver example. Even though we can predict that ordinary, decent
people will feel guilty over being the causal agent of disaster despite their
lack of culpability, there is an explanation ready-to-hand that undermines the
rationality of such predictable guilt. This explanation invokes the deeply
unrealistic idealization of such examples. Someone actually in the driver’s
unfortunate situation cannot be certain of his lack of culpability, let alone
stipulate it. The trouble with the lorry driver case is that it is designed to be
unusual and, in this crucial respect, deeply unrealistic.
A similar problem infects the dilemma cases. In ordinary life, we make
decisions under conditions of uncertainty. Even if the reasons I’m aware of
27
This is the core intuition behind Stocker’s (1996) argument from rational regret
for value pluralism. However, I do not think that the distinction between choices that
justify emotional conflict and conflict over unimportant matters tracks the distinction
between kinds of value. So although I accept value pluralism, I do not find this argument
for it compelling, because the sort of loss that can rationally be emotionally conflicted
can involve one value instantiated in qualitatively different ways or distributed to
different people. In just this respect, I agree with Hurka (1996a, 1996b), but see fn. 29.
120 Daniel Jacobson
favor buying the country house rather than renting in the city, one never
knows—the well could be about to run dry. The general problem with
much of this literature about conflicts and dilemmas is that it focuses on the
most extreme sort of cases and ignores the commonplace uncertainty under
which we make decisions. I suggest we look to more mundane scenarios
where we can expect to feel regret no matter what we do, such as buying a
house. Psychological realism here dictates that we can expect to vacillate
between buyer’s remorse and renter’s regret (as it were) without any new
evidence. This vacillation should not be mysterious, as it has an explicable
source. Our anxiety over such large but hardly heroic or tragic decisions
makes the problems with whatever is currently the likely outcome more
salient, as well as the attractions of the alternative likely forgone. When the
likelihoods change so does the salience, even when nothing else about the
choice alters.
This rather obvious point goes underappreciated in this literature. There
are many circumstances in which you can reliably expect to feel regret no
matter what you do, not because of some deep fact about value or morality,
but because of familiar human tendencies such as those present when
deliberating over buying a house. No important lesson for value theory
can be drawn from the all-too-human phenomenon of shifting salience of
goods and the anxiety produced by prospective regret.28 The fact that
you will feel regret no matter what you do must serve as a defeater of
the presumption of warrant one normally accords to one’s emotions and
dispositions to feel. If I will regret whatever I do, then it would be a mistake
to accord that regret any evidential weight with respect to my decision.
How can I know if it is ordinary regret over making the wrong choice or
residual regret over the right choice? Moreover, we can reliably predict
regret over the better choice when, for reasons that could not be foreseen,
the choice turns out badly. The recognizable human tendency to commit a
“bad outcome, therefore bad decision” fallacy also serves as a defeater in
many mundane cases concerning regret. These are strong reasons not to
accept the normative corollary vindicating the rationality of residual
regrets, even where we accept the residue principle predicting them.
Nevertheless, a profound insight underlies the examples Stocker and
Williams consider, which might be taken to motivate a broader conception
of regret than my error-focused gloss. Their insight is that there is an
ethically important difference between true sacrifices and mere forgone
goods. Consider this example drawn from Stocker. Suppose a man must
28
To be clear, some very interesting results in decision theory and experimental
economics might issue from such phenomena. But these are psychological not axiological
conclusions.
Regret, Agency, Error 121
29
The counterargument given by Hurka (1996a, 1996b) looks like a reductio ad
absurdum of this claim. In his view, whenever you choose the best vacation out of ten
good choices, for example, you should rationally regret not choosing the other nine
(albeit not “to excess”). But any actual bad feeling about the unlimited number of lesser
but still good alternatives would be unseemly. Hurka’s (2001) view makes regret not an
emotion but an evaluative judgment, which is just what he does with love as well,
following Brentano (1969).
122 Daniel Jacobson
feel this way—does not apply to many cases where we sacrifice one kind of
value for another, simply because the good forgone is insufficiently import-
ant. Yet it does hold about some cases where the same kind of value is
at stake in both options, when the choices are qualitatively different
in important respects.30 To be seriously dismayed over genuine losses
of value is compatible with being an admirable person facing an
uncooperative world that demands sacrifice; whereas to be dismayed over
not getting everything you want, though a recognizably human tendency,
falls into the sphere of vice. As Stocker has aptly put the point: it makes you
a whiner. While we could stipulate that dismay is rational only in cases of
significant loss, this will be true by definition; moreover, the rationality
conditions of this residual emotion will be parasitic on an aretaic judgment
about the agent.
Williams’s lorry driver scenario and Stocker’s argument about conflicts
of value share certain virtues and vices. Keen psychological insight underlies
their core claims, particularly about human emotional propensities. These
insights are sometimes obscured, though, by an insufficiently discrimin-
ating theory of emotion. The failure to differentiate adequately between
regret, guilt, and dismay prevents them from drawing the right philosoph-
ical lesson from the psychological data. It is true that we can expect the
decent lorry driver to feel something different from a mere spectator to the
tragedy. He will feel guilt, even though his guilt is (by a stipulation
unavailable to him) unfitting. It is irrational guilt that an admirable person
can nevertheless be expected to feel, at least until he becomes convinced of
his blamelessness. Analogously, Stocker’s cases of conflicts of value reflect
the insight that bad feelings are often driven by uncertainty and anxiety
over our decisions. Sometimes they reflect a good forgone that deserves
tribute from our feelings, but is not best understood as regret. Here we can
say that bad feeling over making the best choice is either rational dismay
about some good forgone or irrational regret over a correct decision—or
perhaps some vacillation between the two.
30
We would need a coherent account of the distinction between value monism and
pluralism to make this argument rigorous, and I’m not sure that one can be found. See
Chang (2001) for doubts along these lines. It suffices for present purposes that different
varieties of sensual pleasure—which must be granted to be instances of the same type of
value if anything is to count as monism—can be sufficiently qualitatively different as to
justify some dismay over forgone choices. This much seems clear to me, though I am
reluctant to go into detail about cases.
Regret, Agency, Error 123
REFERENCES
Gigerenzer, Gerd and Peter Todd (1999). “Fast and Frugal Heuristics: The Adap-
tive Toolbox.” In Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart, eds. Gigerenzer, Todd,
et al. (New York: Oxford University Press).
Greenspan, Patricia (1988). Emotions and Reasons: An Inquiry into Emotional
Justification. (London: Routledge).
—— (1992). “Subjective Guilt and Responsibility.” Mind 101: 287–303.
Griffiths, Paul (2004). “Is Emotion a Natural Kind?” In Emotion, Evolution and
Rationality, eds. P. Cruse.and D. Evans. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Hume, David (1978) [1739]. A Treatise of Human Nature, 2nd edn., ed.
L. A. Selby-Bigge. (Oxford: Clarendon).
Hurka, Thomas (1996a). “Monism, Pluralism, and Rational Regret.” Ethics 106:
555–75.
—— (1996b). “Reply to Critics.” BEARS Symposium, eds. Jamie Dreier and David
Estlund. <http://www.brown.edu/Departments/Philosophy/bears/homepage.html>.
—— (2001). Virtue, Vice, and Value. (New York: Oxford University Press).
Jacobson, Daniel (1997). “In Praise of Immoral Art.” Philosophical Topics 25:
155–99.
—— (2005). “Seeing by Feeling: Virtues, Skills, and Moral Perception.” Ethical
Theory and Moral Practice 8: 387–409.
Knobe, Joshua (2006). “The Concept of Intentional Action: A Case Study in the
Uses of Folk Psychology.” Philosophical Studies 130: 203–31.
Nussbaum, Martha (2001). Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotion.
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Roberts, Robert (1988). “What an Emotion Is: A Sketch.” The Philosophical Review
97: 183–209.
Rorty, Amélie (1978). “Explaining Emotions.” In Explaining Emotions, ed. Amélie
Rorty. (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1980).
Rosebury (1995). “Moral Responsibility and Moral Luck.” The Philosophical Review
104: 499–524.
—— (1980). “Agent Regret.” In Explaining Emotions, ed. Amélie Rorty. (Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press).
Solomon, Robert (1998). “On Emotions as Judgments,” reprinted in Not Passion’s
Slave: Emotions and Choice. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).
Stocker, Michael (1971). “ ‘Ought’ and ‘Can’.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy
49: 303–16.
—— (1990). Plural and Conflicting Values. (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
—— (1996). “Symposium: Monism, Pluralism, and Rational Regret.” BEARS
Symposium, eds. Jamie Dreier and David Estlund. <http://www.brown.edu/
Departments/Philosophy/bears/homepage.html>.
Tangney, June (1995). “Shame and Guilt in Interpersonal Relationships.” In Self-
Conscious Emotions: The Psychology of Shame, Guilt, Embarrassment, and Pride,
eds. June Tangney and Kurt Fischer. (New York: Guilford Press).
—— and Ronda Dearing (2002). Shame and Guilt. (New York: Guilford Press).
Regret, Agency, Error 125
Taylor, Gabrielle (1985). Pride, Shame, and Guilt: Emotions of Self-assessment. (New
York: Oxford University Press).
Williams, Bernard (1965). “Ethical Consistency,” reprinted in Williams (1973a).
—— (1973a). Problems of the Self. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
—— (1973b). “Against Utilitarianism.” In J. J. C. Smart and Bernard Williams,
Utilitarianism: For and Against. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
—— (1976). “Moral Luck,” reprinted in Williams (1981).
—— (1979). “Conflicts of Values,” reprinted in Williams (1981).
—— (1981). Moral Luck. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
—— (1993). Shame and Necessity. (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press).
5
Phenomenal Abilities: Incompatibilism
and the Experience of Agency*
Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
1 . B A C K G R O UN D
1.1 Introduction
Agents act. They buy detergent at the store, they go to work, they celebrate
holidays, they cheat on their taxes. Sometimes we hold agents morally
responsible for what they do, or what they fail to do, meting out credit
and blame as the occasion merits. In typical cases, when agents act they are
thought to have an ability to do otherwise. This is a point on which most
parties to the free-will debates agree. When it comes to characterizing the
ability to do otherwise and asking whether this ability is compatible with
determinism, however, there is no consensus.
In the ensuing debates, the experience as of having an ability to do
otherwise occupies a central role.1 Many libertarians, for instance,
maintain that the ability experienced is incompatible with determinism
(Campbell 1951; O’Connor 1995). Of course, some compatibilists have
challenged this idea (Mill 1865; Grünbaum 1952; Nahmias et al. 2004).
Despite the centrality of the phenomenology of agency in all this, there has
been strikingly little work on its characteristics. Of particular significance,
there is almost no empirical work on whether the experience of agency
* We thank Eddy Nahmias, Dana Nelkin, Paulo Sousa, David Shoemaker, Uriah
Kriegel, and Bertram Malle for comments on earlier drafts.We are also grateful to partici-
pants at the New Orleans Workshop on Agency and Responsibility (November 3–5, 2011)
and two anonymous reviewers at OUP for suggestions and comments.
1 For some of the literature on the ability to do otherwise, see Moore (1912); Berofsky
(2002); J. Campbell (2005); Perry (2004); Vihvelin (2004); Smith (2004); Fara (2008);
John M. Fischer (2008); Randolph Clarke (2009). The claim that moral responsibility
requires alternative possibilities has been disputed since Frankfurt (1969). However, it is
still widely contended that free will requires being able to do otherwise.
Phenomenal Abilities 127
2 One exception in the recent literature is a paper by Nahmias and colleagues (2004),
which we discuss in Section 1.3. Although we challenge their experimental results, we are
indebted to them for pioneering the investigation. We also draw on their scholarship in
setting out some of the historical statements below. See also Monroe and Malle (2010).
3 In the experiments below, we will present this idea in terms of causation to make it
more intuitive and accessible.
128 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
Everyone must make the introspective experiment for himself: but I may perhaps
venture to report . . . that I cannot help believing that it lies with me here and now,
quite absolutely, which of two genuinely open possibilities I adopt. (1951: 463)
Campbell goes on to argue that, unless we have good reason to doubt the
impression that “it lies with me” which of two possibilities I adopt, we
should accept the impression to reflect the truth. Timothy O’Connor
makes this move as well. First, O’Connor describes the character of the
experience of decision-making:
[T]he agency theory is appealing because it captures the way we experience our own
activity. It does not seem to me (at least ordinarily) that I am caused to act by the
reasons which favor doing so; it seems to be the case, rather, that I produce my
decision in view of those reasons, and could have, in an unconditional sense, decided
differently. (1995: 196)
Next, O’Connor says that we should take these experiences to reflect
something important about the nature of decision-making:
Such experiences could, of course, be wholly illusory, but do we not properly
assume, in the absence of strong countervailing reasons, that things are pretty
much the way they appear to us? . . . Skepticism about the veridicality of such
experiences has numerous isomorphs that, if accepted, appear to lead to a greatly
diminished assessment of our knowledge of the world, an assessment that most
philosophers would resist. (1995: 196–7)
A number of compatibilists have challenged the basic phenomenological
claim. These compatibilists deny that we experience our agency as incom-
patible with determinism. John Stuart Mill, for instance, writes,
Take any alternative: say to murder or not to murder. . . . If I elect to abstain: in what
sense am I conscious that I could have elected to commit the crime? Only if I had
desired to commit it with a desire stronger than my horror of murder; not with one
less strong. When we think of ourselves hypothetically as having acted otherwise
than we did, we always suppose a difference in the antecedents: we picture ourselves
as having known something that we did not know, or not known something that we
did know; which is a difference in the external motives; or as having desired
something, or disliked something, more or less than we did; which is a difference
in the internal motives. (1865: 285)
On Mill’s view, the feeling of the ability to do otherwise is always contin-
gent on our supposing that the situation prior to the decision was somehow
different. Adolf Grünbaum repudiates any incompatibilist element with
equal vigor:
Let us carefully examine the content of the feeling that on a certain occasion we
could have acted other than the way we did. . . . Does the feeling we have inform us
Phenomenal Abilities 129
that we could have acted otherwise under exactly the same external and internal
motivational conditions? No, . . . this feeling simply discloses that we were able to act
in accord with our strongest desire at that time, and that we could indeed have acted
otherwise if a different motive had prevailed at the time. (1952: 672)
Grünbaum’s last sentence here gestures at the payoff of denying the phenom-
enological claim of incompatibilist agency: if Mill and Grünbaum are right,
then the feeling of being able to do otherwise is consistent with determinism,
and this would undercut a crucial motivation for libertarianism.
This situation might seem to be a dialectical stalemate (cf. Fischer 1994:
84). However, these philosophers are making general claims about the
nature of our experience of agency. These are empirical claims, and they
can be illuminated by taking up empirical methods.
2. S T UD Y 1
2.1 Overview
In our first study, we had participants imagine a decision about whether to
go left or right on a sled. In one condition, the sledding scenario was set in
the future; in the other condition, the scenario was set in the past. After
reading the scenario, participants in condition 1 were asked whether they
had a feeling of an ability to do otherwise; participants in condition 2 were
asked for a retrospective judgment about whether they could have done
otherwise. Participants who affirmed feeling (or having) an ability to do
otherwise were directed to the training section in which causal complete-
ness (i.e. determinism) was explained to them. Participants who passed the
training were reminded of their affirmation regarding the ability to do
otherwise and asked about consistency with causal completeness.
Our prediction was that when asked about the phenomenology of
imagined decision-making, participants would tend to affirm a feeling of
an ability to do otherwise and also regard this feeling as incompatible with
determinism; but when asked for a retrospective judgment about the ability
to do otherwise, we predicted that participants would be less likely to treat
the ability to do otherwise in an incompatibilist way.4
4 See e.g. van Inwagen 1983 (8–13) for an overview of other uses of “can.”
132 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
Method:
Participants:
Eighty-four participants were initially recruited online through the Mech-
anical Turk (MTurk) website.5 The survey itself was conducted using
SurveyMonkey. Two participants did not complete the survey. They were
excluded from the analysis.
Materials:
Each condition had three parts.
given a similar question to see if they had absorbed the training. If they
answered incorrectly yet again, they did not move on to answer the
compatibility question, as they were deemed to have insufficient compre-
hension of causal completeness.
Participants who passed this first kind of question either on the first or
second try were given another true/false question to test for comprehension:
According to causal completeness, if a week from now Barack Obama decides to
have soda with dinner, all the events leading up to that decision will make it the case
that he has to decide to have a soda with dinner.
Our objective here was to test for and correct overly weak interpretations of
causal completeness. Those who answered “False” (the incorrect answer)
were corrected and given another chance at a similar question. If they
answered incorrectly yet again they failed the training and did not answer
the compatibility question. Participants who passed both kinds of questions
either on the first or second try were deemed to have adequate comprehen-
sion of determinism, and these participants moved on to the third part of
the study, the compatibility question.
Results:
Of the thirty-four participants who started condition 1, thirty-three com-
pleted it. Of these, thirty-one indicated a phenomenology of an ability to
choose among possibilities and all but four of them passed the training
section.8 The remaining twenty-seven participants gave a mean response
of 4.93 on the compatibility question, which differed significantly from
the midpoint of the scale, t(26) = 2.65, p = .014. That is, participants
tended to interpret their agentive experience as being incompatible with
determinism.
In condition 2, of the fifty participants who started the survey, forty-nine
completed it. Of these, forty-seven indicated an ability to choose among
possibilities and all but two of them passed the training section.9 The
remaining forty-five participants gave a mean response of 5.24 on the
compatibility question, which differed significantly from the midpoint of
the scale, t(44) = 5.05, p < .001.
A t-test comparing conditions 1 and 2 showed no significant difference,
p = .448. So participants tended to be just as incompatibilist about
retrospective judgments of their ability to do otherwise as they are
about their current experience as of being able to do otherwise. This
first study provides evidence that people do indeed judge that their
experience of deciding is inconsistent with determinism, in the sense
that the experience is somehow mistaken or nonveridical if determinism
is true. It also suggests that the effect is robust across retrospective and
present-focused cases.
3. S T UD Y 2
3.1 Overview
One major limitation of study 1 is that it involved merely imagined
choices. This inserts a distance between the actual phenomenology of
decision-making and judgments about that phenomenology. As a result,
in study 2 we introduce conditions in which agents actually make decisions.
In addition, study 1 focused on decisions that have no moral weight. We
8 Nine participants required correction, and ultimately passed the training section.
The responses of those who required correction did not differ from those who answered
correctly without training (p >.2).
9 Seven participants required correction, and ultimately passed the training section.
Again, there were no differences between those who required correction and those who
didn’t.
136 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
thus added a condition in study 2 in which the decision does have a moral
element. So this study comprises three conditions to test for any effect from
actual choices or from morally salient choices. We also introduced two
innovations to the study’s design.
First, we wanted to make our vignette more “choicey”. It struck us that in
situations such as sledding down a hill often we don’t have a salient
experience as of deciding which way to go. We just go one way or the
other. Second, we wanted to address a potential worry about our use of the
word “mistaken” in the compatibility question. For example, in condition
1 from our first study, we asked:
Even though it felt like I could either go to the left or go to the right, if causal
completeness is true there is something mistaken about how that decision felt to me.
(Emphasis added.)
One worry about this wording was that participants might misinterpret
it as asking whether they were mistaken in thinking that their experiences
felt a certain way, rather than as asking whether there would be something
mistaken about the content of their felt experiences.10 Our solution was to
replace the above wording with a wording of the following form:
Even though it felt like I could either choose to X or choose to Y, if causal
completeness is true then I couldn’t really have chosen differently than I did.11
With these modifications, condition 1 presented participants with an
imagined choice among two very similar charities, condition 2 presented
participants with an actual choice among two similar charities, and condi-
tion 3 presented participants with an actual morally salient choice among
two charities, one for endangered trees, another for children’s cancer
treatments.
Method:
Participants:
One hundred and fifty-five participants were initially recruited online
through the Mechanical Turk (MTurk) website. The survey itself was
conducted using SurveyMonkey. Twenty-one participants did not com-
plete the survey, or indicated that they had recently taken a “very similar”
survey.12 They were excluded from the analysis.
Materials:
As in study 1, this study had three parts.
12 Studies 2 and 3 were run after study 1, and some of the conditions in studies 2 and
3 were run serially, so we excluded participants who indicated they had taken a very
similar survey to minimize the influence of having previously taken one of our surveys.
13 Castanea Dentata and Ulmus Dentata are the names of the American Chestnut and
the American Elm, respectively. They are endangered species in North America. The
charities we used were The American Chestnut Foundation <http://www.acf.org/>, and
Trees Winnipeg: Coalition to Save the Elms <http://www.savetheelms.mb.ca/>.
14 <http://www.candlelighters.ca>.
138 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
Part 2: Training on determinism The training section was the same as that
used in study 1, and once again only those who passed the training
proceeded to the compatibility question.
Part 3: Consistency The compatibility question was adapted for the new
cases. For example, in conditions 1 and 2, participants were asked to
indicate agreement (on a 7-point scale) with this statement:
Even though it felt like I could either choose to donate to Castanea Dentata or
choose to donate to Ulmus Dentata, if causal completeness is true then I couldn’t
really have chosen differently than I did.
Results:
Of the fifty participants who started condition 1, forty-two completed it
and had not recently taken a very similar survey (three had). Of these,
thirty-eight indicated a phenomenology of an ability to choose among
possibilities and all but three of them passed the training section.16 The
remaining thirty-five participants gave a mean response of 5.60 on the
compatibility question, which differed significantly from the midpoint of
the scale, t(34) = 6.08, p < .001. The results of an imagined choice are
consistent with the results of condition 1, study 1, if not stronger by virtue
of the more “choicey” vignette.
In condition 2, of the forty-eight participants who started the survey,
forty-two completed it and had not recently taken a very similar survey (four
had). Of these, thirty-nine indicated a phenomenology of an ability to choose
among possibilities and all but two of them passed the training section.17
The remaining thirty-seven participants gave a mean response of 5.78 on
the compatibility question, which differed significantly from the midpoint
of the scale, t(36) = 6.85, p < .001. That is, participants were again
incompatibilist about the phenomenology, this time of an actual choice.
In condition 3, of the fifty-seven participants who started the survey, fifty
completed it and had not recently taken a very similar survey (three had).
Of these, forty-three indicated a phenomenology of an ability to choose
among possibilities and all but three of them passed the training section.18
Most of the remaining forty participants (90 percent) opted to donate to
the Childhood Cancer Foundation, as we expected on the assumption that
the cancer charity would be regarded as more morally salient. The forty
participants gave a mean response of 5.85 on the compatibility question,
which differed significantly from the midpoint of the scale, t(39) = 7.66,
p < .001. Once again we find incompatibilist phenomenology—this time
with a morally salient choice.
ANOVA testing showed no overall effect of condition among conditions
1, 2, and 3, F(2, 111) = .254, p = .776. So there appears to be no effect
produced by making the condition an actual choice, or by making the
choice morally salient.
The results of study 2 show that people report incompatibilist phenom-
enology of agency for actual choices. Indeed, whether the decision is set up
as an imagined one or an actual one does not affect the degree to which
participants interpret their agentive experience as being incompatible with
determinism. The results also show that whether or not the decision is
morally salient doesn’t affect the degree to which participants interpret
their agentive experience as being incompatible with determinism. So the
results of previous studies seem to extend to the moral domain, where issues
of responsibility loom large.
17 Six participants required correction and successfully passed the training section.
There was no difference between the responses of those who required correction and
those who didn’t (p > .2).
18 Six participants required correction and successfully passed the training section.
Again, we found no difference between the responses of those who required correction
and those who didn’t (p > .2).
140 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
4. S T UD Y 3
4.1 Overview
One possible concern with our previous studies stems from the way we have
phrased the key compatibility question. Notice our use of an “even though”
locution in the following:
Even though it felt like I could either choose to donate to Castanea Dentata or
choose to donate to Ulmus Dentata, if causal completeness is true then I couldn’t
really have chosen differently than I did. (Emphasis added.)
Although we took this to be a natural phrasing of the question, one might
think that “even though” primes the participant to agree with the state-
ment, which in this case is an incompatibilist response. Our final study
drops this potentially troublesome phrase and also tests whether the phe-
nomenology of epistemic uncertainty differs from the phenomenology of
being able to do otherwise in terms of compatibility with determinism. In
condition 1, we once again presented participants with an actual choice
among two options and tested whether they would continue to report
having an incompatibilist phenomenology as of being able to do otherwise.
In condition 2, we focused on epistemic phenomenology.
Method:
Participants:
One hundred and six participants were initially recruited online through
the Mechanical Turk (MTurk) website. The survey itself was conducted
using SurveyMonkey. Fifteen participants did not complete the survey, or
indicated that they had recently taken a “very similar” survey. They were
excluded from the analysis.
Materials:
The vignette and first question for condition 1 read as follows.
First, consider how things seem to you as you face your decision. In particular,
consider what it’s like to decide which option to choose.
In condition 1, participants were asked to indicate agreement (on a 1–7
scale) with the following statement:
When deciding which option to choose, it feels like I can either choose H or
choose V.
Condition 2 was the same except that we dropped the modal “can” and
asked participants to “consider what it’s like to wonder which option you’ll
choose.” Participants were then asked to indicate their level of agreement
with a statement about epistemic phenomenology:
When wondering which option I’ll choose, it feels like I don’t know for sure before
I select a button which button is the bonus button.
As in study 1, only participants who agreed with the initial statement
proceeded to the training.
The two available options—H and V—appeared at the bottom of the
screen, with a radio button representing each option. Participants were not
told whether they had chosen the bonus button (H) until after they had
answered the compatibility question.
Part 2: Training on determinism The training section was the same as that
used in study 1, and again participants only proceeded to the compatibility
question if they passed the training.
Part 3: Consistency The compatibility question was adjusted for the new
cases. In condition 1, participants were told:
Now, recall the button-choosing situation. You previously agreed with the
following statement:
When deciding which option to choose, it feels like I can either choose H or choose V.
Considering this previous statement about how things felt to you before your choice
and your understanding of causal completeness, please indicate your level of
agreement with the following:
If causal completeness is true, then I couldn’t really have chosen differently than
I did.
In condition 2, participants were reminded that they agreed with this
statement:
When wondering which option I’ll choose, it feels like I don’t know for sure before
I select a button which button is the bonus button.
142 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
They were then asked to indicate their level of agreement with the
following:
If causal completeness is true, then I knew for sure before I selected a button which
button was the bonus button.
Our aim was to test whether participants distinguish the sort of alternative
possibilities they reported themselves as experiencing in other conditions
from clearly compatibilist alternative possibilities, which have to do simply
with our ignorance of the future.
Results:
Of the fifty-three participants who started condition 1, forty-seven com-
pleted it and had not recently taken a very similar survey (two had). Of
these, forty-four indicated a phenomenology as of there being alternative
possibilities in the situation and all but three of them passed the training
section.19 The remaining forty-one participants gave a mean response of
5.34 on the compatibility question, which differed significantly from the
midpoint of the scale, t(40) = 4.54, p < .001. That is, participants once
again demonstrated a strong tendency to interpret their agentive experience
as being incompatible with determinism.
In condition 2, of the fifty-three participants who started the survey,
forty-four completed it and had not recently taken a very similar survey
(eight had). Of these, thirty-nine indicated a phenomenology of an ability
to choose among possibilities and all but one of them passed the training
section.20 The remaining thirty-eight participants gave a mean response of
2.66 on the compatibility question, which differed significantly from the
midpoint of the scale, t(37) = -5.23, p < .001. That is, participants tended
to regard their phenomenology of uncertainty about the future as
compatible with determinism. A t-test between conditions 1 and 2 showed
that results differed significantly between these two conditions, t(76) = 6.85,
p < .001.
This final study provides yet further evidence that people do indeed
judge that their experience of deciding is inconsistent with determinism, in
the sense that the experience is nonveridical if determinism is true. At the
19 Eight participants required correction, and passed the training section. There was a
significant difference in responses between those who required correction and those who
didn’t. Those who required correction reported that their phenomenology was incom-
patible with CC (M = 4.25) but to a lesser degree than those who answered these
questions correctly the first time (M = 5.60), p = .057.
20 Nine participants required correction, and passed the training section. There were
no statistically significant differences in responses between those who required extra
training and those who didn’t (p = .2).
Phenomenal Abilities 143
same time, people tend to think that the feeling of not knowing what will
happen is perfectly consistent with determinism. This suggests an appro-
priate sensitivity to the fact that ignorance is not incompatible with
determinism.
5. GENERAL DISCUSSION
5.1 Incompatibilism
Our results have implications for several issues concerning free will. Per-
haps most importantly, our studies seem to vindicate the incompatibilist
descriptions of our experience as of being able to do otherwise suggested by
Campbell, O’Connor, and Searle. By the same token, our results run
counter to the compatibilist descriptions of our experience suggested by
Mill, Grünbaum, and Nahmias and colleagues. The design of our studies
left it open for participants to describe their experience as involving the
ability to do otherwise, while allowing them to interpret this ability
however they wished. The results indicate that the people in the population
we tested tended to judge that their experience was incompatible with
determinism.
The results also address a concern that has plagued recent work
on intuitions about free will. Nahmias and Murray (2011) contend
that people give incompatibilist responses in previous experiments simply
because people misunderstand determinism. This is an important concern.
But rather than merely testing to see whether people misunderstand
determinism, we attacked the comprehension issue directly by exploiting
the familiar technique of training to criterion. And we did not find any
widespread confusion of determinism and bypassing. Part 1 of our training
controls for confusion between determinism and fatalism, and the majority
of our participants reported that the accuracy of their experience as of being
able to do otherwise is inconsistent with determinism, correctly understood.
Across all our studies, the percentage of participants who didn’t make it to
the compatibility question due to failing the training section was small,
at 6.15 percent. When we look at those participants who answered part 1
of the training incorrectly—that is, at those who did initially confuse
determinism with fatalism, and who were directed to the follow-up
training question—the percentage was small compared with Nahmias
and Murray’s results: only 20.68 percent of participants initially made
this mistake. Of those who initially made the mistake, 85.71 percent
answered the follow-up training question correctly. Thus, fewer than 3
percent of participants continued to confuse determinism and fatalism after
144 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
training. And those who required correction did not respond in any
significant way differently from those who didn’t.21
21 Again, with the exception of study 2, condition 1, and study 3, condition 1. (See
footnotes 16 and 19.)
22 Vihvelin’s exact formulation is as follows: “S has the ability at time t to do X iff, for
some intrinsic property or set of properties B that S has at t, for some time t´ after t, if S
chose (decided, intended, or tried) at t to do X, and S were to retain B until t´, S’s
choosing (deciding, intending, or trying) to do X and S’s having of B would jointly be an
S-complete cause of S’s doing X ” (2004: 438).
23 For similar accounts, see Smith (2004) and Fara (2008). Questions persist (see e.g.
Clarke 2009) about whether any “dispositionalist” account is an adequate analysis of the
ability to act, and thus of the ability to act otherwise.
Phenomenal Abilities 145
I’m saying is that, before Oswald pulled the trigger, for all anyone knew, he
wouldn’t pull the trigger. If I’m merely making a claim about epistemic
possibilities, then there is no conflict with determinism.
By contrast, incompatibilists think being able to do otherwise (in the
relevant contexts) means being able to do something other than what one
does, all prior conditions (including one’s desires) remaining the same.
This ability is presumed to be a matter of fact, not something about our
epistemic access to facts.
At least insofar as the relevant notion of the ability to do otherwise is
reflected in the experience as of being able to do otherwise, our results
suggest that the compatibilist accounts fail. Across three studies, partici-
pants tended to interpret their agentive experience in terms of an ability to
do otherwise, and they interpreted that ability incompatibilistically. Con-
cerning the traditional compatibilist analysis, our results equally undercut
old and new versions. After all, we allowed participants to describe their
experiences as involving the ability to do otherwise or not, where they were
free to interpret this ability however they wished. Participants then judged
that this ability—the one they had been allowed to interpret however they
wished—was incompatible with determinism. The epistemic compatibilist
account is also undermined by these results. Participants gave compatibilist
judgments about the case of ignorance about the future (study 3, condition 2),
indicating that they do have an appreciation that the feeling of uncertainty
is consistent with determinism.
We conclude that the notion of “can do otherwise,” at least with respect
to one’s decisions, is naturally interpreted in ways that contravene the most
familiar compatibilist approaches in the philosophical literature. When
participants attend to their experience while they consider future events,
their usage of “can” tends to reflect a sense of metaphysical openness that is
incompatible with determinism.
determinism . . . , one feels some tendency to judge that the answer to such compati-
bility questions is No. (Forthcoming)24
But Horgan notes that we must distinguish between the content of our
experience and the content of judgments. The former kind of content
Horgan dubs “presentational content,” and it
. . . is the kind that accrues to phenomenology directly—apart from whether or not
one has the capacity to articulate this content linguistically and understand what one
is thus articulating, and apart from whether or not one has the kind of sophisticated
conceptual repertoire that would be required to understand such an articulation.
(forthcoming)
By contrast, “judgmental content” is the kind of content associated with
linguistic articulations. Of course, we make judgments about our phenom-
enology, and so we can have judgmental content that aims to capture our
presentational content. The key point here is that it is possible for our
judgments about the (presentational) content of our experience to go awry.
That said, those judgments are at least prima facie evidence of the nature
of the presentational-cum-phenomenal content, we maintain, so we would
need some positive reason to think that participants have systematically
misinterpreted the nature of their phenomenology. Further, even if we
grant arguendo that the presentational content of agentive experience is (in
the first instance) compatible with determinism, and that reports to the
contrary count as mistaken interpretations, still, the fact that people judge
the experience incompatibilist would be significant. For one thing, when
considering how best to understand the notion of the “ability to do
otherwise,” in many cases what will be of primary importance is how
people think about their ability to do otherwise, and that is clearly judg-
mental. Second and more interestingly, judgmental content can feed back
into presentational content. It is well known that what one judges about a
situation can affect one’s perception of the situation. Horgan recognizes
this, and he notes that the distinction between presentational and judg-
mental content isn’t always sharp: “it may very well be that the two kinds of
content can interpenetrate to a substantial extent” (forthcoming). As a
result, even if the presentational content of agentive experience is, in the
first instance, compatibilist, that doesn’t mean that the presentational con-
tent remains compatibilist. It might be that the incompatibilist judgment
shapes the presentational content.25
24 For Horgan, this representational “aspect of freedom” is what we have been calling
the experience as of being able to do otherwise.
25 Note that Horgan’s notion of “presentational content” is not simply “raw feels”
with no propositional content. For everyone would concede that insofar as we have
Phenomenal Abilities 147
studies indicate this position is mistaken. This does not decide the dispute
concerning deliberation compatibilism, but it does show that we need to
distinguish three versions of deliberation-compatibilism:
(1) People’s beliefs about their current deliberations are compatible with
determinism;
(2) People’s beliefs about their current deliberations are not compatible
with determinism, but they can be adjusted to be compatible;
(3) People’s beliefs about their current deliberations are not, and cannot be
adjusted to be, compatible with determinism, but we can conceive of a
rational being whose beliefs about deliberation are compatible with
determinism.
Our results suggest that the first version of deliberation compatibilism is
false. People’s beliefs about their deliberations are incompatibilist. The
second version—that our actual experiences are incompatibilist but revis-
able—is an interesting possibility, but it remains an open question whether
it is possible to revise this aspect of our experience. Until we know more
about what generates the incompatibilist experience, it is hard to know
whether it can be modified. One possibility is that the incompatibilist
experience is generated in a way that is not cognitively penetrable (see
e.g. Bayne 2011). That is, it might be that even if we form the explicit high-
level belief that deliberation is theoretically compatible with determinism,
this will not eradicate our experience of our deliberation as incompatibilist.
The third version of deliberation compatibilism—that we can conceive of
rational creatures who deliberate as determinists—is not under any threat
from our results. But if it turns out to be impossible for us to be such
rational animals, that might undercut some of the interest of deliberation
compatibilism.
6 . C O N C LU S I O N
REFERENCES
Bayne, Tim (2011). “The Sense of Agency.” In F. Macpherson (ed.) The Senses.
(Oxford: Oxford University Press), 355–74.
Berofsky, Bernard (2002). “Ifs, Cans, and Free Will: The Issues.” In R. Kane (ed.) The
Oxford Handbook of Free Will. (New York: Oxford University Press), 181–201.
Buhrmester, M., T. Kwang, and S. Gosling. (2011). “Amazon’s Mechanical Turk:
A New Source of Inexpensive, Yet High-Quality, Data?” Perspectives on Psycho-
logical Science 6: 3–5.
Campbell, C. A. (1951). “Is ‘Freewill’ a Pseudo-problem?” Mind 60/240: 441–65.
Campbell, Joseph (2005). “Compatibilist Alternatives.” Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 35: 387–406.
Clarke, Randolph (2009). “Dispositions, Abilities to Act, and Free Will: The New
Dispositionalism.” Mind 118: 323–51.
Fara, Michael (2008). “Masked Abilities and Compatibilism.” Mind 117/468:
843–65.
Fischer, John M. (1994). The Metaphysics of Free Will. (Oxford: Blackwell
Publishing).
—— (2008). “Freedom, Foreknowledge, and Frankfurt: A Reply to Vihvelin.”
Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38/3: 327–42.
Frankfurt, Harry (2003/1969). “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility.”
In G. Watson (ed.) Free Will. (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 167–76.
Grünbaum, Adolf (1952). “Causality and the Science of Human Behavior.” Ameri-
can Scientist 40(4): 665–76.
Horgan, Terry (Forthcoming). “Causal Compatibilism about Agentive Phenomen-
ology.” For a festschrift for J. Kim, eds., M. Sabates, D. Sosa, and T. Horgan.
Hume, David (1960/1739). A Treatise on Human Nature, L. A. Selby-Bigge (ed.)
(Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Kapitan, Tomis (1986). “Deliberation and the Presumption of Open Alternatives.”
The Philosophical Quarterly 36/143: 230–51.
150 Oisı́n Deery, Matt Bedke, and Shaun Nichols
Lehrer, Keith (1960). “Can We Know that We have Free Will by Introspection?”
The Journal of Philosophy 57/5: 145–57.
Mill, John Stuart (1865). An Examination of William Hamilton’s Philosophy.
(Boston: William V. Spencer).
Monroe, Andrew E. and Malle, Bertram F. (2010). “From Uncaused Will to
Conscious Choice: The Need to Study, Not Speculate about People’s Folk
Concept of Free Will.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 9: 211–24.
Moore, G. E. (1912). “Free Will.” From Ethics. (Oxford: Oxford University Press),
122–37.
Nahmias, Eddy, Stephen Morris, Thomas Nadelhoffer, and Jason Turner. (2004).
“The Phenomenology of Free Will.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 11/7–8:
162–79.
Nahmias, Eddy and Dylan Murray (2011). “Experimental Philosophy on Free Will:
An Error Theory for Incompatibilist Intuitions.” In New Waves in Philosophy of
Action, Aguilar, Jesús, Andrei Buckareff and Keith Frankish (eds.) (Basingstoke,
UK: Palgrave Macmillan), 189–216.
Nelkin, Dana. (2004). “Deliberative Alternatives.” Philosophical Topics 32: 215–40.
O’Connor, Timothy (1995). “Agent Causation.” In T. O’Connor (ed.), Agents,
Causes, and Events: Essays on Indeterminism and Free Will. (New York: Oxford
University Press), 173–200.
Pereboom, Derk (2008). “A Compatibilist Account of the Epistemic Conditions on
Rational Deliberation,” The Journal of Ethics 12/3: 287–306.
Perry, John (2004). “Compatibilist Options.” In J. Campbell, M. O’Rourke,
and D. Shier (eds.) Freedom and Determinism. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press),
231–54.
Searle, John (1984). Minds, Brains, and Science. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni-
versity Press).
Smart, J. J. C. (1961). “Free Will, Praise and Blame.” Mind 70: 291–306.
Smith, Michael (2004). “Rational Capacities.” In M. Smith, Ethics and the A Priori:
Selected Essays on Moral Psychology and Meta-Ethics. (New York: Cambridge
University Press), 114–35.
Taylor, Richard (1983). Metaphysics, 3rd edn. (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice
Hall).
Van Inwagen, Peter (1983). An Essay on Free Will. (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Vihvelin, Kadri (2004). “Free Will Demystified: A Dispositional Account.”
Philosophical Topics 32: 427–50.
6
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents,
and Mechanisms1
Michael McKenna
1 This paper was written for the 2011 New Orleans Workshop on Agency and
Responsibility (NOWAR), organized by David Shoemaker. I would like to thank him
for arranging this excellent event. I delivered an earlier version of this paper to the
University of Texas at Austin Philosophy Department. I am indebted to various
members of the audience for their instructive comments and criticisms. Notable
among them were Sinan Dogramaci, Jeremy Evans, Alex Grzankowski, Bob Kane,
Chris Simpson, Nicole Smith, David Sosa, and Michael Tye. At NOWAR, I profited
from discussion with many in attendance, especially Michael Bratman, David Brink,
Sarah Buss, Stephen Kearns, Rahul Kumar, Dana Nelkin, Paul Russell, Tim Scanlon,
Josh Sheppard, David Shoemaker, (yet again) Nicole Smith, Jada Strabbing, and Gary
Watson. For further helpful advice, I would also like to thank John Martin Fischer, Ish
Haji, Terry Horgan, Al Mele, Shaun Nichols, Derk Pereboom, Carolina Sartorio, and
Brandon Warmke. Finally, I would like to thank two anonymous referees for Oxford
University Press.
2 For an examination of the further details offered in support of Frankfurt’s argu-
ment, see the introduction to Widerker and McKenna (2003), and also my (2008).
Among those who defend some variation of Frankfurt’s argument are Fischer (1994),
152 Michael McKenna
Fischer and Ravizza (1998), Haji (1998), Hunt (2000), McKenna (2003), Mele (2006),
Mele and Robb (1998), Pereboom (2001), Stump (1996), Widerker (2006), and
Zagzebski (2000).
3 I write in terms of “source freedom,” while Fischer (1994), and Fischer and Ravizza
(1998) use the term “guidance control.” I regard these terms as amounting to the same
thing. Likewise, I prefer the expression “freedom to do otherwise” or “leeway freedom,”
whereas Fischer and Ravizza write in terms of “regulative control.”
4 For example, see Hunt (2000), Pereboom (2001), Stump (1996), Widerker (2006),
and Zagzebski (2000).
5 The consequence argument was first developed by Ginet (1966), and then
subsequently refined by van Inwagen (1975), and Wiggins (1973).
6 The person who deserves the credit for this way of framing the dialectic is Fischer
(1994). Fischer coins a very similar view “semicompatibilism.” Where I differ from him
is that, on the basis of (some version of) the consequence argument, I am prepared to
grant to the incompatibilist the incompatibility of the ability to do otherwise. Fischer
instead wishes to remain uncommitted on this point.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 153
1 . T H E A P PE A L O F A R E A S O N S - R E S P O N S I V E T H E O R Y
Now, in light of the two preceding points, let us examine Fischer and
Ravizza’s carefully developed reasons-responsive theory.9 According to
them, at one end of the spectrum is strong reasons-responsiveness (SRR).
An agent who is SRR with respect to an act is such that, if there were
sufficient reason for her to do otherwise, she would do otherwise (Fischer
and Ravizza, 1998: 41). At the other end of the spectrum is weak reasons-
responsiveness (WRR). An agent who is weakly reasons-responsive with
respect to an act is such that there is at least one (nonactual) scenario in
which there is sufficient reason to do otherwise and the agent does
otherwise (44). As should be clear, and in keeping with the second point
developed above (in Section 1), SRR is too strong; if a condition of free
agency required SRR, it would turn out that almost no one acts freely and is
morally responsible for what she does. On the other hand, WRR is too
weak; if a condition of free agency required no more than WRR, it would
turn out that many severely impaired agents would fully satisfy the freedom
conditions for moral responsibility. Our compulsive hand-washer was
WRR in washing her hands since she’d have not washed them if her
children were on fire. So, what is needed, and what Fischer and Ravizza
develop in admirable detail, is a middle-of-the-spectrum degree of
responsiveness, moderate reasons-responsiveness (MRR), that is suited for
sane, competent, albeit imperfect, moral agency—the sort of agency of
which most psychologically healthy adults are capable while functioning in
normal practical contexts of deliberation and action (69–84).
So how do Fischer and Ravizza develop MRR? Understanding their
proposal requires careful attention to what is involved in being responsive
to reasons. Fischer and Ravizza distinguish between a receptivity component
and a reactivity component (1998: 41). Being reasons-receptive is a matter
of being able to recognize what reasons there are, and in particular, being
able to recognize what reasons count as sufficient for action. Being reasons-
reactive is a matter of being able to react to the reasons one recognizes as
sufficient by choosing and acting as needed. According to Fischer and
Ravizza, MRR requires moderate reasons-receptivity. For a person to be
morally responsible for what she does, she must be receptive to reasons in
9 In examining Fischer and Ravizza’s view in this section, I shall depart from their
doing so in terms of mechanisms that are reasons-responsive and that are owned by the
agent. I shall instead just write in terms of agents being reasons-responsive. In the next
section, I’ll recalibrate to fit their mechanism-based formulation.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 157
10 Fischer (2006: 328) has granted this point in response to Mele (2006b: 290), who
presses a similar worry.
11 This is needed in order to allow for cases in which an agent freely and knowingly
acts contrary to what she has sufficient reason to do. Note, however, that I have only
claimed here that the spectrum of reactivity can be weaker than that of receptivity.
Elsewhere (2005), I have made the stronger claim—that their view requires this asym-
metry. Dana Nelkin and David Brink have convinced me that this is a mistake. The
requirements of morally responsible agency do not, strictly speaking, require any asym-
metry. Nevertheless I suspect for nearly all actual persons who are morally responsible
158 Michael McKenna
the spectrum of reactivity still needs to display a sane, stable pattern along
the lines of moderate receptivity. There are further details that we might
add here to supplement Fischer and Ravizza’s proposal, or instead various
details of their thesis with which we might take issue, but for present
purposes the preceding discussion will do.
While it is important to make clear the delicate effort Fischer and
Ravizza make to get right the degree of responsiveness needed to account
for MRR, the most important factor in their account of freedom is that the
etiology of an agent’s act involved springs that were themselves sensitive to
reasons. This shows Fischer and Ravizza’s deference to the first of the two
preliminary points set out above (in Section 1). I pause here to emphasize
this since it is easy to lose sight of. The salient point to note is that by
demonstrating that when an agent acted she was MRR, one does not just
show how that agent would respond to other reasons if those reasons were
present to her. One also shows that in acting as she did, the agent was
responsive to the conditions she was actually in. Her actually-operative
springs of action were functioning in ways that themselves were responses to
the conditions in which she actually found herself.
To elaborate on the preceding point: It is easy when reflecting upon
Fischer and Ravizza’s proposal to misunderstand the theoretical purpose to
which certain counterfactuals are put. Consider a MRR agent who in
deciding to remain home and work on an article would be receptive and
reactive to the reason that the legendary blues guitarist Buddy Guy is
putting on a concert that night and she could easily go. Were she presented
with this reason, she would not work on her article. Instead, she’d go to the
show. Don’t be snookered here into thinking that what this counterfactual
is meant to establish is that, in acting as the agent did, she could have done
otherwise. That is, the point of this counterfactual, as well as other counter-
factuals involving other reasons to which this agent might be both receptive
and reactive, is not meant to establish that the agent had a freedom that
concerned alternatives to what she did do—leeway freedom. It is instead
meant to establish that in acting as she did, she was sensitive to reasons in
such a way that her actual bringing about of her act of remaining home
and working on her article was itself suitably sensitive to rational consider-
ations. Some compatibilists, such as those classical conditionalists like Ayer
(1954), Davidson (1973), Hobart (1934), and Moore (1912), attempted to
rely upon similar counterfactuals in order to account for a compatibilist
theory of the freedom to do otherwise. But Fischer and Ravizza do not
agents, there will be some asymmetry of this sort; most persons are not moved to act by
the full range of sufficient reasons for action to which they are receptive.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 159
4 . PR O B LE M S W I T H M E C H A N I S M S
12 For Fischer’s replies, see his (2004: 169–71) reply to Watson, and his (2006: 333–4)
reply to Ginet. He replies to Wallace in his (2011, ch. 9: 144–62).
13 They do offer one theoretical constraint. The descriptive content by which the
mechanism is identified must be “temporally intrinsic” (1998: 46–7). That is, it must
pick out the mechanism in such a way that it does not involve reference to later times.
Otherwise, the mechanism would require certain outcomes, and thus would not permit
variability in the face of different reasons. Hence, the temporally extrinsic mechanism
“deliberation prior to donating to a charity” is ruled out since it entails acting in a certain
way.
162 Michael McKenna
14 I am indebted to Carl Ginet for this point. See also his discussion of it (2006: 233).
15 I am indebted to Derk Pereboom, who emphasized this point.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 163
the mechanism of unreflective habit from which this agent acts is plastic
enough to allow reflection when conditions call for aborting reliance on
habit alone.
Ginet’s insightful criticism is a specific instance of a more general problem
that is bound to plague any attempt to give more content to what might count
as the conditions for individuating mechanisms. The general problem, as I see
it, is that any complex system will have “subsystems” that are designed to
function precisely by shutting down or by permitting other systems to
override in some contexts but not others. Assuming a person functioning as
a practical agent can be understood as a complex system, or at least as
relevantly analogous to one, any attempt to whittle down which agential
elements are the ones implicated in “the” mechanism of her action is bound to
restrict the agent’s flexibility as regards reasons-responsiveness.
The postulation of an agent’s mechanism of action as narrower than the
full person herself looks innocent enough when one is invited to consider a
case like Jones and note that Jones’s ability to do calculus is irrelevant to the
agent-involving factors causally contributing to the shooting of Smith.
There are likely lots of these ingredients in Jones’s complete psychic consti-
tution that could be whittled away: his love of his mother, his fondness for
kittens, and so on. But once we seek to put more meat on a restriction of a
pertinent mechanism of action, we will face problems like the one Ginet
has identified. If we back off and allow for the description of the mechan-
ism to be “fatter” so as to allow for shifts between processes like unreflective
and then reflective habit, we pretty much have what is the functional
equivalent of the agent herself as the mechanism, minus various outlier
traits like the ability to do calculus.
Reflection on complex mechanisms like automobiles or computers, things
that are built up out of smaller mechanisms, helps to illustrate the point.
Suppose that one of a computer’s programs runs unimpeded, but the
computer is designed to divert that program and prioritize other operations
if the system is under stress, or uploading new software, or about to lose
power, or what have you. The same applies to an automobile. A car will allow
things like unimpeded gas flow through the fuel injection system unless
another part of the system recognizes problems with the fuel mix or some-
thing of the sort. If we were to evaluate the degree of sensitivity of such a
system by “holding fixed the actually operative sub-mechanism” we’d ham-
string the system for a variety of conditions to which, without holding these
fixed, the larger system as a whole would be able to respond quite easily.18
18 An anonymous referee for OUP has astutely asked about the following way of
defending Fischer and Ravizza’s appeal to mechanisms. To illustrate, consider Ginet’s
example of the driver acting from the mechanism of unreflective habit. Why is it a
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 165
problem for Fischer and Ravizza that in some scenarios the agent would have to “shift” to
a different mechanism by beginning to deliberate? Isn’t it enough that the mechanism of
unreflective habit is responsive enough to certain reasons to allow for it to, so to speak,
shut down and allow another to come on line? Why isn’t this enough to say that the
mechanism is suitably reasons-responsive? In response, I acknowledge that this is after all
a thoughtful way to attempt to defend Fischer and Ravizza. But the upshot is to do so by
claiming that the full spectrum of reasons to which an agent (by way of mechanisms or
otherwise) ought to be responsive for (something like MRR) requires the postulation of a
plurality of mechanisms. At this point, it appears that it is not a matter of holding fixed a
mechanism, and now one wonders how close we are getting to just straightforwardly
talking of the responsiveness of persons.
19 In correspondence, David Shoemaker has thoughtfully expressed some skepticism
about this last point—that a more inclusive notion of a mechanism of action will be so
inclusive that we might as well identify it with the person, or with the functional
equivalent of the person. In conversation, Shaun Nichols has as well, citing the work
by Fodor on the modularity of the mind. Here, I have no problem leaving it as an open
question whether there is some richer notion of mechanisms that would do the work that
needs to be done for a mechanism-based view like Fischer and Ravizza’s. But I strongly
suspect that even if such a kind of mechanism were identified, and even if it turned out to
166 Michael McKenna
be narrower than the full person qua agent, it would be much richer in content than
anything like something restricted just to what is actually involved in the causal
generation of action.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 167
20 Smith’s (2003) essay is written in a more general, programmatic style. He does not
develop the kind of detailed proposal that either Fara or Vihvelin does, but it is clear
from his exposition that he is open to the development of his view in ways are amenable
to Fara’s or Vihvelin’s efforts.
168 Michael McKenna
for the moment set aside his acting in a Frankfurt example. Suppose for now
he is not in a Frankfurt example and that he shot Smith on his own and for
his own reasons. Suppose also that one of the reasons to which Jones would
have been both receptive and reactive in a way that would have resulted in his
not shooting Smith is if he were to have learned that Smith’s child was with
him at the time. Were Jones to have learned of this, he would not have shot
Smith. But as it happens in the actual world, he learns of no such reason and
proceeds to shoot Smith. Here is a counterfactual, built by modeling it on
SC, that shows how it is that Jones is responsive to this reason, call it R1:
RR1: If Jones were to become aware of R1, and if Jones retained during
the relevant duration of time intrinsic agential properties P1-Pn, and if
Jones were not interfered with in a way that would impede the casual
efficacy of those properties, then Jones would not shoot Smith.
By compiling a collection of counterfactuals like RR1, say RR1 through
RRn, for a spectrum of reasons R1 through Rn, the new dispositionalists
could establish that an agent like Jones is MRR in just the fashion that
Fischer and Ravizza have been careful to work out.
Thus far, I have tried to show, in admittedly only broad brushstrokes,
how it is that by relying upon counterfactuals like RR1 through RRn, the
new dispositionalists could make use of their account of abilities to develop
a theory of reasons-responsiveness. As I have explained, it is open to them
to build the theory in such a way that it is very much like Fischer and
Ravizza’s proposal for MRR but for the fact that their account would be
agent-based, not mechanism-based. But how is it that on their view the
truth of counterfactuals RR1 through RRn also underwrites the ability to do
otherwise in a way that shows how an agent retains this ability even in a
Frankfurt example? This is what is needed for them to put the nail in the
coffin of source compatibilists. Here their rationale is simple. Take Jones
whom we pulled from the context of a Frankfurt example, and take RR1
through RRn. Now place Jones back in a Frankfurt example. All of RR1
through RRn, the new dispositionalists will tell us, remain true. Like Fischer
and Ravizza, to assess the truth of RR1 through RRn they too must go to
worlds in which P1-Pn are allowed to operate unfettered, and this will also
require factoring out the presence of a counterfactual intervener like Black.
But according to them, this is perfectly consistent with Jones’s possession of
the ability to do otherwise when he acts on his own. How so? When Jones
acts in a Frankfurt example, according to the new dispositionalists, Black
plays the role of a fink. When Black remains inactive, because he in no way
alters or impedes the efficacy of the pertinent agential properties such as
P1-Pn, Jones retains the ability to do otherwise—just like the vase sitting on
the shelf remains fragile despite that fact that, if toppled, a sorcerer would
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 169
turn it to stone. Of course, were Black to intervene, Jones would lose that
ability. But Black remains passive (like the sorcerer). So, when Jones acts
freely, according to the new dispositionalists, and contra Fischer and
Ravizza, he retains the ability to do otherwise.
Is the new dispositionalists’ effort to undermine Frankfurt’s argument
successful? No. As Clarke (2009: 339–42) is careful to point out, the
problem with the new dispositionalists’ reply to source theorists is not
that they fail to identify an ability that an agent like Jones retains in a
Frankfurt example. Indeed, because when Jones acts on his own, none of
his relevant dispositions are disturbed, there clearly is a kind of ability that
he retains. But this ability can be described more carefully as a general
capacity to do otherwise, or instead as a general ability to do otherwise that
can, for instance, be exercised outside the context of Frankfurt examples, or
when the agent is not asleep, or when she is not tied up, and so on.21
Nevertheless, as Clarke remarks:
[T]here apparently are abilities that Jones lacks, because of Black’s readiness to
intervene. Though Jones might have the capacity to act otherwise, the circumstances
are not friendly to his exercising that capacity, and it may fairly be said that it is not
up to him whether he exercises it, or that he does not have a choice about whether he
does so. (2009: 340)
Furthermore, Clarke notes (341), Fischer, in articulating Frankfurt’s argu-
ment, is careful to point out that what is in dispute is whether under the
circumstances an agent can chose and do otherwise (Fischer, 2002: 304).
The salient point is that the new dispositionalists are only able to claim
victory in refuting Frankfurt’s argument if the ability that they contend
remains for an agent in a Frankfurt example is the same ability that is in
dispute in debates about free will and moral responsibility—and it is this
ability at which Frankfurt’s argument is aimed.
Precisely the same point applies regarding the question of whether
an agent can be reasons-responsive while acting within the context of a
Frankfurt example. If, as Fischer and Ravizza suppose, reasons-responsiveness
requires that an agent be able to react otherwise in response to sufficient
reasons to do otherwise, then what is in question is whether under the
circumstances of a Frankfurt example, an agent is able to react as required.
Recall (from Section 3) Fischer and Ravizza’s qualification regarding the
counterfactuals in virtue of which MRR is confirmed; they do not involve
worlds that are accessible to the agent (1998: 53). In the context of a Frankfurt
example, it is not accessible to an agent like Jones to react otherwise in
response to different reasons and, while in the presence of Black, not shoot
Smith.
7 . A N E W P R O P O S A L : A N A G E N T - B A SE D ,
R E A S O N S - R E S PO N S I V E , S O U R C E
COMPATIBILIST THEORY
available to show that, when she acts unimpeded, she, the agent, is reactive
to sufficient reasons to do otherwise. Being reactive to sufficient reasons to
do otherwise, I now propose, is not the same as being able to react otherwise
in response to sufficient reason to do otherwise. In a Frankfurt example, an
agent who is suitably reasons-responsive is reactive to sufficient reasons to
do otherwise even if, due to the presence of a character like Black, she is
unable to react otherwise.
To illustrate this point, consider again Jones outside the context of a
Frankfurt example. Again suppose he shoots Smith for his own reasons. In
this case, suppose that his actual reason for shooting Smith is revenge.
Smith harmed Jones’s family, and now, as Jones sees it, it’s payback time.
Let us also assign Jones a pattern of receptivity and reactivity that, we can
stipulate, satisfies the conditions of MRR. Jones is receptive to reasons R1
through Rz, and is reactive to reasons R1 through Rn. Assume that the latter
is a subset of the former in such a way that Jones’s degree of reactivity is
weaker than his degree of receptivity. Recall that reason R1 as mentioned
above is that Smith’s child is with him, and were Jones to learn of this, he’d
be receptive to this as a sufficient reason not to shoot Smith, despite his
actual reason of revenge, and he would react accordingly, not shooting
Smith. And so it would be for the entire spectrum of reasons R1 through
Rn, but not for the reasons ranging Rn + 1 through Rz. For this latter range,
Jones would be receptive to these reasons as sufficient for not shooting
Smith, but he’d shoot Smith regardless. Imagine, for instance, that reason
Rn + 1 is that shooting Smith would cause Jones’s mother to be disap-
pointed with her son. While Jones would recognize this as a sufficient
reason for not shooting Smith, sorry son that he is, he’d not be reactive to it;
he’d shoot Smith for his own reasons of revenge, despite the grief he’d
knowingly cause his dear mum. Jones, given this set up, for the range of
reasons R1 through Rn is both reactive to sufficient reasons to do otherwise,
and would react otherwise in light of such reasons.
Now reinsert Black. Note that Black need not interfere with Jones were
Jones to face up to any of the reasons within the spectrum of Rn + 1 through
Rz. Jones is not reactive to these reasons in the sense that they would not
deter him from acting on his own reasons for shooting Smith. So Black is
able to leave Jones to function on his own. Should Jones consider the reason
Rn + 1, that his mother would be disappointed with him if he shot Smith,
he’d shoot Smith on his own anyway. Hence, Black can leave well enough
alone. But as for the reasons R1 through Rn, were any of these reasons to
become relevant to Jones’s practical context, Black would intervene. In
being prepared to do so, clearly Black makes it the case that Jones is unable
to react otherwise in response to these reasons. But it is nevertheless true
that Jones is reactive to this spectrum of reasons R1 through Rn in just this
172 Michael McKenna
sense: for each reason, were it to become salient for Jones, it is not the case
that, given his own intrinsic agential condition, he would act on his own
reasons of revenge for shooting Jones. He is at least reactive to reasons in
this manner. In reacting to this spectrum of reasons (at relevant possible
worlds), he, by virtue of his own agency and his own reasons of revenge, is
not the cause of shooting Smith. This is so despite that fact that he is unable
to act otherwise and thereby avoid shooting Smith. While acting within
the context of a Frankfurt example, Jones is reactive to this spectrum of
sufficient reasons to do otherwise, R1 through Rn, despite the fact that he is
not able to react otherwise. His being reactive in this context consists in his
not persisting in acting on his own reasons of revenge to shoot Smith in
light of reasons such an R1 (Smith’s child is with him).
Drawing upon the metaphysics of causation, Carolina Sartorio has made
important contributions to our understanding of source compatibilist
accounts of freedom, one of which is relevant to my current proposal. In
threat-cancelation scenarios, Sartorio (forthcoming) points out, causation
is not transitive along the path of a single causal chain. And the contrary to
fact scenarios in Frankfurt examples—that is, the scenarios in which the
intervener becomes activated—are set up as threat-cancelation scenarios.
To explain: Jones, given his own reasons for shooting Smith, is such that, in
the presence of certain reasons, such as R1 (Smith’s child is with him), he
would not shoot Smith. Suppose that, indeed, Jones is in the presence of
this reason, R1. This creates a threat to the event of his shooting Smith; it’s
the sort of thing that’s liable to lead to Jones not shooting Smith. The
presence of this threat, as a link in a causal chain, then causes the intervener
to bring it about that Jones shoots Smith. Hence, there is a causal chain
from Jones and his relation to R1 through to his shooting Smith. But
because of the way this causal chain unfolds, Jones, given the way he is and
his own reasons prior to the intervention, does not cause his shooting of
Smith. Why? Because, the way he is disposed to respond to reasons like R1
creates a threat to his shooting Smith. So, despite the fact that there is a
causal chain from Jones to the event of his shooting Smith via Black’s
manipulation, Jones—just as he is as an agent, given his intrinsic proper-
ties—is not the cause of shooting Smith. Thus, as Sartorio makes clear, the
difference between actual and counterfactual cases in Frankfurt examples is
a difference in the causal role played by agents such as Jones. This,
I maintain, helps cast light on the point I am at pains to emphasize here.
The point has to do with the way Jones is reactive to the different kind
of reasons that might bear on exercises of his agency. Some reasons, such as
Rn + 1, are such that, in their presence, Jones persists in being the right kind
of agential cause of his action (of shooting Smith). Some, such as R1, are
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 173
such that, in their presence, he does not persist in being the right kind of
agential cause of his action.
The first point I am offering here bears some similarity to earlier failed
efforts to defend PAP against Frankfurt’s argument by distinguishing
acting on one’s own and not acting on one’s own, which seems to be a
kind of alternative that cannot be expunged from Frankfurt examples (e.g.
see Naylor, 1984). This strategy for defending PAP was handily rejected
because the alternative of acting or not acting on one’s own in suitably
structured Frankfurt examples were not alternatives that were themselves
within the voluntary control of the agent (Fischer, 1994). Why doesn’t this
apply to my current proposal?22 Here’s why: My focus on the distinction
between an agent’s acting upon her own reasons in an actual scenario and
her not acting upon her own reasons in alternative scenarios is not being
used to underwrite any claim about an agent’s freedom to do otherwise. It is
only being used to call attention to a fact about the mode of an agent’s
acting in the actual-world scenario in which she acts on her own. The only
reason that in the alternative scenario the counterfactual intervener causes
Jones to act as he does is because, given Jones’s state, just as he is as an agent,
he would not act on his own reasons of revenge for shooting Smith were
these other reasons also salient. Granted, in the alternative scenario in
which the intervener forces him to act, Jones does not do anything
intentional to make it so that he does not act on his own reasons to shoot
Smith; this scenario is not within the scope of his voluntary control. But
there is no claim here that the degree of reactivity displayed by Jones in this
range of counterfactuals affords Jones anything like a freedom to do
otherwise. These counterfactual scenarios are not alleged to be accessible
to Jones from the actual world. But, I say, they still display that, given the
way he is in the actual world, he is in some manner reactive to pertinent
reasons to do otherwise.
Perhaps some will find my argument here too thin. They might demand
that being reactive to sufficient reasons to do otherwise requires that, in the
presence of the relevant range of reasons, the agent’s own responsiveness-
grounding resources have to be directly causally involved in the mode of
differential reactivity. And when Black the intervener is in the driver’s
seat—that is, when Black has taken over and is generating the action—
that’s just not what is going on. In fairness, I grant that this is a reasonable
source of resistance. However, in my own estimation, those inclined to
press it in this context are fixed upon an alternative possibilities model of
22 Thanks to both Derk Pereboom and Brandon Warmke for raising this worry.
174 Michael McKenna
23 Ginet (2006: 235–6) makes a similar point when advising Fischer and Ravizza to
give up the mechanism component of their theory and instead just consider the reasons-
responsiveness of agents.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 175
24 An anonymous referee for OUP has raised the following insightful objection: Here
I advocate an account of an agent’s reactivity by claiming that the pertinent counter-
factuals help to reveal the manner of the agent’s causing her action. But, as I myself have
noted above, Fischer and Ravizza themselves contend that they do not mean to reify
the notion of a mechanism, and all they mean by appeal to an agent’s mechanism is the
“manner that an action was caused.” Why, the referee asks, is my proposal any different
from Fischer and Ravizza’s? This is an especially keen question, but the answer, to my
mind, is telling in a way that speaks against Fischer and Ravizza and on behalf of my
agent-based proposal. Even if Fischer and Ravizza mean to pick out no more than “the
way an action is brought about,” they are at least committed to the existential claim of
there being such a way, and to holding that fixed when testing it for responsiveness to
different reasons. My proposal is that what gets held fixed for the pertinent testing is the
agent. Now, either Fischer and Ravizza will grant that they mean the same thing, in which
case their appeal to mechanisms really is the functional equivalent of the notion of agency
itself and they might as well drop talk of mechanisms altogether, or they will insist that
they mean to fix on something narrower than the agent. In that case we have just the very
difference I have been at pains to bring out in this essay.
25 Stephen Kearns, Nicole Smith, David Sosa, and Jada Strabbing each pressed this
challenging concern in slightly different ways.
176 Michael McKenna
Previously, it was precisely because of cases like these that I had been
convinced that reasons-responsive theorists could not recover an agent-
based theory while remaining committed to source compatibilism. But
upon reflection, I do not think that these sorts of cases should carry the
day. Admittedly, they are problematic. However, there are two quite
different strategies for resisting their threat to the current agent-based
proposal for explaining reasons-reactivity. One is to resist what seems
intuitive in such cases. It’s not entirely clear that in such cases the agents
really do act freely even when the pertinent psychosis or the phobia is inert.
The agent’s “success” in acting uninfluenced by the troubling latent condi-
tion seems too fluky. The agent, after all, seems highly constrained in
responding to just the reasons she does, so much so that her own agential
resources impede her from responding to relevant patterns of reasons.
A very different strategy would be to consider whether, when specifying
the agent-constituting intrinsic properties that are to be held fixed in
counterfactuals like R1, there is a principled way to rule out those consti-
tuting the psychosis or the phobia. The rough idea would be to treat these
conditions as in some way alien or distant from those ingredients consti-
tuting the agent’s identity, or her real self.26 This is a promising avenue
worth pursuing, though I’ll not do so here. It is enough, it seems to me, just
to make clear that cases such as these pose a threat to the current proposal,
but that there are avenues for addressing them which allow preservation of
this basic claim. When a range of counterfactuals like RR1 through RRn are
true of an agent, these do help to show how it is that when she acts as she
does, she is reacting to reasons, even if she cannot react otherwise.
For a long while now, at least since the appearance of Fischer and Ravizza’s
excellent and highly influential Responsibility and Control (1998), it has been
assumed that the only way to marry a reasons-responsive theory of freedom
to the lesson learned from Frankfurt’s argument is to forgo an agent-based
theory. The way to account for source freedom in terms of reasons-
responsiveness, I had previously thought, is by shifting to a mechanism-
based theory. In light of the two preceding points, combined with the
difficulties involved in accounting for mechanism individuation, I believe
that this is mistaken. I propose an agent-based, reasons-responsive compati-
bilist theory of source freedom.
26 I am indebted to Michael Bratman for this point. He drew upon it to point out that
this gives us reason to consider joining the resources of a reasons-responsive strategy with
those of mesh theories like Frankfurt’s. The latter seek to make sense of something like
the boundaries of the “real self ” as narrower than the full spectrum on an agent’s
psychological profile. (Though Bratman then raised the question of whether such a
joint venture should be regarded as a friendly or instead a hostile takeover.)
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 177
In the wider philosophical community, perhaps the best known source compatibi-
list account of freedom is not a reasons-responsive theory. It is Frankfurt’s own,
which he expresses in terms of acting freely and of one’s own free will (1971).
Frankfurt developed his position by attending to a fitting relation between higher-
order and lower-order desires. An agent acts of her own free will when the first-order
desire moving her all the way to action is the one that, at a higher order, she
identifies with and so most wants to act upon. Here, the further details do not
interest me. What does is the general strategy. Frankfurt’s is one version of a mesh
theory because it accounts for freedom in terms of a harmonious mesh between
different sub-systems within an agent’s overall mental economy.27 On Frankfurt’s
approach, an agent’s freedom consists in the well-functioning relation between
different orders of desire. When these different elements “line up,” the agent acts
unencumbered, and so she acts freely. But when, for instance, what Sally most wants
is for her desire not to drink the beer to win out, and when, despite that, her first-
order desire to drink the beer leads her all the way to action, Sally acts from an
unharmonious mesh. She is, in a sense, impeded or encumbered by her own
psychological constitution and so, according to Frankfurt, is not free. The system
issuing in her actions is out of alignment with the system that at a higher order
constitutes what she most wants.
When reflecting upon cases in which an agent acts from a harmonious mesh,
it is easy to see how that agent’s freedom, so construed, could easily be slipped
into a Frankfurt example. So long as her action does actually issue from the
mesh, there is no reason to be concerned about alternatives to what an agent
does do. All that matters in such a case is that her well-functioning mesh
operated unfettered. Thus, mesh theories such as Frankfurt’s fit seamlessly into
the actual-sequence demands of Frankfurt examples. Why then explore the
prospects of a reasons-responsive theory at all? Why not opt for some variation
on a mesh theory?
In my estimation, all mesh theories, not just Frankfurt’s, face a deep problem for
those committed to source compatibilism, one that I suspect is insurmountable. Mesh
theories might comfortably capture conditions sufficient for acting freely: When
an agent acts from a harmonious mesh, she acts freely. But in many cases in
which an agent acts from an unharmonious mesh, mesh theories either generate
the wrong results, or are instead unsatisfactorily silent—at least this is so for
those committed to source compatibilism. Mesh theories generate the wrong
results when they treat acting from a harmonious mesh as also necessary for
27 For other efforts to develop a mesh theory, see Dworkin (1970), and Watson
(1975). Bratman (2007) has explored similar ideas. For a more detailed critical
discussion of mesh theories, see McKenna (2011).
178 Michael McKenna
acting freely; they are unsatisfactorily silent when they refrain from accounting
for an agent’s freedom in such cases.
To explain, consider the case of Sally above. Grant that on Frankfurt’s view,
acting from a harmonious mesh is not only sufficient but also necessary for free
action. Maybe Sally acts from a freedom-compromising compulsion in drinking
that beer; suppose she is a full-blown, hopeless alcoholic. If so, there is no threat to
Frankfurt’s mesh theory; it yields the result that Sally does not act freely insofar as
she fails to satisfy the necessary condition at issue. But maybe instead Sally freely
acts upon her lower-order desire as in opposition to the higher-order preferences
with which she identifies. Suppose she also judges it best not to drink the beer.
This is a classic case of weakness of will, understood in terms of freely acting
contrary to one’s better judgment. A mesh theory such as Frankfurt’s generates the
wrong result in a case like this. It has it that Sally does not act freely when in fact
she does.
A viable option for the mesh theorist is to claim that the necessary condition
which she proposes is merely an ability to act from a harmonious mesh. This
would allow the mesh theorist to handle the distinction between exercises of free,
weak-willed agency and failures that are due to freedom-undermining compulsion.
The weak-willed agent, it can be argued, did not act from a harmonious mesh,
but it remains true that she had the ability to do so; she could have done otherwise.
Obviously, this reply will not work for any mesh theorist who, like Frankfurt, is
also committed to source compatibilism, since it relies on claims about leeway
freedom.
It is open to the mesh theorist who is committed to source compatibilism to
retreat by weakening the reach of her theory. She could give up any proffered
necessity condition and claim that she is only offering sufficient conditions for free
action in those cases involving acting from a harmonious mesh. These conditions
can be shown to be compatible with determinism without in any way relying
upon any assumptions about leeway freedom. After all, this is all that is strictly
required for her to answer the metaphysical challenge of the incompatibilist: the
incompatibilist contends that determinism is incompatible with free action;
she has produced cases of free action from a harmonious mesh that are compatible
with determinism. Case closed. The objection to mesh theories currently
under consideration concerns a refutation of the necessary conditions they pro-
pose. Why can’t the mesh theorist simply retreat by relinquishing this necessary
condition?
Such a retreat strikes me as an unpromising dialectical tactic. A mesh theory that
remained silent with respect to acting freely from an unharmonious mesh would
leave unaccounted for a wide swath of (putatively) free actions. A credible theory of
freedom should be able to account for these sorts of mundane cases of agency.
And so a theoretical lacuna would invite further attempts to account for freedom
in these cases. But then, once these kinds of cases are accounted for in ways that
would be satisfying to compatibilists, it will only be natural to consider whether
the proper account can also explain the freedom present in the cases involving
a harmonious mesh. If so, then the work of accounting for free action will be
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 179
done more systematically with these alternative resources. Hence, the work
done by the mesh theory will be rendered otiose. This is, in fact, how I see the
explanatory resources of a reasons-responsive theory of freedom.28
To illustrate a place where, without an independent rationale for doing so, Fischer
and Ravizza are too quick to allow sameness of mechanism to fall their way, consider
their contention that reactivity is all of a piece (1998: 73). They offer this proposal
in response to the incompatibilist worry that in the actual world, assuming a
deterministic context, when a blameworthy agent fails to act on the moral reason
to do otherwise, the agent cannot react to this reason. After all, holding fixed
the past and the laws, when that reason is present in the nearest possible world
(the actual one), the agent does not react to it. Fischer and Ravizza attempt to
ward off this objection by arguing that an agent’s reacting differently to a
different reason to do otherwise in another possible world is sufficient to
establish that she is able to react differently to any reason to do otherwise. Of
course, if this were so, she would be able to react differently to the moral reasons
that were present in the actual scenario, even though she did not. It is in this
context that Fischer and Ravizza (1998: 73–4) consider the following
incompatibilist-friendly challenge to their ‘reactivity is all of a piece’ thesis
(which I paraphrase here):
Is it not possible for the same mechanism to get more energy or focus from different incentives?
If it were, then the fact that an agent would react to some reasons to do otherwise, does not
mean that she is able to respond to all reasons to do otherwise, and so it does not mean that she
is able to react differently to the actual moral reason to do otherwise that was present to her at
the time of action.
If mechanisms were to behave this way—that is, in a way that disconfirms that
reactivity is all of a piece—then Fischer and Ravizza would be forced into a difficult
dialectical corner. They would be forced to take head on the incompatibilist worry
that, in a deterministic context, a blameworthy agent in the actual situation in which
she acts is not able to react to the moral reasons that were in fact present at the time.
28 I do, however, think that there is a way for mesh theories and reasons-responsive
theories to form a mutually beneficial alliance. The basic idea would be that a mesh
theory could be used to account for the nature of agency more generally (rather than free
agency). In particular, on the proposal I am considering, only agents able to adopt
higher-order attitudes towards their motivations can even be regarded as candidates for
having the kind of complexity for free agency as specified by something like MRR. Note
this might very well afford reasons-responsive theorists the resources to handle the sorts
of problems alluded to above. (See especially note 26).
180 Michael McKenna
They would have to show directly that, contrary to what the incompatibilist
claims, such an agent is able to react differently to the particular moral reasons
that were present, or they would have to commit to the claim that an agent could
be blameworthy for failing to act on moral reasons that she was not able to act
upon.29
To this challenge, they counter that in those cases in which an agent reacts
differently to some incentives only because she acquires more energy or focus, it is
natural to say that it is because a different mechanism of action is operative (74). This
is one particular point where, I contend, Fischer and Ravizza are too quick to allow
sameness of mechanism—or, rather, in this case, difference of mechanism—to fall
their way (McKenna, 2001: 98–9). They claim that it is natural to think of the
pertinent mechanisms as they propose. But it is hard to see how it is natural. It’s not
clear in the first place what a mechanism of action is. It’s not a term of folk psychology
that has accrued enough use to allow for much in the way of intuitive baggage. Why
can’t a mechanism of action be reactive under, say, extreme pressures, but fail in
normal contexts? After all, literal mechanisms, like thermostats, behave this way all the
time, especially when they begin to fail. Indeed, what is the exception is to find an
actual mechanism—a manmade gizmo of some sort—that does not respond
differentially under extreme pressures, that does not have foibles and limits, and so on.
Fischer has responded to my objections by likening the problem I raise here to
generality problems in other areas of philosophy. A certain level of generality, and
thus lack of specification, is acceptable in other domains of inquiry, such as ethical
theory. So too, Fischer argues, is a degree of generality acceptable when theorizing in
terms of mechanisms of agency (Fischer, 2004: 169). Fischer also points out that it
is unreasonable to demand of a successful theory that all of its elements are fully
analyzed (168). Thus, he resists the burden of offering any “purely ‘principled’
account of mechanism individuation—an account that did not at some level appeal
to intuition” (167–8). He thus remains committed to relying exclusively on appeal
to intuitions in response to difference cases.
While I sympathize with Fischer’s thoughtful reply, it is not enough to put the
objection to rest. Requesting some principled basis of mechanism individuation is
not the same as demanding a full analysis of mechanisms—one that is “purely”
principled. And a degree of generality is of course acceptable in theorizing in areas
such as this one. But when the degree of generality and an exclusive reliance on
intuition will not help adjudicate differences between cases crucial to assessing the
theory, then demanding some principled basis for settling the dispute is only
dialectically fair and reasonable. This is fully consistent with accepting Fischer’s
contention that appeal to intuitions ought to enter the scene at some level.
29 I have defended the former of these two options (2005), while Pereboom (2006)
has advised Fischer and Ravizza to opt for the latter. Watson has also commented on this
issue (2001, as appearing in 2004: 300–1). He suggests that on pain of consistency,
Fischer and Ravizza should opt for the latter option.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 181
REFERENCES
Ayer, A. J. (1954). “Freedom and Necessity.” In his Philosophical Essays. (New York:
St Martin’s Press), 3–20.
Bratman, Michael (2007). Structures of Agency. (New York: Oxford University
Press).
Buss, Sarah and Lee Overton (2002). Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from
Harry Frankfurt. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Clarke, Randolph (2009). “Dispositions, Abilities to Act, and Free Will: The New
Dispositionalism.” Mind 118: 323–51.
Davidson, Donald (1973). “Freedom to Act.” In Honderich (ed.), 1973: 67–86.
Dworkin, Gerald (1970). “Acting Freely.” Noûs 4: 367–83.
Fara, Michael (2008). “Masked Abilities and Compatibilism.” Mind 117 (468):
843–65.
Fischer, John Martin (1994). The Metaphysics of Free Will. (Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers).
—— (2002). “Frankfurt Style Compatibilism.” In Buss and Overton (eds.), 2002:
1–26.
—— (2004). “Responsibility and Manipulation.” Journal of Ethics 8. 2: 145–77.
—— (2006). “The Free Will Revolution (Continued).” Journal of Ethics 10, No. 3:
315–45.
—— (2011). Deep Control. (New York: Oxford University Press).
—— and Mark Ravizza (1998). Responsibility and Control: An Essay on Moral
Responsibility. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Frankfurt, Harry (1969). “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility.” Journal
of Philosophy 66: 829–39.
—— (1971). “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of
Philosophy 68: 5–20.
Ginet, Carl (1966). “Might We Have No Choice?” In Lehrer, 1966: 87–104.
—— (2006). “Working With Fischer and Ravizza’s Account of Moral Responsi-
bility.” Journal of Ethics 10: 229–53.
Haji, Ishtiyaque (1998). Moral Appraisability. (New York: Oxford University
Press).
Hobart, R. E. (1934). “Free Will as Involving Indeterminism and Inconceivable
Without It.” Mind 43: 1–27.
Honderich, Ted (ed.) (1973). Essays on Freedom and Action. (London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul).
Howard-Snyder, Daniel and Jeff Jordan (eds.) (1996). Faith, Freedom, and Ration-
ality. (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield).
Hunt, David P. (2000). “Moral Responsibility and Unavoidable Action.” Philo-
sophical Studies 97: 195–227.
Irwin, T. H. (1980). “Reason and Responsibility in Aristotle.” In A.O. Rorty (ed.),
1980: 117–55.
Lewis, David (1997). “Finkish Dispositions.” Philosophical Quarterly 47: 143–58.
182 Michael McKenna
McKenna, Michael (2001). “Review of John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza’s
Responsibility & Control.” Journal of Philosophy. XCVIII, no. 2: 93–100.
—— (2003). “Robustness, Control, and the Demand for Morally Significant
Alternatives.” In Moral Responsibility and Alternative Possibilities (eds.), Widerker
and McKenna. 2003.
—— (2005). “Reasons Reactivity & Incompatibilist Intuitions.” Philosophical
Explorations 8. 2: 131–43.
—— (2008). “Frankfurt’s Argument against Alternative Possibilities: Looking
Beyond the Examples,” Noûs 42: 770–93.
—— (2011). “Contemporary Compatibilism: Mesh Theories and Reasons-
Responsive Theories.” In R. Kane (ed.), 2011, Oxford Handbook of Free Will,
2nd edn. (New York: Oxford University Press), 175–98.
Martin, C. B. (1994). “Dispositions and Conditionals.” Philosophical Quarterly 44:
1–8.
Mele, Alfred (1995). Autonomous Agents. (New York: Oxford University Press).
—— (2006a). Free Will and Luck. (New York: Oxford University Press).
—— (2006b). “Fischer and Ravizza on Moral Responsibility.” Journal of Ethics 10.
3: 283–94.
—— and David Robb (1998). “Rescuing Frankfurt-Style Cases.” Philosophical
Review 107: 97–112.
Moore, G. E. (1912). Ethics. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Naylor, Marjory (1984). “Frankfurt on the Principle of Alternate Possibilities.”
Philosophical Studies 46: 249–58.
Pereboom, Derek (2001). Living Without Free Will. (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
—— (2006). “Reasons Responsiveness, Alternative Possibilities, and Manipulation
Arguments Against Compatibilism: Reflections on John Martin Fischer’s My
Way.” Philosophical Books 47: 198–212.
Sartorio, Carolina (forthcoming). “Actuality and Responsibility.” Mind.
Smith, Michael (2003). “Rational Capacities, or: How to Distinguish Recklessness,
Weakness, and Compulsion.” In Stroud and Tappolet (eds.), 2003: 17–38.
Stroud, Sarah and Christine Tappolet (eds.) (2003). Weakness of Will and Practical
Irrationality. (New York: Oxford University Press).
Stump, Eleonore (1996). “Libertarian Freedom and the Principle of Alternative
Possibilities.” In Howard-Snyder and Jordan, 1996: 73–88.
Van Inwagen, Peter (1975). “The Incompatibility of Free Will and Determinism.”
Philosophical Studies. 27:185–99.
Vihvelin, Kadri (2004). “Free Will Demystified: A Dispositional Account.” In
Philosophical Topics 32: 427–50.
Wallace, R. Jay (1997). “Review of John Martin Fischer’s The Metaphysics of Free
Will.” Journal of Philosophy 94. 3: 156–59.
Watson, Gary (1975). “Free Agency.” Journal of Philosophy 72: 205–20.
—— (2001). “Reason and Responsibility.” Ethics 111: 374–94.
—— (2004). Agency and Answerability. (New York: Oxford University Press).
Whittle, Ann (2010). “Dispositional Abilities.” Philosophers’ Imprint 10. 12: 1–23.
Reasons-Responsiveness, Agents, and Mechanisms 183
Theory typically uses the assumption that we probably have too many
ethical ideas . . . Our major problem now is actually that we have not
too many but too few, and we need to cherish as many as we can.
Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
Lying at the heart of P. F. Strawson’s core strategy in “Freedom and
Resentment” is his effort to direct his naturalist claims and observations
against not only the philosophical extravagance of a general skepticism about
moral responsibility but also against all nonskeptical attempts to provide
responsibility with some form of external rational justification (Strawson
1962: 23). According to Strawson, efforts of this kind are not only misguided
and unconvincing in themselves, when they fail they encourage a general
skepticism about moral responsibility. The alternative strategy that Strawson
pursues is one that places the foundations of responsibility on our natural,
universal emotional propensities and dispositions relating to moral
sentiments or reactive attitudes. This naturalistic turn invites us to focus
our attention on familiar facts about human moral psychology, and to drop
our focus on the analysis of the concept of “freedom” as a way of dealing with
the threat of determinism. Beyond these general features, however, the details
of Strawson’s strategy become both complex and layered. As a consequence
of this, interpretations and assessments of his arguments differ greatly. There
is, nevertheless, a general consensus among both followers and critics alike
that there are significant strands in Strawson’s specific naturalistic arguments
that are implausible and unconvincing and that some “retreat” from the
original strong naturalist program that he advanced is required.
In this paper I take up two closely related issues arising out of this overall
problem. First, I want to consider if the right way to amend and modify the
naturalistic program is to adopt a “narrow” construal of our moral reactive
attitudes along the lines proposed by R. Jay Wallace, one of Strawson’s
most prominent followers on this subject. The narrower approach, as I will
explain, involves a substantial retreat from Strawson’s original naturalistic
program and has significant implications for Strawson’s core claim that our
commitment to responsibility requires no external rational justification.
The second issue that will be addressed is whether or not we should
interpret moral responsibility entirely within the confines of what Bernard
Williams has described as “the morality system.” (Williams 1985: ch.1).
The narrow construal of responsibility requires that we understand moral
responsibility within the conceptual resources provided by the morality
system, making notions of obligation, wrongness, and blame essential
to the analysis of moral responsibility. There is, therefore, an intimate
connection between these two issues. With respect to both these issues
I will argue that the narrow approach, while it has legitimate criticisms to
make of Strawson’s original strategy, nevertheless takes us in the wrong
direction and involves an unacceptable distortion and truncation of moral
responsibility.
1
For a more detailed development of this analysis of Strawson’s naturalism see
Russell (1992).
Responsibility, Naturalism, and “The Morality System” 187
2
Wallace 1994: 39–40, 64–66; and Williams 1985: esp. ch. 10.
190 Paul Russell
3
Clearly confrontation between ethical cultures that are removed from each other in
historical time or geographical space may be, as Williams observes, either “notional” or
“real” (Williams 1985: ch. 9). Be this as it may, historical sensitivity about the
contingency of our own “local” commitments naturally puts pressure on reflective
confidence in our own attitudes and practices. To this extent our awareness of other
modes and forms of ethical life, less attached to the rigidities of “the morality system,”
192 Paul Russell
4 . T Y P E - N A T U R A L I S M AN D B R O A D R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y
4
I have argued elsewhere that there is a more intimate relationship between our
capacity for holding agents responsible and our capacity for reflective self-control than
(Kantian) theories such as Wallace’s acknowledge. See, in particular, Russell 2004 and
Russell 2011.
194 Paul Russell
need any external rational justification for reactive attitudes (i.e. justifica-
tion at the foundational level). Whether this further claim is acceptable or
not will depend on whether we accept the narrow construal of our reactive
attitudes. Clearly if we go narrow, then type-naturalism and the associated
claim regarding the dispensability of external rational justifications must be
dropped. The resolution of this issue depends, therefore, on our interpret-
ation of reactive attitudes.
As I have argued, although we do need a narrower account of our reactive
attitudes, we need to make sure we do not go too narrow, as otherwise we
will generate some of the difficulties that have already been noted. Wallace’s
narrow view places considerable and appropriate emphasis on the “propos-
itional content” involved in the beliefs that serve to delineate our reactive
attitudes (1994: 11,19,74).5 The narrow view would restrict the contents in
question to the limited range provided by the conceptual resources of “the
morality system.” It is these limits that result in the problems of asymmetry
and localism, as we have described them. We need to find, therefore, a
middle path that avoids the inclusiveness of Strawson, on one side, and the
excessively narrow approach of Wallace on the other. To put ourselves back
on the right track we may turn again to Bernard Williams’s critique of “the
morality system.”
The narrow view, as we have seen, presents ethical considerations in highly
restricted terms, specifically with reference to obligation and blame, which is
appropriate when obligations are violated. Williams identifies these features
as central to the morality system (1985: ch. 10). This tendency to reduce and
simplify is also manifest in ethical theory, a philosophical project which is
itself intimately linked to the assumptions and prejudices of the morality
system (1985: ch. 1). One aim of ethical theory is to provide an account of
morality that will provide an exact boundary between ethical and nonethical
considerations. This is done primarily by reducing the diversity of ethical
(and nonethical) considerations, with a view to identifying a narrow and
strict range of ethical considerations that may serve as moral reasons available
to all rational agents—the universal constituency. The most notable features
of moral theory are its simplicity, reductionism, and systemization of our
ethical concepts and claims. Williams’s critique of the morality system
involves challenging and rejecting these assumptions. In the first place,
while our ethical considerations certainly include obligations, under some
5
Wallace claims that Strawson’s account of reactive attitudes does not manage to
clearly connect them with any propositional content (1994: 39). This charge seems
unfair to Strawson since he is careful to ground reactive attitudes in our beliefs about the
attitudes and intentions of other human beings and “the very great importance” that we
attach to them (Strawson 1962: 5).
Responsibility, Naturalism, and “The Morality System” 195
interpretation, they extend well beyond this. The scope of the ethical relates
more broadly to “the demands, needs, claims, desires, and, generally the lives
of other people, and it is helpful to preserve this conception in what we are
prepared to call an ethical consideration” (1985: 12; see also 1985: 153,
where Williams mentions our need to share a social world in relation to these
various ethical considerations). What is required, from this perspective, is an
account of ethical considerations that also includes forward-looking concerns
relating to welfarism and utilitarianism, as well as ethical considerations that
relate to our ideals and self-conceptions that mark out actions that fail the
standards and boundaries that we may set for ourselves (e.g. considerations of
what we regard as demeaning, base, dishonorable, etc.). When we interpret
ethical considerations in this broader manner we find that these interests are
plural and varied in their nature and secure no sharp boundary between
ethical and nonethical considerations. Vagueness, conflict, and diversity—
contrary to the demands of “theory” and the prejudices of “the morality
system”—are of the essence of human ethical life.
Our own ethical reactive attitudes must be understood in these broader
and vaguer terms. One of the implications that Williams draws from this is
that we should be skeptical of the effort to understand reactive attitudes in
the reductive, thin language of binary judgments; approval and disap-
proval, guilt and innocence, and so on (1985: 37, 177, 192). If we recon-
figure our ethical reactive attitudes in terms of a broader construal of the
ethical considerations that ground them and serve as their propositional
content, then we may acquire a very different understanding of the scope
and content of moral responsibility, as based upon these emotions. Our
ethical qualities are manifest in the “deliberative priority” and “import-
ance” that we give to ethical considerations as expressed in our conduct and
character. So interpreted, ethical reactive attitudes may be construed as
reactive ethical value, where this is understood as emotional responses to the
weight and value given by an agent or person to ethical considerations
widely conceived (i.e. in terms of our human needs, interests, welfare,
claims, and the requirements of social cooperation). Ethical reactive atti-
tudes involve coming to see a person in a certain ethical “light” based on
these lower-order evaluations of their ethical qualities. Clearly we have
varied and diverse ethical norms and standards that serve as the relevant
basis for evaluating an agent’s ethical qualities understood in these terms.
These evaluations of agents based on their ethical qualities serve to generate
or arouse a myriad of ethical reactive attitudes which may be either
“positive” or “negative” in nature. As Williams argues, our ethical and
emotional language here is not at all “thin” (e.g. praise and blame etc.) but
is “thick” and varied, involving notions such as “being creepy,” or a “cad,”
and so on—all of which are responses loaded with ethical significance.
196 Paul Russell
Different cultures and different forms of ethical life will not only have
different lower-order ethical norms, they also deploy a different or variable
set of ethical reactive attitudes (reflecting their variable propositional content).
The significance of this criticism of “the morality system,” along with the
style of ethical theory associated with it, for our understanding of ethical
reactive attitudes should be clear. The revised account is broad enough to
accommodate positive ethical reactive attitudes (e.g. gratitude, admiration,
etc.) as well as “alien” reactive attitudes (e.g. shame) all under the umbrella
of those ethical considerations that serve to ground or justify them. This
avoids the costs of going too narrow, by way of relying on the limited and
restricted resources of the morality system. The broader construal is,
nevertheless, controlled and focused enough to exclude elements that do
not relate at all to ethical considerations and ethical qualities (e.g. friendly
feeling, sympathy, romantic love, etc. do not count as ethical reactive
attitudes because they are not reactive to ethical qualities as such). On
this analysis, we should not be surprised or disappointed to find that
there is no sharp or clear boundary between ethical reactive attitudes and
other emotional responses to qualities and features of those with whom we
are dealing. No such sharp boundary should be expected if we want an
accurate understanding of the nature of ethical life and the way in which it
“bleeds” into human life in general.6
Taking this broader approach to ethical reactive attitudes has other signifi-
cant advantages as well. It avoids, for example, the “legalism” of the narrow
account, which turns moral responsibility into a model of legal responsi-
bility—eliminating the more nuanced and complex set of responses we have
outside legal contexts. We also avoid the failings of what Williams refers to as
“progressivism,” the assumption that we moderns alone have access to a full
and complete concept of moral responsibility and are “better off ” than those
who lack our own understanding.7 It is Williams’s view that not only should
we be open to the possibility that we might learn from the ancients, this is in
fact our situation. Learning from the ancients is possible—and desirable—
precisely because we share a concept of moral responsibility with them,
however differently we may interpret various key elements associated with
it (1993: 55).
For our present purposes, our concern is not to present a worked-out
alternative to the narrow model of reactive attitudes—not the least because,
6
This is, of course, a recurrent theme throughout Williams’s writings.
7
Williams 1985: 32 n. 2; and, more generally, Williams 1993: esp. ch. 1. Williams’s
view is, of course, the opposite of this, since he holds that we would be better off without
the morality system (1985: 174), just as we don’t need ethical theory and should
abandon its aims (1985: 17, 74).
Responsibility, Naturalism, and “The Morality System” 197
for reasons given, this may itself be a problematic ambition driven by the
aims of “ethical theory.” What is important, however, is to insist on finding
some middle ground that can accommodate ethical reactive attitudes
broadly conceived without expanding this set to include interpersonal
emotions that have no relevant ethical content (i.e. which do not involve
our emotional reactions to a person’s ethical qualities). Wallace’s own
observations suggest that this can readily be done, since he allows “analo-
gous” forms of responsibility and also speaks of “responsibility for worthy
acts” (Wallace 1994: 38–40, 64–6, 71). To see, in a particular case, how
this middle ground between an excessively narrow and overly inclusive view
may be found let us consider shame. Shame may be based on standards and
norms that have no ethical content, as in the case of concern about one’s
physical appearance (e.g. my frail constitution) or economic status (e.g.
my family’s poverty). In other cases, however, the relevant standards and
norms may move into the territory of our ethical qualities and
characteristics, such as feeling shame about being lazy or being vulgar.
Whether a response is an ethical reactive attitude or not will depend on
the nature of the quality or consideration it is a reaction to. There are,
moreover, clear cases of ethical shame that cannot be analyzed or
understood in terms of the apparatus of obligation and doing wrong.
We may, for example, feel ashamed of failing to live up to our own ethical
ideals and standards, even when we are well aware that we have not failed
to comply with any obligations and cannot be blamed for our conduct.
An example of this is provided in Joseph Conrad’s Lord Jim, where Jim is
ashamed of himself because he fails to act heroically and is, therefore,
disappointed in himself in these ethical terms but not in terms of any
recognizable requirements of “the morality system.”8 The general point
here is that there is a wide range of ethical reactive attitudes lying outside
the theoretical schema of the narrow interpretation that, nevertheless, do
not collapse into an overly “inclusive” set of interpersonal emotions
lacking any relevant ethical content. Some cases of shame will be cases
of ethical reactive attitudes and others will not. What will settle this issue
will be the specific content and target of what we are ashamed of.
Moreover, the fact that there are no sharp or precise boundaries to draw
here is a failing only if we assume the prejudices of the morality system
and the forms of “theorizing” associated with it.
We have noted that it is essential that the naturalist approach to moral
responsibility should be sensitive to historical and cultural variations with
regard to our understanding of moral responsibility and the specific and
8
For an illuminating discussion of this example see Doris 2002: 160–4.
198 Paul Russell
various forms which our ethical reactive attitudes may take. It should be
pointed out that Strawson is himself alive to these concerns. Speaking of
our increased “historical and anthropological awareness of the great variety
of forms which these human attitudes may take at different times and in
different cultures” Strawson says:
This makes one rightly chary of claiming as essential features of the concept of
morality in general, forms of these attitudes which may have a local and temporary
prominence. No doubt to some extent my own descriptions of human attitudes
have reflected local and temporary features of our own culture. But an awareness of
variety of forms should not prevent us from acknowledging also that in the absence
of any forms of these attitudes it is doubtful whether we should have anything that
we could find intelligible as a system of human relationships, as human society.
(1962: 24–5. Strawson’s emphasis)
It may be argued, along the lines of Wallace’s criticisms of Strawson’s
claims about the objective attitude, that Strawson’s remarks in this passage
run together two distinct issues. One claim is that we could not recognize a
society as truly human without any ethical reactive attitudes. Clearly this
need not be the case, so long as we do not overly expand the class of ethical
reactive attitudes to include all interpersonal emotions. Nevertheless, the
general point that Strawson is primarily concerned to make in this context
still stands: namely, without some form of ethical reactive attitudes we could
not recognize or find intelligible a system of human relationships that
would qualify as a human ethical life. In other words, an ethical life devoid
of all forms of ethical reactive attitudes is not recognizable or intelligible to
us as a form of human ethical life.
It should be clear, in light of Strawson’s observations, that we do not
need to choose between naturalism and genealogy, where this is understood
in terms of sensitivity to historical and cultural variation and diversity. On
the broad construal, ethical norms and the ethical considerations to which
they give weight, may vary greatly from one culture and historical period to
another. With these variations we will also find variations in the particular
forms of ethical reactive attitudes that are adopted and endorsed. One form
these ethical reactive attitudes may take is the narrow form encouraged
by the morality system—which makes obligation and blame its central
features. While this form of ethical reactive attitude may be local and
contingent, it does not follow that ethical reactive attitudes broadly con-
strued are local and contingent, unless we take the local form to be the sole
legitimate representative form of moral responsibility. Since the broad
construal neither interprets ethical reactive attitudes nor moral responsi-
bility in these restrictive terms, it is able to acknowledge that the ancient
Greeks, among others, have ethical reactive attitudes that are recognizably
Responsibility, Naturalism, and “The Morality System” 199
9
Wallace refers to the utilitarian approach as “the economy of threats” model (1994:
54–61). It is crucial to his critique of this model that it lacks “depth,” where depth is
provided by the “attitudinal” features of blame and retribution (1994: 56, 75). On a
broader construal, however, “depth” can be found in other forms of ethical reactive
attitude, such as shame and anger—a point that Wallace comes close to endorsing in
some passages. See, e.g. 1994: 89.
10
This may well be regarded as highly unlikely or even incredible—but it is not
inconceivable. Imagine, for example, the spread of some terrible disease or genetic
mutation that affected us all by damaging our most basic and universal moral capacities
in such a manner that exemptions applied universally (however broadly interpreted).
Responsibility, Naturalism, and “The Morality System” 201
and, from another point of view, would place her outside the recognizable
human ethical community.11
We have already noted that whereas the narrow construal would place
the ancient Greeks (and other shame cultures) outside the framework and
fabric of moral responsibility, the broad construal does not. What, then,
about the skeptic? In contrast with individuals who are engaged partici-
pants in forms of ethical life involving ethical reactive attitudes, the skeptic
has systematically disengaged from all such participation or involvement.
Disengagement of this kind requires (internal) doubts about the justifica-
tion for any proposed tokens of ethical reactive attitude. So described, the
skeptic cannot evade the challenge of providing some account of the
excusing and exempting considerations that apply universally in such a
manner that all tokens of ethical reactive attitude are discredited. If the
skeptic fails or refuses to provide any such rationale for her (disengaged)
stance then her skeptical stance has not been vindicated or justified.
Contrast the skeptic with another distinct character, who we may call the
“Vulcan.”12 Vulcans are understood to be entirely rational but incapable of
human emotion. As such, Vulcans may rationally understand (human)
ethical norms but are incapable of feeling or entertaining ethical reactive
attitudes (or similar moral emotions with an attitudinal aspect). Vulcans
have, in other words, no type-naturalist commitments with regard to
ethical reactive attitudes. It is, for this reason, a mistake to assimilate the
skeptic to a Vulcan, as plainly the skeptic is not a Vulcan. The Vulcan faces
no skeptical problem with respect to ethical reactive attitudes. They have no
token commitment because they have no type commitment to this range of
(ethical) emotion. For the (human) skeptic, however, the skeptical
challenge is real because their type propensities require something to be
said with respect to disengaging all tokens of these reactions to the ethical
qualities of others in their community. In this way, both the skeptic and
the anti-skeptic, in contrast with the Vulcan, can accept Strawson’s type-
naturalism and dispense with the search for external rational justifications.
What divides them is the issue of whether or not a theory of excuses and
exemptions can handle relevant internal skeptical worries (e.g. as based on
the implications of determinism).
11
An individual who lacks any type commitment to ethical reactive attitudes would
not be recognizably human, not because she is a systematic skeptic with respect to these
attitudes but because the skeptical issue does not arise for her with respect to these
attitudes, since she is constitutionally incapable of experiencing or entertaining such
attitudes.
12
Vulcans are aliens from the planet Vulcan, as described in Star Trek. The character
of Mr Spock was half Vulcan and half human. Wallace refers to this example in a related
context at Wallace 1994: 78 n.41. See also Russell 2011: esp. 212–14.
202 Paul Russell
5 . A G AI N ST T H E N A R R O W C O N S T R U A L
O F M O R AL R E S PO N S I B I LI T Y
It has been argued that the narrow construal of reactive attitudes and its
associated account of moral responsibility has unacceptable costs. While it is
true that there are significant failings in Strawson’s original naturalistic project
that need to be addressed and corrected (e.g. we should reject token-natural-
ism), we should retain the core feature of type-naturalism. In order to do this
we need to provide a broader account of ethical reactive attitudes that extends
beyond the constraints and limits of “the morality system” and its conceptual
structures. It is only by taking this route that the difficulties we have described
relating to “asymmetry” and “localism,” as well as the fruitless and misguided
search for external rational justifications, can be avoided. We may summarize
the significance of these observations in the following points.
(1) The narrow construal of moral responsibility, as developed on the basis
of the morality system, both distorts and truncates our understanding of
human ethical life as it relates to moral responsibility. In particular, it
makes it impossible to accommodate both positive ethical reactive attitudes
and alien ethical reactive attitudes as they may arise from outside our
(modern, Western) culture. Even our own local understanding of moral
responsibility is not fully or adequately captured by this narrow construal.
(2) It is the broad construal, along with its commitment to type-naturalism,
which is able to accommodate genealogical sensitivity to historical and
cultural variation in relation to our understanding of moral responsibility.
The narrow construal excludes all alternative forms that do not fall into the
constraints imposed by “the morality system” as mere analogues or proto-
types of moral responsibility. As such, the narrow construal constitutes a
form of conceptual imperialism with regard to (real, true) moral responsi-
bility and also commits us to an implausible “progressivism” concerning
our own (modern, Western) views. In contrast with this, the broad
approach recognizes the variation in modes and forms of ethical reactive
attitude within a wider understanding and appreciation of the emotional
fabric of moral responsibility.
(3) Type-naturalism, as understood on the broad construal, provides no
easy way of dealing with a potential internal skeptical challenge (i.e. in
contrast with the aims of token-naturalism). Even allowing for our natural
liability to ethical reactive attitudes, on a broad construal, we must still
formulate some relevant schema of excuses and exemptions. From this
perspective it is always conceivable that a systematic or global skepticism
Responsibility, Naturalism, and “The Morality System” 203
could be generated from “the inside” (i.e. extending to all our token ethical
reactive attitudes). This possibility does not, however, license a search for
external rational justifications, since our liability or propensity to such
emotions is natural and not rationally grounded. The skeptic remains
committed to ethical reactive attitudes at this level, even if she has entirely
abandoned or disengaged any commitment to tokens of these attitudes (in
light of internal skeptical pressures of some kind).
(4) Much of the motivation behind Wallace’s narrow construal of the
reactive attitudes is to find a satisfactory compatibilist account of moral
responsibility consistent with the core requirements and constraints of the
morality system. From this perspective the internal skeptical challenge is
especially acute, since it is targeted on the notions of wrongness, blame,
desert, and retribution that are central to moral responsibility as the
morality system interprets it. It is evident, however, that the broad con-
strual of ethical reactive attitudes, along the lines that has been sketched,
significantly deflates these (internal) skeptical pressures. The reason for this
is that a broader and more liberal conception of ethical reactive attitudes
does not place such heavy weight or emphasis on the very elements of the
morality system that have proved especially vulnerable to skeptical criticism
(i.e. desert, blame, etc., along with their apparent dependence on ultimate
or absolute agency). Even if—contrary to what Wallace argues—it proves
impossible to vindicate this local interpretation of moral responsibility, as
understood on the narrow construal, it does not follow, given a broad
interpretation of ethical reactive attitudes, that global skepticism results. All
that follows from the success of the skeptical challenge, so described, is that
the local understanding of moral responsibility encouraged by the morality
system cannot survive critical reflection.13
13
It is true, of course, that many skeptics about moral responsibility are concerned to
discredit the local conceptions of moral responsibility associated with the morality
system. However, for reasons that have been discussed, skepticism of this kind does
not in itself constitute global skepticism—since it does not discredit, and may not even
aim to discredit, alternative forms of ethical reactive attitudes. Having said this, it is
important to note that many skeptical projects of this kind either explicitly or tacitly
endorse the narrow construal and its assumption that alternative accounts of ethical
reactive attitudes somehow fail the standard of real or genuine forms of moral responsi-
bility. When this assumption is made, the critique of our local conception of moral
responsibility framed in terms of the requirements of the morality system is (mistakenly)
inflated into a form of global skepticism about moral responsibility. Suffice it to say that
much of the contemporary free-will debate, along with its associated worries about the
skeptical threat, proceeds on this assumption of the narrow construal and the morality
system.
204 Paul Russell
In sum, we may contrast the relative strengths and weaknesses of the broad
and narrow accounts in these terms. The narrow construal not only
generates a partial and incomplete account of moral responsibility, it also
leaves the entire edifice of moral responsibility, so understood, vulnerable
to both internal and external skeptical threat. The broad construal not only
avoids the significant difficulties that the narrow construal encounters (e.g.
asymmetry), it provides for the complexity, variation and nuance that we
find in this sphere. Moreover, the broad construal, by moving away from
the rigidities and (peculiar) demands of the morality system, deflates the
internal skeptical threat and eliminates all worries relating to the misguided
ambition of providing a satisfactory external rational justification. These
are fundamental points relating to moral responsibility and the defects of
the morality system that the discussions of both Strawson and Williams
converge on.
REFERENCES
Doris, John (2002). Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior. (Cambridge &
New York: Cambridge University Press).
Russell, Paul (1992). “Strawson’s Way of Naturalizing Responsibility.” Ethics 102. 2.
—— (2004). “Responsibility and the Condition of Moral Sense.” Philosophical
Topics, 32, 1; 2, 287–305.
—— (2011). “Moral Sense and the Foundations of Responsibility.” In Free Will,
2nd edn., ed. Robert Kane (New York: Oxford University Press).
Strawson, P. F. (1962). “Freedom and Resentment,” reprinted in P. F. Strawson,
Freedom and Resentment and other essays. (London, New York and Oxford:
Methuen. 1974).
Wallace, R. Jay (1994). Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press).
Williams, Bernard (1985). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. (London: Fontana).
—— (1993). Shame and Necessity. (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.).
8
The Three-Fold Significance
of the Blaming Emotions
Zac Cogley
1. INTRODUCTION
1 While there are positive emotions that are connected to moral responsibility, I focus
on the blaming emotions as they have received much more philosophical and psycho-
logical discussion than have candidate positive emotions like gratitude.
2 An anonymous reviewer points out that these also correspond to three broad
categories of response to wrongdoing. I agree—in fact, I think we categorize responses
206 Zac Cogley
2 . A P PR AI SA L
For example, Jesse Prinz and Shaun Nichols claim that “Anger arises when
people violate autonomy norms, which are norms prohibiting harms against
persons” (2010, 122). If we make the plausible assumption that slights and
offenses both involve the violation of norms, we can see all these authors
offering a roughly similar account of the appraisal involved with the blaming
emotions, though they do disagree about how best to capture it.
While I agree that the blaming emotions have a characteristic appraisal,
the above accounts make two errors regarding it. First, these accounts fail to
pinpoint the characteristic appraisal of the blaming emotions. The early
Lazarus, as well as Prinz and Nichols, construe the appraisal too narrowly.
For example, blaming emotions are commonly elicited by harms against
nonhuman animals, violations of religious commandments, the nonharm-
ful breaking of promises and many other situations that go beyond slights
and harms against persons.7 On the other hand, the account from Lazarus
and Smith is too broad; adding up their three appraisal components (an
emotion directed toward a personally relevant situation that is inconsistent
with what is desired) does not give us the characteristic appraisal of the
blaming emotions. Such an appraisal is also compatible with sadness. We do
better if we follow James Averill, who argues that “the typical instigation to
anger is a value judgment. More than anything else, anger is an attribution
of blame” (1983, 1150) or Shaver et al., who hold that the eliciting
appraisal is that “the situation is illegitimate, wrong, unfair, contrary to
what ought to be” (1987, 1078).
I propose, then, that the way a person feeling a blaming emotion
appraises her situation is best captured as an appraisal of wrongful conduct.
This is the core appraisal of the blaming emotions, but we can break it into
constituent parts as follows:
If a person, A, feels a blaming emotion, she evaluates her situation as containing:
(i) a person, B,8 whose
(ii) action or omission
(iii) transgresses a norm on proper conduct (including, but not limited to,
moral norms, though the norm need not be codifiable by a rule)
(iv) because B is motivated by ill will or has shown insufficient concern,
(v) and A glosses B’s action as bad.9
7 Surprisingly, Prinz and Nichols themselves note the connection between blaming
emotions and harms against nonhuman animals (2010, 130).
8 In some situations A and B will be the same person.
9 I have in mind here the fact that anger has a distinctive unpleasant phenomenology
that might be glossed as “feeling ready to explode” (Roseman, Wiest, and Swartz 1994).
Significance of the Blaming Emotions 209
true belief. Anger, resentment, and indignation are fitting to feel when, for
example, someone intentionally wrongs you out of ill will.
Thus, the blaming emotions are fitting when they are felt in response to a
person who satisfies conditions (i)-(v), above. The lack of any one of the
five conditions means that a blaming emotion is unfitting.10 We can also
distinguish between “degrees” of fit between a blaming emotion and the
situation it appraises. I should be angrier with someone who tries to ruin
my career than a neighbor who thoughtlessly mows his lawn at 8 a.m. on a
Sunday morning. And you should be more upset with the driver who
intentionally tries to run you over while you are out for a walk than you
should be with a person who somewhat carelessly backs his car into your
path. Thus, the seriousness of the wrong in question and the person’s
relation to the wrong both help to determine the amount of anger fitting
for the situation.
3. COMMUNICATION
(Fernández-Dols and Ruiz-Belda 1995) and bowlers are less likely to smile
when they first roll a strike than when they turn to face others watching at
the end of the alley (Kraut and Johnston 1979).
In a typical interpersonal episode of a blaming emotion, various bodily,
vocal, and facial responses communicate that the person feeling the emo-
tion is angry and thereby give the person who is the target of the blaming
emotion information about the way her conduct is being appraised. In
many situations, this information is not contained in spoken words but is
transmitted instead by the overall emotional demeanor of the person feeling
the blaming emotion. These communicative aspects of a person’s emo-
tional demeanor are observed, responded to, or ignored by others. The
responses of others—or the lack of a response—are then an opportunity for
continued emotional engagement and transformation. Thus, in most inter-
personal interactions, a person who feels a blaming emotion not only
appraises the conduct of another as wrongful, she also communicates to
the target of the blaming emotion that she construes his behavior as
wrongful.11
In human psychological response, these communicative aspects are very
closely connected to the having of the blaming emotion itself. It turns out to
be almost impossible not to register your emotional state on your face in
some way, even if briefly, and it is hardest to mask negative emotions (Porter
and Brinke 2008). Since others are extremely attentive to such displays, it is
often better to try not to have the emotion than to allow the emotion to run
its course while attempting to mask what you feel. Thus, I want to suggest
that the communicative significance of the blaming emotions can sometimes
result in their being inappropriate to feel even when they fittingly appraise a
target. That is, there are additional considerations that bear on whether to
have a blaming emotion than merely considerations of fit. In characterizing
communicative considerations that bear on emotional appropriateness, I am
inclined to follow Angela Smith in distinguishing between considerations of
standing, the degree of fault displayed in the wrongful action, and the
response that the blamed person takes (or will, or could take) to the person
who feels the blaming emotion.12
Whether or not someone has proper standing, or authority, to feel what
would be a fitting blaming emotion toward a wrongdoer has much to do
with her relationship to the wrongdoer and those who are wronged. So, for
example, even though I may observe what I regard as condescending and
obnoxious behavior from one of two parties having a public argument,
I may be inappropriately angry with the offending party if I have no social
connection to either one of them. We can see this more clearly when we
consider that it would not be uncommon for the victim of the obnoxious
behavior to become angry with me when my indignation on his behalf
becomes known.
My own fault and hypocrisy can also affect my standing to react to
another’s conduct with a blaming emotion. Thus, if my awareness of its
health effects has not moderated my long-time smoking habit, my friend
with a drinking problem will regard as out-of-line my fitting anger at him
for neglecting his health when he succumbs to the temptation to drink. My
friend’s failing, just as my own, may be a legitimately moral one, but the
fact that I am unable or unwilling to similarly guide my own behavior
makes it inappropriate to feel angry toward him even though anger is fitting
for what he does.
Beside the fact that the communicative appropriateness of the blaming
emotions can be undermined by my standing to have such responses, it can
also be affected by the relative significance of the fault a person displays in her
conduct. Thus, while a blaming emotion would fittingly appraise a student
who fails to keep his scheduled appointment with me, the degree of fault
(simple forgetfulness) and the degree of harm to me (a very mild inconveni-
ence) prohibit me from feeling any resentment toward him. We can see this
interact with another communicatively salient factor—the agent’s own
response—if we suppose that the student rushes over to my office, apologiz-
ing profusely even as he walks in the door. The student’s self-reproach
indicates that he understands he did wrong and is committed to doing
what he can to prevent it from occurring in the future. While being indignant
would fittingly appraise his faulty conduct, I should not feel indignant
toward him because it would be communicatively inappropriate for me to
target him with a blaming emotion given his indication that he understands
his error and the importance of keeping appointments.13 (Of course, things
might be different if this same student has routinely missed appointments
even while protesting that it will never happen again.)
In such a case, we again have a communicative reason against feeling a
blaming emotion, even though the blaming emotions fittingly appraise the
actions of the person in the situation.
4. SANCTION
Another way in which the blaming emotions are significant for our moral
responsibility practices relates to communication but is ultimately distinct,
namely, affecting the behavior of others by imposing costs.14 While this is
sometimes accomplished via the communication of a message, at other
times it is accomplished simply through changing the costs and benefits of
another person’s possible actions. Though the relationship between the
blaming emotions, deliberation, and action-aimed-at-sanction is complex,
in this section I will highlight some of the relevant psychological findings to
demonstrate the connection of the blaming emotions to sanction.
Anger has important effects on deliberation and social perception that play
a role in determining the behavior of someone feeling a blaming emotion
(though the effects vary across individuals, depending on their level of
awareness and cognitive skills). Angry people tend to have a sense of signifi-
cant control (Lerner and Keltner 2000) that leads them to be optimistic about
the success of their probable actions (Lerner and Keltner 2001). They are also
“eager to make decisions and are unlikely to stop and ponder or carefully
analyze” (Lerner and Tiedens 2006, 132), which likely leads them to take
actions that have a low probability of succeeding but high payoffs (Leith and
Baumeister 1996). When they act, angry people tend to be more punitive
toward those they blame (Lerner, Goldberg, and Tetlock 1998).15
We can see these deliberative effects demonstrated in experimental work
on altruistic punishment and ultimatum games. In altruistic punishment,
the punisher receives no material benefit but imposes a cost on the party
punished. Thus, people are willing to punish free-riders even when it is
costly for them to do so and they cannot expect future benefits from
punishing (Fehr and Gächter 2000). Jonathan Haidt has argued that a
paradigm feature of human morality is this third-party enforcement of
moral norms (2001). In one significant study, Ernst Fehr and Simon
Gächter (2002) demonstrated that free-riding on a common good is less
prevalent when altruistic punishment of free-riders is possible. When such
punishment occurs, it is reported by punishers to express their anger and
those who are punished perceive their punishers as angry.16 A similar
14 I am not arguing that such costs are always intended by the person feeling the
blaming emotion, though they certainly sometimes are.
15 For an excellent overview of recent empirical study of anger’s effects on judgment
and decision-making, see (Litvak et al. 2010).
16 Notably, angry sanctions lead to positive behavior change even when free-riders
interact with a new group of people that does not include their previous punishers.
214 Zac Cogley
17 Again, note that while the sanctioning effects of the blaming emotions are at least
sometimes directly intended by people who feel a blaming emotion (Fehr and Gächter
2000), they need not always be. However, even if people feeling blaming emotions do
not intend that their emotions be experienced as harms by the targets of the blaming
emotion, that doesn’t mean they are not experienced as such by the targets.
Significance of the Blaming Emotions 215
already. Again, the lesson is that the question of whether a blaming emotion
is appropriate, all things considered, is not solely determined by whether or
not the blaming emotion fittingly appraises someone’s conduct. For
example, the propriety of sanctioning someone with a blaming emotion
can be affected by the seriousness of the wrong done. Just as with commu-
nicative appropriateness, some extremely minor wrongs ought not be
responded to, while the propriety of sanctioning a wrongdoer may increase
with the seriousness of the wrong.18 The person’s own repentance, or lack
thereof, is relevant because sanctioning an already repentant person may be
unnecessary to affect his future conduct.
As each of us has only limited motivational and actional resources, the
appropriateness of a blaming emotion qua sanction can also be affected by
what other wrongs you might plausibly respond to. For example, you do
better to get angry with the perpetrators of wrongs when you might
successfully undo the wrong or positively influence the perpetrator. If,
hypothetically, you became aware of two different wrongs committed by
two different people that were approximately as severe, your blaming
emotions would be better directed toward a wrongdoer who would be
more swayed by the communicative and motivational significance of your
blaming emotions. Thus, there is something to the phenomenon where
people are more likely to feel a blaming emotion in response to a wrong
that directly affects them or someone they know well, rather than a wrong
that affects persons with whom they have little contact. Other things equal,
your motivational resources are more likely to lead to beneficial outcomes if
you address concerns with which you can profitably engage.19
A related, but distinct, issue concerns what I will term the fairness of
sanctioning a wrongdoer with a blaming emotion. We can see this notion
displayed first by returning to the phenomenon of hypocrisy, earlier raised
in reference to the communicative appropriateness of a blaming emotion. If
you habitually commit a certain type of wrong, your right to sanction
others with the blaming emotions for similar wrongs will be called into
question—especially if you protest the sanction of the blaming emotions
when it is applied to you. Similarly, if two people jointly undertake to
commit a wrong (say, robbing someone’s home) but one of them plays
more of a role in planning and executing the deed than the other, it is
appropriate to sanction the “mastermind” to a greater degree with a
blaming emotion. Thus, if you must choose where to direct your blaming
emotions, fairness considerations speak to you blaming the mastermind
more than the accomplice. I believe the notion of the unfairness of blaming
emotions qua sanction also accounts for our appropriate reluctance to
blame the victims of wrongs or injustices, even if the victims of such wrongs
are complicit in, or partially responsible for, the wrongdoing. In such a
situation, targeting the person who was wronged with a blaming emotion
amounts to piling another bad thing on top of whatever misfortune the
person has already suffered.
To this point, I have argued that the blaming emotions are significant for
our moral responsibility practices as appraisals, communications, and
sanctions. I have also argued that the appropriateness of a blaming emotion
in one sense does not guarantee that the blaming emotion is appropriate in
others. I have particularly focused on situations where a blaming emotion
fittingly appraises another’s conduct but is at the same time communi-
catively inappropriate or is inappropriate as a sanction. I do not take myself
to have exhausted all possible appropriateness considerations that bear on
these three functions, though I do hope to have captured many of the most
interesting and relevant appropriateness considerations for our practices of
moral responsibility. I now want to discuss several prominent accounts of
moral responsibility to suggest that differing accounts of moral responsi-
bility are motivated by attention to different ways in which the blaming
emotions are significant for moral responsibility.20
The notion that the blaming emotions involve appraisals of conduct as
wrongful is implicit in a number of theories of moral responsibility. For
example, John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza hold that someone is
morally responsible for her conduct to the extent that she is an “appropriate
candidate for at least some of the reactive attitudes on the basis of that
behavior” (1998, 6). Fischer and Ravizza admit that “in some contexts it
20 While this project seeks to locate the source of agreements and disputes about the
concept of moral responsibility, my own view is that considerations of fit are the only
appropriateness conditions of the blaming emotions that bear on a person’s moral
responsibility because these considerations circumscribe the concept of blameworthiness.
Unfortunately, I don’t have space to make that case here.
Significance of the Blaming Emotions 217
action (given that she understands its moral status), and not by virtue of conse-
quentialist considerations. (2007, 86).23
Also placing the sanctioning function at the fore of their analyses are
Tamler Sommers and Neil Levy who, like Galen Strawson, are skeptics
about desert-entailing moral responsibility.24 Sommers claims that “we feel
resentment when we feel that people have wronged us, and that they
deserve blame (and perhaps punishment) for what they did” (2007, 327).
Levy agrees that moral responsibility has a link to desert, but that the
connection between moral responsibility and deserved sanction is less
direct than Strawson and Sommers believe. On Levy’s view, the thought
that someone is morally responsible for wrongful acts she performs
amounts to the claim that such a person no longer deserves the full
protection of a right they would otherwise be entitled to: “a right against
having their interests discounted in consequentialist calculations” (2011, 3).
To have one’s interests discounted in such calculations is to incur a cost on
acting wrongfully: a sanction.
6 . C O N C LU S I O N
In this paper, I’ve argued that the blaming emotions relate to our practices
of holding people morally responsible in three different ways: appraisal,
communication, and sanction. I’ve shown that these ways in which the
blaming emotions are significant for our moral responsibility practices are
themselves associated with distinct considerations of appropriateness (fit-
tingness, communicative appropriateness, and appropriateness qua sanc-
tion) and that these different considerations can come apart from one
another. A blaming emotion can be fitting, for example, but inappropriate
qua communicative considerations or fitting yet inappropriate as a sanc-
tion. Finally, I’ve suggested that the different functions of the blaming
emotions and their characteristic conditions of appropriateness are quite
25 For an overview of some of the relevant empirical data, see (Bargh and Chartrand
1999).
Significance of the Blaming Emotions 221
REFERENCES
26 This paper has been much improved by helpful discussion with a friendly audience
at the New Orleans Workshop on Agency and Responsibility. Antony Aumann, Andrea
Scarpino, and David Shoemaker also provided particularly beneficial constructive com-
ments and discussion. Finally, two anonymous referees from Oxford University Press
supplied instructive comments.
222 Zac Cogley
Fehr, Ernst and Simon Gächter (2000). “Cooperation and Punishment in Public
Goods Experiments.” The American Economic Review 90 (4): 980–94.
——.(2002). “Altruistic Punishment in Humans.” Nature 415, 137–40.
Fernández-Dols, José-Miguel, and Marı́a-Angeles Ruiz-Belda.(1995). “Are Smiles a Sign
of Happiness? Gold Medal Winners at the Olympic Games.” Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology 69 (6): 1113–19. doi.10.1037/0022-3514.69.6.1113.
Fischer, John Martin and Mark Ravizza (1998). Responsibility and Control: A Theory
of Moral Responsibility. (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press).
—— and Neal A. Tognazzini (2010). “The Physiognomy of Responsibility.” Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research (December). doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00458.x.
Haidt, J. (2001). “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist
Approach to Moral Judgment.” Psychological Review 108 (4): 814.
Hieronymi, Pamela (2004). “The Force and Fairness of Blame.” Philosophical
Perspectives 18 (1): 115–148. doi:10.1111/j.1520-8583.2004.00023.x.
Horstmann, Gernot (2003). “What Do Facial Expressions Convey: Feeling States,
Behavioral Intentions, or Actions Requests?” Emotion 3 (2): 150–66. doi:10.1037/
1528-3542.3.2.150.
Kraut, Robert E, and Robert E. Johnston (1979). “Social and Emotional Messages
of Smiling: An Ethological Approach.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
37 (9): 1539–53. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.37.9.1539.
Lazarus, R. S. (1982). “Thoughts on the Relations Between Emotion and Cogni-
tion.” American Psychologist 37 (9): 1019–24.
—— (1984). “On the Primacy of Cognition.” American Psychologist 39 (2): 124–9.
—— (1991). Emotion and Adaptation. (New York: Oxford University Press).
Leith, K. P, and Roy Baumeister (1996). “Why Do Bad Moods Increase Self-
defeating Behavior? Emotion, Risk Tasking, and Self-regulation.” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 71 (6): 1250–67.
Lerner, Jennifer S., and D. Keltner (2000). “Beyond Valence: Toward a Model of
Emotion-specific Influences on Judgement and Choice.” Cognition & Emotion 14
(4): 473–93.
—— —— (2001). “Fear, Anger, and Risk.” Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology 81 (1): 146–59.
Lerner, Jennifer S., and Larissa Z Tiedens (2006). “Portrait of the Angry Decision
Maker: How Appraisal Tendencies Shape Anger’s Influence on Cognition.”
Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 19 (2) (April 1): 115–37. doi:10.1002/
bdm.515.
Lerner, Jennifer S., Julie H. Goldberg, and Philip. E. Tetlock (1998). “Sober
Second Thought: The Effects of Accountability, Anger, and Authoritarianism
on Attributions of Responsibility.” Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 24 (6)
(June 1): 563–74. doi:10.1177/0146167298246001.
Levy, Neil (2011). Hard Luck. (New York: Oxford University Press).
Litvak, P. M, J. S Lerner, L. Z Tiedens, and K. Shonk. 2010. “Fuel in the Fire: How
Anger Impacts Judgment and Decision-Making.” International Handbook of
Anger: 287–310.
Significance of the Blaming Emotions 223
McKenna, Michael (1998). “The Limits of Evil and the Role of Moral Address:
A Defense of Strawsonian Compatibilism.” The Journal of Ethics 2 (2) (June 1):
123–42. doi:10.1023/A:1009754626801.
—— (2004). “Responsibility and Globally Manipulated Agents.” Philosophical
Topics 32 (1/2): 169.
Macnamara, Coleen (forthcoming). “ ‘Screw You!’ & ‘Thank You’.” Philosophical
Studies: 1–22. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-9995-3.
—— (2009). “Holding Others Responsible.” Philosophical Studies 152 (October
23): 81–102. doi:10.1007/s11098-009-9464-9.
Ochs, Jack and Alvin E. Roth (1989). “An Experimental Study of Sequential
Bargaining.” The American Economic Review 79 (3) (June 1): 355–84.
Parkinson, Brian (1997). “Untangling the Appraisal-emotion Connection.” Person-
ality and Social Psychology Review 1 (1): 62–79.
——— (1999). “Relations and Dissociations Between Appraisal and Emotion
Ratings of Reasonable and Unreasonable Anger and Guilt.” Cognition & Emotion
13 (4): 347–85.
Pereboom, Derk (2001). Living Without Free Will. (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge
University Press).
—— (2007). “Hard Incompatibilism.” Four Views on Free Will: 85–125.
—— (2009). “Free Will, Love, And Anger.” Ideas y Valores: Revista Colombiana De
Filosofı́a (141): 169–89.
—— (2011). “Free Will Skepticism and Meaning in Life.” In The Oxford Hand-
book of Free Will, ed. Robert Kane. 2nd edn. (New York: Oxford University
Press).
Pillutla, Madan M., and J. Keith Murnighan (1996). “Unfairness, Anger, and Spite:
Emotional Rejections of Ultimatum Offers.” Organizational Behavior and
Human Decision Processes 68 (3) (December): 208–24. doi:06/obhd.1996.0100.
Porter, Stephen and Leanne ten Brinke (2008). “Reading Between the Lies.” Psycho-
logical Science 19 (5) (May 1): 508–14. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2008.02116.x.
Prinz, Jesse (2004). Gut Reactions: A Perceptual Theory of Emotion. (New York:
Oxford University Press).
—— and Shaun Nichols (2010). “Moral Emotions.” In The Moral Psychology
Handbook, ed. John Doris (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 111–48.
Roseman, Ira J., Cynthia Wiest, and Tamara S Swartz (1994). “Phenomenology,
Behaviors, and Goals Differentiate Discrete Emotions.” Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology 67 (2): 206–21. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.67.2.206.
Scanlon, T. M. (2008). Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame. (Cam-
bridge, MA: Belknap, Harvard University Press).
Scherer, K. R. (1986). “Vocal Affect Expression: A Review and a Model for Future
Research.” Psychological Bulletin 99 (2): 143–65.
Shah, Nishi. (2003). “How Truth Governs Belief.” The Philosophical Review
112 (4) : 447.
—— R. Banse, H. G Wallbott, and T. Goldbeck. (1991). “Vocal Cues in Emotion
Encoding and Decoding.” Motivation and Emotion 15 (2): 123–48.
224 Zac Cogley
1 I would like to thank the participants at the 2011 New Orleans Workshop on
Agency and Responsibility for their questions and comments on this paper, particularly
Sarah Buss, T. M. Scanlon, Sarah Stroud, and Gary Watson. I am also very grateful to
David Shoemaker and to two anonymous referees for Oxford University Press for their
written comments.
2 It is true that the doctor suffers from normative ignorance since she does not know
that she has prescribed an inappropriate medication, but this is not what I mean by
“moral ignorance.” A doctor who suffers from moral ignorance (as I shall use the phrase)
would not know that it is wrong to intentionally prescribe a patient the wrong medica-
tion. The doctor in the example suffers from circumstantial ignorance because she is not
aware that, given her circumstances, her action will lead to bad consequences for her
patient.
226 Matthew Talbert
circumstantial and moral ignorance (Rosen 2004).3 Rosen assumes that for
an agent to be blameworthy for actions that issue from moral or
circumstantial ignorance, the agent must be culpable for her ignorance.
This assumption plays a crucial role for Rosen in a skeptical argument that
calls into question many intuitive judgments of moral blameworthiness.
Though I reject Rosen’s conclusion, I find his skeptical argument
powerful. Indeed, and as I attempt to show, the argument is sufficiently
strong that a relatively conservative approach to overturning it does not
succeed.4 Instead, if we are to avoid the skeptical conclusion, we must reject
the plausible sounding assumption that unwitting wrongdoers are
blameworthy only if they are culpable for their ignorance. To this end,
I argue that while ignorance of the circumstances and consequences of one’s
actions often undermines blame, moral ignorance typically does not do so.
For example, while I might not be blameworthy for injuring you if I was
unaware that my action would have that result, I likely would be
blameworthy if I were simply unaware that injuring you is impermissible.
I will argue, moreover, that a morally ignorant wrongdoer can be
blameworthy even if it is not her fault that she is ignorant of the moral
status of her behavior, and even if it would be unreasonable to expect her to
be aware of its status. In the context of making these points, I also try to
shed light on the role that moral disagreement plays in our judgments of
blameworthiness.
1 . S K E P T I C I S M A B O U T M OR A L R E S P ON S I B I L I T Y
3 Also see Rosen (2003). Michael Zimmerman (1997) offers a view similar to
Rosen’s; also see Zimmerman (2008).
4 The conservative approach I have in mind is the one pursued by William FitzPatrick
(2008). I discuss FitzPatrick’s view in Section 2.
The Role of Moral Disagreement in Blame 227
having done it” (296). Thus, if we judge that X is blameworthy, this means
“that X is liable [in our judgment] to a negative emotional response of this
sort for having done A, or equivalently, that some such response would be
appropriate or fitting” (297). Rosen’s skepticism amounts, then, to skepti-
cism about the aptness of negative reactive attitudes like resentment. In
what follows, I will understand moral responsibility in just the way Rosen
suggests: the primary question will be about whether judgments of blame-
worthiness, and responses like resentment, are apt.
Rosen’s skeptical argument proceeds as follows. Wrongdoing is either
witting or unwitting. While a knowing wrongdoer may be directly blame-
worthy for her behavior, an unwitting wrongdoer will be blameworthy for
her wrongdoing only derivatively or indirectly. This means that an ignorant
wrongdoer will be morally responsible, in the sense of being open to blame,
only if she is culpable for her ignorance.5 However, according to Rosen,
“[i]gnorance is culpable only if it derives from culpable recklessness or
negligence in the management of one’s opinion” and this prior recklessness
will be culpable only if it was knowing or was itself the product of knowing
mismanagement of one’s opinions (302). So, as Rosen puts it, ignorance is
culpable—and unwitting wrongdoing blameworthy—only if it results, at
some point, from an akratic act in which the agent knowingly violated an
epistemic or moral duty:
One is responsible for the act done from ignorance only if one is independently
responsible for something else . . . this entails that the only possible locus of original
responsibility is an akratic act. . . . Our first sin must be a knowing sin—a sin done in
full knowledge of every pertinent fact or principle. (307)6
Rosen applies this perspective to cases of circumstantial ignorance (like that
of the doctor in the introduction), but also to cases of moral ignorance. For
example, Rosen’s view suggests that an “ancient slaveholder who . . . believes
that it is morally permissible for him to buy and sell” slaves is blameworthy
for his behavior “only if he is culpable for the moral ignorance from which
he acts” (304).
The skeptical force of this position emerges when we consider the
possibility that many unwitting wrongdoers have never committed the
kind of akratic act that would make them culpable for their ignorance.
7 Unlike the ambitious capitalist, Bill is mistaken about the force of moral consider-
ations rather than about a moral principle.
8 For discussion of a related example, see Rosen (2008: 605–9).
The Role of Moral Disagreement in Blame 229
significant confidence in” the judgment that an agent has such a history
(308). In a recent response to Rosen, William FitzPatrick has argued that in
fact we often have good grounds for attributing akrasia to ourselves and
others (FitzPatrick 2008: 593–9). However, as FitzPatrick notes, this leaves
untouched Rosen’s conclusion that blameworthy wrongdoing is always
either knowing or the result of knowing wrongdoing (599). We are left,
then, with a striking skeptical challenge, for very many ordinary wrong-
doers may not have a relevant instance of akrasia in their past and so are not
morally responsible for their wrongdoing.9 Below, I consider Fitzpatrick’s
attempt to meet this skeptical challenge.
Levy concludes that since Potter “could not rationally have taken advantage
of the opportunities for moral improvement” with which he was presented,
“we cannot reasonably expect him to do so” (735).10
There is also the question of how Potter acquired his vices. As FitzPatrick
notes, it may seem “problematic that the vices Potter exhibits in his
epistemically debilitating choices may trace back to his childhood and
may be largely a result of moral (bad) luck” (607). FitzPatrick deflects
this worry by noting that for most people “character traits are not merely
given but are formed, reformed and continuously shaped by our choices
from the point of moral maturity onward” (608). But this is not a helpful
response to the problem of constitutive moral luck since it simply pushes
the problem back to earlier stages of Potter’s development. Apparently,
Potter made poor choices as he shaped his character. But why did he make
such poor choices? By hypothesis, he did not knowingly make poor charac-
ter-forming choices, so perhaps Potter’s tendency to make “epistemically
debilitating” choices is explained by a tendency to see poor self-forming
choices as choice-worthy. But in this case, Potter’s self-forming choices
would seem to be shaped by incipient versions of the vices that his self-
formation is invoked to explain. And given the presence of these incipient
vices, why should we expect Potter to make the right choice when it comes
to choosing whether to act in a way that will strengthen his vices?
Finally, it is worth noting that FitzPatrick says that “cultural and
historical contexts” may make it unreasonable to expect a wrongdoer to
know better because “the relevant [moral] knowledge isn’t reasonably
available” (612). Aristotle, for example, may not be blameworthy for
10 This discussion is taken up again in (Levy 2011: 124–8). A referee for Oxford
University Press points out that we use the word “expect” in normative and descriptive
senses (to use the referee’s terminology). The descriptive sense presumably has to do with
what we anticipate from an agent in view of his capacities and the context in which he
acts, whereas the normative sense has to do with standards against which we measure
agents. When I say, “I expect it to rain tomorrow,” I use “expect” in the descriptive sense.
I anticipate rain; it seems like a safe bet. Neither Levy nor FitzPatrick expect moral
reform from Potter in this sense; neither regards it as a safe bet. (Though FitzPatrick is
keen to draw attention to Potter’s abilities and his social context and the way that these
make reform at least possible; he regards such reform as a live possibility even if not as a
likely outcome.) By contrast, both Levy and FitzPatrick agree that Potter falls short of
our expectations in at least one normative sense: they both regard Potter’s behavior as
morally subpar. The question is whether this subpar behavior opens Potter up to moral
blame. Here we might identify a slightly different sense in which “expect” can be
normative, the sense in which we talk about holding someone to an expectation.
Fitzpatrick thinks it is reasonable to hold Potter to our moral expectations because it is
possible for him to live up to these expectations given his abilities and the context in
which he acts. Levy thinks it is unfair to hold Potter to our moral expectations because he
can fulfill these only by behaving irrationally.
232 Matthew Talbert
3 . R E J E C T I N G T H E SK E P T I C A L AR GU M E N T
I take it that Rosen believes that Bill is responsible for lying, in the sense
of being open to attitudes like resentment, only if he is responsible for
lying in the sense of having played the right sort of role in bringing about
his own tendency to favor lying. But Bill’s case is a good example of why
moral responsibility, in the sense of blameworthiness, does not require
that agents have this sort “inculpating history.” It is reasonable for Bill’s
wife to blame him because of the way his lying expresses Bill’s morally
faulty judgments and attitudes. Bill has these faults, and they contribute
to his behavior, regardless of whether he is at fault for having them, and
regardless of whether Bill genuinely believes that lying to his wife is the
thing to do.
One of Bill’s faults has to do with how his wife’s interests rate when he is
trying to figure out what to do: Bill is willing to overlook his wife’s interests
when they conflict with Bill avoiding trouble. It is reasonable, then, to
attribute to Bill the judgment that his wife’s interest in not being lied to can
be overlooked, if that is how Bill can get what he wants. If Bill’s wife were to
find out how her interests rate with her husband, that he lied to her and the
basis on which he did so, then she would have good grounds for blame.
That is, it would be appropriate for her to be offended and hurt by what
Bill’s action expresses, for her to protest that her interests ought to rate
more highly with Bill, to resent him for his callousness, to insist that he
change his ways, and so on.
The general perspective developed above is as follows. Even if a wrongdoer
is ignorant of the fact that her behavior is wrong, and even if this ignorance is
not her fault, her actions may still express the contemptuous judgment that
certain others do not merit consideration, that their interests do not matter,
and that their objections can be overlooked. If one is injured by a wrongdoer
who is moved by such judgments, then the attitudes and responses involved
in moral blame are reasonable regardless of what the wrongdoer thinks about
the moral status of her behavior. I will develop this perspective below, but
there is enough here to see one way of rejecting the skeptical perspective on
moral responsibility with which this paper began. Rosen’s skepticism
depends on assuming that unwitting wrongdoers are open to blame only if
they are culpable for their ignorance. However, as I have argued, certain
features of an unwitting wrongdoer’s behavior can qualify her for blame
regardless of whether she is culpable for her ignorance.
Angela Smith has applied a view like the one I just outlined to show that
agents are often morally responsible for things that are not under their
The Role of Moral Disagreement in Blame 235
direct control: their desires and emotions, their advertences and inadver-
tences, and so on. We are responsible for these things, on Smith’s view,
because of the evaluative judgments they express and the importance of
these judgments for our interpersonal relations.
Smith gives special attention to the fact that “we often take what a person
notices and neglects to have an enormous amount of expressive signifi-
cance” (2005: 242). What a person notices attracts our attention because
we assume a connection between what one notices and what one values.
According to Smith, “if one judges some thing or person to be important or
significant,” this should “have an influence on one’s tendency to notice
factors which pertain to the existence, welfare, or flourishing of that thing
or person” (244). And if one fails to notice such factors, this “is at least
some indication that she does not accept this evaluative judgment [about
the thing’s importance]” (244). As Smith says, I may fail to “notice when
my music is too loud,” or that “my advice is unwelcome,” or that “my
assistance might be helpful to others,” and even if these failures are involun-
tary, they may still indicate “that I do not judge your needs and interests to
be important, or at least that I do not take them very seriously” (244).
Though she does not describe them this way, the examples Smith cites
are instances of circumstantial ignorance. On Smith’s view, then, judg-
ments about a circumstantially ignorant wrongdoer’s moral responsibility
should track the plausibility of associating her behavior with interpersonally
significant evaluative judgments—particularly judgments about the nor-
mative status of the needs and interests of those affected by the wrongdoer’s
actions and omissions.
As should be clear from the previous section, I am largely in agreement
with Smith, but it is worth emphasizing that we cannot always infer that an
agent does not care about something from the fact that she fails to notice
how her actions (or omissions) will affect it. Smith is aware of this; she
notes that in some cases of inadvertence, “the person in question may be
extremely tired or under a lot of stress” and this may “block the normal
inference from what a person notices to what she cares about” (244 n. 14).
Indeed, we sometimes hesitate to make the inference from what a person
notices to what she cares about even when we cannot point to stressors that
intuitively explain an agent’s inadvertence. Sometimes, and for no obvious
reason, we just forget things, or fail to notice them, yet we may have as
much concern for these things as we ought to have. This can be true even in
cases in which an inadvertence has horrible consequences, such as when a
parent mistakenly leaves a child in a hot car. In some of these cases, it is no
doubt correct to infer that the parent has a condemnable lack of concern for
the child’s welfare. But in other cases, it is difficult to read the testimony of
the parents involved and come away with the thought that their forgetting
236 Matthew Talbert
13 Cf. Levy (2011: 182). Gene Weingarten’s (2008) Pulitzer Prize winning article,
“Fatal Distraction,” offers a detailed and affecting account of some of these cases.
The Role of Moral Disagreement in Blame 237
and as the severity of this disagreement decreases, so too may the intensity
of our blame. Take the case of Robert E. Lee. Those interested in burnish-
ing Lee’s reputation often note that he joined the secessionist cause in the
US Civil War out of loyalty to the state of Virginia. Lee did wrong,
I assume, in leading Confederate troops against the Union, but he thought
he was doing what duty and loyalty required. Suppose, however, that Lee
was motivated to support the Confederacy solely by racial hatred and a
desire to see slavery preserved. In this case, Lee would still be a morally
ignorant wrongdoer, but his defenders would face a much more difficult
task in convincing us to excuse him. This is because Lee’s actions would
have been associated with judgments and attitudes that we find deeply
objectionable. An excuse like, “Lee thought he was doing the right thing,”
would, I submit, have little influence on us if we found the judgments that
informed his choices thoroughly repugnant. And if we do have some
tendency to accept this excuse, I suspect it is because the judgments
about the value and requirements of loyalty that purportedly guided Lee
are not utterly foreign or repellant to us.
rationally chosen to omit the action, and what agents can do rationally is a
function of their internalist reasons alone” (739).
I believe that the sense in which Potter has trouble avoiding wrong
actions does not make it unfair to blame him. Let us agree that Potter
has no internal reason to avoid a morally bad action, and that if he had
avoided the action, this would have been because of a “glitch” in his agency,
as Levy puts it. Importantly, this does not mean that Potter’s actual bad
behavior is the result of a glitch, mistake, compulsion, or anything similar.
If someone is subject to a compulsion or to “glitchy” agency, then some of
her actions may be unavoidable and she will have a claim to being excused
for this behavior. But the basis of excuse here—the reason the compulsive
agent is not appropriately targeted with resentment—is that her behavior is
not under her control in such a way that it can express the objectionable
judgments that would make blame appropriate. Usually, an agent’s inability
to avoid an action goes together with that action not being under the agent’s
control in this way, but cases of moral ignorance like Potter’s are an excep-
tion. Even if Potter does not have rational access to doing the right thing, his
bad behavior may be a manifestation of perfect reflective self-control and
subjective practical rationality: he may be acting just as he likes and for
reasons that really do speak in favor of so acting, given his proattitudes. But if
Potter’s bad actions are guided in this way by his judgment about reasons,
then they can express the kinds of attitudes and evaluative judgments that
I have argued make blaming responses appropriate.14
In addition, Potter presumably has the capacity to avoid wrongdoing in
the sense that, for any wrong action, he would have refrained from per-
forming that action if he had taken himself to have a decisive reason to do
so. Of course, if Potter’s actual constitution entails that he will see no such
reason, then he will not rationally avoid his wrongdoing, and it is this lack
of rational access to avoiding wrongdoing that Levy thinks makes blame
unfair. But if Potter’s bad actions are guided by his judgments about how to
behave, and if he would have acted differently if he had recognized a reason
to do so, then his wrongdoing is unavoidable mainly in the sense that an
action that is wrong (by our lights) is bound to seem choice-worthy to
Potter. Since this sort of unavoidability does nothing to make Potter’s
behavior less knowing, deliberate, and dismissive of the interests of those
his actions affect, I do not see why it should make blame unfair.
So, while I agree with Levy that it is not reasonable to demand that
Potter behave contrary to his internal reasons, what I think this tells us is
14 There is an important relation here with the theme of Harry Frankfurt (1969).
I develop this point in (2012a).
The Role of Moral Disagreement in Blame 239
15 What if a wild animal injured George? Would we say that the animal’s behavior
expresses a blame-grounding rejection of the significance of George’s welfare? I think
not. The behavior of animals is not morally significant in this way because a judgment
like, “George’s injuries don’t matter,” is not meaningfully attributed to them. I don’t
mean that nonhuman animals can never be described as being sensitive to reasons but
rather that their behavior does not have the same significance for us as that of beings
whose behavior is more richly and generally informed by evaluative judgments.
240 Matthew Talbert
agrees that, in the internalist sense, Potter has no reason to care how he
fares, it is still appropriate for George to insist that his welfare is valuable
and to see Potter’s rejection of this claim as a manifestation of ill will.
If we agree with George that his welfare is valuable, and that a person of
good will would see his welfare as a source of reasons, we should conclude
that Potter’s judgment about the significance of George’s welfare reason-
ably elicits blaming responses on George’s part. By contrast, if we think that
George’s welfare has little normative significance, we are likely to find
George’s blame inappropriate. However, this conclusion would stem not
from the thought that Potter can’t reasonably be expected to recognize the
significance of George’s welfare, but rather from our disagreement with
George about this significance.
It may be thought that Potter can reject the normative status of George’s
welfare in a morally relevant way only if he had rational access to an
accurate judgment about this status.16 I don’t see why this should be so.
What reason is there to think that the expressive significance, for George
and for us, of Potter’s behavior should hang on whether Potter might
rationally have made different judgments about reasons? After all (and as
I pointed out above), Potter’s actual behavior, and his actual failure to agree
with George about the significance of his welfare, need not have been
caused by a glitch, but may be a thoroughly deliberate and controlled
exercise of his agency. And suppose that Potter did have some internal
reason to take George’s welfare as a constraint on his behavior, but that he
still unjustifiably and deliberately injured him. If we did not already think
that Potter’s action was offensive in a blame-grounding way, I do not see
how adding this element to the story would make blame appropriate. What
matters is that George believes (and we believe) that he has standing that
makes Potter’s treatment of him illegitimate. Regardless of whether Potter
could have been rationally moved to accept our view about the treatment to
which George is entitled, his knowing and willing behavior demonstrates
that he rejects this view.
In one of his discussions of internal reasons, Bernard Williams charac-
terizes blame as functioning like advice given after the fact—it tells wrong-
doers what they ought to have done. As Williams says, “if ‘ought to have’ is
appropriate afterwards in the modality of blame, then (roughly) ‘ought to’
was appropriate at the time in the modality of advice” (Williams 1995: 40).
However,
16 This would be similar to Gary Watson’s claim that a wrongdoer flouts a moral
demand in a way that justifies resentment only if he is capable of recognizing the validity
of the demand (Watson 2004 : 234).
The Role of Moral Disagreement in Blame 241
‘ought to’ in the modality of advice implies ‘can,’ because advice aims to offer
something as a candidate for a deliberative conclusion. If ç-ing is not available to
the agent, ‘You ought to ç’ cannot function as a piece of advice about what he
should now do; when it is a matter of what I am to do, manifestly ‘I cannot’ acts as a
stopper. (40)
Similarly, we might worry that if a wrongdoer has no internal reason to
refrain from an action, this is a “stopper” on blame because there is no
point to the advice that is supposedly implicit in blame.
I agree that when we blame a person, we are typically committed to the
claim that she ought not to have done what she did. But the “ought” of
blame is not always, or at least not solely, in the mode of advice. It can also
be an “ought” that points to an ideal or to a moral fact: the fact, for
example, that George deserves better treatment from Potter, and that a
person of good will would not have disregarded George’s interests and
welfare. This sort of “ought” does not imply “can.” Of course, as a form of
advice, it may be futile for George to insist to Potter that his welfare
matters. But as a form of protest this insistence is a natural way of expressing
the moral offense and resentment involved in blame.17 The reasons that
matter most for blame are our reasons—the considerations recognized by
the victim and by those who sympathize with her. Whether these
considerations can also be reasons for the blamed party is, I think, of
secondary importance.18
17 I argue that moral blame is sometimes best construed as a form of moral protest in
(2012a).
18 A referee for Oxford University Press suggests that I might note the affinity
between what I say in this section and, e.g., the sort of view once defended by Philippa
Foot (1972). There certainly seem to me to be affinities here but I am not sure how to
characterize them; I will simply note that I am very attracted to the sort of view Foot
outlines. Another referee suggests that I can in fact say that it is reasonable to expect
wrongdoers like Mr Potter to correct their moral ignorance. This suggestion relies on my
characterization of these wrongdoers as expressing ill will, the fact that expressions of ill
will (arguably) flout the demand to treat others with reasonable regard, and the fact that
this demand is connected to our normative expectations of other agents. I don’t doubt
that this proposal is workable but (in this and previous work) I prefer to grant to
opponents that certain moral demands and expectations are off the table in Potter’s
case (and other related cases). I think this helps to make the debate more clear than it
would be otherwise. However, the referee’s comment prompts me to note that my
disagreement with FitzPatrick is in some ways less stark than I presented it in
Section 2. FitzPatrick and I agree that Potter can reasonably be held to our moral
standards in the sense that we regard him as a proper target of moral blame. (I suspect
this is the sense in which the referee believes I can say that we properly expect better
things of Potter.) However, for FitzPatrick, the legitimacy of blaming Potter depends on
his having been able to avoid his moral ignorance. On my view, Potter’s blameworthiness
does not depend on this but only on the actual judgments that inform his behavior.
242 Matthew Talbert
Suppose that there is a kind of harm that is objectively morally relevant, but of
which we are ignorant. Suppose, for instance, that plants can be harmed, and that
this harm is a moral reason against killing or treading on them. In that case, many of
us are causally responsible for a great many moral harms. Are we morally responsible
for them? Do we flout a moral requirement, and challenge plants’ standing as
objects to which some moral consideration is owed? No to all these questions: If
we do not grasp the moral requirement, and this ignorance is not culpable, we do
nothing blameworthy. (2005: 9)19
Now I agree that we are not blameworthy for stepping on plants in Levy’s
example, but the example is offered as an instance of exculpation by way of
nonculpable moral ignorance and this is not what it shows. Levy’s example
fails to illustrate the exculpatory power of moral ignorance because what
explains why we are not blameworthy in the example is that we lack crucial
information about how walking on plants affects them. Since I do not
know that plants can be harmed, my stepping on one does not express a
denial of the significance of its being harmed. So, on the view I advocate,
stepping on a plant does not express a judgment that could properly ground
blame.
The problem is that Levy’s example does not involve the relevant sort of
moral ignorance. There is, of course, a kind of moral ignorance in the
example: we lack knowledge of the moral status of stepping on plants
(because we are ignorant of their capacity for suffering). But this moral
ignorance derives from circumstantial ignorance and not from ignorance of
a moral principle. In the example, I presumably know that I generally have
moral reasons to not cause pain; I just don’t know that stepping on plants
causes them pain. However, the moral ignorance of someone like Mr Potter
is just the reverse: he knows that his actions will cause George Bailey and
others pain, but he does not know (because he does not believe) that this
counts decisively against performing these actions.
For Levy’s example to help us see that Potter’s sort of moral ignorance
counts as an excuse, the example would have to feature Potter’s sort of
ignorance. The example would need to be one in which I know, say, that
stepping on a plant will cause it pain and I (nonculpably, but wrongly)
believe that this pain does not matter. Now if we think that I am blameless
in this revised version of Levy’s example, we might draw a conclusion about
the exculpatory significance of nonculpable ignorance of moral principles.
Of course, I would not agree that I am blameless in this revised case. If
19 I should note that Levy is considering psychopaths (rather than relatively normal
wrongdoers like Mr Potter) when he offers this example, but I don’t think this affects its
usefulness here. David Shoemaker (2011) treats a similar example; I reply to Shoemaker
in (2012b).
244 Matthew Talbert
CONCLUSION
I have argued against the assumption that morally ignorant wrongdoers are
open to moral blame only if they are culpable for their ignorance. Thus,
I reject skepticism about moral responsibility that depends on this assump-
tion. On the view I have defended, the attitudes involved in moral blame
are responses to the features of an action that make it objectionable from
the perspective of the one who issues the blame. One important way that an
action can appear objectionable to us is that it expresses a judgment with
which we disagree about the significance of the needs and interests of those
affected by the action. Whether a wrongdoer’s action has this feature
depends more on whether she is aware of the consequences of her behavior
than on whether she regards her behavior as wrong.
REFERENCES
1. INTRODUCTION
Moral luck occurs when agents are morally evaluated for things that are
beyond their control (Williams, 1981; Nagel, 1979). A particularly clear
kind of moral luck is “resultant luck,” or luck in the way things turn out.
Attempted murderers are judged less harshly than successful ones though
both intended to kill their victims. Drunk drivers who have an accident
resulting in the death of a pedestrian may be convicted for manslaughter or
worse; drunk drivers who are caught without incident get nothing more
than a suspended driver’s license or compulsory participation in an online
seminar. Some philosophers, most notably Aristotle, accepted moral luck as
a fact of life. Contemporary philosophers, however, tend to regard moral
luck as a serious problem or even a paradox because they employ a Kantian
concept of moral desert according to which agents can be justly blamed or
praised only for aspects of actions that are within their control.
The ongoing controversy over victim impact statements (VIS) shows
that this conception of moral desert is pervasive within criminal justice
systems as well, at least in the West. VIS are statements that express the grief
and suffering of the victims of crimes as well as their views on what would
be a suitable punishment for the offender. In the well known 1987
Supreme Court case Booth v. Maryland, the Justices overturned a lower
court’s use of a VIS in a capital crime. Writing for the majority decision,
Justice Lewis Powell explains:
The focus of a VIS . . . is not on the defendant, but on the character and reputation
of the victim and the effect on his family. These factors may be wholly unrelated to the
blameworthiness of a particular defendant. As our cases have shown, the defendant
often will not know the victim, and therefore will have no knowledge about the
existence or characteristics of the victim’s family. Moreover, defendants rarely select
their victims based on whether the murder will have an effect on anyone other than
the person murdered. Allowing the jury to rely on a VIS therefore could result in
Partial Desert 247
imposing the death sentence because of factors about which the defendant was unaware,
and that were irrelevant to the decision to kill. This evidence thus could divert the
jury’s attention away from the defendant’s background and record, and the circum-
stances of the crime. ((Booth v. Maryland, 1987, p. 253; my italics)
The worry about VIS noted in the majority decision is precisely that it
introduces an unacceptable degree of resultant luck in the sentencing
process. According to Powell, punishment should be tied exclusively to
the “personal responsibility and moral guilt” of the offender. The VIS
contains information that the offender could not possibly have known or
foreseen at the time of the crime. The amount of grief a particular family
will feel, how vindictive or forgiving their natures happen to be—all of this
is beyond the control of the offender. It has nothing to do with the
offender’s “decision to kill” and, according to Powell, is therefore unrelated
to his moral guilt and personal responsibility.
Though the courts may try to minimize its effects in certain cases, it is
clear that moral luck pervades our legal system and everyday lives. It seems
right that a drunk driver who accidentally kills a pedestrian deserves more
punishment than one who made it home safely, even if it is perhaps unfair
for the difference to be so extreme. How can we account for our intuitions
in such cases? One alternative would be to claim that although their
intentions were the same, the drivers performed two different actions.
The first driver is judged for the act of killing a pedestrian while driving
drunk, the second for a normal DUI. Another would be to claim that the
two drivers are equally deserving of blame, but that judgments about the
proper punishment must take harm into account.1 Finally, one may claim
that the drivers deserve the same amount of punishment, but that for
various consequentialist reasons we have to punish the second driver
more harshly.
In this chapter, I defend a fourth alternative. I argue that we should not
understand desert as impartial or “blind,” connected only to the personal
culpability of the agent. Rather, we should instead adopt a “partial” account
according to which desert judgments are properly sensitive to the feelings,
desires, and behavior of those most closely affected by the wrongdoing.
Section 2 outlines in a little more detail the conception of moral desert that
I wish to challenge. Sections 3 and 4 present several cases and variations that
appear to undermine the impartial view and offers a new account of desert
that can better account for our judgments in the cases. Section 5 introduces a
1
This alternative may just push the problem back a step, however, since it does not
explain why it is fair to punish wrongdoers for aspects of their behavior that are beyond
their control.
248 Tamler Sommers
2
This chapter focuses only on desert for morally wrong or bad actions.
3
See e.g. Fischer and Ravizza (1998), Kane (1996), van Inwagen (1983). Exceptions
to this rule, depending on one’s interpretation, may include Strawson (1962), Wallace
(1994), and Scanlon (2008).
4
It is surprisingly difficult to find discussions of the degrees of moral responsibility in
the philosophical literature. Perhaps this is because theories of moral responsibility tend
to be framed in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions.
Partial Desert 249
3. PARTIAL DESERT
The following two cases offer some support for my proposal. They begin
the same way:
John is a 33-year-old graduate student at the University of Utah. He goes
to a football game and gets very drunk. He plans to leave his car at the
stadium and get a ride home from a friend, but there is miscommunica-
tion and his friend leaves without him. In general, John is morally
opposed to drunk driving and almost never does. But it is almost impos-
sible to get a cab, so John reluctantly drives home in his intoxicated state.
Just before he reaches his house, he has an accident causing him to swerve
into a driveway where a young girl was playing. The girl is killed instantly.
Panicked, still drunk, not thinking clearly, he leaves the scene and goes
home. As he sobers up, he is overcome with remorse. He considers
turning himself in but is terrified of going to jail and decides against it.
Now the story splits into two directions.
First Scenario
The police track down John, arrest him, and put him on trial. Perhaps
because the death involved a child, as well as a hit and run, the DA
5
As should be clear, I use “partial” here to contrast with “impartial” rather than with
“wholly” or “fully.”
250 Tamler Sommers
manages to convict John for homicide and the judge sentences him to
the death penalty. Since this takes place in Utah, John dies at the hands
of a firing squad.
Judgment: Most, I imagine, would call this an unjust verdict. The killing,
after all, was completely unintentional. John showed no ill will whatsoever
towards his victim or anyone else. True, he made the decision to drive drunk
but there were many people in far worse condition than John who drove
home from the game and were lucky enough to avoid this tragedy. It is truly
a case of terrible moral luck that his accident resulted in the death of a child.
To be sure, John deserves a harsh sentence for his crime, John himself would
likely agree with that. But few would say that he deserves to die for it.
Second Scenario
The police are unable to discover who caused the accident. The parents
of the child are grief stricken, completely distraught. Their daughter
meant everything to them. Since the police are overtaxed and the case has
gone cold, they vow to find the culprit themselves. They cash out their
retirement funds, sell their house, and hire the best private investigators.
Eventually they discover that it was John who caused the death of their
daughter. The father goes to John’s house, taking his gun. When he sees
John, he is overwhelmed with anger and grief. The image of his daughter
playing in their driveway flashes through his head. He takes out his gun
and shoots John in the heart, killing him.
Judgment: In this scenario, by contrast, it seems far more plausible that John
gets what he deserves. At the very least, John seems significantly more
deserving of his fate in the second scenario than the first. (If “John gets
what he deserves” were on a Likert scale, I imagine people would be much
closer to “agree” in the second scenario than the first.) Furthermore, John
himself would likely feel the same way—I certainly would in his shoes.
Facing the firing squad, John might be furious at the injustice and the
unlawfulness of the verdict. But looking down the barrel of the father’s gun,
he may think: “I ended the life of this man’s child. If he wants to shoot me,
that’s his right. I have this coming, it’s what I deserve.”
I should emphasize we are not evaluating the morality of the father’s
action, but rather whether John receives what he deserves. These are
separate matters. To take a grisly example, imagine that a gang of rapists
coincidentally choose as their victim a man who is a serial rapist himself.
We might say that gang acted immorally but nevertheless that the serial
rapist got precisely what he deserved. My claim, then, is not that the father
acted rightly in shooting John. It is that John seems to deserve his fate
(being shot in the heart) more when it is the father, rather than State, who
Partial Desert 251
carries it out. Yet the accepted framework cannot account for this judg-
ment. In both cases, John’s personal culpability and his punishment (being
shot in the heart) are identical. Our judgments about what John deserves,
then, do not seem to be based entirely on facts about the wrongdoing and
John’s responsibility for performing it.6
For readers who lack my intuitions about these cases, my argument will
likely not have much force—at least not yet. Those who share my intuitions
but still wish to preserve the impartial conception of desert must explain
why we come to different judgments in the two cases. One might appeal to
consequentialist considerations, but desert—as a backwards-looking con-
cept—is essentially nonconsequentialist in nature; it would be surprising if
the difference in intuitions were sensitive to such factors. More import-
antly, it is not clear that the consequences are better in the second case than
in the first. Indeed, they may be worse, since the father will likely be
imprisoned himself, causing even more suffering for himself and his wife.
One might object that our intuitions in the first case are responding to
the legal injustice of the verdict. After all, involuntary vehicular manslaugh-
ter is not a capital crime. The DA would probably have to fudge the
evidence or mislead the jury to get the conviction. Perhaps we are feeling
more lenient towards John in the first case because of the legally unfounded
conviction for homicide. I agree that there seems to be a legal injustice in
the first case, but I do not think it can account for the difference in
intuitions. After all, the law is not being respected in the second scenario
either. Federal or State law does not allow for parents of victims to take the
law into their own hands. And if it is unjust in principle to issue a capital
sentence when there is no mens rea on the criminal’s part, then it should be
equally unjust for the father to carry out the killing himself.
A more promising strategy might appeal to our natural sympathy for the
father. We may feel that the father’s actions were understandable in a way
that the State’s was not. We may even believe that the father deserves his
vengeance, which then affects our judgment about what John deserves.
I agree that our judgments may be sensitive to our sympathy for the father,
but it is not clear that this is a distorting influence rather than an appropri-
ate one. My claim is that our desert judgments should be sensitive to our
sympathy for the particular victims of wrongdoing. Again, imagine the case
6
We may also imagine an analogous set of cases in which John receives what seems
like too lenient a sentence. In the first case, the judge gives him probation and no jail
time. In the second, the father finds John, sees that he feels tremendous guilt, that he is
horrified by what happened, and decides not to turn him in to the police. Again, I would
suggest that John seems more deserving of the lighter sentence in the second case than the
first.
252 Tamler Sommers
from John’s perspective. If I were John, I would feel enormous sympathy for
the child’s father, and my sympathy might lead me to think it is in large part
up to him as an individual to determine what I deserve. Unless we are already
committed to the impartial conception, I see no reason why we should regard
this sympathy as a distortion of John’s judgment. One might try to turn this
reply into another objection to the partial conception. Perhaps the difference
in judgments can be traced to what happens when we take the agent’s
perspective. But again, there is no reason to think that this is a distorting
influence—why shouldn’t we take the agent’s perspective into account? The
reply: “Because the agents’ subjective perspective is irrelevant to objective
judgments about what they deserve” begs the question. It is true that agents
are likely to be biased in their own favor, or at times feel excessive unwar-
ranted guilt. But this just means we should be careful about how we interpret
the agent’s perspective, not that we should ignore it entirely.7
Two more cases may help to illustrate the relevance of the victims’ feelings
to the offender’s deservingness. Both are variations of the second case in
which the father shoots John. The variations focus on the father’s feelings
after the shooting.8
Third Scenario
The father recognizes that he acted in a moment of blind rage and
despair, and regrets the shooting immediately. He calls for an ambulance
but it arrives too late, John is dead. Although there is a small glimmer of
satisfaction that John will not get away unpunished, on balance he feels
7
As an anonymous referee notes, this case has an additional complication, namely that
the victim is dead and her wishes regarding the punishment are unknown. (Or she may be
too young to have well-considered feelings about John’s punishment.) This raises the
question of how desert might be affected if her parents or close relatives had different
wishes regarding the punishment—for example, if the mother felt more retributive and the
father more merciful. I agree that this is a difficult and important question, one that my
“partial” view of desert must address. For the purposes of this more programmatic paper,
however, it’s enough to point out that such factors (agreement or disagreement among the
relatives or those closely connected to the victim) actually matter, even if we cannot yet
specify how much. On the impartial conception of desert, these factors would be irrelevant.
8
These variations are inspired by Chandra Sripada and his comments on the Flickers
of Freedom blog. I am grateful for his contributions as well as many others on that post.
See: <http://agencyandresponsibility.typepad.com/flickers-of-freedom/2010/08/can-there-
be-partial-as-opposed-to-impartial-desert.html>.
Partial Desert 253
worse than before. John did not mean to hurt his daughter, people drive
drunk all the time. As the father looks down at John’s lifeless body, the
senselessness of his revenge seems tangible. The only thing he seems to
have accomplished is the waste of another life. The father wishes desper-
ately that he had simply turned John into the police.
Judgment. Before learning about the father’s feelings, it seemed that John
deserved his fate (or at least that he was more deserving than in the first
scenario). But the father’s regret seems to undermine this intuition. Now
my reaction resembles when John was executed by the State—the punish-
ment seems excessive and undeserved.
Scenario 4
The father recognizes that he acted in a moment of blind rage. Still, upon
reflection, he feels that justice was done. He recognizes that this act will
not bring his daughter back, and that nothing will alleviate the suffering
he feels in her absence. But at least he has paid his debt to her and did not
allow the person who killed her to get away with it. He feels a strange
sense of peace, although his grief is just as acute. The father calls 911
right away and confesses to the crime. He accepts responsibility for his
action, and waits for the police to come and arrest him.
Judgment: Now my initial intuitions that John deserved his fate are, if
anything, even stronger than in the second case. The father has performed
the act, owns up to it, and even feels a small degree of satisfaction. He has
risked and sacrificed a great deal to bring about the punishment. He accepts
responsibility and will now go to prison. Perhaps if we were in the father’s
place, we would not feel or act this way. But there is a significant sense in
which it is not up to us, because we did not suffer from the offense. Again, if
I can inhabit John’s perspective (now from beyond the grave), I would
accept that I had received what was coming to me.
It may seem that I am edging (or hurtling) towards a reductio of my own
position. Judgments of John’s deservingness are supposed to be sensitive to
the father’s feelings about his act of revenge after performing it? To how
much the father risked and sacrificed to make it happen? To his willingness
to accept responsibility and punishment? In the remainder of this chapter
I hope to minimize the incredulity that accompanies such questions and
argue that the answer to all of them is a simple “yes.”
proportionality must remain “range only,” issuing upper and lower limits
where punishments would obviously be either too severe or too light. Ordinal
proportionality is relative. It has two aspects. The first is parity: like crimes
must be treated alike. If two criminals are equally culpable then they should
receive the same punishment. Second, punishments must be proportionate
relative to one another. If one crime is twice as serious as another, the
punishment should be twice as serious as well. The leeway that cardinal
proportionality allows in deciding the anchoring points of the scale explains
why we cannot perceive a single right or fitting penalty for a particular
criminal. Once the anchoring points of the scale have been fixed, however,
the more restrictive requirements of ordinal proportionality begin to apply.
In practical terms, the idea would be roughly as follows. We do not know
precisely what the punishment should be for, say, car theft. There are a
range of punishments that might be proportionate for this crime and in
absolute terms, proportionality just requires that we stay within this range.
We do know, however, that car theft is a less serious crime than armed
robbery. So the proportionality principle requires that (a) two equally
culpable car thieves receive the same punishment, and (b) armed robbers
receive a more severe punishment than car thieves. Von Hirsch offers
university grading practices as an analogy. The standards for “A” papers
and “B” papers and so forth are real but indeterminate (cardinal propor-
tionality) and may depend on nonmerit based factors about the university.
But once those standards are set, fairness requires that we give papers of
equal merit the same grade (ordinal proportionality).
The initial intuitive resistance to the idea of partial desert is rooted in our
commitment to ordinal proportionality. But the depth of this commitment
is open to question. In fact, outside of the context of criminal justice, it’s
not clear that we are committed to ordinal proportionality at all. Imagine
that a woman decides to leave her philandering husband and he replies:
“I understand you’re angry, but fairness requires that you don’t leave me.
Bill’s wife stayed with him and he’s had several more affairs than I have.”
Would the wife be moved by this consideration? Should she be? Everyday
life is filled with cases like this—acts of infidelity, betrayals of trust,
insulting or offensive remarks, and many others. We do not imagine that
there is a correct response or punishment, one that is tied only to the agent’s
personal culpability. Nor do we cry foul when people who are equally
culpable do not receive the same amount of blame or punishment. We
leave it up to the relevant parties to determine the right response, within
certain boundaries.
What does survive outside the context of criminal justice is our commit-
ment to cardinal proportionality. We maintain that there is a range of
appropriate blame or punishment responses and that responses outside of
256 Tamler Sommers
this range would be undeserved. Whether the betrayed spouse asks for a trial
separation, files for divorce, gives the partner another chance is largely up to
her. All of these are proportionate responses. But imprisoning the spouse or
killing him or even cutting off all access to the children would be dispropor-
tionate. The husband (as well as third parties) might legitimately complain
that the treatment is undeserved. It is significant that von Hirsch employs the
practice of essay grading to illustrate the importance of ordinal proportion-
ality. Certainly, it is a desert-based practice, but when a student writes a bad
paper, there is no victim.9 Offenses or crimes, by contrast, have identifiable
victims who have suffered at the hands of the offender. The presence of
victims is a morally relevant factor that affects our understanding of
proportionality and desert. Exactly how is the topic of the next section.
9
Aside from the instructors who have to comment on them.
Partial Desert 257
7 . P H I L O S O PH I C A L B U S Y B O D I E S
10
See e.g. Barnett (1977), Strang and Braithwaite (2000), Van Ness (1993), and
Zedner (1994).
258 Tamler Sommers
According to Lucia Zedner, the system “has transformed the drama and
emotion of social interaction and strife into technical categories which can
be subjected to the ordering practices of the criminal process.” (Zedner
1994: 231) Proponents of restorative justice argue that the blend of
retributive (desert-based) and utilitarian principles of our current system
is unjustly one-sided in its focus on the criminal. The victim is just a faceless
vessel for wrongdoing—like a poor essay that justifies a low grade. This has
the effect of alienating the victims and diminishing their self-respect even
further.
The criminologist Nils Christie has famously accused the criminal justice
system of “stealing conflicts” from their rightful owners. Lawyers, he
claims, are particular good at this form of larceny:
Lawyers are . . . trained into agreement on what is relevant in a case. But that means a
trained incapacity in letting the parties decide what they think is relevant. If the
offender is well educated, ought he then to suffer more, or maybe less, for his sins?
Or if he is black, or if he is young, or if the other party is an insurance company, or if
his wife has just left him, or if his factory will break down if he has to go to jail, or if
his daughter will lose her fiancé, or if he was drunk, or if he was sad, or if he was
mad? There is no end to it. And maybe there ought to be none. (Christie 1977:.8)
This extraordinary passage should trouble more than just lawyers. For if we
replace “lawyers” with “philosophers” or “desert theorists” in Christie’s
remarks, we expose some of the dubious assumptions and aspirations in our
current approach to moral desert. Our ever-more refined accounts of blame
and punishment—accounts that are supposed to apply across the board, no
matter what the relevant parties might think—may have the effect of
stealing conflicts from particular individuals. This whole approach exhibits
a “trained incapacity” to let individuals decide which factors are relevant
and how much. Zedner’s accusation seems apt as well. By focusing entirely
on impartial conditions of criminal culpability, our theories transform the
drama and emotion of social interaction and strife into technical (often
metaphysical) categories which can be subjected to a systematic ordering
process of desert attribution.11
Let me conclude this section by describing a real criminal case that
occurred recently in Grand Junction, Colorado, one that resembles
the hypothetical example I introduced earlier. A woman was driving in
the early morning, drunk and high on methamphetamines. On the way, she
had an accident and hit a sanitation worker. The worker’s legs were
11
One might interpret Strawson (1962) as making a similar point about the moral
responsibility skeptic who believes that “blame is metaphysical.” “The metaphysics,”
Strawson writes, “is in the eye of the metaphysician.” (p. 24).
Partial Desert 259
shattered, causing him to endure ten surgeries. During her trial, the worker
testified and asked the judge to give the woman a lenient sentence. He
explained that he could relate to her predicament, that he had been in a
dark place once, and he hoped she could eventually get to a better place.
The prosecutors and judge took his desires into account, dismissed the
most serious charges, and the woman received the minimum sentence
allowable—still over five years in jail.
Here we have a clear violation of ordinal proportionality. Many people
who are equally culpable in Colorado have been given much higher
sentences and many will again. But did the judge and prosecutor violate a
“basic requirement of fairness”? Is this case clearly unjust? The victim of the
offense is satisfied, more than he would be if his wishes had not been
considered. The woman is still receiving a punishment within a reasonable
cardinal range. Is it our business as philosophers to complain about the
verdict, those of us who have not suffered in any way from this crime?
Doing so, in my view, would make us “philosophical busybodies” sticking
our collective nose where it doesn’t belong.
8 . C O N C LU S I O N
For all the insights it provides, there is a crucial difference between the
restorative justice critique and my own. Proponents of restorative justice
regard it as an alternative to retributivist or desert-based approaches to
criminal justice. In my view, we should incorporate facts about individual
victims into the way we understand desert for wrongdoing, criminal and
noncriminal. My account, then, is not an alternative but rather a revised
version of desert theory or retributivism. In order to make a judgment
about what John deserves in our original case, we have to know more about
what John and the parents want and believe. For partial desert judgments, it
matters whether the parents are vindictive or forgiving. And it matters what
John himself feels when he looks into their eyes.
Defenders of our current criminal justice system like to think that as an
enlightened society, we have transcended the revenge feelings and practices
of our barbarous past and replaced them with “justice,” which is rational
and not subject to emotional bias. But the retributivist project in the West
has struggled to develop a coherent notion of “just-deserts” that does not
appeal in any way to our natural disposition for vengeance. In my view, the
fears of allowing emotions into the equation are way overblown. No one is
advocating for a return to the days of endless tribal warfare. There is a
middle ground, one that allows individual victims to influence our desert
judgments under certain defined parameters, but not to determine them.
260 Tamler Sommers
12
In penal philosophy, this type of account is known as the “hybrid view” developed
by Paul Robinson (1987) among others.
13
Once again, this objection is inspired by comments on my Flickers of Freedom
post. A related objection, raised by an anonymous referee, is that I am conflating the
notions of what John deserves and those of what “serves him right.” In response, let me
first say that I’m not sure there is a substantive difference between the notions of desert
and those like “serves him right” and “had it coming to him”—although I recognize that
many or most philosophers will disagree with me on this point. Second, even if there is
an important difference between those notions, it’s not clear that the distinctions explain
our different intuitions regarding desert in the John cases.
14
Thanks to Tim Scanlon and Sarah Buss for convincing me on this point.
Partial Desert 261
REFERENCES
15
Thanks to Sarah Buss, Dave Shoemaker, Chandra Sripada, two anonymous refer-
ees, and the commentators at the Flickers of Freedom blog for valuable comments. This
project has benefited immensely from the discussion at the 2011 New Orleans Work-
shop on Agency and Responsibility organized by Dave Shoemaker.
262 Tamler Sommers
Von Hirsch, Andrew (1978). “Proportionality and Desert: Reply to Bedau.” Journal
and Philosophy 75.11: 622–4.
—— (1992). “Proportionality in the Philosophy of Punishment.” Crime and Justice
16: 55–98.
—— (1993). Censure and Sanctions. (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Wallace, R. Jay (1994). Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press).
Williams, Bernard Arthur Owen (1981). Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers, 1973–1980.
(Cambridge Cambridge University Press).
Zedner, Lucia (1994). “Reparation and Retribution.” Modern Law Review 57. 2:
228–50.
11
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility*
Heidi L. Maibom
between addicts on the basis of their so-called deep selves; one might be a
willing addict, the other unwilling. Wolf thinks Frankfurt’s view cannot
accommodate our intuitions about the insane because they have the will
they want to have, yet we hesitate to hold them (fully) morally responsible.
The trouble is that the insane are not able to know “the difference between
right and wrong” (382) and they cannot but possess “values that are
unavoidably mistaken” (383).
Wolf uses the example of the son of an evil dictator to illustrate her
point. JoJo’s father habitually sent people to prison, torture chamber, or
death on a whim. Having been under his father’s educational regimen, JoJo
grows up performing just the kinds of actions that his father did. He does so
willingly; just like a willing addict satisfies his addiction. He has the first-
order volitions that he wants to have and the freedom to act on them.
Contrary to what Frankfurt claimed, this is not all the freedom anyone
could want, Wolf argues. For it seems unavoidable that JoJo should have
the values—second-order volitions—that he does, and therefore it is not
right to blame him:
These are people, we imagine, who falsely believe that the ways in which they are
acting are morally acceptable, and so, we may assume, their behavior is expressive of
or at least in accordance with these agents’ deep selves. But their false beliefs in the
moral permissibility of their actions and the false values from which these beliefs
derived may have been inevitable, given the social circumstances in which they
developed. If we think that the agents could not help but be mistaken about their
values we do not blame them for the actions those values inspired. (382)
Wolf ’s point is not that we must be the authors of our second-order
volitions. The inevitability of which she speaks does not refer to the origin
of such values, but to their continued existence as values that characterize an
agent’s deep self. What is central to sanity is the ability to transform one’s
values, and thereby one’s deeper self. Seriously wrongheaded values trap a
subject, in a manner of speaking, by making her incapable of evaluating
them realistically. Since the insane are stuck with their second-order voli-
tions, but we are not, they are not responsible whereas we are. That JoJo
espouses the values that he does shows that he is insane:
Sanity, remember, involves the ability to know the difference between right and
wrong, and a person who, even on reflection, cannot see that having someone tortured
because he failed to salute you is wrong plainly lacks the requisite ability. (382)
This suggests that in order to possess the abilities required for sanity and
responsibility mentioned above (a and b), we must first have:
(c) the ability cognitively and normatively to recognize and appreciate the
world for what it is. (383)
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 265
2 . I N SA N I T Y I N L AW
The widely used McNaughtan Rule stipulates that in order to be insane the
defendant must suffer from a mental illness which is causally implicated in
the criminal action that the defendant is on trial for: (Moran 1981: 169)2
To establish a defence on the ground of insanity it must be clearly proved that, at the
time of committing the act, the party accused was labouring under such a defect of
reason from disease of the mind, as not to know the nature and quality of the act he
was doing, or if he did know it, that he did not know that what he was doing was
wrong.
If the accused was conscious that the act was one which he ought not to do, and if
that act was at the same time contrary to the law of the land, he is punishable.
Contrary to what is sometimes thought, mental illness is not synonymous
with insanity. A mental illness does not simply deprive a person of responsi-
bility for her actions, but it can sometimes overwhelm her, and when it
does, she cannot be held responsible for the actions performed under its
influence. The law acknowledges that mental illness can affect everyone
alike, and though it may affect a person profoundly, it rarely blots out her
preexisting character or moral sensibilities. As such, a crime committed by a
person suffering from a mental illness may not, in any interesting sense, be
the result of that person’s illness, but of their deficient moral character.
A person can be both bad and mad.
Most of those judged to be not guilty by reason of insanity3 suffer from
paranoia.4 The majority of successful insanity pleas in Canada (Rice and
2
If not directly used, the Rule often serves as the basis of acts concerning the
responsibility of persons judged to be insane. In Canada, the Criminal Code section 16
specifies that “(1) No person is criminally responsible for an act committed or an
omission made while suffering from a mental disorder that rendered the person incap-
able of appreciating the nature and quality of the act or omission or of knowing that it
was wrong.” In Britain, the corresponding act concerns diminished responsibility.
According to section 52 of the Coroners and Justice Act 2009 (the Act), “a person
who kills or is a party to the killing of another is not to be convicted of murder if they
were suffering from an abnormality of mental functioning which: (a) arose from a
recognised medical condition, (b) substantially impaired their ability to do one or
more of the following: understand the nature of their contact, form a rational judgement,
or exercise self control, and (c) provides an explanation for [their] acts and omissions in
doing or being a party to the killing. An abnormality of mental functioning provides an
explanation for the conduct if it causes, or is a significant contributory factor in causing,
the defendant to carry out that conduct.”
3
In Canada, “not criminally responsible on account of mental disorder” has replaced
“not guilty by reason of insanity” (Criminal Code section 672.34).
4
The DSM-IV lists three different types: paranoid personality disorder, paranoid
subtype of schizophrenia, and the persecutory type of delusional disorder.
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 267
Harris 1990), New York (Steadman et al. 1983), Colorado (Jeffrey et al.
1988), and Oregon (Rogers et al. 1984) involve defendants who have been
diagnosed with psychosis, mostly commonly schizophrenia (often 80
percent or higher). Psychosis is characterized by delusions, hallucinations,
and disorganized thought and speech. Consequently, people deemed insane
are usually disturbed individuals who have profound problems with reality
generally, not just moral reality if such a thing exists. For instance, Daniel
McNaughtan, who gave the name to the famous insanity rule, killed
Edward Drummond because he mistook him for the British Prime
Minister Robert Peel, whose secretary he was. He believed himself to be
persecuted by Peel and his political party to such an extent that his life was
becoming unbearable. He also thought they were planning his demise.
Andrea Yates was suffering from severe postpartum psychosis and believed
that, were her children to live, they would eventually face eternal
damnation. To kill them was therefore an act of mercy in her mind. So
she drowned her five children in a bathtub, one after the other. James
Hadfield thought he was something of a new Messiah whose lawful
execution or death would bring about the second coming of Christ,
thereby saving humanity from much unnecessary suffering. He shot at
King George III—missing by a wide margin—because he knew that
attempted regicide was punishable by death.5 Henry Maudsley (1898)
tells the story of a father who believed that he was fighting a fierce snake
only to find that he had killed his infant son.
In typical successful insanity pleas it is the subjects’ delusions that cause
the problem, not their moral compass. Yates and Hadfield clearly thought
they were acting for the greater good, and at the expense of their own well-
being. Had Yates and Hadfield been right about their mistaken beliefs,
their actions would not have been culpable. The so-called As-if rule stipu-
lates that someone who acts on beliefs about the world that are due to
delusions or hallucinations has an excuse on the condition that had their
beliefs been true, their action would have been morally acceptable (Reznik
1997). The complimentary If-only rule specifies that in the absence of
mental disorder, the subject would not have performed the action in
question. And, in fact, Yates or Hadfield would probably not have done
what they did had they not been in the grip of strong delusional beliefs. The
As-if and the Only-if rules typically characterize successful insanity pleas. In
other words, it is not usually the case that a person judged to be not guilty
by reason of insanity is someone whose values are foreign to us or are such
that we cannot identify with them, in some sense.
5
He could not kill himself as he believed suicide was not permitted by God.
268 Heidi L. Maibom
Some, like Lawrie Reznik (1997), think that the notion of a good
character is central to insanity pleas. For the defendant to have an excuse,
in cases of insanity, he must be shown to have acted out of character, in some
sense. His actions may be the result of his mental illness, for instance.
Character, for Reznik, is similar to the deeper self that Frankfurt refers to.6
We are responsible for actions performed “in character” even if we are not
responsible for our character or, to be more precise, our moral character.7
If, however, “a person changes from a good character to an evil one,
commits an offense, then changes back again, the good character has an
excuse” (227). Mental illness and brain injury can result in such character
change. If the disorder is irreversible—a progressive brain disease, for
instance—the individual cannot be held responsible, and if the disorder is
reversible, we cannot blame the good character should we succeed in
restoring it. Lack of prior convictions, due regard for the well-being of
others, etc., are all signs of a good character.
The Yates case helps illustrate the importance of character. Yates was
diagnosed with postpartum psychosis. As already mentioned, psychotic
subjects appear to inhabit, at least part of the time, a different reality
from the rest of us, and usually experience great difficulties functioning
normally. Parents suffering from postpartum depression or psychosis often
fantasize about killing their infants. Prior to the murders, Yates had been
catatonic and unable to breastfeed her youngest child properly. She had a
history of postpartum depression and attempted suicides, but no criminal
record. Yates’s husband testified to her declining condition and insisted
that she had undergone a personality change. She had expressed doubts
about her ability to be a good mother, but ultimately claimed to have
drowned her children to save them from an eternity of suffering in Hell.
Her history of relatively blameless behavior suggests that an otherwise
morally upstanding citizen—to put it somewhat primly—had been over-
come by mental illness.
People judged not guilty by reason of insanity are not always so benevo-
lent, of course. Where Yates and Hadfield thought of themselves as min-
imizing harm by their actions, subjects of command hallucinations believe
they are simply obeying orders. Following orders, however, is usually not
6
Reznik explicitly rejects Frankfurt’s notion of personhood. This, however, seems
based on a misunderstanding of Frankfurt’s philosophical position.
7
A person’s moral character consists in “the set of dispositions that explain his ethical
beliefs, his moral sentiments, and ethical conduct.” (Reznik, 223) Talking about moral
character is required at least for legal purposes. If someone has a temporary change in
character, but it does not affect their moral outlook or their moral dispositions, it cannot
excuse any crime that they may commit in their altered state.
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 269
an excusing condition in civilian life when the action is illegal. Yet, people
who kill because they hallucinate God commanding them to do so are
sometimes deemed insane even though their actions would not have been
legally or morally acceptable had their beliefs been true (at least in a secular
society). Kim John, together with Francis Philip, bludgeoned a Catholic
nun to death and set a priest on fire at the Cathedral of the Immaculate
Conception in St Lucia. He was subsequently diagnosed with delusional
disorder, paranoid type.
Kim John claims to have been under a divine injunction to target the
Catholic Church, which he also believed was persecuting him. He blamed
the Church for his own troubles and for “child abuse, molesting, stealing
the tithes and offerings, buying off the land, poisoning the water and food,
robbing and taking funds” (Larbey 2007). Unlike McNaughten, Kim did
not think that his life was in danger. He did not, therefore, have the excuse
that had his beliefs been true, his act would have been reasonable.
Nevertheless, his delusions were judged to be of such a nature as to make
him unfit for punishment (Francis Philip & Kim John v. The Queen). He
claims to have had visions from an early age of “[s]elling of human beings,
children like cargo, women raped and murdered, tortured, castrations. The
falling of the wicked in flames, seeing them burn up, skeletons, ashes,
smoke, fire, weeping and wailing” (Larbey 2007). He also thought he
could do magic. The pervasiveness of Kim’s delusions made the Appellate
Court think it useless to try to assess his moral character, which,
presumably, they thought obliterated by, or buried under, his mental
illness.
It is notable that not all command hallucinations excuse criminal behav-
ior. Ronald Lafferty claimed to have had a divine revelation that he was to
“remove” certain individuals that stood in God’s way. Conveniently, they
were all people he blamed for encouraging his wife to leave him with their
children. He talked his brother Dan into killing their other brother’s wife
Brenda and their 15-month-old daughter. Ron received the death sentence
in 1985. In the much publicized 1996 retrial, his lawyer entered an insanity
plea, arguing that Ron’s religious ideas and “revelations” were signs of a
delusional mind. The prosecution countered that irrational and strange
ideas—including the idea that one receives revelations from God—are a
stable of religion. But we cannot simply assume that all religious people are
insane. That would render much of the population and the political
establishment in large parts of the world insane.8 Instead, witness for the
8
The DSM-IV specifies that “culturally sanctioned” responses (p. xxxi) or political,
religious, or sexual deviant behavior are not signs of mental illness unless they are
symptoms of a dysfunction of the individual associated with present distress, disability,
270 Heidi L. Maibom
makes it rather likely that the disorder played an important role in Kim’s
beliefs about the Church’s responsibility in his misfortunes. Compare such
delusions with Ron Lafferty again. Ron blamed a group of people for his
wife leaving him and he was, in part, right. Clearly he failed to take into
account his own role in the split, but these individuals did encourage her to
leave and take the kids. In short, Ron had the quite reasonable belief that a
number of individuals encouraged his wife to abandon him. His ensuing
belief that they should be killed was therefore not the result of delusions
that these individuals were (partly) responsible for his wife’s departure.
Quite likely, it was the result of his desire for revenge.
3. LESSONS OF INSANITY
Chadwick 1997). Having command hallucinations to harm someone are most likely not
sufficient to cause people to comply in the absence of other deluded beliefs (McNiel,
Eisner, and Binder 2000). Kim John, however, seemed to have no shortage of delusions.
10
According to David Faraci and David Shoemaker (2010), most ordinary subjects
also judge JoJo to be blameworthy for his actions.
272 Heidi L. Maibom
Obviously. But this cannot be the right reading of the As-if rule since
any conviction could pass the rule. Rather, it is its acceptability within
our moral and legal system that is at issue, and within those torturing or
killing people on a whim is not permissible. This means that the posses-
sion of divergent moral or legal values is not typically an excusing condi-
tion even if such values are the result of mental disorder. As mentioned
above, command hallucinations are an exception. Here the defendant’s
actions may not have been justified had their beliefs been true. In these
cases, it is usually the pervasiveness of delusions that excuses, as in the case
of Kim John. As in other cases of insanity, it is not the subject’s moral
values that are the primary issue. Indeed, if the Church were responsible
for the actions John thought it was, it would be culpable. This fact
shows just how much overlap there is between John’s moral values and
ours. The main problem with JoJo, however, is his values.
This brings us to the If-only rule, which JoJo also does not satisfy. He
does not suffer from any currently recognized mental illness. Someone
might argue that had JoJo been raised otherwise, he would not have
performed the actions that he did, wherefore we cannot hold him respon-
sible. It is instructive to note that this is not Wolf ’s argument. How people
come to have the values they do is irrelevant. What matters are the values
with which they end up. If we are to believe Wolf, most values that diverge
from ours in significant respects render the agents who possess them unable
to evaluate themselves “sensibly and accurately” and change themselves
accordingly.
JoJo is, of course, just one example. The fact that JoJo is not unable,
rather than merely unwilling, to change his values does not show that there
are not people who are incapable of comprehending that certain types of
actions are morally or legally impermissible, such as torture, murder, rape,
or persecution of others. What would it take, one wonders, to be incapable
of such a thing? Two interpretations present themselves. Either the agent’s
ability to evaluate and change values is directly affected, or it is intact, but
her environment does not yield opportunities for such evaluation and for
changing her values to be more aligned with values that we now regard to be
right. In the latter case, in particular, we need to distinguish those who have
sufficient access to values and information for us to say that they hold on to
their values from those whose environment and values are such that we
cannot expect them to be able to reach values similar to those we now
adopt. But first we must explore what knowing that what one is doing is
wrong amounts to.
The law typically does not care whether you are ignorant of the law or
whether you agree with it. Nevertheless, some readings of the McNaughtan
Rule demand that the defendant know that what he was doing was
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 273
morally wrong. In other words, the person must understand that the
action committed was not merely illegal (malum prohibitum), but
also bad in itself (malum in se). It is not just the ability to appreciate
that, say, killing in general is malum in se that can be required for legal
responsibility, for most people judged not guilty by reason of insanity
understand that. What must be meant is that, at the time of the crime, the
defendant was able to understand that committing this action was morally
impermissible.
Being able to understand that an action is morally wrong cannot
translate to truly believing, at the time, that what you are doing is wrong.
For, according to Roy Baumeister, “[m]ost people who perpetrate evil do
not see what they are doing as being evil.” (1997: 1).11 Our assessment of a
criminal act is usually different from that of the perpetrator. Perpetrators tend
to trivialize their transgressions and think that, given the circumstances, they
could not have helped doing what they did. By contrast, most victims magnify
the wrongness of the event and the wickedness of perpetrator’s intentions
(Baumeister 1997). In the laboratory, too, people minimize their own wrong
doings while they magnify wrongs perpetrated against them (Baumeister,
Stillwell, and Wotman 1990). Not surprisingly, therefore, there is a good
correlation between a person’s access to justification for violence and the
degree to which they engage in it (Berkowitz and Powers 1979; Calvete
2008, Schwartz, O’Leary, and Kendziora 1997, Zelli et al. 1999).
Crimes like violent assault or homicide are often the result of an escalated
process of reciprocal provocation (Berkowitz 1978, Luckenbill 1977,
Berkowitz 1978). It is not uncommon for the victim to throw the first
punch in such confrontations (Wolfgang 1958). Consequently, the person
who ends up killing another often sees himself as a victim. He was, after all
provoked, threatened, or attacked, and his action was justified under the
circumstances (Katz 1988). In such escalations, one person sees his act of
retaliation as equitable whereas the other usually regards it as an unjustified
escalation. As a result, both end up feeling victimized (Stillwell, Baumeister,
and Del Priore 2008). Clearly, therefore, many convicted criminals did not
see their actions as impermissible at the time.
The above makes it clear that we cannot simply demand that the subject
understands that there is some general moral injunction against the action
at hand. The average killer, like the average insane person, does not disagree
with the injunction against killing. Typically, he thinks that this instance of
11
Philosophers will be familiar with the idea from The Meno where Socrates argues
that nobody who “recognizes evils for what they are” desires them (77C).
274 Heidi L. Maibom
killing is not wrong or at least that it is not that wrong. The circumstances
were sufficiently mitigating—he insulted me, she was cheating on me, he
attacked me first, she is a blot on my honor—that I should not be held
responsible for murder (but perhaps for some lesser crime). Though it is
quite possible that the criminal is right in some of these cases, in most cases
the court judges that he should have realized that the situation did not call
for that degree of violence. The standard here is usually that of a “reason-
able man.” So perhaps this is a better way of thinking about the require-
ment that one understands that one’s action is malum in se: if there is an
inferential link from beliefs and values that the person has at the time of
the crime to the recognition that the action is morally impermissible, then
the person is responsible and culpable should they nevertheless perform the
action (cf. Williams 1981).
The condition is too weak, however. A person might defend herself by
pointing out that she did not embrace the relevant values at the time. If she
does not believe killing, or this form of killing, to be wrong there is no
inferential route to her appreciating that this killing was wrong. But clearly
we would still hold her responsible. Being on the fence about, or disagree-
ing with, a moral prohibition does not seem to excuse. Consider honor
killing in the West.
People who commit honor killings believe that killing to preserve or
reinstate honor is morally permissible by contrast to other forms of
killing, which they agree are impermissible. This is causing something
of a stir in North America. In Canada, Mohammad Shafia, his second
wife, and their son were recently found guilty of killing Shafia’s first wife
and the couple’s three daughters. Apparently, the three daughters
objected to wearing the hijab, wanted to spend time with their friends
after school, have boyfriends, and so on. The story is very similar to
another recent honor killing in Toronto where Aqsa Parvez was murdered
by her father, Muhammad, and her brother, Waqas, for bringing “insult”
to the family for similar reasons (CBC News, June 15, 2010). The two
Waqas’s received life sentences.
Both Mohammad Shafia and Muhammad Pavez and their families are
recent immigrants from, respectively, Afghanistan and Pakistan, where
values differ significantly from those of the West. In both countries
honor killings are disturbingly common, and though prohibited by law,
are rarely punished. Pakistan has a long tradition of karo-kari, the practice
of killing women for their perceived immoral behavior, e.g. adultery,
having been raped, refusing an arranged marriage, or wanting a divorce.
Often, girls and women are killed on mere suspicion of some sort of
affiliation with a male outside the family. Honor killers doubtlessly regard
their actions as justified. The Shafias and Pavezs evidently acted in
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 275
accordance with their native morality.12 They do not accept that killing to
save honor is wrong.
In the case of honor killings, it is fairly clear that failure to accept or
adopt a moral or legal norm does not deprive someone of responsibility.
Honor killings are cases of moral intransigence, not of moral inability.
They are no different from typical homicides. Neither killer believes they
are truly culpable. However, this lack of recognition is not usually thought
to be mitigating. By contrast, it is often thought to make the offender more
culpable. For their action is not the result of a mistake or an accident, it is
the result of adopting values that we find despicable. It is their beliefs about
the moral value of Jews, in particular, that make Nazis so despised. It is the
belief that women are chattel and have no value other than to serve men and
bear male children that makes many of the practices in the Middle East so
horrific. The inferential link we require for responsibility, therefore, must
be to the current values of the person in question or to values that we judge
that she ought to have had under the circumstances.
If we assume that culture does not inhibit people’s ability to evaluate or
change their values—I shall argue for this shortly—then what is at issue
with honor killers is whether they hold on to their values or whether they do
not have access to relevant values and information that would enable them
to change them in the right way. Wolf suggests that if one is brought up in a
particular moral milieu, which allows, perhaps encourages, certain wrongs,
one is not really in a position to accurately evaluate or change those values.
It remains obscure, however, why we have the capacity to change our
wrongheaded values. My hunch is that Wolf thinks that there is a pretty
straightforward inferential route from our current moral values to future,
improved, ones. For instance, our indifference to the death and suffering of
nonhuman animals, particularly the ones that we eat, is quite plausibly
culpable. We have the capacity to arrive at valuing the life and well-being of
nonhuman animals because of values and beliefs that we either possess or
that are readily available in our environment. We believe that if an action or
policy creates unnecessary or avoidable suffering, then we have a prima facie
reason not to perform or institute it. We also know—or if we do not
actually know, we could easily come to know—that factory farming creates
a great amount of suffering, and that we do not need to consume as much
meat as we do for proper nutrition. From those beliefs, there is a relatively
straightforward inferential route to the belief that factory farming is wrong
and that we ought to oppose policies that permit it. As we shall see, this line
12
This is not to say that many people living in those countries do not regard honor
killings with horror, and would never engage in, nor condone such acts.
276 Heidi L. Maibom
of reasoning shows not only that we are responsible, but also that there
usually is little question of someone’s culture inhibiting her responsibility.
If we are responsible for our wrongdoings, so are the slaveholders of Ancient
Greece and the male chauvinists of our father’s generation. If they are not,
neither are we.
Michele Moody-Adams (1994) has argued that people in cultures that
permit, or encourage, practices that we condemn, such as slavery, are
typically exercising so-called affected ignorance. That is, they chose not to
question, seek information or otherwise know about these practices of
wrongdoing.13 I suspect that there is another form of affected ignorance
that derives from the degree of difficulty involved in endorsing values that
significantly diverge from the culture at large, not to mention advocating a
societal change of standards. It requires some imagination to envisage a
different moral order. It is, perhaps, an affected lack of imagination. Wolf
maintains that the ancient Greeks cannot be held responsible for their
attitudes towards slavery. The question, however, is whether there is a not
too onerous inferential route from beliefs and values that the ancients
possessed that leads to the recognition that slavery is morally wrong.
At the time of its practice, slavery was widely regarded as a terrible fate.
When Andromache bewails the death of Hector in The Illiad, she decries
the fate of the citizens of Troy: “all who will soon be carried off in the
hollow ships and I with them—And you, my child, will follow me to labor,
somewhere, at harsh, degrading, work, slaving under some heartless
master’s eye” (Book 24, line 860 ff.).14 In Xenophon’s Symposium,
Antisthenes suggests that enslaving others is a crime: “Want prompts a
thousand crimes, you must admit. Why do men steal? why break
burglariously into houses? why hale men and women captive and make
slaves of them? Is it not from want?” (Xenophon 2008a: }27) In Hellenica,
Xenophon not only talks about the great lengths that people will go to, to
avoid being “reduced to” slavery, but also recounts of the Spartan general
Callicratidas who refused to enslave the Methymnaeans because they were
fellow Hellenes (Xenophon 2008b). In the Politics, Aristotle refers to
people who “affirm that the rule of a master over slaves is contrary to
nature, and that the distinction between slave and freeman exists by law
13
Another feature of affected ignorance is the rephrasing of wrongs in relatively
inoffensive sounding language. For instance, the message on the Rwandan radio encour-
aging the Hutus to kill the Tutsis was “cut down the tall trees” (Dallaire 2004).
14
The sentiment appears to have been typical in all times where slavery was a
predictable result of conquest. Thus, in Beowulf “[a] Geat woman too sang out in
grief; with hair bound up, she unburdened herself of her worst fears, a wild litany of
nightmare and lament: her nation invaded, enemies on the rampage, bodies in piles,
slavery and abasement.” (line 3150 ff.)
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 277
only, and not by nature; and being an interference with nature is therefore
unjust.” (Politics, Book I, Part III) In Rhetorica ad Alexandrum,15 the Sophist
Alcidamas says “The deity gave liberty to all men and nature created no one a
slave” in reference to the Thebans freeing the Messenians, who had been
taken slaves by the Spartans (Garlan 1988: 125).
The passages above suggest that it was not unthinkable to the Ancient
Greeks that slavery was wrong. Clearly some people thought slavery was
unjust. Furthermore, the elements for a realization of the moral wrong-
ness of slavery were there. Every free person wanted to remain free and
regarded slavery as degrading and awful (1988). They recognized that
slaves were fellow human beings, that they were capable of suffering,
that suffering was morally relevant, that they themselves might be in
danger of enslavement by others, and so on. All the talk of the baseness
and stupidity of slaves that we also find in the extant literature seems
designed to protect an affected ignorance of the wrongness of the insti-
tution. After all, as long as you are not a slave but others are your slaves, it is
to your advantage to embrace a norm that permits slavery. If we were to
make a comparison to current culture, we might point out that we, too,
are in the possession of everything we need to know to recognize that
factory farming, for instance, is an immoral practice. Far from being
incapable of recognizing that this is so, we are choosing to ignore it
because it is difficult to imagine not eating meat or eating meat much
more rarely, to imagine a societal change, to eat differently from every-
body else, and so on, not to mention the economic difficulties that would
be involved. Despite these difficulties, however, we are hardly unable to
recognize the wrongness of the practice.
There are other features of cultural value systems that speak against them
having the power to deprive agents of responsibility. It is no secret that to
talk of a value system of a particular culture is something of an idealization.
Though there may be agreement about the most serious forms of transgres-
sions, a society is not characterized by complete agreement about moral
norms. Furthermore, such values are subject to change. And, as a matter of
historical fact, values do change. Such change may be a relatively fluid affair,
or be more cataclysmic. Now, people instantiate or embody norms (Moody-
Adams 1994). For change in values to be possible, people must be able to
change their norms: evaluate them, adopt them, defend them, relinquish
them, overthrow them, and so on. The point is obvious on reflection. If
it were true that people brought up in societies where slavery was
15
Written around the same time as Rhetoric, it was traditionally attributed to
Aristotle, but might have been written by Anaximander.
278 Heidi L. Maibom
16
This is why I think psychopaths are not insane (Maibom 2008).
17
One might argue that people from different cultures possess a whole range of false
beliefs, which play a distorting role similar to that of delusions or hallucinations, and that
therefore the analogy between insanity and culturally induced values holds. Not so. First,
people who have looked for such differences in beliefs that would be relevant to the
morally divergent views have had difficulties finding them (Brink 1989; Doris and
Plakias 2008). Second, by contrast to ordinary beliefs, subjects tend to be deeply
convinced by the truth of their delusions although they are often bizarre. A delusion is
not justified by the available evidence—it is isolated from other relevant beliefs—and is
often held despite overwhelming reasons not to believe it. And hallucinations involve as-
if perceptions, which is not characteristic of false beliefs generally. Third, insofar as we
are all subject to culturally induced beliefs, that are similar to delusions, either we are as
little responsible for holding values derived from them as are people from different times
or cultures, or we are all responsible.
18
Or rather, we may excuse her for small failures that seem to flow from her
anhedonic state, but should she kill someone we will be skeptical that “the depression
made her do it.”
280 Heidi L. Maibom
4 . C O N C LU S I O N
REFERENCES
Jeffrey, R., Pasewark, R., and Bieber, S. (1988). “Insanity pleas: predicting Not
Guilty by Reason of Insanity adjudications.” Bulletin of the American Academy of
Psychiatry and Law 16, 35–9.
Katz, J. (1988). Seductions of Crime: Moral and Sensual Attractions in Doing Evil.
(New York: Basic Books).
Krakauer, J. (2003). Under the Banner of Heaven: A Story of Violent Faith.
(New York: Anchor Books).
Larbey, C. (2007). “The secret lives of Kim John and Francis Philip. What do we
really know about the Cathedral killers?” St. Lucia Star, May 18, 2007.
Luckenbill, D. (1977). “Criminal homicide as a situated transaction.” Social
Problems 25, 176–86.
McNiel, D., Eisner, J., and Binder, R. (2000). “The relationship between command
hallucinations and violence.” Psychiatric Services 51, 1288–92.
Maibom, H. (2008). “The mad, the bad, and the psychopath.” Neuroethics 1, 167–84.
Maudsley, H. (1898). Responsibility in Mental Disease. (New York: D. Appleton and
Company).
Moody-Adams, M. (1994). “Culture, responsibility, and affected ignorance.” Ethics
104, 291–309.
Moran, R. (1981). Knowing Right From Wrong. (New York: The Free Press).
MY Lee, T., Chong, S., Chan, Y., Sathyadevan, G. (2004). “Command hallucin-
ations among Asian patients with schizophrenia.” Canadian Journal of Psychiatry
49, 838–42.
Reznik, L. (1997). Evil or Ill: Defending the Insanity Defence. (New York: Routledge).
Rice, M. and Harris, G. (1990). “The predictors of insanity acquittal.” International
Journal of Law and Psychiatry 13, 217–24.
Rogers, J., Bloom, J., and Manson, S. (1984). “Insanity defences: contested or
conceded?” American Journal of Psychiatry 141, 885–8.
Schwartz, M., O’Leary, S., and Kendziora, K. (1997). “Dating aggression among
high school students.” Violence and Victims, 295–305.
Steadman, H., Keitner, L., Braff, J., and Arranites, T. (1983). “Factors associated
with a successful insanity plea.” American Journal of Psychiatry 140, 401–405.
Stillwell, A., Baumeister, R., and Del Priore, R. (2008). “We’re all victims here:
Towards a psychology of revenge.” Basic and Applied Social Psychology 30, 253–63.
Taylor, C. (1976). “Responsibility for self.” In A. E. Rorty (ed.) The Identities of
Persons. (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press), 281–99.
Watson, G. (1975). Free agency. Journal of Philosophy, LXII, 205–20.
Williams, B. (1981). “Internal and external reasons.” In his Moral Luck. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press), 101–13.
Wolf, S. (2003). “Sanity and the metaphysics of responsibility.” In G. Watson (ed.),
Free Will, 2nd edn. (New York: Oxford University Press), 372–87.
Wolfgang, M. (1958). Patterns in Criminal Homicide. (Philadelphia, PA: University
of Pennsylvania Press).
Xenophon. (2008a). Symposium. Trans. H. G. Dakyns. Project Guttenberg
(accessed January 14, 2012).
Values, Sanity, and Responsibility 283
1
This essay is fully collaborative. The authors are listed in alphabetical order. The
ideas for this essay grew out of a graduate seminar that we taught together on the topic of
partial responsibility in 2008 and were refined in a seminar on responsibility that DB
taught in 2011. Versions of this material were presented at the University of Illinois, the
University of Calgary, the Murphy Institute at Tulane University, Cornell University,
the University of Western Ontario, and the New Orleans Workshop on Agency and
Responsibility. We would like to thank audiences on those occasions for helpful
feedback. We owe special thanks to input from Craig Agule, Sarah Aikin, Amy Berg,
Mitch Berman, Michael McKenna, Per Milam, Richard Miller, Michael Moore,
Stephen Morse, Derk Pereboom, Erick Ramirez, Sam Rickless, Tim Scanlon, David
Shoemaker, Jada Twedt Strabbing, Sarah Stroud, Matt Talbert, Michael Tiboris, and
Gary Watson.
2
The philosophical work in the reasons-responsive wing of the compatibilist trad-
ition on which we draw includes Fischer and Ravizza 1998, Wallace 1994, Wolf 1990,
and Nelkin 2011. The criminal jurisprudence work on which we draw includes Hart
1957 and 1961, Moore 1997, and Morse 1994, 2002, and 2003.
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 285
on moral responsibility, some familiar and some novel, can fill this need.
However, we think that moral philosophers tend to focus on the capacities
involved in responsibility and so tend to ignore the situational element in
responsibility recognized in the criminal law literature. Our conception of
responsibility brings together the dimensions of normative competence
and situational control, and we factor normative competence into
cognitive and volitional capacities, which we treat as equally important
to normative competence and, ultimately, responsibility. Moreover,
we argue that normative competence and situational control can and
should be understood as expressing a common concern that blame and
punishment presuppose that the agent had a fair opportunity to avoid
wrongdoing. Thus, we treat the value that criminal law theorists associate
with the situational element of responsibility as the umbrella concept for
our conception of responsibility, one that explains the distinctive
architecture of responsibility.
This essay aims to motivate and articulate this sort of fair opportunity
conception of the architecture of responsibility. It is part of a larger project
that develops this conception and applies it to issues of partial responsi-
bility, involving insanity and psychopathy, immaturity, addiction, provo-
cation, and duress. The details and applications of the fair opportunity
conception of responsibility are interesting and important, and we hope to
address them more fully elsewhere. But the framework itself is important
and requires articulation.
1 . R E S P O N S I B I L I T Y , BL A M E , A N D T H E
REACTIVE ATTITUDES
way. This kind of moral judgment does not seem to apply to a very young
child. The idea that assumptions about responsibility are embedded in the
reactive attitudes makes most sense if we focus on this narrower class of
reactive attitudes that are moralized (cf. Wallace 1994: ch. 2).
In particular, we want to focus on the attitudes and practices of praise
and blame, especially as they reflect assumptions about responsibility. Some
negative reactive attitudes, such as regret, don’t seem to implicate responsi-
bility at all. Bernard Williams describes the case of a truck driver who,
through no fault of his own, hits and kills a child who has darted into the
street (1976: 28). As Williams claims, it is appropriate for the driver to feel
a kind of agent-regret at being the instrument of the child’s death, which is
distinct both from the regret or horror that bystanders might feel and from
guilt for having been responsible for wrongdoing.
Normally, blame only makes sense if the agent is responsible for some
kind of wrong. Some philosophers distinguish between two kinds of blame
and responsibility. For instance, Gary Watson distinguishes between
responsibility as attributability and as accountability (1996). An agent is
responsible in the attributive sense, roughly speaking, when her actions
reflect the quality of her will in the right way. Some kinds of blame can be a
fitting response to the quality of the agent’s will. For instance, A might have
hard feelings toward B if B injures A through malice, recklessness, or
negligence. Here, our reactive attitudes track the insufficient regard that
B shows A’s interests and rights. But attributability does not guarantee
accountability. Consider a situation in which we find out that though B’s
actions exhibit malice, in no relevant sense did B have an opportunity to do
otherwise, perhaps because he suffers from a serious mental illness and is
not a competent decision-maker as a result. In these cases, we are likely to
think that B was not at fault or culpable and so not accountable for the harm
he did. Although hard feelings may remain and be perfectly appropriate in
such cases, reactive attitudes involving resentment and indignation cease to
be appropriate and tend to dissipate. Attributability is necessary but not
sufficient for accountability. In this essay, we are especially interested in
responsibility as accountability and its connection with reactive practices and
attitudes involving blame, and we rely on an intuitive understanding of the
reactive attitudes that seem to be especially responsive to accountability.3 It is
this sense of blame and responsibility that we take to be most relevant to the
sort of responsibility required for punishment and to capture what is
common to both moral and legal responsibility.
3
Here, we are in agreement with Watson (1996: 276, 2011). By contrast,
T. M. Scanlon develops a conception of blame that seems to presuppose only
attributability, not accountability (2008: ch. 4, esp. 202).
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 287
4
Watson defends this response-dependent interpretation of Strawson’s thesis, at least
on interpretive grounds (1987: esp. 222). Wallace defends this interpretation of Strawson’s
thesis in its own right (2004: 19), though we think other elements in Wallace’s account fit
better with an alternative realist reading.
288 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
5
Because we think that reactive attitudes involving praise and blame presuppose that
the targets of these attitudes are responsible, we accept the need to provide a response-
independent conception of responsibility and to answer skeptical doubts about responsi-
bility. Consequently, we see response-dependent conceptions of responsibility as offering
skeptical solutions to skeptical worries (cf. Kripke 1982: 66–7). We view skeptical
solutions to skeptical problems as, at best, a kind of fallback solution to be entertained
only after straight solutions have clearly failed. For a fuller exploration of the
compatibilist aspects of this conception of responsibility, see Nelkin 2011. We believe
that at least some of what we say here can be accepted by incompatibilists who accept
further conditions on responsibility, beyond that of indeterminism.
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 289
6
Cf. Bedau and Kelly 2010. We aim for a normatively neutral and ecumenical
definition of punishment and one that identifies punishment as involving deprivations
of certain sorts, but not essentially involving the imposition of pain or suffering.
290 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
7
Cf. Duff 2008. The view that we have called “negative retributivism” is sometimes
called a “mixed theory” of punishment, because it requires more than one type of
justificatory reason, typically, both retributivist and consequentialist. It is also worth
noting that our definition of retributivism does not commit retributivists to endorsing
the thesis that punishment is intrinsically good, as some retributivists claim.
8
Precisely for this reason, a skeptic about moral responsibility will deny that any
retributivist view of punishment can be correct. For a skeptical view and its relation to
punishment, see Pereboom 2012.
9
Moore describes excuse as the “royal road” to responsibility (1997: 548). Whereas
the realist regards our practices of excuse as potential evidence of a response-independent
conception of responsibility, a response-dependent conception will understand our
practices of excuse as constitutive of responsibility.
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 291
2 . N O R M A T I VE CO M P E T E N C E
10
In framing our approach to the internal dimension of responsibility this way, we
draw on previous work in the compatibilist tradition that emphasizes normative compe-
tence (Wolf 1990, Wallace 1994) and reasons-responsiveness (Wolf 1990, Wallace
1994, Fischer and Ravizza 1998, and Nelkin 2011) and distinguishes cognitive and
volitional dimensions of reasons-responsiveness (Wallace 1994, Fischer and Ravizza
1998).
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 293
11
Sidgwick famously objects to Kant’s conception of autonomy as conformity to
principles of practical reason that this would prevent us from holding criminals respon-
sible and would allow us to recognize only morally upright behavior as responsible
(Sidgwick 1907: 511–16). The solution to this problem is for Kant to define autonomy
in terms of capacities for conformity to principles of practical reason.
12
The conception of reasons-responsiveness that Fischer and Ravizza defend is
mechanism-based, rather than agent-based (1998: 38). By contrast, we favor a version
of reasons-responsiveness that is agent-based, rather than mechanism-based, precisely
because we think that responsibility and excuse track the agent’s capacities, rather than
the capacities of her mechanisms. For defense of the agent-based approach, see Nelkin
2011: 64–79 and McKenna 2012.
13
For present purposes, in specifying an agent’s capacities in terms of such counter-
factuals, we can remain agnostic about whether capacities or counterfactuals have
explanatory priority, in particular, whether capacities ground the counterfactuals or
whether the capacities just consist in the truth of such counterfactuals.
294 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
depending on how well her judgments about what she ought to do and her
choices would track her reasons for action.
We could begin this process by distinguishing two extreme degrees of
responsiveness.
Strong Responsiveness: Whenever there is sufficient reason for the agent to
act, she recognizes the reason and conforms her behavior to it.
Weak Responsiveness: There is at least one situation in which there is
a sufficient reason to act, and the agent recognizes that reason and
conforms her behavior to it.
However, it does not seem plausible to model normative competence in
terms of either strong or weak responsiveness. Strong responsiveness is too
strong for the same reason we gave for focusing on competence, rather
than performance. We do not require that people actually act for sufficient
reasons to do otherwise; it is the capacities with which they act that matter.
The weak-willed are, at least typically, responsible for their poor choices.
Moreover, weak responsiveness seems too weak. It treats someone as respon-
sive in the actual situation even if she did not respond in the actual situation
and there is only one extreme circumstance in which she would recognize and
respond to reasons for action. The Goldilocks standard of responsiveness
evidently lies somewhere between these extremes. Of course, there is consid-
erable space between the extremes—the gap between always and once.
We might stake out an intermediate form of responsiveness in something
like the following terms.
Moderate Responsiveness: Where there is sufficient reason for the agent to
act, she regularly recognizes the reason and conforms her behavior to it.
Moderate responsiveness is deliberately vague; it specifies a range or space
of counterfactuals that must be true for the agent to be responsive. Ideally,
we would be able to specify a preferred form of moderate responsiveness
more precisely. But what is important for present purposes is that reasons-
responsiveness is a matter of degree and that the right threshold for
responsibility is probably some form of moderate responsiveness.
So far, this conception of responsiveness is coarse-grained in ways that
might prove problematic. For one thing, it lumps together cognitive and
volitional dimensions of responsiveness. But if they are independent aspects
of normative competence, then we may need to assess responsiveness along
these two dimensions separately. Moreover, it is at least conceivable that we
might require different degrees of responsiveness in cognitive and volitional
dimensions of competence. For instance, Fischer and Ravizza distinguish the
cognitive and volitional dimensions of reasons-responsiveness in terms of
“reasons-receptivity” and “reasons-reactivity” (respectively). Their conception
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 295
14
M’Naghten’s Case, 10 Cl. & F. 200, 8 Eng. Rep. 718 (1843).
15
There is a debate about whether the cognitive dimension of the insanity test,
expressed in M’Naghten’s rule, should be formulated in terms of capacities for recogniz-
ing criminal or moral wrongdoing. British criminal law has focused on criminal wrong-
doing, and American jurisdictions remain divided.
296 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
16
See Blair et al. 2005: 57–9. For some skepticism, see Aharoni et al. 2012.
17
We suspect that severe psychopathy impairs, but does not eliminate, reasons-
responsiveness and that it may make for a better moral excuse than a criminal excuse.
Contrast Fine and Kennett 2004.
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 297
18
Mele understands a desire as conquerable when one can resist it and as circumven-
table when one can perform an action that makes acting on the desire difficult or
impossible (1990). The alcoholic who simply resists cravings conquers his impulses,
whereas the alcoholic who throws out his liquor and stops associating with former
drinking partners or won’t meet them at places that serve alcohol circumvents his
impulses. Conquerability is mostly a matter of will power, whereas circumventability is
mostly a matter of foresight and strategy.
19
Phineas Gage was a nineteenth-century railway worker who was laying tracks in
Vermont and accidentally used his tamping iron to tamp down a live explosive charge,
which detonated and shot the iron bar up and through his skull. Though he did not lose
consciousness, over time his character was altered. Whereas he had been described as
someone possessing an “iron will” before the accident, afterward he had considerable
difficulty conforming his behavior to his own judgments about what he ought to do. The
story of Phineas Gage is related, and its larger significance explored, in Damasio 1994.
298 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
M’Naghten test, which recognizes only cognitive deficits as the basis for
insanity, and in favor of the more inclusive Model Penal Code conception.
Mental Disease or Defect Excluding Responsibility: (1) A person is not responsible
for criminal conduct if at the time of such conduct as the result of a mental disease
or defect he lacks substantial capacity either to appreciate the criminality [wrongful-
ness] of his conduct or to conform his conduct to the requirements of law. (2) [T]he
terms “mental disease or defect” do not include an abnormality manifested only by
repeated criminal or otherwise anti-social conduct.20
The Model Penal Code conception of insanity is an important advance on
the M’Naghten conception, precisely because it recognizes an independent
volitional dimension to sanity and so recognizes a wider conception of
insanity as involving significant impairment of either cognitive or volitional
competence.
Recognizing the volitional dimension of normative competence may
require revising the rationality or practical reason conceptions of responsi-
bility employed by criminal law theorists such as Michael Moore and
Stephen Morse. Strictly speaking, rationality conceptions of normative
competence need not reject the volitional dimension of normative compe-
tence. There might be more to rationality than correct belief or knowledge.
For instance, one might not count as practically rational unless one’s
appetites and passions are sufficiently under control to enable one to
conform one’s will to one’s normative judgment.
As far as we can tell, Moore is noncommittal on this issue and could
agree with these claims about the importance of the volitional dimension of
normative competence, folding them into claims about rational capacities.
However, Morse is skeptical about the volitional dimension of normative
competence. In part because his skepticism finds echoes in Fischer and
Ravizza’s treatment of reasons-reactivity, it is worth considering his com-
plaints about the volitional dimension in some detail.
In his essay “Uncontrollable Urges and Irrational People,” Morse critic-
ally discusses proposals to treat wrongdoers with irresistible impulses as
20
American Law Institute, Model Penal Code }4.01, emphasis added. The Model
Penal Code is a model statutory text of fundamental provisions of the criminal law, first
developed by the American Law Institute in 1962 and subsequently updated in 1981.
The MPC was intended to serve as a model for local jurisdictions drafting and revising
their criminal codes. Notice three differences between MPC and M’Naghten: (a) unlike
M’Naghten, MPC includes volitional, as well as cognitive, capacities in its conception of
insanity; (b) whereas M’Naghten makes complete incapacity a condition of insanity,
MPC makes substantial incapacity a condition of insanity; and (c) whereas M’Naghten
requires only capacity for normative recognition for sanity, MPC requires capacity for
normative appreciation. Here, we focus only on (a), but all three points of contrast
between MPC and M’Naghten are potentially significant.
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 299
excused for lack of control. He claims, not implausibly, that many with
emotional or appetitive disorders are nonetheless responsible, because they
retain sufficient capacity for rationality (2002: 1040). In discussing excuses
that appeal to uncontrollable urges, he makes clear that his conception of
rationality excludes volitional components.
This . . . Essay claims that our ambivalence about control problems is caused by a
confused understanding of the nature of those problems and argues that control or
volitional problems should be abandoned as legal criteria [for excuse] (2002: 1054).
But why should we abandon a volitional dimension to normative compe-
tence and control? Morse focuses on the alleged threat posed by irresistible
urges and makes several (incompatible) claims about them: (1) we cannot
make sense of irresistible urges, (2) we cannot distinguish between genu-
inely irresistible urges and urges not resisted, (3) there are no irresistible
urges, because under sufficient threat of sanction we can resist any strong
urge.
Morse focuses on irresistible urges. This is already problematic, because
it ignores the varieties of volitional impairment, which include not just
irresistible urges but also paralyzing fears, depression, and systematic weak-
ness caused by damage to the prefrontal cortex.
But consider what Morse does say about irresistible urges. He argues
against the claim made by the majority in Kansas v. Crane that civil detention
be limited to those who are dangerous to themselves or others on account of
control problems that are the result of mental abnormality.21 Morse plausibly
claims that mental disease or abnormality, as such, is irrelevant to excuse
(2002: 1034, 1040). All that mental abnormality signals is something about
the cause of urges; by itself, it does not signify anything about the agent’s
capacities, and so cannot serve as an excuse (2002: 1040). That is surely right,
but the Court in Crane did not say that mental abnormality was sufficient
for excuse, but at most that it was necessary.22 What was critical, the Court
claimed, was whether the urges were sufficiently irresistible to present a
control problem. A control problem can be understood as a lack of
relevant volitional capacities. So the Court is just not making the fallacious
argument that Morse rightly criticizes. Demonstrating that abnormality does
not imply incapacity does not show that responsibility does not require
volitional capacity. So Morse’s criticism of the abnormal cause requirement
does not support a rationality conception of agency that eschews volitional
capacities.
21
Kansas v. Crane, 534 US 407 (2002).
22
Insofar as the Court is requiring a mental abnormality, perhaps defined on the
disease model, we disagree. It is neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for excuse.
300 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
Morse goes on to claim that the idea of irresistible urges is not coherent
and that, even if it was, we could not distinguish between irresistible urges
and urges not resisted (1994: 1601, 2002: 1062). This is the problem of
distinguishing between can’t and won’t. Finally, he asserts that even if we
could distinguish between irresistible urges and urges not resisted, we
would find that in actual cases the urges in question would be resistible.
In discussing whether an addict’s cravings are irresistible, Morse argues that
they are not because if you hold a gun to the addict’s head and tell him that
you’ll shoot him if he gives in, he can resist (2002: 1057–8, 1070). This is
reminiscent of the sort of weak reactivity that Fischer and Ravizza defend
and that Kant requires in The Critique of Practical Reason.
Suppose that someone says his lust is irresistible when the desired object and
opportunity are present. Ask him whether he would not control his passion if, in
front of the house where he had this opportunity, a gallows were erected on which
he would be hanged immediately after gratifying his lust. We do not have to guess
very long what his answer would be. (Kant 1788: 30)
But these different complaints about irresistible urges are all resistible.
First, there seems to be no conceptual problem with irresistible urges.
We can conceive of paralyzing emotions or irresistible desires, as Mele does,
as emotional states or appetites that stand in the way of implementing the
verdicts of practical reason that are virtually unconquerable and uncircum-
ventable (1990). Resistibility is a modal notion. There is a question about
how unconquerable or uncircumventable impulses must be to be excusing,
and there may be evidential or pragmatic problems about identifying
desires that are genuinely irresistible. But the concept of irresistible desires
does not seem especially problematic.
Second, consider the worry that we cannot reliably distinguish between
an inability to overcome and a failure to overcome such obstacles. First of
all, this is an evidentiary problem, not a claim about the ingredients of
normative competence. Moreover, this evidentiary problem seems no
worse than the one for the cognitive dimension of normative competence,
which requires us to distinguish between a genuine inability to recognize
something as wrong and a failure to form correct normative beliefs or
attend to normative information at hand. Making the distinction between
can’t and won’t is a challenge, but not an insurmountable one, in either the
cognitive or volitional case. For instance, there are neurophysiological tests
for various forms of affective, as well as cognitive, sensitivity, such as
electrodermal tests of empathetic responsiveness (Blair et al. 2005: 49–50).
Finally, consider Morse’s claim that volitional capacity is easily demon-
strated insofar as agents can always resist desires and temptations under
sufficient threat. Morse’s position here bears comparison with that of
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 301
Fischer and Ravizza. As we saw earlier, while they defend moderate reasons-
receptivity, they require only weak reasons-reactivity.23 In defense of weak
reactivity, Fischer and Ravizza claim that reactivity is “all of a piece”—if
you can conform in some cases, even one case, that shows that you can
conform in any case. (1998: 73). Kant and Morse seem to agree. There are
two problems here. First, they want to recognize an asymmetry between
cognitive and volitional capacities. Yet, if reactivity were “all of a piece,”
then why not say the same thing about receptivity? If one can recognize
some moral reasons, one can recognize any. Or if one can recognize them
under some circumstances, then one can recognize them under any. This
would be to accept weak reasons-receptivity, which both Morse and Fischer
and Ravizza reject. Second, they are committed to claiming, at least about
reasons-reactivity, that one can’t have weak responsiveness without having
moderate responsiveness. Anyone who can resist an urge in one extreme
situation can resist it in others. But we see no reason to accept this
psychological stipulation. An agoraphobe might have such a paralyzing
fear of public spaces that she would be induced to leave her home only
under imminent threat of death. There’s no reason to assume that we
cannot have weak reactivity without moderate reactivity (cf. McKenna
2001, Watson 2001, Pereboom 2006, and Todd and Tognazzini 2008).
Our own view is that weak reactivity is simply implausible as a general
reactivity condition on responsibility. Cases in which a person would only
react differently under a threat of imminent death, because of a paralyzing
fear or compulsion, for example, seem to be cases in which we should
excuse.24 If a desire is really only resistible in this one counterfactual case,
then we think that the agent is not responsible, or at least not fully
responsible, in the actual case. That doesn’t mean that we can’t detain
him if he is dangerous to himself or others, but it would mean that it would
be inappropriate to blame and punish him.
On closer inspection, it seems Morse is really ambivalent between two
different kinds of skepticism about the volitional dimension of normative
competence and its significance. In some moments, he denies that there is
any separate volitional dimension to normative competence, beyond the
cognitive dimension. At other times, he recognizes the need for a separate
23
It is worth noting that Fischer’s and Ravizza’s view is doubly asymmetric insofar as
they require receptivity to at least some moral reasons, but require reactivity only to
reasons in general, not necessarily moral ones (1998: 79). We reject this sort of
asymmetry, as well.
24
Mele’s example of the agoraphobe, who will not leave his house, even for his
daughter’s wedding, but would leave it if it were on fire, seems coherently described as
one in which someone is weakly reactive, but nevertheless, not responsible.
302 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
5. SITUATIONAL CONTROL
because the threat or pressure was more than a person could or should be
expected to resist.25 The Model Penal Code adopts a reasonable person
version of the conditions under which a threat excuses, namely, when a
person of reasonable firmness would have been unable to resist, provided
the actor was not himself responsible for being subject to duress (section
2.09).
Whereas the situational aspect of responsibility was recognized by clas-
sical writers, such as Aristotle, Hobbes, and Locke, it has been less promin-
ent in more recent philosophical discussions of responsibility. Perhaps
because of case law and doctrine involving duress, criminal theorists, such
as Moore, and Morse, have clearly recognized the importance of the
situational component of responsibility (Moore 1997: 554, 560–1,
Morse 1994: 1605, 1617, and Morse 2002: 1058). They explain the
rationale for this situational component and the associated excuse of
duress in terms of the fair opportunity to avoid wrongdoing. The idea is
that normatively competent agents, through no fault of their own, due to
external threat or hard choice may lack the fair opportunity to avoid
wrongdoing. In normal cases, this opportunity may just blend into the
background, taken for granted. But in cases of duress it is absent. This not
only explains why duress should be excusing but also alerts us to the
importance of this opportunity in the normal case, where duress is absent.
6 . T W O M O D E L S O F N O R M A T I VE C O M P E T E N C E
AND SITUATIONAL CONTROL
25
Exactly when duress justifies and when it excuses is an interesting and difficult
question. Much will depend on how the necessity and balance of evils doctrines are
understood. Suppose A threatens to rape B’s loved one if B doesn’t kill C, who is
innocent. On one interpretation, this case fails the balance of evils test (murder is
worse than rape), so it tends to excuse, rather than justify. But this may be less clear if
the balance of evils test is performed using a moral balance employing agent-centered
prerogatives. We can’t get a clear handle on the difference between duress justifications
and duress excuses until we fix the moral conception employed in the balance of evils test.
But we think that it is safe to assume that however exactly the lines are drawn on these
issues about interpreting the balance of evils test there will be some duress excuses. That
is especially plausible, we think, when we recognize that duress and excuse can be scalar.
That is sufficient to justify our architectural assumption that there should be a separate
wing for situational control, whether or not that wing is densely populated.
304 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
7 . R E S P O N SI B I L I T Y A S T H E F A I R O P P O R T U N I T Y
TO AVOID WRONGDOING
Fair
Opportunity to
Avoid
Wrongdoing
Normative Situational
Competence Control
Cognitive Volitional
Competence Competence
One way to see the importance of the fair opportunity to avoid wrong-
doing is to think about why strict liability is problematic. Strict liability
offenses are those for which wrongdoing is sufficient and culpability is not
required. While tort law recognizes some strict liability offenses, it is
significant that the penalties for such torts are civil monetary damages.
Strict liability is extremely problematic within the criminal law, where guilt
results in blame and imprisonment. Indeed, the main strict liability crime is
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 307
26
For a brief discussion of the anomalous position of strict liability crimes within the
criminal law, see Dressler 2009: ch. 11.
27
See Wallace 1994: 109, 116, 161–6. The substance of our conception of
responsibility agrees with Wallace on many points, including the idea that
responsibility requires normative competence, that normative competence has both
cognitive and volitional dimensions, and that normative requirement is a condition of
the fairness of blame and punishment. But there are important differences. Wallace’s
account of excusing and exempting conditions (chs. 5–6) fails at many points to
distinguish properly between justification and excuse. Also, like Fischer and Ravizza
and other philosophers, Wallace tends to focus on the kind of normative competence
that fairness requires for responsibility, thus ignoring or at least underestimating the
importance of the kind of situational control that fairness also requires for responsibility.
Finally, and perhaps most importantly, Wallace insists on adopting a response-
dependent interpretation of this conception of responsibility insofar as he claims that
308 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
and, at the time of the action, nothing impairs these capacities and
opportunities in a relevant way. Such a condition can be satisfied in
Frankfurt-style cases, and, we claim, in deterministic settings.29 There is,
to be sure, another sense of the ability to do otherwise, in which the agents
in Frankfurt-style cases lack such an ability, but this is not the sense we
believe is required by the fair opportunity to avoid wrongdoing. The
legitimate threats to the opportunity to avoid wrongdoing and, hence,
responsibility come not from the fact that our actions are caused but
rather from specific impairments of cognitive and volitional capacities
and specific kinds of external interference with our ability to conform to
the relevant norms.
8 . PA R T I AL R E S PO N S I B I LI T Y AN D EX C US E
29
The skeptic might reply that a determined past prevents one from exercising one’s
capacities. But, as Nelkin has argued (2011: 64–79), the fact that the past is deterministic
does not make it interference or prevention in the relevant sense any more than is the
counterfactual intervener in a Frankfurt scenario. See Wolf (1990: 94–116) for a
different kind of defense of the conclusion.
30
One recent discussion of the scalar character of reasons-responsiveness is Coates
and Swenson 2012. For a defense of the scalar character of immaturity and the resulting
partial responsibility appropriate for juvenile justice, see Brink 2004.
310 David O. Brink and Dana K. Nelkin
31
The one exception to the generalization that American criminal law does not
recognize partial excuse is the provocation defense, under which intentional homicides
committed with adequate provocation reduce to an offense of voluntary manslaughter.
32
See Morse 2003. Morse’s position is especially interesting, because this defense of
partial excuse is a reversal of his previous skepticism about partial excuse (Morse 1984).
Fairness and Architecture of Responsibility 311
REFERENCES
Watson, G., (ed.) (1982). Free Will (New York: Oxford University Press).
—— (1987). “Responsibility and the Limits of Evil,” reprinted in Watson (2004).
—— (1996). “Two Faces of Responsibility,” reprinted in Watson (2004).
—— (2001). “Reasons and Responsibility,” reprinted in Watson (2004).
—— (2004). Agency and Answerability (New York: Oxford University Press).
—— (2011). “The Trouble with Psychopaths.” In Reasons and Recognition: Essays
on the Philosophy of T. M. Scanlon (New York: Oxford University Press).
Williams, B. (1976). “Moral Luck,” reprinted in Williams (1981).
—— (1981). Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Wolf, S. (1990). Freedom Within Reason (New York: Oxford University Press).
This page intentionally left blank
Index
intentions 50–1, 71–2, 79–83, 90–3, partial conception of 249, 252, 257,
297 259, 260–1
attributions of 70–1, 90 moral disagreement 236–7, 239–40;
future-directed 17 see also group/cultural differences in
present-directed 17 values
shared 56–60, 71 moral intransigence 265, 271, 275, 278,
internal reasons 230–1, 237–41 279, 280
It’s a Wonderful Life 229, 232 moral luck 231, 246, 260–1
moral responsibility 6–8, 151–2, 166,
Jacobson, Dan 209 168–70, 172, 175, 177–8, 184–5,
John, Kim 269, 270–1 187, 189–93, 195–207, 213,
JoJo 264, 271–2 216–21, 260, 293; see also
justification 290, 302 responsibility
as accountability 206, 219 n.24
Kansas v. Crane 299 as attributability 206, 217
Kant, Immanuel 30 as blameworthiness 226, 233–4
Kapitan, Tomis 147 as playing a certain causal role 233–4
Korsgaard, Christine 29, 31–2, 34–6, 43 rational justification of 184–5, 187,
192, 194, 199–204
Lafferty, Ronald 269–71 skepticism about 184, 186–7, 192–3,
Lavin, Doug 71 199, 201–4, 226, 228–9, 234,
Lazarus, Richard 207–8 290 n.8, 308
legality 307 moral sentiments 189
Lehrer, Keith 127 Morris, Norval 254
Levy, Neil 219, 230–1, 237–8, 242–4 Morse, Stephen 298–302, 303
Lewis, David 166
libertarianism 4–5, 126–7, 129, 148 Nahmias, Eddy 129–30, 143
Locke, John 53, 63 naturalism 184–7, 189, 197–8, 201–2
token naturalism 186–9, 193, 200–2
M’Naghten test; see McNaughtan Rule type naturalism 187, 189, 192–4,
McKenna, Michael 218 199–202
Macnamara, Coleen 217 new dispositionalism 166–70, 174
McNaughtan, Daniel 267 Nichols, Shaun 208
McNaughtan Rule 266, 272–3, 295, Nils, Christie 258
297–8 normative competence 288, 292–5,
Mele, Alfred 165 304–5
mental disorder; see mental illness normative judgments 17–18, 25, 33, 35
mental illness 265, 266, 268, 279; see also
delusions; hallucinations; insanity; O’Connor, Timothy 128, 143
mental abnormality as excuse; objective attitude 186
psychosis obligation(s) 185, 190, 194, 197
distinct from insanity 266 conflicting 99, 114
Mill, John Stuart 128–9, 143 obsessive-compulsive disorder 19
mitigation 310
Model Penal Code 298, 303 Pereboom, Derk 207, 218–19
Moody-Adams, Michelle 276 personal culpability 248
Moore, Michael 298, 303, 304 relationship to desert 248–9, 251, 255,
moral character 266, 268 256–7
moral desert personal identity 53, 63
compatibilist theories of 248 Principle of Alternative Possibilities
impartial conception of 248–9, 251, (PAP) 308–9
252, 258 Prinz, Jesse 208
incompatibilist theories of 248 psychological realism 98, 120
318 Index