0% found this document useful (0 votes)
466 views6 pages

Saharon Shelah - Cardinalities of Countably Based Topologies

This document presents a proof that if a topological space has a countable base but is uncountable, then the cardinality of its topology must be at least continuum (2^aleph_0). It first shows this is true if the space is countable or linearly ordered. It then considers an uncountable space and aims to reach a contradiction. The main step is to show that for any large subset, there is an element and open set such that the "backward" set from that element is also large. This leads to a linearly ordered subset, contradicting an earlier lemma. Therefore the topology must have cardinality continuum.

Uploaded by

Jtyhmf
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
466 views6 pages

Saharon Shelah - Cardinalities of Countably Based Topologies

This document presents a proof that if a topological space has a countable base but is uncountable, then the cardinality of its topology must be at least continuum (2^aleph_0). It first shows this is true if the space is countable or linearly ordered. It then considers an uncountable space and aims to reach a contradiction. The main step is to show that for any large subset, there is an element and open set such that the "backward" set from that element is also large. This leads to a linearly ordered subset, contradicting an earlier lemma. Therefore the topology must have cardinality continuum.

Uploaded by

Jtyhmf
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 6

4

5
4


r
e
v
i
s
i
o
n
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9







m
o
d
i
f
i
e
d
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9


Cardinalities of countably based topologies
Saharon Shelah
Aug 1991
Department of Mathematics, The Hebrew University, Jerusalem, Israel
1
Department of Mathematics, Rutgers University, New Brunswick NJ, USA
ABSTRACT
Let T be the family of open subsets of a topological space (not necessarily
Hausdor or even T
0
). We prove that if T has a countable base and is not
countable, then T has cardinality at least continuum.
* * *
Topological spaces are not assumed to be Hausdor, or even T
0
.
Theorem 1 Let T be the set of open subsets of a topological space, and
suppose that T has a countable base B (more precisely, B is a countable
subset of T which is closed under nite intersections, and the sets in T are
the unions of subsets of B). Then the cardinality of T is either 2

0
or
0
.
This answers a question of Kishor Kale. We thank Wilfrid Hodges for telling
us the question and for writing up the proof from notes. In a subsequent
1
Partially supported by the Basic Research Fund, Israeli Academy of Sciences. Publi-
cation no. 454 done 6,8/1991.
1
4
5
4


r
e
v
i
s
i
o
n
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9







m
o
d
i
f
i
e
d
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9


work we shall deal with the case [B[ < 2

, [T[ > [B[, strong limit of


conality
0
and prove that [T[ 2

Our proof begins with some notation. A set is given, together with a
countable family B of subsets of ; =

B and B is closed under nite
intersections. We write T for the set of all unions of subsets of B. Thus T is
a topology on and B is a base for this topology.
We write X, Y etc. for subsets of . We write T(X) for the set X Y :
Y T, and likewise B(X) with B in place of T. We say X is small if
[T(X)[ , and large otherwise.
Lemma 2 If [[ =
0
and [T[ >
0
then [T[ = 2

0
.
PROOF: Identify with the ordinal , and list the set B by a function
with domain , so that B = (m) : m < . Then a set X is in T if and
only if
(Y )(n ) (n X m(m Y n (m))).
Thus B is an analytic set, and so its cardinality must be either 2

0
or
0
(cf. Manseld & Weitkamp [1] Theorem 6.3). 2
2
Lemma 3 Suppose is linearly ordered by some ordering _ in such a way
that the sets in T are initial segments of and any initial segment of the
form (, x) is open. If [T[ >
0
then [T[ = 2

0
.
PROOF: As B is countable, the linear order has a countable dense subset
D, but as T is countable, the rationals are not embeddable in D, i.e. D is
scattered. By Hausdors structure theorem for scattered linear orderings,
D has at most countably many initial segments (cf. Manseld & Weitkamp
[1] Theorem 9.21). 2
3
Henceforth we assume that is uncountable and large, and that [T[ <
2

0
, and we aim for a contradiction. Replacing by a suitable subset if
necessary, we can also assume:
Hypothesis The cardinality of is
1
.
Finally we can assume without loss that if x, y are any two distinct elements
of then there is a set in B which contains one but not the other. (Dene x
2
4
5
4


r
e
v
i
s
i
o
n
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9







m
o
d
i
f
i
e
d
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9


and y to be equivalent if they lie in exactly the same sets in B. Choose one
representative of each equivalence class.)
Lemma 4 If for each n < , X
n
is a small subset of , then

n<
X
n
is
small.
PROOF: Each X
n
has a countable subset Y
n
such that if V, W are el-
ements of T with V X
n
,= W X
n
then there is some element y Y
n
which is in exactly one of V, W. Now if V, W are elements of T which dier
on

n<
X
n
, then they already dier on some X
n
and hence they dier on
Y =

n<
Y
n
. But Y is countable; so Lemma 2 implies that either Y is small
or [T(Y )[ = 2

0
. The latter is impossible since [T[ < 2

0
, and so Y is small,
hence

n<
X
n
is small. 2
4
Our main argument lies in the next lemma, which needs some further
notation. Let Z be a subset of . The Z-closure of a subset X of Z is the set
cl
Z
(X) of all elements y of Z such that every set in B which contains y meets
X. Given an element x of Z and a subset X of Z, we write back
Z
(x, X) for
the set y Z : y , X cl
Z
x.
Lemma 5 Suppose Z is a large subset of . Then there are an element x
of Z and a set X B such that x X and back
Z
(x, X) is large.
PROOF: Assume Z is a counterexample; we shall reach a contradiction.
By a Z-rich set we mean a subset N of Z TZ such that
N is countable.
If x N and X B then back
Z
(x, X) N.
If U is a subset of Z which is a member of N and is small, and V, W
are elements of T such that V U ,= WU, then there is some element
of N U which lies in exactly one of V and W.
Since Z has cardinality at most
1
, we can construct a strictly increasing
continuous chain N
i
: i <
1
) of Z-rich sets, such that Z

i<
1
N
i
.
Let us say that an element x of Z is pertinent if there is some i <
1
such
that x N
i+1
N
i
, and x lies in some small subset of Z which is in N
i
. If z
is not pertinent, we say it is impertinent.
3
4
5
4


r
e
v
i
s
i
o
n
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9







m
o
d
i
f
i
e
d
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9


We claim that if V, W are any two distinct members of T(Z) then some
impertinent element is in exactly one of V and W. For this, consider the least
i <
1
such that some element z of N
i+1
N
i
is in the symmetric dierence of
V and W. If z is pertinent, then by the last clause in the denition of Z-rich
sets, some element of N
i
already distinguishes V and W, contradicting the
choice of i. This proves the claim.
Now let I be the set of all impertinent elements of Z. Since Z is large
and N
0
Z is small, the claim implies that I is large. Thinning the chain if
necessary, we can arrange that for each i <
1
, N
i+1
N
i
contains innitely
many elements of I.
We can partition I into countably many sets, so that for every i <
1
,
each set meets I (N
i+1
N
i
) in exactly one element. By Lemma 4 above,
since I is large, at least one of these partition sets must be large. Let J be
a large partition set. We dene a binary relation _ on J by:
x _ y for all U B, if y U then x U.
We shall reach a contradiction with Lemma 3 by showing that _ is a linear
ordering and T(J) is a set of initial segments of J under _ which contains
all the initial segments of the form x : x y.
The relation _ is clearly reexive and transitive. We made it antisym-
metric by assuming that no two distinct elements of lie in exactly the same
sets in B. We must show that if x and y are distinct elements of Z then either
x _ y or y _ x.
Let x, y be a counterexample, so that there are sets X, Y B with
x X Y and y Y X. By symmetry and the choice of J we can assume
that for some i <
1
, x N
i
and y N
i+1
N
i
. Since y is impertinent,
no small set containing y is in N
i
. In particular back
Z
(x, X) contains y
and hence is not both small and in N
i
. But since N
i
is Z-rich, it contains
back
Z
(x, X). Also we assumed that Z is a counterexample to the lemma;
this implies that back
Z
(x, X) is small. We have a contradiction.
Thus it follows that _ is a linear ordering of J, and the denition of _
then implies that T(J) is a set of initial segments of _. As B separates
points, every set x : x y is open. This contradicts Lemma 3 and so
proves the present lemma. 2
5
PROOF OF THEOREM 1: Now we can nish the proof of the theorem.
We shall nd elements x
n
of and sets X
n
T (n < ) such that x
m
X
n
4
4
5
4


r
e
v
i
s
i
o
n
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9







m
o
d
i
f
i
e
d
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9


if and only if m = n. By taking arbitrary unions of the sets X
n
it clearly
follows that [T[ = 2

.
We dene x
n
and X
n
by induction on n. Writing Z
1
for and Z
n
for
back
Z
n1
(x
n
, X
n
), we require that x
n+1
Z
n
and each set Z
n
is large. Since
is large, Lemma 5 tells us that we can begin by choosing x
0
and X
0
so
that back

(x
0
, X
0
) is large.
After x
n
and X
n
have been chosen, we use Lemma 5 again to choose
x
n+1
in Z
n
and Y
n+1
in B so that x
n+1
Y
n+1
and back
Zn
(x
n+1
, Y
n+1
) is
large. For each m n, x
n+1
is in Z
m
and hence it is not in cl
Z
m1
x
m
,
so that there is some set U
m
B which contains x
n+1
but not x
m
. Put
X
n+1
=

mn
U
m
Y
n+1
. (Note that this is the one place where we use the
fact that B, and hence also T, is closed under nite intersections.) Since
X
n+1
Y
n+1
, back
Zn
(x
n+1
, X
n+1
) is large.
We must show that this works. First, x
n
X
n
for each n by construction.
Next, if m n then x
n+1
is in Z
m
and hence it is not in X
m
. Finally if m n
then x
m
, X
n+1
by the denition of X
n+1
. 2
5
The following theorem has a similar proof. We omit details, except to
say that (i) countable is replaced by of cardinality at most [B[, and
1
by [B[
+
, and (ii) a more complicated analogue of Lemma 2 is needed.
Theorem 6 Let T be the set of open subsets of a topological space (not
neccessarily Hausdor, nor even T
0
), and suppose that T has a base B which
is closed under nite intersections, and [T[ > [B[ +
0
.Then
(1) there are x
n
and X
n
B for n < such that for all m, n < ,
x
n
X
m
i m = n, and
(2) [T[ 2

0
.
One naturally asks whether we can let B in Theorem 1 be any set such
that T is the set of unions of sets in B, without the requirement that B is
closed under nite intersections. The answer is no, for the following reason.
Lemma 7 Suppose there is a tree S with levels, nodes and at least
branches of length , where ; suppose also that S is normal (i.e. at each
limit level there are never two or more nodes with the same predecessors).
Then there are a set of cardinality and a family of subsets of which
has exactly unions.
5
4
5
4


r
e
v
i
s
i
o
n
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9







m
o
d
i
f
i
e
d
:
1
9
9
3
-
0
8
-
2
9


CONSTRUCTION: Let be a set of branches of length ; for each
s S let U
s
be x : s , x. Lastly let B be the family of sets
U
s
: s S, so that [B[ = . Now the sets in T are: members of B, itself
and complements of singletons; so [T[ = . 2
7
Thus by starting with the full binary tree of height , we can build
examples where B is countable and T is any cardinal between and 2

.
References
[1] Richard Manseld and Galen Weitkamp, Recursive aspects of descriptive
set theory, Oxford Univ. Press 1985.
6

You might also like