Stephen Wang - Aquinas and Sartre - On Freedom, Personal Identity, and The Possibility of Happiness-The Catholic University of America Press (2009)
Stephen Wang - Aquinas and Sartre - On Freedom, Personal Identity, and The Possibility of Happiness-The Catholic University of America Press (2009)
Stephen Wang
A q u i na s & Sar t r e
O n F r e e d o m , P e r s o n a l I d e n t i t y, AND
t h e P o s s i b i l i t y of H a ppi n e s s
Preface ix
Acknowledgments xix
Abbreviations xxiii
Notes about the Text xxv
Introduction 1
Aquinas: Historical and Intellectual Background 1
Aquinas: Philosophical and Theological Influences 6
Aquinas: Subsequent Interpretation 8
Sartre: Historical and Intellectual Background 10
Sartre: Philosophical and Theological Influences 13
Sartre: Subsequent Interpretation 16
Pa r t O n e Human Being
1. Identity and Human Incompletion in Sartre 23
The Nature of Human Action 23
Anguish, Vertigo, and the Ambiguity of Identity 24
Consciousness and Intentionality 32
Self-Consciousness and Being-for-Itself 37
Imagination and the Power of Negation 43
Lack, Possibility, and the Projection of Values 48
The Self, Selfness, and Personhood 53
Pa r t T h r e e Human Freedom
5. Freedom, Choice, and the
Indetermination of Reason in Sartre 155
The Intentional Structure of the Act 155
Indetermination and the Projection of Ends 159
Choice and Self-Constitution 163
The Reasonableness of the Project 168
Temporality, Conversion, and the Unity of Life 175
Facticity and the Limits of Freedom 180
The Persistence of Existential Freedom 186
Pa r t F o u r Human Fulfillment
7. The Possibility of Human Happiness in Sartre 243
The Goal of Happiness 243
The Ideal of Self-Coincidence 245
Existential Denial and Human Relationships 247
The Link between Ontology and Theology 250
Failure and Hope 253
Conclusion 275
Bibliography 281
Works by Sartre 281
Works by Aquinas 282
Works about Sartre 282
Works about Aquinas 286
Other Works 289
Index 293
P r e f ac e
ix
x = p r e fa c e
ally does justice to Sartre’s project in Being and Nothingness.3 A 1996 edi-
tion of the American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly dedicated to Sartre
succeeded in bringing him to the attention of Catholic philosophers, but
it did not attempt to make many connections between Sartre and think-
ers such as Aquinas who stand at the heart of the Catholic philosophical
tradition.4 My own research has convinced me not just that there are some
points of contact between Aquinas and Sartre, but that their approach to a
number of key philosophical issues—centered around the question of free-
dom—is almost identical. In my conclusion I summarize this approach,
and try to present a combined Thomistic-Sartrean theory of freedom.
Here in this preface I offer a summary of the summary in order to give the
reader a taste of what is to come; and toward the end I make one or two in-
troductory points about how I have structured this work.
The best way to understand their common approach is to think of what
happens when we face a choice. When there are different options before
me, and I have to make a decision, a number of factors will usually influ-
ence that decision. Three of the most important factors are undoubtedly
who I am, where I am, and what I am seeking. In other words, my personal
identity, the objective circumstances in which I find myself, and the goals I
am seeking will all have some kind of influence on the choice I eventually
make. They make up what we could call the “total situation” that informs
my choice.
In philosophical theories about human action, it is common to assume
that this total situation, once I start reflecting on it, is something stable and
accessible. So when I have a choice to make, I think about what kind of
icano, 1995), 293–96; the brief reflections in Denis J. M. Bradley, Aquinas on the Twofold Hu-
man Good: Reason and Human Happiness in Aquinas’s Moral Science (Washington, D.C.: The
Catholic University of America Press, 1997), 532; and M. Qizilbash, “Aristotle and Sartre on the
Human Condition: Lack, Responsibility and the Desire to Be God,” Angelaki 3, no. 1 (1998): 34,
endnote 13.
3. Existence and the Existent, for example, fails to get to the heart of Sartre’s distinction be-
tween essence and existence, and is more an exposition of Maritain’s Thomism than of Sartre’s
existentialism. Maritain wrongly insists, for example, that Sartre’s vision of the human being is
devoid of a place for an intelligible nature or essence. See Jacques Maritain, Existence and the
Existent, trans. Lewis Galantiere and Gerald B. Phelan (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday & Com-
pany, 1956), esp. 15–16.
4. There is an essay on Sartre and Yves Simon, but most of the articles (comparing Sar-
tre with Foucault, Ricoeur, etc.) could have appeared in any general philosophical journal. See
American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70, no. 4: Jean-Paul Sartre (1996).
p r e fa c e = xi
person I am (what would suit me, what I am interested in, what I am ca-
pable of, etc.); I think about the objective circumstances confronting me
(what is going on here, what needs to be done, what the practical options
available are, what the consequences of any action will be, etc.); and I think
about the goals I am seeking (what my ambitions are, what my hopes are,
what my fears are, what my dreams are, etc.). My understanding of this
total situation will be a starting point for the process of deliberation that
leads to making a choice.
Philosophical theories that are more “intellectualist” argue that my un-
derstanding of this total situation will determine which way the decision
goes: my will (my orientation to a particular course of action) will always
follow the direction suggested by my intellect (by my understanding of
what this total situation means). Philosophical theories that are more “vol-
untarist” argue that my choice will not, ultimately, be determined by my un-
derstanding of this situation: my will acts independently from my intellect,
and I can respond to this total situation in any way I like, even if it makes
no sense of what I have come to understand. It should be obvious that intel-
lectualist theories have a more deterministic conception of human action—
there is not much room for freedom. And voluntaristic theories have plenty
of room for freedom, but human action becomes irrational and capricious.
Aquinas and Sartre find a third way of understanding human action
that avoids both the determinism of intellectualist theories and the irratio-
nalism of voluntarist ones. They do this by questioning the very assump-
tions of these theories. They do accept the idea that certain factors have an
important bearing on our decisions and that our understanding of the “to-
tal situation” will determine how we act—this is why they are not volun-
tarists. But they both argue that when we deliberate about a choice, these
factors themselves are not fully determined. My personal identity is not
static: I can question who I am, I can reinterpret the meaning of my iden-
tity, I can rethink the significance of my life. The objective circumstances
confronting me in this choice are not clear-cut: there are different ways
of interpreting things, different points of view, different conclusions to be
drawn. And the goals I am attracted to are more ambiguous than I might
have imagined: I can make new priorities among the goals I already have, I
can set some of them aside for a time, I can even seek new goals that I have
never considered before.
xii = p r e fa c e
For Aquinas and Sartre, there is no single way of understanding the to-
tal situation before me. This is precisely why I face the dilemma of having
to choose, because each of the options before me is attractive and makes
sense on its own terms. Reason, when it confronts reality, is not led to a
single conclusion about what is going on or what should be done. This is
not because of any doubt about the objectivity of reality, it is because it is
part of human nature to be able to interpret reality in different ways, to
reinterpret the meaning of one’s own existence, and to redefine the goals
one is seeking. What is extraordinary about human beings is that we can
change the way we look at things, change the way we look at ourselves, and
change the goals we are seeking—this is what allows us to make a choice.
Freedom, on this model, is not about accepting or rejecting a predeter-
mined understanding of what a certain situation involves, it is our ability
to determine for ourselves which kind of understanding will guide our de-
liberations. The will neither follows the intellect (intellectualism) nor goes
its own way (voluntarism)—instead it is intimately involved in the very
working of intellect itself, and helps the intellect to determine which way it
will see the world. Freedom is still about deciding what to do, but for Aqui-
nas and Sartre the question of what to do depends on the deeper questions
of how to see things, who to be, and what to seek. All of this, it bears re-
peating, is done without denying the objectivity of reality, without falling
into relativism or subjectivism—since for Aquinas and Sartre it is the na-
ture of objective reality that it can be interpreted in different ways, and it is
the nature of human reason that it can consider these differences.
Reason is not fully determined. Human identity is not fixed. Happiness
can take many forms. These are some of the powerful insights that Aquinas
and Sartre share. Freedom is therefore not a capricious choice that turns
us against our rational understanding of what is important and good. It
is rather the necessity of interpreting the open-ended significance of our-
selves and our circumstances. Our freedom to choose between different
goals is inseparable from our freedom to interpret the world in different
ways, and to choose—within certain limits—what kind of person we will
become. This is why the question of freedom cannot be separated from the
questions of personal identity, of the nature of human understanding, and
of our longing for fulfillment in a future happiness.
Some readers may be unconvinced by these ideas. Others may be in-
terested in the ideas themselves, but may remain unconvinced that they
p r e fa c e = xiii
Aquinas. On the whole, the texts of one author are analyzed without much
reference to the other, so that each author can be understood on his own
terms, and so that the exposition is not prejudiced by the comparison
that is made. The comparison itself only occurs toward the end of each
part, and more particularly in part four. The similarities will stand out and
speak for themselves once the ideas of Sartre and Aquinas have been prop-
erly understood and placed side by side.
Each main part begins with Sartre, for two reasons. First, he is closer
to us in time. Despite the distance between English-language philosophy
and continental philosophy, Sartre’s ideas will be more accessible to many
readers than Aquinas’s. They are part of our culture—whether we like it or
not. It will help to look back through this more familiar figure to a more
distant one, presenting Sartre’s conclusions with all their force, then show-
ing that Aquinas reaches the same conclusions in a different philosophical
language—a language that is too familiar to many Christian theologians
and too alien to many secular philosophers to be appreciated properly. The
second reason for starting with Sartre is that this reflects the development
of my own ideas. As I began to work in this area, I found myself making
connections between existentialist critiques of the view that there is a fixed
human nature and the concept of character development in contemporary
virtue ethics. In both philosophies, human life is open-ended, and it is up
to us, within certain limits, to develop our own identity and form our own
character. This led me to investigate Sartre as the key exponent of existen-
tialism and Aquinas as a central figure in the development of virtue ethics.
The focus then shifted from ethics to wider questions of philosophical an-
thropology.
This book concentrates on some key texts from the writings of Aqui-
nas and Sartre. There are also references to the sometimes contradictory
interpretations of each philosopher that have been offered by scholars over
the years. On a few occasions, when the background is important, there are
references to the biographical, historical, or philosophical context in which
certain arguments were developed. I do believe, however, that each thinker,
in his own texts, is developing an argument that can be followed on its own
terms. While it would be a distortion to imply that Aquinas and Sartre are
interlocutors in a timeless debate about some supposed “perennial philoso-
phy,” it is nevertheless true that each thinker offers us a view of what it is to
be human, and these views can be discussed and compared despite their dif-
p r e fa c e = xv
ferent contexts. It is essential to follow the line of thought that is being de-
veloped and weigh up the central insight that is being presented.
The advantage of concentrating on these key texts is that it gives a clear
focus to the work, and I can analyze in detail some difficult and highly nu-
anced arguments. The disadvantage of this concentration is that many im-
portant topics and connections remain unexplored. I spend far too little
time, for example, on Aquinas’s thinking about virtue, character, friendship,
right and wrong, or law; or on Sartre’s thinking about bad faith, the Look,
being-for-others, the body, or existential psychoanalysis. I do not move into
a discussion about concrete ethics and ethical norms, but remain at the
level of what could be called fundamental ethics or action theory. These la-
cunae threaten to distort the whole account of the human being presented
here. This is the price paid for specialization, and the distortion will not be
too great if one keeps this work in perspective and remembers that it forms
one small part of a wider philosophical anthropology.
There is an almost exclusive concentration in this work on the individ-
ual human being, which is a serious limitation. I make only passing refer-
ence to interpersonal relationships, the family, love, society, or politics—
subjects that Aquinas and Sartre deal with extensively. My only defense is
to refer again to the aim of this project, which is to examine the nature of
human freedom. All of our relationships, whether intimate and personal,
or diffuse and political, somehow involve bonds between individual hu-
man beings, and all of them depend somehow on our free response to the
relationship and our search for fulfillment in that relationship. So if we are
to understand the nature of society and of human relationships, we shall
have to understand what it is for the individual who is in relationship to be
free and to seek happiness. The communal and the political have to have
some basis in the personal.
One of the stumbling blocks to a sympathetic reading of both Aquinas
and Sartre is the teleological nature of their act theory. For these thinkers,
human beings are always seeking some goal or end (telos, in Greek), seek-
ing fulfillment in some form, and this raises the suspicion that in these
theories human action is unavoidably “selfish.” It is enough to say here that
a teleological theory of action leaves as much room for love, kindness, as-
ceticism, altruism, and self-sacrifice as any other theory—but these virtues
will always relate in some way to the self. In other words, in a teleological
theory, the most selfless acts—if they are mine—must relate in some way
xvi = p r e fa c e
5. On the theological nature of the Summa, see, e.g., Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thom-
as Aquinas, Vol. 1: The Person and His Work (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of
America Press, 1996), 148–55; Leonard E. Boyle, “The Setting of the Summa Theologiae of St.
Thomas—Revisited,” in The Ethics of Aquinas, ed. Stephen J. Pope (Washington, D.C.: George-
town University Press, 2002), 6–7; and Servais Pinckaers, The Sources of Christian Ethics, trans.
Sr. Mary Thomas Noble (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1995), 21–25. See also my introduction
below.
6. Fergus Kerr muses: “Perhaps we should rescue Thomas from philosophy altogether—
but then, after all, he is a great philosopher, indeed that is one of the sources of the ambiva-
p r e fa c e = xvii
lence of his thought. He is a philosopher and he is a theologian, and we are never going to
agree where to put the emphasis”; see Fergus Kerr, After Aquinas: Versions of Thomism (Ox-
ford: Blackwell, 2002), 210.
Ac k n o w l e d g m e n t s
xix
xx = a c k n o w l e d g m e n t s
This book includes material reworked from the following articles: “Rea-
son and the Limits of Existential Freedom: Why Sartre Is Not a Voluntarist”
(Philosophy Today 50, no. 3, [2006]: 338–48); “Aquinas on Human Happi-
ness and the Natural Desire for God” (New Blackfriars 88, no. 1015 [2007]:
322–34 [published by Blackwell Publishing on behalf of the Provincial
Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers]); “Incomple-
tion, Happiness, and the Desire for God in Sartre’s Being and Nothingness”
(Sartre Studies International 12, no. 1 [2006]: 1–17); “The Ambiguity of the
a c k n o w l e d g m e n t s = xxi
Self and the Construction of Human Identity in the Early Sartre” (American
Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 81, no. 1 [2007]: 73–88); “Subjective Ob-
jectivity in Aquinas: The Interdependence and Reflexivity of Intellect and
Will” (Acta Philosophica I, vol. 16 [2007]: 91–108); “Motivation and the Es-
tablishment of Ends in Satre’s Act Theory (Sartre Studies International 14,
no. 1 [2008]: 13–25); and “The Indetermination of Reason and the Role of
the Will in Aquinas’s Account of Human Freedom” (New Blackfriars 90, no.
1025 [2009]; published by Blackwell Publishing on behalf of the Provincial
Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers). These articles
are used with permission.
xxi
A b b r e v i at io n s
xxiii
xxiv = a b b r e v i at i o n s
ant: Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique, édition corrigée avec index par Arlette
Elkaïm-Sartre (Paris: Gallimard, 1996).
Two page references are given for each reference to EN, e.g., EN 478/509. The
first number refers to the corrected 1996 edition, from which I have quoted. The sec-
ond number refers to the original 1943 edition, which is the one most often cited in
secondary works.
IM: Jean-Paul Sartre, The Psychology of the Imagination, and Jean-Paul Sartre,
L’imaginaire
Two page references are given for each reference to IM, e.g., IM 12 [32]. The first
number refers to the English translation, the second in square brackets refers to the
French original.
ST or the Summa: Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae. The numbers refer to the
part of the Summa, then the question, then the article, then the section of the article.
For example, ST I-II.5:2ad2 refers to Part I-II, question 5, article 2, response to sec-
ond objection. The Latin text is from the Leonine edition of Aquinas’s Opera Om-
nia (complete works), vols. 4–11. The English translation is from St. Thomas Aqui-
nas, Summa Theologica, translated by Fathers of the English Dominican Province,
5 vols.
TE: Jean-Paul Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Con-
sciousness, and Jean-Paul Sartre, La transcendance de l’ego: Esquisse d’une description
phénoménologique
Two page references are given for each reference to TE, e.g., TE 40 [23]. The first
number refers to the English translation, the second in square brackets refers to the
French original.
No t e s a b o u t t h e T e x t
xxv
A q u i n a s & Sa r t r e
I n t r o d u c t io n
1
2 = introduction
the thirteenth century various aspects of human freedom had been distin-
guished (by Bernard of Clairvaux, John of La Rochelle, Odo Regaldus, and
others). In the early part of the thirteenth century William of Auxerre argued
that free decision is essentially an act of reason; Philip the Chancellor that it
is principally a matter of the will (although reason and will are in substance
the same faculty but two different activities); and an anonymous writer from
the same period that it is a third power distinct from both. The relation of
reason, will, and freedom of decision remained a major topic throughout the
century. It became characteristic of Dominican writers to associate freedom
closely with reason, and of Franciscans to locate it more in the will.
Happiness, beatitudo, was another concept with a long history.3 There
was a theological conviction, much influenced by Augustine, that true
happiness is to be found only in the contemplation of God in the world to
come. There can be no happiness in this world because “all men, so long as
they are mortal, are also necessarily wretched.”4 For the most part, prior to
the thirteenth century, the Boethian concept of happiness that grew out of
this attitude was generally accepted: the fragility of earthly things admits
of no perfect condition; and human happiness is to be found only in an-
other world where multiplicity is made one and fragility is exchanged for
permanence.5 Yet Aristotelian and even some Christian conceptions of hu-
man nature also understood happiness as the perfection of human nature,
in which human achievements must play some part. Is there such a thing
as a purely human good that can be attained by one’s own actions? What
connection do our present attempts to find fulfillment have with a future
fulfillment that will transform our very existence? There seemed to be a
need to distinguish between different types of happiness. It was William
of Auxerre (died 1231) who first made the theological distinction between
perfect happiness, experienced by the saints in heaven, and imperfect happi-
ness, which we can taste here in the present. It was against this background
that Aquinas developed his own interpretation of happiness.
One of the most significant factors that influenced in a more direct
way Aquinas’s teaching on subjects such as human freedom was the long-
3. See Georg Wieland, “Happiness: The Perfection of Man,” in The Cambridge History of
Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 673–79.
4. Augustine, De civitate Dei, IX, 15.
5. Cf. Boethius, Consolatio III, pr. 9 and 10.
introduction = 3
I mention this Averroist dispute just to give one example in this introduc-
tion of how Aquinas wrote in a particular context, for a particular reason.
It will not be possible or necessary in this present work to go deeply into
the background of every aspect of Aquinas’s teachings—but at least we can
remind ourselves that there is a background, often with pressing political
and ecclesiastical features, as well as philosophical and theological ones.
The main writings of Aquinas considered in this work are the Quaes-
tiones disputatae de veritate, the Quaestiones disputatae de malo, and the
Summa theologiae, so it is worth giving some more specific background
to their composition.11 After lecturing on the Bible, the main academic
task of a master of theology in Paris was to take part in disputations—
some of them “private” (the master teaching his students within the con-
fines of the school) and some of them more formal and “public.” The texts
of the Quaestiones disputatae were often written up at some remove from
the original classroom discussions, but they reflect the way in which issues
were clarified by the thorough consideration of conflicting points of view.
De veritate, however, which seems to have grown out of private disputa-
tions, was adapted, written up, and distributed very soon after the discus-
sions took place—a testimony to the vibrancy of intellectual life in Paris at
the time. The disputes took place sometime in the three years of Aquinas’s
first teaching period as a master in Paris, from 1256 to 1259.
Question 6 of De malo, which concerns us most here, seems to have a
history independent from the rest of the text; but its date, and its signifi-
cance in an argument about the development of Aquinas’s thought, remain
much disputed. Torrell places it a little before or after the Avveroist con-
demnations of December 1270. But Kevin Flannery argues that it is a much
earlier work than usually thought, from no later than 1259, and that parts
of De veritate 24:1 are in fact based on De malo 6.12
it is understood by me in one way and by you in another, that is, by another intelligible species.
And my act of understanding is one thing, and yours another”; Thomas Aquinas, “De Unitate
Intellectus Contra Averroistas,” in Sancti Thomae De Aquino Opera Omnia, vol. 43 (Rome: Edi-
tori di San Tonomaso, 1976), book 5, 312.
11. See Tugwell, “Thomas Aquinas: Introduction,” 248–55; Leonard E. Boyle, “The Setting of
the Summa Theologiae of St. Thomas—Revisited,” in The Ethics of Aquinas, ed. Stephen J. Pope
(Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2002), 2–9; and Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas,
60–65, 145–55, and 202–4. I often suggest in this book that Aquinas “writes” something or other,
but in fact works such as the Summa was spoken in dictation to one of Aquinas’s secretaries.
12. See Torrell, St Thomas Aquinas, 336; and Kevin L. Flannery, Acts Amid Precepts (Edin-
burgh: T & T Clark, 2001), 247–49.
introduction = 5
There is still disagreement about the exact times and places of com-
position of the various parts of the Summa theologiae. Of the two parts
that concern us (Part 1a, the Prima Pars—the first part; and Part 1a2ae,
the Prima Secundae—the first part of the second part), the Prima Pars was
probably begun in Rome in 1265 or 1266 and completed by the time Aqui-
nas left for Paris in late 1268 to begin his second regency there. The early
sections of the Prima Secundae may have been taught in Rome, but they
were probably not written up before Aquinas arrived in Paris. Torrell ac-
cepts R.-A. Gauthier’s textual argument that the Prima Secundae was not
written before 1271 since it draws heavily on a translation of Aristotle’s
Rhetoric that was not available to Aquinas before the end of 1270.13
Whatever the exact details of its provenance, the Summa marks a de-
cisive shift in Aquinas’s approach to teaching theology. Moving to Rome
in the autumn of 1265, to the community of Santa Sabina on the Aventine
Hill, he was given the task of setting up a studium for students from vari-
ous Dominican houses around the province as they prepared for priest-
hood and the Dominican apostolate. He was free to devise a curriculum of
his own, and free to break out of the narrow tradition of practical (moral)
theology that formed the heart of clerical studies at that time. The Summa
was designed to introduce beginners to theology in an orderly, intelligible,
and interesting way. He abandoned the traditional practice of basing his
own teaching on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, and decided to give his
teaching a “dogmatic” or “systematic” theological structure. The moral or
anthropological part of the whole, the Secunda Pars, is thus prefaced by a
theological section on God, the Trinity, and Creation, and is rounded off
with a third Christological section on the Son of God, the Incarnation, and
the Sacraments. The study of the Christian life is given its proper theo-
logical context. Human beings are created by God, and only return to him
through the grace of Christ and the sacraments.14 The proper organiza-
tion of the Summa, as Ignatius Eschmann has emphasized, is understood
through the various prologues that punctuate the text.15 And so at the be-
24. Bradley, Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good: Reason and Human Happiness in Aqui-
nas’s Moral Science, 399–400.
25. Kenny, “Aquinas on Aristotelian Happiness,” 24. This ambiguity is carried into Catholic
moral theology in the debate about whether we can have a natural desire for a supernatural end.
For the issues involved, particularly as they are stirred up by proponents of the so-called new
natural law theory, see Benedict M. Ashley, ”What Is the End of the Human Person? The Vision
of God and Integral Human Fulfillment,” in Moral Truth and Moral Tradition: Essays in Honour
of Peter Geach and Elizabeth Anscombe, ed. Luke Gormally (Dublin: Four Courts Press, 1994).
introduction = 9
26. For a brief account of the events, and for references to some of the secondary litera-
ture, see Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, 298–304.
27. See Gerald A. McCool, “Is Thomas’ Way of Philosophizing Still Viable Today?,” Pro-
ceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 64 (1990): 2–9.
28. For accounts of divergent twentieth-century interpretations of Aquinas, see the six es-
says in part 3 of Stephen J. Pope, ed., The Ethics of Aquinas (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown
University Press, 2002), 355–455.
29. Kerr, After Aquinas: Versions of Thomism, 14.
10 = i n t r o d u c t i o n
Meudon. They moved back to Paris, then to La Rochelle (with his new
stepfather), and eventually settled in Paris in 1920. Sartre entered the pres-
tigious École Normale Supérieure in 1924 where he settled on philoso-
phy as his major interest. He taught philosophy in various places at lycée
level for most of the 1930s. He was conscripted at the beginning of the war,
captured, and sent to prisoner-of-war camp—from which he escaped in
1941 by posing as a civilian. He taught at another lycée in Paris for the next
three years. The rest of his life was spent as the archetypal French intellec-
tual: writing, editing, teaching, debating, lecturing, talking, traveling, cam-
paigning, resisting. The royalties from his books saved him having to take
a paid university teaching post, so he had an enormous amount of social
and intellectual freedom. He died in 1980.
Sartre was not a religious person, although he became more open to
religious questions at the end of his life. He had the distinction of having
his works put on the Index of prohibited books by the Catholic Church in
1948. He was baptized a few weeks after his birth at the church of Notre-
Dame de Grâce in Passy, presumably under the influence of his maternal
grandmother who was Catholic. He had a nominally Catholic upbringing,
and though he didn’t go to mass regularly, Sartre’s clearest childhood “reli-
gious” memories were of being taken to hear organ music in St. Sulpice or
the cathedral of Notre-Dame. He certainly knew Catholic priests well over
the years: Stalag XII D, for example, his prisoner-of-war camp at Trèves,
was full of priests, and as a writer and teacher he formed a natural bond
with them, joining in their Gregorian plainsong rehearsals, and teaching
them the ins and outs of Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit.
The subtitle to Sartre’s great work Being and Nothingness is “An Essay
on Phenomenological Ontology,” and he stands firmly in the phenomeno-
logical tradition of philosophy. In the last years of the nineteenth century
the work of Henri Bergson and Maurice Blondel anticipated certain as-
pects of the Husserlian outlook, so there was a kind of receptivity to Ger-
man phenomenology among French thinkers. Husserl thus received a slow
but favorable reception in France during the late 1920s and early 1930s, and
was welcomed as someone who could develop themes present implicitly in
French philosophy.35
35. See Christian Dupont, “Receptions of Phenomenology in French Philosophy and Reli-
gious Thought, 1889–1939” (Ph.D. dissertation, University of Notre Dame, 1997), 10–22.
12 = i n t r o d u c t i o n
40. See esp. Michel Rybalka, Oreste F. Pucciani, and Susan Gruenheck, “An Interview with
Jean-Paul Sartre,” in The Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre, ed. Paul A. Schilpp, The Library of Liv-
ing Philosophers Vol. 16 (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1981); William Ralph Schroeder, Sartre and
His Predecessors: The Self and the Other (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984); Thomas W.
Busch, The Power of Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in Sartre’s Philosophy (Bloom-
ington: Indiana University Press, 1990); Dupont, “Receptions of Phenomenology in French Phi-
losophy and Religious Thought, 1889–1939,” esp. 212–45; and Herbert Spiegelberg, The Phenome-
nological Movement, 3rd ed. (The Hague, The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982), esp. 473–501.
41. See Ronald Aronson, Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosophy in the World (London: Verso, 1980),
30; and Hayman, Writing Against: A Biography of Sartre, 186.
42. See Adrian Mirvish, “Sartre on Perception and the World,” Journal of the British So-
ciety for Phenomenology 14 (1983), esp. 160–67, and “Sartre and the Gestaltists,” Journal of the
British Society for Phenomenology 11 (1980).
43. See Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement, 485.
44. He later attributed his reluctance to familiarize himself with Kierkegaard’s work to the
14 = i n t r o d u c t i o n
of Hegel, although it seems that he only took Hegel up in a serious way af-
ter the war.45
The three dominant influences on his thought are undoubtedly Des-
cartes, Heidegger, and Husserl. Descartes was the intellectual starting point
in his formal studies.46 He corrected and built on this foundation but never
abandoned it: the idea of the cogito, of a consciousness conscious of itself,
questioning itself, and the liberty that comes with this self-questioning.
Doubt, as he wrote in his essay on Cartesian freedom, is what brings about
the power of escaping, disengaging oneself, and withdrawing; it is the basis
of humanism. No one before Descartes, Sartre believed, had stressed this
connection between negativity and free will.47 Ronald Hayman has writ-
ten that Sartre never forgave Heidegger for not taking consciousness as the
starting point of philosophy: “Underneath Sartre’s radicalism is a bedrock
of Cartesian conservatism.”48
Sartre had been acquainted with Heidegger’s philosophy at least since
his time in Berlin, but a serious study only began later in the 1930s.49 Sar-
tre certainly seized upon Heidegger for some of his insights, and in the
heyday of postwar existentialism their names were often linked. But by the
time of writing Being and Nothingness the differences between the two had
become more apparent. Heidegger becomes a kind of foil for Sartre, who
criticizes his focus on Dasein and his lack of attention to the constructive
role of consciousness and subjectivity. Heidegger, likewise, in his Letter on
Humanism,50 which was in part a response to Sartre’s 1945 lecture “Exis-
spelling of his name: “Before then [1939–40] I knew he existed, but he was only a name for me
and, for some reason, I did not like the name. Because of the double a, I think ..... That kept
me from reading him”; see Rybalka, Pucciani, and Gruenheck, “An Interview with Jean-Paul
Sartre,” 10.
45. See ibid., 9–10.
46. See Aronson, Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosophy in the World, 31; and Busch, The Power of
Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in Sartre’s Philosophy, 1–2, 5–7.
47. Translated as Jean-Paul Sartre, “Cartesian Freedom,” in Literary and Philosophical Es-
says (New York: Collier Books, 1962).
48. Hayman, Writing Against: A Biography of Sartre, 189.
49. See Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement, 473–501; Michel Haar, “Sartre and
Heidegger,” in Jean Paul Sartre: Contemporary Approaches to His Philosophy, ed. Hugh J. Silver-
man and Frederick A. Elliston (Pittsburgh, Pa.: Duquesne University Press, 1980); and Francis
Jeanson, Sartre and the Problem of Morality, trans. Robert V. Stone (Bloomington: Indiana Uni-
versity Press, 1980), 80–82.
50. Reprinted in English translation in Martin Heidegger, Basic Writings (San Francisco:
HarperSanFrancisco, 1993).
i n t r o d u c t i o n = 15
51. First published in French in 1946; for an English translation, see Jean-Paul Sartre, “Ex-
istentialism and Humanism,” in Jean-Paul Sartre: Basic Writings, ed. Stephen Priest (London:
Routledge, 2001).
52. See Busch, The Power of Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in Sartre’s Phi-
losophy, 3–4; Dupont, “Receptions of Phenomenology in French Philosophy and Religious
Thought, 1889–1939,” 212–19, 35–45; and Thompson and Thompson, Sartre: Life and Works,
26–29.
53. Jean-Paul Sartre, “Intentionality: A Fundamental Idea of Husserl’s Phenomenology,”
Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 1, no. 2 (1970). The essay was written in the pe-
riod 1933–1934 but not published until 1939.
16 = i n t r o d u c t i o n
doubts about the initial effect Husserl had on Sartre’s thinking, and the
continuing force he exerted on his philosophical development.
54. For rich collections of essays that reveal many of the different approaches taken to Sar-
tre over recent decades, see Hugh J. Silverman and Frederick A. Elliston, Jean-Paul Sartre: Con-
temporary Approaches to His Philosophy (Pittsburgh, Pa.: Duquesne University Press, 1980);
Paul Arthur Schilpp, The Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre, The Library of Living Philosophers,
Vol. 16 (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1981); Robert Wilcocks, ed., Critical Essays on Jean-Paul Sar-
tre (Boston: G. K. Hall, 1988); Ronald Aronson and Adrian Van den Hoven, Sartre Alive (De-
troit, Mich.: Wayne State University Press, 1991); and Christina Howells, ed., The Cambridge
Companion to Sartre (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992).
55. See the section “The Objective Resistance of the World” in chapter 3 below; and M.
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1962), esp. part 3. The work was first published in French in 1945. On the differences be-
tween Merleau-Ponty and Sartre, see Monika Langer, “Sartre and Merleau-Ponty: A Reapprais-
al,” in The Philosophy of Jean Paul Sartre, ed. Paul A. Schilpp (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1981);
Jeanson, Sartre and the Problem of Morality, 187; and Hubert L. Dreyfus and Piotr Hoffman,
“Sartre’s Changed Conception of Consciousness: From Lucidity to Opacity,” in The Philosophy
of Jean Paul Sartre, ed. Paul A. Schilpp (La Salle: Open Court, 1981).
56. Herbert Marcuse, “Existentialism: Remarks on Jean-Paul Sartre’s ‘L’être et le néant,’ ”
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 8 (1948): 322. See the section “The Persistence of
Existential Freedom” in chapter 5 below.
i n t r o d u c t i o n = 17
57. A. J. Ayer, “Novelist-Philosophers: V. Jean-Paul Sartre,” Horizon 12 (1945): 19; and Phyl-
lis Sutton Morris, Sartre’s Concept of a Person: An Analytic Approach (Amherst: University of
Massachusetts Press, 1976), 24–25.
58. See the section “Consciousness and Intentionality” in chapter 1 below.
59. Jean-Paul Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Conscious-
ness, trans. Forrest Williams and Robert Kirkpatrick (New York: Hill & Wang, 1957). See the in-
troductory essay by his translators, Forrest Williams and Robert Kirkpatrick.
60. Peter Caws, Sartre, The Arguments of the Philosophers (London, Boston, and Henley,
U.K.: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979), 52–60.
61. Herbert Spiegelberg, “Husserl’s Phenomenology and Sartre’s Existentialism,” in The
Context of the Phenomenological Movement (The Hague, The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff,
1981), at 60.
18 = i n t r o d u c t i o n
62. Thomas W. Busch, “Sartre’s Use of the Reduction: Being and Nothingness Reconsid-
ered,” in Jean-Paul Sartre: Contemporary Approaches to His Philosophy, ed. Hugh J. Silverman
and Frederick A. Elliston (Pittsburgh, Pa.: Duquesne University Press, 1980), 28.
63. James M. Edie, “The Roots of the Existentialist Theory of Freedom in ‘Ideas I,’ ” Husserl
Studies 1 (1984): 245–50; and James M. Edie, “The Question of the Transcendental Ego: Sartre’s
Critique of Husserl,” Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 24 (1993): 105–15.
64. See Leo Fretz, “Individuality in Sartre’s Philosophy,” in The Cambridge Companion to
Sartre, ed. Christina Howells (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 71–83; and Rhi-
annon Goldthorpe, “Sartre and the Self: Discontinuity or Continuity?,” American Catholic Phil-
osophical Quarterly 70, no. 4 (1996): 525–30.
65. See, e.g., Jean-Paul Sartre, “The Itinerary of a Thought,” in Between Existentialism and
Marxism (New York: Pantheon Books, 1974), 44.
i n t r o d u c t i o n = 19
Howells warns us against thinking that in the later Sartre human beings
are dissolved into the structures that traverse them. She quotes Sartre’s own
contention that human beings must maintain “the perpetually resolved
and perpetually renewed contradiction between man-as-producer and
man-as-product, in each individual and at the heart of each multiplicity.”68
In Sartre’s later works we are conditioned all the way down, and respon-
sibility is now more about identifying and integrating the many anteced-
ent influences that have conditioned us than abandoning them. But the re-
sponsibility remains, and within our conditioning we are free agents, able
to assume and make something of that conditioning, and not merely ve-
hicles for inhuman forces operating through us.69 So Sartre develops but
does not repudiate his phenomenological ontology.
66. Christina Howells, “Conclusion: Sartre and the Deconstruction of the Subject,” in The
Cambridge Companion to Sartre, ed. Christina Howells (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1992), 337.
67. Jean-Paul Sartre, Situations IX (Paris: Gallimard, 1972), 102–3.
68. Howells, “Conclusion: Sartre and the Deconstruction of the Subject,” 342.
69. See David A. Jopling, “Sartre’s Moral Psychology,” in The Cambridge Companion to Sar-
tre, ed. Christina Howells (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), esp. 105–8 and 130.
Part One
H u ma n B e i n g
Chapter 1
I d e n t i t y a n d H u m a n I n co m p l e t io n
in Sartre
23
24 = h u m a n b e i n g
view, that we act in a certain way because of our identity and the objective
demands we meet. Rather, it is by acting in a certain way that we establish a
particular identity and allow a certain set of demands to guide our action.
Instead of saying “He runs away because he is a coward,” we should say “He
is a coward because he runs away.” Instead of saying “I get out of bed because
I have to be at the office in an hour,” we should say “It is by getting out of bed
that I turn the possibility of going to work into an obligation.” These descrip-
tions are counterintuitive and may seem forced; they may even strike some
readers as patently false. Surely, to take one of the other examples, she is a
qualified doctor, whether she treats the patient or not. Surely the cup is dirty,
whether he washes it or not. I hope to clarify in this chapter what Sartre does
and doesn’t mean by his awkward inversion of everyday language. He wants
to show that our freely chosen actions establish our identity and give force
to certain demands. Our commitments allow us to become people we might
not have become and illuminate a set of priorities that might have remained
obscure. We are not slaves to our being but creators of our existence.
In his reflections on action Sartre goes to the very heart of what it is to
be human. He shows that our free actions are not the consequence of our
identity, they are its foundation, and it is our nature as human beings al-
ways to go beyond who we are toward a freely chosen self. In this chapter
we will examine the ambiguity of human identity that arises because of the
nature of human consciousness as being-for-itself. Then we will be in a po-
sition to understand how human beings create imaginative possibilities for
themselves and choose to pursue certain of these possibilities, thus estab-
lishing their identity as persons.
1. BN is subtitled “An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology.” Its four parts deal with “The
Problem of Nothingness” (negation, bad faith, etc.), “Being-for-Itself ” (presence to self, factic-
i d e n t i t y i n s a r t r e = 25
merable facts about our life that we have not chosen.2 These make up the
contingency of our being, the sense in which our life is given, discovered,
inherited, and dependent on circumstances outside our control. We are
bodily creatures, in a certain time and place, with a personal history, living
in certain conditions. There are many undeniable facts about our individual
psychology. Sartre lists the various characteristics, habits, states, etc., that
make up the psychic unity of our ego.3 These include not only latent quali-
ties that inform our behavior (such as industriousness, jealousy, ambition)
and actual states that embody a certain behavior (such as loving or hating),
but also a whole pattern of acts. Our acts manifest the unified purposes of
the psyche as they are embodied in the world. Human acts take on a kind of
objectivity and our purposes unfold with some continuity: boxers train, sci-
entists do research, artists create their work, politicians campaign.
Our individual facticity is itself dependent on a particular language,
a concrete community, a political structure, and on being part of the hu-
man species.4 We are, in other words, natural and cultural beings who at
no point determine the conditions and facts of our being. If we need this
complex environment in order to have an identity, we also need relation-
ships with other people in order to comprehend our own identity. It is
through the mediation of others that we can apprehend ourselves. We ap-
preciate ourselves in a new way, for example, when we are known or de-
sired or loved. “I recognize I am as the other [autrui] sees me”5; “I see my-
self because somebody sees me.”6
In these different ways Sartre reveals an immensely rich understanding
of all that makes up an individual human life, and concerns himself deeply
with questions of sociology, culture, language, psychology, and human re-
lations. All of this makes up the facticity of our being, the givenness of our
unique human identity. We should remember throughout this chapter that
Sartre never denies that human beings have an essence: “Essence is every-
thing about the human being which we can indicate by the words: that is.”7
For each human being, “certain original structures are invariable.”8
ity, temporality, knowledge, etc.), “[Being] For-Others” (the look, the body, relationships, etc.),
and “Having, Doing, and Being” (freedom, psychoanalysis, etc.).
2. BN 79–84; EN 115–20/122–27. 3. BN 162–70; EN 197–206/209–18.
4. BN 509–31; EN 554–76/591–615. 5. BN 222; EN 260/222.
6. BN 260; EN 299/318. 7. BN 35; EN 70/72.
8. BN 456; EN 500/532.
26 = h u m a n b e i n g
9. He was afraid that a so-called Aristotelian philosophy of essence would involve the to-
tal determination of the individual, but in fact his own view is compatible with an Aristotelian
theory of natural kinds. For Sartre’s suspicions about Aristotelianism, see Thomas C. Ander-
son, “Sartre and Human Nature,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70, no. 4 (1996).
For the compatibility of Sartre and Aristotle, see M. Qizilbash, “Aristotle and Sartre on the Hu-
man Condition: Lack, Responsibility and the Desire to Be God,” Angelaki 3, no. 1 (1998); and
Frederick A. Olafson, Principles and Persons: An Ethical Interpretation of Existentialism (Balti-
more, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1967), 87–88.
10. BN 30–32; EN 65–67/67–69.
i d e n t i t y i n s a r t r e = 27
ward steadily on the basis of who we are, but now and then we are struck
by a parallel awareness that we could be someone else.
The experience of vertigo is one form of anguish: we realize that we
cannot guarantee the perpetuation of the motives that have influenced
us up to this point. Identity is not a straight-jacket, it does not predeter-
mine the future. At this moment, halfway along the dangerous path, we
may feel confident; but in a few steps, who knows what we might do? “If
nothing compels me to save my life, nothing prevents me from precipitat-
ing myself into the abyss. The decisive conduct will emanate from a me [un
moi] which I am not yet.”11 Normally, of course, most people finish their
walk safely. Sartre wants us to realize that the decision to walk carefully is
not determined by our identity; instead, it is the decision itself that deter-
mines our identity and ensures that we continue to be people who want to
live. It’s a subtle distinction, the importance of which will become more
apparent.
The second example of anguish is the reformed gambler.12 This person
has sincerely decided never to gamble again. He has taken a firm resolu-
tion to quit. He considers himself to be a reformed gambler, and he relies
on this identity to get him through the temptations that come his way. Yet
now, as he nears the gaming table, his resolution melts away.
What he apprehends then in anguish is precisely the total inefficacy of the past
resolution. It is there, doubtless, but fixed, ineffectual, surpassed [dépassée] by
the very fact that I am conscious of it. The resolution is still me to the extent that
I realize constantly my identity with myself across the temporal flux, but it is no
longer me—due to the fact that it has become an object for my consciousness. I
am not subject to it, it fails in the mission which I have given to it.13
11. Sartre often oscillates between the first and third person; see BN 32; EN 67/69.
12. BN 32–33; EN 67–69/69–71. 13. BN 33; EN 68/70.
28 = h u m a n b e i n g
The cliff walker is anguished because he can’t ensure that his present
resolution to live will survive all the way along the path; the gambler is an-
guished because his past resolution not to gamble isn’t sustaining him in the
present. For both characters, their very consciousness of an identity comes
with a corresponding detachment as they realize that they are not bound by
it. By searching for reasons, they objectify them and make them ineffective.
This realization is what paralyzes Matthieu in Sartre’s novel The Age of Rea-
son. He wants to justify his actions and base them on good reasons, or at
least on some overwhelming desire, but by interrogating these motives, by
trying to establish whether they are compelling, he distances himself from
them. The process of examining them shows they have no binding power
over his future; the search for obligations leads him to freedom because it
uncovers the fact that alternative courses of action are also viable.14
However strong it seems, the price of being conscious of an identity is
a corresponding liberation from that identity, and an ever-present respon-
sibility for continuing or denying that identity. We experience this respon-
sibility through anguish. This is not just a point about the fact that our
identities change for various reasons, since anguish does not come about
when a past identity is forgotten and a new one adopted. Instead, anguish
is a sign that human beings are separated from themselves, from the very
identities that constitute who they are now. We can review the present and
not just the past. We have a continual responsibility to re-create our iden-
tity through our choices.
Sartre’s examples may seem extreme: we are not often paralyzed by
vertigo or struggling with addiction. The reader may suspect that he is de-
liberately choosing to examine situations that lie outside our normal ex-
perience of deliberating and acting, moments of high drama or psychopa-
thology. Anguish, perhaps, should be confined to the world of the novelist
or the consulting rooms of the psychiatrist. There are a few brief responses
to this. First, it is often only in moments of crisis or difficulty or extremity
that we appreciate the fragility of our own identity. Second, such moments
may not occur often in the life of any individual, but they seem to occur in
some form to most human beings, and in this sense Sartre’s examples have
a wide applicability. Third, the heightened sensitivity we have in extraor-
dinary situations can give us a greater appreciation for what is happening
14. Jean-Paul Sartre, The Age of Reason (London: Penguin Books, 2001).
i d e n t i t y i n s a r t r e = 29
in ordinary life. Sartre believes that in theory we can stop at any moment
and reflect in this way. Aquinas, in a similar vein, will use murder, adul-
tery, and shipwreck to exemplify universal aspects of the process of human
deliberation. Fourth, if in the most ordinary of circumstances we were to
have an experience of anguish, this experience would actually make those
circumstances seem extraordinary. Anguish by definition undermines our
identity and disrupts our world, so even if we chose examples that were set
safely within the confines of mundane human behavior they would never-
theless prove to be unusual and disruptive. In other words, it is impossible
to talk about a routine experience of anguish since anguish necessarily un-
dercuts our routine.
There are many ways of trying to avoid the responsibility for ourselves
that comes with anguish. In Sartre’s scheme they all come under the head-
ing of la mauvaise foi (“bad faith” or “self-deception”). For our purposes
the most instructive type of bad faith is la sincérité (“sincerity”). This is a
technical term in Sartre’s vocabulary. It is the attempt to be who we are,
to make our life match our identity, to conform our external actions with
our supposed inner reality.15 Sartre’s first example is a little misleading: the
café waiter who tries so hard to make the right gestures and voices that he
seems awkward and patronizing.16 We might say that he is simply not be-
ing a good waiter, but Sartre is interested in the way he strains too hard to
match his actions with some conception of who he is. The real contradic-
tion lies in his desire to make himself what he believes himself to be. “What
are we then if we have the constant obligation to make ourselves what we
are, if our mode of being is having the obligation to be what we are?”17 The
ideal of sincerity, to be what one is, “supposes that I am not originally what
I am.”18 So as soon as we spot whatever “essential” aspect of our being it is
that we want to achieve, we realize that we are neither identified with this
nor bound by it. To explain or excuse our behavior with reference to “who
we are” is already to put some distance between our present actions and
the past “identity” that supposedly caused it. We stake a claim to a “self ”
(soi) and immediately betray our distance from it.
15. A better translation might be “genuine,” which has the connotation of matching up to
what we really are—in contemporary English the word “sincere” implies simply wanting to tell
the truth.
16. BN 59–60; EN 94–95/98–100. 17. BN 59; EN 93–94/98.
18. BN 62; EN 97/102.
30 = h u m a n b e i n g
Total, constant sincerity as a constant effort to adhere to oneself [à soi] is by na-
ture a constant effort to dissociate oneself from oneself [se désolidariser de soi].
One frees oneself from oneself by the very act by which one makes oneself an
object for oneself [On se libère de soi par l’acte même par lequel on se fait objet
pour soi]. To draw up a perpetual inventory of what one is means constantly to
redeny oneself and to take refuge in a sphere where one is no longer anything
but a pure, free look [un pur et libre regard].19
Sartre summarizes this idea later in Being and Nothingness concluding with
one of his most misunderstood phrases:
By the sole fact that I am conscious of the motives which inspire my action,
these motives are already transcendent objects for my consciousness; they are
outside. In vain shall I seek to catch hold of them; I escape them by my very ex-
istence. I am condemned to exist forever beyond my essence, beyond the moti-
vations and motives of my act. I am condemned to be free.25
The language may sound overblown (there is not much difference between
saying “I am free” or “I am always free” and “I am condemned to be free”),
but the truth conveyed is clear: if we are conscious of and present to any
aspect of our identity, then it loses its hold over us and we have to choose
how to respond to it. It’s important to remember that Sartre does not deny
that human beings have an essence, he simply denies that this essence can
be enough to determine our choices. It is in this significant but limited
sense that we are forever beyond our essence.
We should clear up some possible misunderstandings at this stage.
First, Sartre never imagines that anguish is present within all our activities.
He acknowledges that in most everyday situations we are acting without
anguish; we are usually caught up in things without much reflection, tak-
ing for granted a certain identity and certain goals.26 Even in the midst of
the most spontaneous or habitual act, however, “there remains the possi-
bility of putting this act into question.”27
Second, there is no suggestion that our identity is cut off from a world
of causes and influences. Take the café waiter: He may avoid sincerity and
freely choose what to make of his life and his role. Yet his starting point is
that he is a café waiter—this is the facticity of his situation, and it makes
the drama of realizing what it means for him to be a waiter quite different
from “the drama pure and simple” (i.e., without any facts to ground it) of
pretending to be a diplomat or a sailor when he is not.28 However we re-
spond to the facticity of our essence, it remains present to us as a factual
necessity even if we reconstruct it through our decisions about how to act.
Third, Sartre does not think that everything human beings do is within
their control. He would accept that many “actions” that human beings “do”
are involuntary (we hiccup, sleepwalk, blush), many are instinctive (we
eat when we are hungry, we smash things in anger, we run from danger),
many unfold almost unconsciously (we drive with astounding skill while
on a kind of mental autopilot, we sing a song without paying it much at-
tention), and many have unforeseen consequences. He notes, for example,
that “the careless smoker who has through negligence caused the explosion
of a powder magazine has not acted.”29 Sartre simply says that sometimes
we are conscious that an action is ours, conscious that there are alternative
courses of action. The fact that we can take a view on certain actions, that
we can deliberate and decide between alternative possibilities, shows that
in these cases we are free to determine the course of our action. Only a de-
liberated act such as this can be an acte humain, a “human act.”30
Fourth, Sartre’s argument is not undermined by someone insisting that
this experience of detachment and freedom is just an illusion: “You think
you are free, but really everything is determined, and even your belief in
freedom is psychologically determined.” Sartre’s method is phenomeno-
logical. He starts with human experience and tries to clarify what is found
within that experience. In this case, we do not experience a psychological
belief that “we are detached and free,” some stubborn conviction that would
form the basis of our philosophy. Rather, we experience the detachment it-
self. It is not a conclusion or an implication. Anguish is the very experi-
ence of being unable to identify with our presumed identity, of being at a
distance from who we are, of having to choose without adequate grounds
for choosing, of having to be free. This is the starting point of Sartre’s phe-
nomenology, the original data on which his philosophy is built. It does not
reveal a prejudice in favor of freedom. On the contrary, to insist that all hu-
man actions are determined would be to impose a prejudice on the data of
experience and contradict it. This prejudice would be a form of bad faith.
tions about the nature of thought or the thinker. Sartre believes, however,
that he has a significant disagreement to make. Husserl postulates a “tran-
scendental ego,” an “I” or subject that stands behind consciousness, mak-
ing it possible and unifying it. For Sartre and others this was a betrayal of
intentionality. It is an unnecessary return to idealism; it renders objects
and their characteristics dependent on the activity of the ego; and it calls
for some third reality to mediate between ego and world.
Instead, insists Sartre, consciousness is simply the sheer activity of tran-
scending toward objects. There are no intermediary mental entities within
consciousness or between it and the world. It is, as Thomas Busch puts it,
a category mistake to apply the mode of object relations and causality to
a transcendental consciousness that is an act rather than an object.48 All
content is on the side of the object,49 and even the things we know about
ourselves as subjects (in general or in particular), even “the psychic and
psycho-physical me [moi psychique et psycho-psychique],” are objects for
consciousness.50 This is why Sartre allows for a transcendent ego (which
can be an object of our awareness) but not a transcendental ego (which
would account for and determine the awareness itself). “The conscious-
ness which says ‘I think’ is precisely not the consciousness which thinks.”51
Therefore “the transcendental field becomes impersonal; or, if you like,
‘pre-personal,’ without an I [sans Je].”52 The unity of consciousness is given
by the unity and permanence of the transcendent object, whatever it is, not
by a unifying ego. A section from the conclusion of The Transcendence of
the Ego expresses this very clearly.
48. Busch, The Power of Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in Sartre’s Philoso-
phy, 9.
49. Kathleen Wider sees similarities between Sartre’s and Wittgenstein’s view of the self,
which is a limit for the world, a formal condition for its possibility. “For Wittgenstein you can
describe the world completely, give all the propositions of natural science, state all meaningful
propositions, and still there is something left over—a something that is nothing and so cannot
be spoken of but can be shown. What is left over is the metaphysical self.” See Kathleen Wider,
“A Nothing about Which Something Can Be Said: Sartre and Wittgenstein on the Self,” in Sartre
Alive, ed. Ronald Aronson and Adrian Van den Hoven (Detroit, Mich.: Wayne State University
Press, 1991), 337. Wittgenstein writes: “This is the way I have travelled: Idealism singles men out
from the world as unique, solipsism singles me out alone, and at last I see that I too belong with
the rest of the world, and so on the one side nothing is left over, on the other side, as unique, the
world. In this way idealism leads to realism if it is strictly thought out.” See Ludwig Wittgenstein,
Notebooks, 1914–1916, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, 2nd ed. (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979), 85e.
50. TE 36 [18]. 51. TE 45 [28].
52. TE 36 [19].
i d e n t i t y i n s a r t r e = 37
The Transcendental Field, purified of all egological structure, recovers its primary
transparency. In a sense, it is a nothing, since all physical, psycho-physical, and
psychic objects, all truths, all values are outside it; since my Me has itself ceased to
be any part of it. But this nothing is all since it is consciousness of all these objects.
There is no longer an “inner life” [.....] because there is no longer anything which
is an object and which can at the same time partake of the intimacy of conscious-
ness. Doubts, remorse, the so-called “mental crises of consciousness,” etc.—in
short, all the content of intimate diaries—become simple representations.53
In Being and Nothingness Sartre calls this conscience (de) soi, “conscious-
ness (of) self ”63—putting the “of ” in parentheses to show that this “self ”
is not an explicit object of knowledge, nor merely an implicit condition of
consciousness, but rather the implicit consciousness that accompanies and
is one with any consciousness of an object. In English one is able to use
the word “self ” as a prefix and say “self-consciousness” which conveniently
lessens the danger of considering this “self ” to be an object. It may seem
that immediate self-awareness is revealed through reflection and a kind of
questioning introspection. However, “it is the non-reflective consciousness
59. BN xxviii; EN 18/18. 60. BN xxix; EN 19/19.
61. BN xxix; EN 19/19. 62. TE 40 [23–24].
63. BN xxx; EN 20/20.
i d e n t i t y i n s a r t r e = 39
So these are the two senses in which negation exists in the heart of
human beings. First, there is no subject of experience, there is just con-
sciousness of something. This is open, transparent, empty. Second, even
though we are conscious (of) being conscious, in an implicit way, we can
never know or identify with the one who is conscious; we are immediately
present to ourselves and our experience, and at the same time immediately
withdrawn from them. Without reflection, our attention is directed out-
ward, to objects, away from ourselves, with an implicit awareness of our-
selves as conscious subjects; in reflection, our attention is directed to the
process of attention, which thus becomes an object.
As conscious beings we are fractured, without a stable identity, distant
from ourselves, and this inner negation allows us to be conscious and to
act. What then remains? One could argue that in Sartre’s account there is
nothing left of the subject at all, there is just the world-as-experienced. We
are so identified with the world that no comments or criticisms are possi-
ble. There is no human experience. Being and Nothingness, however, has a
rich understanding of the human subject, which is constituted in the pro-
cess of going beyond and reinterpreting the self to which we are present.
This brings us to concept of l’être-pour-soi, being-for-itself.71
The key to Sartre’s understanding is his contention that there is an iden-
tity that is denied.72 This is quite different from saying that there is no hu-
man identity. We have seen how Sartre pays full attention to the numer-
ous aspects of each human life which make up an individual identity, the
extensive catalogue of answers we could give to the question “Who am I?”
But he insists that no aspect of our identity can exist as ours unless we have
some distance from it. Affirmation always involves taking a point of view
on what is affirmed. Sartre was delighted to discover Heidegger’s descrip-
“Presence” here is the very thing that saves the human being from an ossi-
fied identity, and is therefore quite different from that metaphysical “pres-
ence” attacked by Derrida, a presence that he thought reduced us to be-
ing one “being” among other beings.82 Sartre’s presence to self destabilizes
and decenters the subject since it places us perpetually at one remove from
who we are, without creating an alternative center of stability.
One question arises: Why is Sartre’s language so absolute and so neg-
ative? Is this an example of what Peter Caws has called “that peculiar
taste for philosophical melodrama which has so alienated sceptical An-
glo-Saxons from their excitable Continental colleagues,”83 which incited
A. J. Ayer famously to accuse Sartre of trickery and nonsense as early as
1945?84 Would it not be possible to use more nuanced verbs to describe
this distance from our identity? Instead of an identity being denied and
fragmented and nihilated, why could it not be qualified or limited or put
tion; every sensation, every event, every encounter, reveals its own fullness.
What, then, enables us to go beyond the purity and plenitude of our present
experience and wonder what it is not? Sartre concludes that negation must
come from ourselves: we reveal the negation that lies hidden in things. He
associates the power to negate with our imagination, and he locates the
source of that power in the negative structure of our consciousness.
It would be impossible to summarize Sartre’s thinking about negation
in a few pages—the relevant passages of Being and Nothingness contain
some of his most complex ideas.93 It will be enough to highlight one im-
portant observation that has already been made: human beings are able
to conceive of what is not. This kind of conceiving, like so many things, is
more puzzling than we usually think. It requires an ability to detach our-
selves from what is and to think of something else as not existing. This is
implied in the simplest act of questioning.94 If we are simply caught up in
a stream of positive experiences, in a constant flow of positive informa-
tion telling us about the world, then how could we even ask a question? We
could do no more than affirm and acknowledge.
If we question, then we are not sure of the answer.95 Ignorance by it-
self is not an interesting phenomenon—it is knowledge of our ignorance
that provokes Sartre. This knowledge, this doubt, presupposes that we have
some kind of awareness that the world could surprise us. If we doubt, then
we must have some kind of expectation that the world could turn out to be
different from what we expect it to be.96 This everyday presupposition is of
huge significance since it means that we are often withdrawing from the
fullness of what is given to us and relating it to what is not. “It is important
therefore that the questioner have the permanent possibility of dissociat-
ing himself from the causal series which constitutes being and which can
93. Esp. BN part 1, 3–70; EN 37–106/37–111.
94. See esp. BN 21–25; EN 56–60/58–62.
95. Sartre’s analysis of interrogation is similar to Heidegger’s in Sein und Zeit, but Sartre is
more concerned with the possibility of a negative answer and the implications of this for the
relation of human beings to what is not. See Spiegelberg, The Phenomenological Movement,
505–6.
96. Sartre notes here his debt to Descartes (BN 25; EN 60/62) and acknowledges it more
fully in Jean-Paul Sartre, “Cartesian Freedom,” in Literary and Philosophical Essays (New York:
Collier Books, 1962), 190, where he writes that Cartesian doubt implies the “power of escaping,
disengaging oneself and withdrawing.” It is “a breaking of contact with being,” man’s “perma-
nent possibility of disentangling himself from the existing universe,” and “the most magnifi-
cent affirmation of the reign of the human.”
46 = h u m a n b e i n g
produce only being.”97 A negative reply tears us away from a wall of posi-
tivity that surrounds us, it is “an abrupt break in continuity which can not
in any case result from prior affirmations.”98 Notice that Sartre’s argument
does not assume that the answer to a question will be without explanation.
The answer may be a brute scientific fact with a perfectly comprehensible
network of causes—“There is no milk in the fridge”; “It’s three o’clock in
the morning.” What confirms our withdrawal from the causal series is the
knowledge of our ignorance. The simplest question, the smallest doubt,
shows that the totality of our experience is not enough and forces us to re-
late that experience with what is not.
Being can generate only being and if human beings [l’homme] are enclosed in
this process of generation, only being will come out of them. If we are to assume
that human beings are able to question this process—i.e., to make it the object
of interrogation—they must be able to hold it up to view as a totality, i.e., to put
themselves outside of being [en dehors de l’être].99
In order to see the picture as a picture of Peter, it is not enough just to look
at the picture as it is; I have to imagine Peter as absent and allow the pic-
ture to become the means by which Peter appears to me as absent.105
Sartre’s persistent concern is to undermine theories that suffer from
the illusion of immanence.106 In these theories our relationship with the
world would be completely determined by the positive facts of what we
experience, by our perceptions; our consciousness would be passive and
“completely absorbed in its intuitions of the real,”107 “engulfed in the real,”
“enmired in the world.”108 If everything were immanent there would be no
way of accounting for the numerous ways in which we judge something
to be absent, relate something to what it is not, question something about
what it could be, and act for a future that does not yet exist. The imagina-
tion is this extraordinary human capacity to deal with what is not.109
102. BN 26; EN 61/63. 103. IM 12 [32].
104. IM 13 [34]. 105. IM 25 [54].
106. IM 12 [32]. 107. IM 208 [344].
108. IM 213 [353].
109. It is a philosophical concept, but Sartre’s attraction to this concept undoubtedly re-
flected as well the instincts of his own heart as a writer. As Ronald Hayman has written: “Like
Kafka, he never felt more free than when he was writing, creating an imaginary space. Paper as
magic carpet; pen as wand”; see Hayman, Writing Against: A Biography of Sartre, 7.
48 = h u m a n b e i n g
one thing (“the existing”) in terms of its relation to what it could be (“the
synthesis,” “the lacked”). We understand this bright crescent in the sky as
the moon because we relate it to our idea of the full moon; we can say that
the Venus de Milo statue is broken only because we relate it to a complete
statue of a human figure that includes both arms; we think our friend is a
coward only because we have some conception of the courage we believe
she could have. Judgments about value, however, also depend on the com-
parisons we make—comparisons that require us to go beyond the world as
it is given to us, as we find it. The value we seek, the new thing desired (the
“desideratum”), is indeed “an objective lack,”113 it is not some subjective
fancy imposed on a world unable to accept it; yet it is not present in the
world—it is the world insofar as the world is not what it could be.
Sartre gives some examples. The emperor Constantine wants to build
a new Rome in the eastern part of his empire.114 Why? Because in the old
Rome the taxes are collected badly, the city is insecure from invasions, its
position as a Mediterranean capital is impractical, and its morals are cor-
rupt. All these considerations are negative, they are value judgments about
what is lacking in the city with respect to an ideal city. Not one observable
fact forces Constantine to envisage this ideal, since “the most miserable
situation can by itself be designated only as it is, without any reference to
an ideal nothingness.”115 In itself Rome just has this position, this security,
these morals—no more. It is the dreams of the emperor that help him see
what is lacking in his city.
Sartre jumps from this example of a Roman emperor to that of a nine-
teenth-century French worker. Why does a certain worker not rise up in
protest against his oppressive working conditions? One reason, Sartre
says, is because his misfortunes seem natural, they seem to be an inevi-
table part of his condition and of his being. Suffering is not a demand that
calls to him and motivates him, it just is. “He suffers without considering
his suffering and without conferring value on it. To suffer and to be are one
and the same for him.”116 Consciousness of suffering as intolerable does
not emerge from the situation as he finds it, it only comes if he can con-
template it in relation to an ideal. This is the heart of Sartre’s inversion of
our commonsense view of values as things that exist plainly in the world.
Normally, we take certain values for granted and they have an unques-
tioned urgency. The momentum of our action confirms their relevance,
117. BN 435; EN 479/510.
118. Olafson suggests that Sartre has much in common here with G. E. Moore, who used
his “open question” argument against all forms of ethical naturalism. According to Moore, no
matter what “natural” properties a thing or situation may have, this leaves open the question
of whether it is good, whether it is valuable. He believed, however, that there are “nonnatural”
properties that settle evaluative questions. Sartre pushes the open question argument further
and shows that no property could possibly determine by itself the value of any thing or situa-
tion. See Olafson, Principles and Persons: An Ethical Interpretation of Existentialism, 126–27.
119. BN 437; EN 481/512. See chapter 5 for a proper discussion of motive and motivation.
120. BN 434–35; EN 478–79/509–10.
52 = h u m a n b e i n g
and our “acts cause values to spring up like partridges.”121 In the settled
world of the bourgeois, for example, a pattern of respectable behavior re-
inforces both one’s identity as bourgeois and the bourgeois values them-
selves. “Values are sown on my path as thousands of little real demands,
like signs which order us to keep off the grass.”122 Then we may realize that
these values have no foundation in the immediate being of the world, there
is nothing necessary about them. This is another instance of anguish. We
have to bring the values to light by envisaging an alternative world. “It fol-
lows that my freedom is the unique foundation of values and that nothing,
absolutely nothing, justifies me in adopting this or that particular scale of
values.”123 Lack, possibility, and value are all forms of negation that de-
pend on the fundamental negation within consciousness. “The condition
on which human reality can deny all or part of the world is that human re-
ality carry nothingness within itself as the nothing which separates its pres-
ent from all its past.”124
We can return to some of the examples already given. How can the an-
guished cliff walker both desire to be safe in the future and fear that he could
renounce this desire? Because “I am the one which I will be, in the mode of
not being it.”125 Why can’t the reformed gambler cling onto his resolution
definitively? Because “by the very fact of taking my position in existence as
consciousness of being, I make myself not to be the past of good resolutions
which I am [je me fais n’être pas ce passé de bonnes résolutions que je suis].”126
Consciousness confronts its past and its future as “facing a self which it is
in the mode of not-being.”127 The project of sincerity depends on an aware-
ness within our consciousness that we are not who we are, that is, that we
want to embrace an identity even while claiming that it already constitutes
us.128 The worker conscious of his oppression is able to take a new view on
his sufferings. “This implies for consciousness the permanent possibility of
effecting a rupture with its own past, of wrenching itself away from its own
past so as to be able to consider it in the light of a non-being.”129 In all these
ways, action implies negation, and negation depends on an inner fragmen-
tation, a lack of identity, a nothingness, within the human being.
We are able to hold any enterprise at a distance and question the values
we have been pursuing. In that moment of reflection we realize that there
is no necessity built into the world that requires us to get out of bed when
the alarm rings or do what the boss orders or finish the book we are writ-
ing or even feed the starving baby. Some values may seem to have a greater
immediacy or a more primal connection with our instinctive needs and
biological nature (to eat, to talk, to love .....), but all of them, if we reflect on
them, can be questioned and then affirmed or denied.
Sartre is not promoting lethargy, or moral anarchy, he is merely draw-
ing attention to the human foundation of value. We are not enslaved to the
values of the world, rather we are free to release them. To deny this is to
be sérieux (“serious”), a technical word that Sartre applies to anyone who
resides “in the reassuring, materialistic substantiation of values” (dans la
substantification rassurante et chosiste des valeurs) and pushes aside “a pri-
ori as impossible all enterprises in which [the person is] not engaged at the
moment.”130 There will be much more to say in chapter 3 about how values
are still objective, still real, but our concern here is just to appreciate the
part we play in establishing values, the anguish we feel when we discover
this, and the responsibility this calls us to.
are also more constructive and less polemical.132 There are two reflective
movements that make us persons. The first we have already dealt with at
great length: it is the presence to self of consciousness. In itself the ego (the
“me,” le moi; the “self,” le soi) is not the conscious subject but an object that
we are conscious of. As we have seen, nothing will constitute our identity
unless we are conscious of it. Personal existence is conferred partly by this
presence to ourselves, to the ego and all that we are. The second reflective
movement that makes us persons Sartre calls ipséité,133 for which Hazel
Barnes substitutes the term “selfness.” In selfness we become present not
only to the identity that we are, but also to the identity that we could be.
We understand ourselves in relation to a future identity that cannot be ad-
equately derived from or determined by who we are now. Our being is to
be present to what it is (through consciousness) and present-yet-absent to
what we could be but are not yet (through selfness). Just as consciousness
in the very structure of its being refers to an identity it denies, it also refers
to a possible future identity.
The for-itself is “self ” over there [Le pour-soi est soi là-bas], beyond its grasp,
in the far reaches of its possibilities. This free necessity of being—over there—
what one is in the form of lack is what constitutes selfness [l’ipséité] or the sec-
ond essential aspect of the person. In fact how can the person be defined if not
as a free relation to oneself [à soi]?134
132. Cf. the language about the impersonal and the prepersonal at TE 36 [19]. For an ac-
count of the shift in language from TE to BN, see Fretz, “Individuality in Sartre’s Philosophy,”
esp 77–83; and Rhiannon Goldthorpe, “Sartre and the Self: Discontinuity or Continuity?”
American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70, no. 4 (1996): 525–30. Sartre was influenced by
his own experiences (an increasing engagement with the world brought about by the war) and
by reading Gide (where a disintegration of the self is offset by its recovery through writing, cre-
ativity, and spontaneity).
133. L’ipséité is the translation of Heidegger’s Selbstheit, a neologism Sartre attributes to
Heidegger’s French translator M. Corbin. See Thomas R. Flynn, Sartre and Marxist Existen-
tialism: The Test Case of Collective Responsibility (Chicago and London: University of Chicago
Press, 1984), 12 (endnote 27) and cf. BN 17; EN 52/53.
134. BN 103–4; EN 140/148. 135. BN 104; EN 141/149.
56 = h u m a n b e i n g
Sartre writes that we are like an ass pulling a cart and chasing a carrot that
hangs from a stick attached to the cart:143 our very movement causes the
carrot (our goal) to draw us forward, which confirms the momentum cre-
ated by the cart (our identity), and which makes it impossible that we shall
ever reach the goal and realize this future identity.
So to return to the ideas suggested at the beginning of this chapter: We
do act on the basis of an identity and an appreciation for the objective de-
mands we meet in the world, but this identity does not exist before the ac-
tivity as a determining cause, it exists as part of that dynamic reaching into
the future that we are. Our activity determines our identity, our freedom
determines our choice, our future determines our present. We are who we
are through our verbs. As Ilham Dilman has written, our beliefs and proj-
ects belong to us only if we actively possess them:
[A person] holds those beliefs, he forms his projects, he makes the promises and
commitments he makes, he maintains his allegiances, he dedicates himself to
their object. He is not just saddled with them.144
We are temporal creatures whose being consists in crossing the gulf be-
tween present and future, in choosing to become through free acts what
we are not by nature. This is Sartre’s understanding of action and of being
human; it is also that of Thomas Aquinas.
Creating Selves: Sartre and Foucault,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70, no. 4
(1996): 542.
143. BN 202; EN 239/253.
144. Ilham Dilman, “Sartre and Our Identity as Individuals,” in Human Beings: Royal In-
stitute of Philosophy Supplement: 29, ed. David Cockburn (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991), 249.
145. BN 38; EN 73/76.
146. BN 35; EN 70/72.
Chapter 2
I de n t i t y a n d H uman
I n co m p l e t io n i n A q u i n a s
58
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 59
their inherent nature, they grow and decay in a fixed way. Animal move-
ments depend not just on their own nature but also on the nature of the
things around them as they are apprehended through the senses. Plants,
of course, are influenced by their immediate environment, but animals are
more open to the world around them and influenced by things that re-
main apart from them. The goal of an animal, however, the direction of its
movements, is still determined by its natural instincts. An animal’s deci-
sion to fight or flee, for example, while it may involve highly complex men-
tal processes, is ultimately determined by the animal’s nature and the na-
ture of its environment (the degree of danger, the possibility of escape, the
needs of its offspring, etc.). Animals, as Stephen Brock writes, “only make
themselves do what they are made to make themselves do.”3
A third type of movement belongs to human beings, since we are crea-
tures with intellect. Our life has much in common with that of plants and
animals. Yet the distinctive thing about the movement of human beings is
that “they move themselves to an end that they themselves propose.”4 The
goals of our activity are not determined solely by our nature or by the na-
ture of the world around us. Aquinas believes, in the terms of the previous
chapter, that our actions cannot be explained solely with reference to an
established identity or to the objective circumstances of our environment.
Something else is involved. The direction of our life is somehow up to us.
We choose our goals and in that choice we establish a meaning for our life
and determine the person we will become. Human identity is not some-
thing fixed and definitive, it unfolds over time, and it constantly has to be
appropriated, acknowledged, and re-created through our actions.
This whole book is an exploration of the nature of human identity,
and only in chapter 6 will we look properly at Aquinas’s understanding
of how human beings constitute themselves through their free choices. In
this present chapter we will examine two distinct aspects of the question of
identity. First, Aquinas argues that human beings have a peculiar openness
to the world around them because of their intellect. We can, in a certain
sense, share in the being of other things. We are formed by what we under-
stand, to the extent that our identity depends in part on what we identify
3. Stephen Brock, Action and Conduct: Thomas Aquinas and the Theory of Action (Edin-
burgh: T & T Clark, 1998), 35.
4. ST I.18:3c.
60 = h u m a n b e i n g
with. We are (through understanding other things) what we are not (by
our own nature). Human identity, at any one time, is therefore a result of
our willingness to go beyond ourselves and engage with what is other than
ourselves through our understanding.
The second aspect of the question concerns the transformation of iden-
tity that takes place over time through our actions. In Aquinas’s understand-
ing, all things, nonliving as well as living, are in a process of development.
In common with all things, we seek our own good, which is the perfec-
tion of our being. Human appetite is distinctive, however, because we de-
termine for ourselves which goals to seek and what form our good will take.
By seeking one particular good rather than another we ensure that one par-
ticular identity rather than another will emerge through our actions. We are
becoming (as we seek our fulfillment in this goal) what we are not (since this
goal is precisely an identity that is sought and not yet found).
There are startling similarities between the arguments of Aquinas and
those of Sartre that were presented in chapter 1. I will not allude to these
similarities much here—they will become clear as the argument develops.
Human beings never lose their identity as human, yet this very identity
consists of an ability to be transformed by our understanding of what is
present and by our desire for what is future (and what is therefore absent).
Aquinas, like Sartre, argues that we are what we are not (through the in-
tellect), and that we become what we are not (through the will). Human
identity is out there in other things and over there in the future.
It is worth making some preliminary notes here about “form” and
“matter” since Aquinas’s thinking is incomprehensible without some fa-
miliarity with these Aristotelian concepts. “Form” and “matter” are cor-
relative terms. Forma (“form”) is the inner principle that makes a thing to
be what it is. A “thing” here, and throughout this book, is not just a physi-
cal object but anything that has its own unity. The English word is as broad
and useful as its Latin equivalent, res, which has the following synonyms
associated with it in one lexicon: thing, object, concrete being, matter, af-
fair, event, fact, circumstance, occurrence, deed, condition.5 So when we
hear about understanding something or knowing the form of a thing we
have all these possibilities in mind.
5. Roy J. Deferrari and Sister M. Inviolata Barry, A Lexicon of St. Thomas Aquinas (Wash-
ington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1948), 968.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 61
self and is not just the conglomeration of matter that went into it. Each
substance, by virtue of its substantial form, has its own level of unity, sta-
bility, and structure. This form cannot be reduced to the constitutive mat-
ter nor separated from that matter—it is the concrete forming of this par-
ticular matter.
All things have a form. The form of living things is called anima (“the
soul”),8 which is the primary principle of life, that which makes something
alive and not dead. A body can have eyes, legs, and lungs, but if it is not
alive then the form of life is missing, and it does not have a soul. The hu-
man soul, as we shall see, is distinctive because of the nature of intellect
and will.
There is no need to summarize here Aquinas’s understanding of hu-
man nature since the four Thomistic chapters of this present study are in
effect investigations into the main aspects of this question. We will reflect
on the place of the human being in the natural world; on what we have in
common with immaterial objects, with plants, with animals, with angels;
on the distinctive features of human beings as creatures of intellect and
will, whose freedom allows them to take responsibility for their lives and
their goals; and on the constitutive ambiguity of a human nature that nat-
urally seeks a perfect fulfillment that it cannot naturally find. It is worth
making a final note, however, about one aspect of the human soul that
does not receive a great deal of attention in this study; namely, its subsis-
tence. Aquinas argues that the human intellectual soul, unlike the souls of
plants and animals, is an incorporeal, subsistent principle,9 which means
that it is capable of continuing to exist after separating from its material
body at death. There is therefore a double aspect to the human soul: it in-
forms the human body, just as the soul of an animal does, yet it is also able
to exist immaterially, as the angels do. This creates a host of philosophi-
cal problems for Aquinas—for example, about how the intellect can oper-
ate when it is not united with a body10—but it is the best way he can find
of holding onto his key insights about what it is to be a human being, and
especially about the peculiarities of a material creature that has an intel-
lectual nature. This topic is not the focus of my study, and I do not go into
the complex debates about the subsistence of the human soul;11 but it is
good to bear in mind that for Aquinas the human soul by its very nature is
open to a kind of existence quite distinct from that available to other cor-
poreal creatures. We have a double kinship: with the angels as well as with
the other animals.
11. I pay more attention to the soul’s immateriality than to its subsistence (see the section
“Intellect, Knowledge, and Immateriality” below, and elsewhere).
12. See the various references that follow.
13. ST I.78:1c.
64 = h u m a n b e i n g
ceive the form of the thing known, without matter indeed, but subject to
material conditions.”14 Even though they can remember and plan ahead
and instinctively make connections between means and ends, they cannot
see that one thing within their experience can be more than their experi-
ence—that its form is distinct from the concrete conditions in which it is
found.
Human beings, however, through intellectual knowledge, are present
to things as they are in themselves, and not only as they are in this expe-
rience. This doesn’t mean that things are present without the experience.
We know “what is in individual matter” but “not as it is in such matter.”15
Aquinas uses the language of knowing something absolute (“absolutely,”
“as separated,” “freed” from the limitations of sense experience) and uni-
versaliter (“universally,” “in general,” “not as individual”):
Now a thing is known insofar as its form is in the knower. But the intellectual
soul knows a thing in its nature absolutely: for instance, it knows a stone abso-
lutely as a stone; and therefore the form of a stone absolutely, as to its proper for-
mal idea [secundum propriam rationem formalem], is in the intellectual soul.16
intellect [ut sic anima hominis sit omnia quodammodo secundum sensum
et intellectum].” 17 The soul, the human form, can become other things by
knowing them. This means that our lives are given their distinctive shape
by what we know. We are what we are not since the form our soul is given
derives from what only exists outside ourselves in the world. There is a
kind of austerity to Aquinas’s theory of knowledge: human beings do not
get in the way.
John Haldane has re-presented these Thomistic ideas in his “mind-
world identity theory,” and tried to draw out their relevance for contempo-
rary debates about “realism” and “antirealism” in the analytic tradition.18
For Haldane the two features of Aquinas’s theory of cognition that have
most bearing on the issue of epistemological realism are, “First, the insis-
tence that the intellect engages directly with reality and not with some ter-
tium quid intervening between them (concepts being the means and, apart
from in reflection, not the objects of thought). And second, the striking
claim that the forms or natures which give structure to the world, and the
concepts which give ‘shape’ to thought, are one and the same.”19 A central
epistemological idea in Aquinas, according to Haldane, is that “thought is
constituted by the world” and that the intellect “is not to be regarded as a
pre-existing cognitive mechanism but as a capacity to be informed by the
structuring principles of the world. It is, so to say, ‘not a something but
not a nothing either’—in this case being a potentiality for the reception of
form.”20
When we come to understand something it is possible to say that
nothing “happens,” there is no “action,” since no new form comes about.
There is simply the same form of whatever exists, only now this form is a
known form. The intellectual form that constitutes our knowledge is not af-
fected by the form of the thing known, it is the form of the thing known.
“The act of knowledge extends to things outside the knower: for we know
things even that are external to us [cognoscimus enim etiam ea quae extra
nos sunt].” 21 Timothy McDermott’s interpretative translation of this last
17. ST I.80:1c.
18. See his “Mind-World Identity Theory and the Anti-Realist Challenge,” in Reality, Rep-
resentation, and Projection, ed. John Haldane and Crispin Wright (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1993), 15–37.
19. Ibid., 21. 20. Ibid., 33.
21. ST I.84:2c.
66 = h u m a n b e i n g
phrase runs: “When we know a thing it remains other than us.”22 These are
the same arguments and conclusions made by Sartre in his phenomeno-
logical account of intentionality. Human beings are not trapped in their
own interiority, looking out at the distant world and wondering how they
might make contact with it. The self is to exist beyond the self. We are “over
there” in whatever we experience, essentially open to what we are not. We
are constituted by our relationship with what is other.
The process of identification that takes place between the human be-
ing and what is known depends on the intellectus possibilis (“possible in-
tellect,” “receptive intellect”). Aquinas takes up Aristotle’s description. The
human intellect “is in potentiality with regard to things intelligible, and is
at first ‘like a clean tablet on which nothing is written,’ as the Philosopher
says in De Anima III.”23 He refers again to Aristotle in ST I.79:6 and notes
that there is an identification between the possible intellect and the indi-
vidual things it knows which (in a certain sense) actualizes it.24 The pos-
sible intellect is said “to become all things, inasmuch as it receives the [in-
telligible] species of each thing [fieri singula, secundum quod recipit species
singulorum].”25 The thing understood is in the intellect by its own “like-
ness” (similitudo).26 This language might seem to imply that we have some
kind of indirect representational knowledge. We are so used to imagin-
ing the mind as a “place” within us, and we slip into thinking that these
forms are somehow within us too. The English phrase “to have something
in mind” reflects this ambiguity—it can imply either a thought within or
an external object of mental attention. The related phrase “to have some-
thing in sight” is more clearly Thomistic: the seeing is referred to the ob-
ject as it is out there. When we say “I can’t get my mind round this” we are
suggesting that the thing we wish to understand is separate from the mind
and the mind must somehow go out to it and embrace it. These phrases are
useful because they help us to resist the idea that the form proceeds from
the thing outside to the mind within. We mean instead that human beings,
as intellectual, are able to exist out there in the forms of other things. Aqui-
nas is clear that having the form or likeness involves a formal identity be-
tween knower and known:
The thing understood is in the intellect by its own likeness [per suam simili-
tudinem]; and it is in this sense that we say that the thing actually understood
is the intellect in act [intellectum in actu est intellectus in actu], because the like-
ness of the thing understood is the form of the intellect [similitude rei intellec-
tae est forma intellectus], just as the likeness of a sensible thing is the form of the
sense in act.27
27. ST I.85:2ad1.
28. There is an active aspect to the whole process of understanding which I do not pay
much attention to in this chapter. The intellect has the power to “abstract” forms from the
things it meets. Concrete experiences (“forms existing in matter”; “formae autem in materia
existentes non sunt intelligibiles actu”) are not actually intelligible, “we must therefore assign
on the part of the intellect some power to make things actually intelligible, by abstraction of
the species from material conditions” (ST I.79:3c). We have to light up and understand the im-
mediate impressions (phantasmata) which things have made on us (ST I.79:4). For Aquinas’s
theory of abstraction and universals, see ST I.85.
29. ST I.75:2c. 30. ST I.75:2c.
31. There is a good discussion of this in Norman Kretzmann, “Philosophy of Mind,” in The
Cambridge Companion to Aquinas, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1993), 132–33.
68 = h u m a n b e i n g
lectual soul is simply the ability of human beings to be formed by what they
are not. Human life, as we have seen, is open to the presence of other things
in a distinctive way, it is not limited by its own bodily form. In fact the form
of its body, its very nature, is not to be a form limited by a particular mate-
rial body, it is rather to be the form of what it understands. Our existence is
larger than ourselves—this is why our intellect is said to be immaterial.
Herbert McCabe writes that the noncorporeal nature of understanding
is meant to be obvious, it is a platitude and not an explanation of the pro-
cess of understanding:
It says “what I have in mind when I know the nature of a cow is the nature of a
cow and nothing else.” [To understand the nature of a cow] is to have this nature
precisely without being a cow, and this is what is made clear by saying that one
has the nature in mind. To have it in mind doesn’t mean anything except that
you have the nature without being the thing whose nature it is.32
If the intellect were a body, it would necessarily have a different sort of rela-
tionship with other bodies, one dependent on bodily change, which would
never allow the intellect to go beyond each particular change and draw any
wider conclusions through questioning and abstraction. Timothy Suttor
writes that for Aquinas “thinking is being things,” and Aquinas’s proof of
the nonbodiliness of human intelligence is intelligible “only in the light of
this principle: to be able-to-be all bodies, a thing must not-actually-be any
body.”33 The intellectual soul that becomes other forms must itself be “an
absolute form, and not something composed of matter and form.”34
The immateriality of the intellect and of the forms that are known
should not be thought of as some sort of dualism that would take us away
from the material world of human beings and the things they know. It
is the individual, concrete, material things that are known through their
forms. The nonbodiliness of the intellect allows us to look through or bet-
ter still into the objects and situations we sense so that we can know what
they are and not just what they are doing to us at this very moment. When
we go beyond the instinctive delight we take in an object’s shape and color
32. Herbert McCabe, “The Immortality of the Soul,” in Aquinas: A Collection of Critical
Essays, ed. Anthony Kenny (London and South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press,
1976), 304.
33. Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, vol. 11, footnote b, 10.
34. ST I.75:5c.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 69
35. ST I.76:4c.
36. ST I.76:1c. Referring to Aristotle’s De Anima 2:2, 414a4–19. For an English version, see
Ackrill, ed., A New Aristotle Reader, 169.
70 = h u m a n b e i n g
37. It could be objected that Aquinas’s conception of personhood suggests a much more
static understanding of individual human identity. There is no space here to explore properly
his definitions of the word “person.” See, e.g., ST I.29; Commentum in quatuor libros Senten-
tiarum Magistri Petri Lombardi, in Sancti Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris angelici ordinis predica-
torum Opera omnia ad fidem optimarum editionum accurate recognita, vols. 6–7 (Parma: ty-
pis Petri Fiaccadori, 1856–1858), I.25:1:1; and De potentia, in Quaestiones disputatae, vol. 2, ed.
P. Pession (Turin/Rome: Marietti, 1953), 9:2. At this stage it is enough to point out that his use
of Boethius’s definition (persona est rationalis naturae individua substantia; “a person is an in-
dividual substance of a rational nature”) does not in any way exclude the more developmental
and open-ended account of individual identity presented in this discussion of the intellectual
soul in ST I.76—indeed it prepares the way for it. In ST I.29:1c, for example, Aquinas argues
that the point of putting the word “rational” into the definition of “person” is that particularity
and individuality are found in a more special and perfect way in rational substances, “which
have dominion over their own actions; and which are not only acted upon, like other things,
but which can act of themselves [sed per se agunt].” So human action, which will include the
remarkable ability of the intellectual soul to be transformed by what it understands, is one sig-
nificant aspect of subsisting individual that is the person.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 71
38. ST I.76:4c.
39. ST I.85:2ad1.
72 = h u m a n b e i n g
who we are. Our life has no shape apart from that given to it by our under-
standing. The form of the human being is the form of the world known to
us. One could say that the human being is the world as understood. We are
what we understand, and our body is therefore out there in what we know.
Further weight is given to this conclusion through Aquinas’s conten-
tion that the intellect cannot know itself as an object of its own knowledge
but only through its activity. It does not, in itself, have its own form (which
might have given it a certain identity and allowed it to become an object
of knowledge). Its only form is that taken from the things it knows. Con-
sidered in its essence “the human mind is potentially understanding” and
does not have the power “to be understood” outside its activity of know-
ing.40 Its essence is to have the ability to be other things through their form.
To put it in more Sartrean language, the essence of the human intellectual
soul is not to be or to be what it is not; it is not to have its own form but to
have the forms of other things:
But as in this life our intellect has material and sensible things for its proper nat-
ural object, as stated above [cf. ST I.84:7], so it follows that our intellect under-
stands itself insofar as it is made actual by the species abstracted from sensible
things, through the light of the active intellect, which not only actuates the in-
telligible things themselves, but also, by their instrumentality, actuates the pos-
sible intellect. Therefore our intellect knows itself not by its essence, but by its
act. This happens in two ways: In the first place, singularly, as when Socrates or
Plato perceives that he has an intellectual soul because he perceives that he un-
derstands. In the second place, universally, as when we consider the nature of
the human mind [naturam humanae mentis] from knowledge of the intellec-
tual act.41
40. ST I.87:1c.
41. ST I.87:1c.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 73
itself [sufficit ipsa mentis praesentia, quae est principium actus ex quo mens
percipit seipsam], and hence it is said to know itself by its own presence.”42
The mind is knowing its own knowing, and so is in some way at the same
time within that knowing as a participant and detached from that know-
ing as an observer—it is present to itself. This has an effect on the knowl-
edge we have of things. If we are not only present to things but also present
to our presence to things we are therefore conscious of the relationship be-
tween things and ourselves. This is why unlike that of animals, our knowl-
edge has the kind of objectivity described above. We can take account of
our place in the knowledge and factor it out and thereby acknowledge the
reality of things as they are apart from their relation to us. Our intellectual
presence to things as they are (and not only as they are for us) and our self-
consciousness are one and the same thing. The “self ” we are conscious of
is not another “thing” (with a form) but a “nothing,” a lack of form, a “not
being” the form of what is known.
From this we can conclude that no amount of mental introspection
will reveal our core identity. The only identity we have is actively consti-
tuted through that relationship we have with the world around us through
understanding. The human form is therefore changing and is itself deter-
mined by the active knowing of each person. There is, as Sartre would say,
no transcendental ego. We cannot find ourselves, we have to make our-
selves by knowing other things. David Burrell, commenting on a different
aspect of Aquinas’s thought, comes to the same conclusion:
I have remarked how Aquinas’ analysis of action appears truncated. For it seems
that the development of habitus as a proximate principle of activity demands
one more step: to articulate what it is who acts. Such a step would carry us to
the “transcendental ego.” But Aquinas neatly avoids that problem by recogniz-
ing there is no step at all. The one who acts, as Aquinas views the matter, is ar-
ticulated in the remote and proximate principles of action. Nothing more need
be said because nothing more can be said: the self we know is known by those
characteristics which mark it.43
42. ST I.87:1c.
43. David B. Burrell, Aquinas: God and Action (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1979), 129. See Romanus Cessario, Moral Virtues and Theological Ethics (South
Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1991), 35–40, on how the personal development of
habitus (character) transforms the very constitution of oneself.
74 = h u m a n b e i n g
44. Aquinas often writes about one’s goals, one’s ends, the goods one desires, the values
one seeks, the perfection one longs for. It sounds as if, in his philosophical system, human be-
ings are inherently selfish, capable only of seeking their own fulfillment at the expense of that
of everyone else. Yet it needs to be said very clearly that for Aquinas (and indeed for Sartre)
“the good that we desire,” “the fulfillment that we seek,” lies wherever we put it. So we can find
our good and fulfillment, for example, in the well-being of a spouse or a stranger or a commu-
nity as much as we can in the pleasures of our own body or in the success of our own work. We
can choose to make their good into our own end. Indeed we can find our good in absolutely
anything that we choose. The good is simply what we seek, what we care about—even if it is
not caring about “ourselves.” The fact that we can seek things in a way that means something
to us personally (“my good,” “my perfection”) is the very thing that ensures that our other-
directed actions (“for you,” “for them”) are still our own actions. This is why love can be disin-
terested and personal at the same time. There is no contradiction in loving the other for one’s
own sake or in seeking the good of the other because it will make one happy. This meaning of
“one’s good” should be borne in mind throughout the book.
45. DV 21:1c, citing Nichomachean Ethics, 1:1, 1094a3. For an English version, see Aristotle,
Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1985), 1.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 75
It is clear how wide ranging this use of “good” is. If the language of desire
(appetitus) is never far away, one should remember that desire is an ana-
logical term that applies to all relationships that involve attraction and per-
fection—from bodies falling and finding their “preferred” place of rest to
spiritual beings willing and discovering their happiness.50
To say that something is good, therefore, is to point to a particular type
of relationship it can have with something else. The house is good for those
who live in it; the fire is good for those who are warmed by it; the mu-
sic is good to those who listen to it. These things are good insofar as they
46. DV 21:1c.
47. DV 21:1c.
48. DV 21:1c, when “something is said to be referred which is not dependent upon that to
which it is referred, but vice versa.”
49. DV 21:1c.
50. Cf. David M. Gallagher, “Aquinas on Goodness and Moral Goodness,” in Thomas
Aquinas and His Legacy, ed. David M. Gallagher, Studies in Philosophy and the History of Phi-
losophy (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1994), 38–40.
76 = h u m a n b e i n g
So the choice is not between “being and not being,” but between “being
and more being.” There is, however, one hugely important point to note.
The perfection achieved, the additional being, is not like an external pos-
session that leaves the substantial being indifferent and unaffected. The
perfections do not stand to the substance as a hat on someone’s head or a
magnet on a fridge door. It is the substantial being itself that is perfected:
the child is kind, and does not exist at this moment except as kind; the tree
is tall, and tallness is not something added to an otherwise small tree, it
simply is the present existence of this tree. At any moment there is only
55. ST I.5:1ad1.
56. Cf. DV 21:2ad6, “A thing can be called good both from its being and from some added
property or state.”
57. ST I.5:1ad1.
78 = h u m a n b e i n g
one actual being, which is this substantial thing perfected in these ways
and existing in these forms.
We should at all costs avoid thinking that there is a core substantial be-
ing that remains unaffected by superficial changes. Aquinas wants to show
how something can change and become more what it “is,” without ceasing
to be what it was all along, without losing its identity. There are always two
ways of looking at anything: in terms of its unchanging identity (its sub-
stantial being), and in terms of what it could become (its perfection). This
allows Aquinas to say something quite startling:
In this way, therefore, viewed in its primal (i.e., substantial) being [primum esse,
quod est substantiale], a thing is said to be simply and to be good in a certain
respect (i.e., in so far as it has being), but viewed in its complete actuality [ul-
timum actum], a thing is said to be in a certain respect and to be good simply
[dicitur aliquid ens secundum quid, et bonum simpliciter].58
In other words, in the light of what it could yet be (“its complete actuality,”
its unqualified goodness), a thing exists only secundum quid, in a certain
sense: “a thing is said to be in a certain sense.” So in relation to the good,
each thing lacks being, it lacks itself as perfected. Someone could ask: Why
say “lacks itself ” instead of just saying “lacks perfection”? One could an-
swer: Because what is lacked is the whole substantial being as perfected
and not just the additional perfections themselves. The child doesn’t just
want to possess “kindness,” the child wants to be a kind child, which it is
not; the tree doesn’t just strive to possess “tallness,” it strives to be a tall
tree, which it is not yet. Something becomes good through perfections in
the accidental order, yet these accidents are not themselves good, rather
they make the thing itself to be good. The imperfect wants to be more per-
fect. To seek one’s good is, in one specific sense only, to seek to be what
one is not.59 As Aquinas will say later in Part I-II, “It happens with some
things, that they have being in some respect, and yet they are lacking in the
fullness of being due to them.”60 For this reason, even before considering
58. ST I.5:1ad1.
59. In DV 21:5 Aquinas uses the language of generation, which he defines as a “motion to-
ward being.” To receive substantial being is to be generated without qualification (simpliciter);
to receive accidental being, that is, to be perfected, is to be generated in a certain sense (secun-
dum quid). If something seeks its own good, it is seeking its own being, and this shows that in
a certain respect it lacks its own being.
60. ST I-II.18:1c.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 79
the special nature of the human appetite, we can see how at any given mo-
ment the identity of anything at all is unstable and open to development.
The very being of anything can be changed and can be perfected or dimin-
ished, so nothing has a fixed and invulnerable identity—despite the con-
tinuation of its substantial form.
So there are two approaches to the good: it is something desired by an-
other in order to perfect whatever desires it; and it is a being in so far as it
has been perfected. The two approaches are brought together in this way:
the good is the perfection sought by a being through the attainment of what
is desired. The end which is sought through another being is always the
perfection of the being which does the seeking. The “external” good always
refers to the “internal” good of the one seeking. The root of all desire is
not solely a desire for something else but a desire for the perfection of the
seeker’s being—to attain this perfection if it is not yet attained and to love
or “enjoy” what is already possessed.61
61. Cf. DV 21:2c, “For whatever does not yet participate in the act of being tends toward it
by a certain natural appetite. [.....] But everything which already has being naturally loves its
being and with all its strength preserves it.”
80 = h u m a n b e i n g
Therefore, as forms exist in those things that have knowledge in a higher man-
ner and above the manner of natural forms, so must there be in them an in-
clination surpassing the natural inclination, which is called the natural appe-
tite. And this superior inclination belongs to the appetitive power of the soul,
through which the animal is able to desire what it apprehends, and not only that
to which it is inclined by its natural form. And so it is necessary to assign an ap-
petitive power to the soul.62
our senses. This sensitive appetite has two aspects: we are concupiscent (we
are attracted to what is good for us and repelled by what is harmful), and
we are irascible (we resist those things that get in the way of our good or
produce harm).64 Love, hate, and aggression are perfectly natural passions,
and like most animals we quarrel about things like food and sex.65 Ani-
mals form these intentions “only by some natural instinct,” while human
beings gain them through the “particular reason” which makes a “compar-
ison of individual intentions.”66
Given that we have so much in common with other animals, a ques-
tion remains: Is our inclination to a particular good determined solely by
our natural form and by our environment as it is apprehended through the
senses? Are we no different from other animals? Aquinas’s answer is clear.
Although the sensitive appetite (moved through the estimative power) de-
termines the actions of animals, the extraordinary thing about the human
sensitive appetite (moved through the particular reason) is that it is itself
determined by other powers. Human beings are not controlled by the sen-
sitive appetite, rather they control the sensitive appetite. First, the particu-
lar reason is “guided and moved according to universal reason” that draws
“particular conclusions from universal principles.” “Anyone can experience
this in himself: for by applying certain universal considerations, anger or
fear or the like may be calmed down or stirred up.”67 Second, the sensi-
tive appetite does not move the human being unless it is commanded by a
higher appetite, a rational appetite, namely, the will:
For in other animals movement follows at once the concupiscible and irascible
appetites: for instance, the sheep, fearing the wolf, flees at once [statim fugit],
because it has no superior appetite which goes against it. On the contrary, hu-
man beings are not moved at once [homo non statim movetur], according to the
irascible and concupiscible appetites, but they await the command of the will,
which is the superior appetite.68
Our instinctive desires and fears, just like those of animals, are real (they
belong to us) and immediate (we do not argue to them from abstract
principles). Yet unlike other animals, we have a particular kind of dis-
64. These technical terms do not have the negative connotations of lust and irritability
that they have today.
65. ST I.81:2c. 66. ST I.78:4c.
67. ST I.81:3c. 68. ST I.81:3c.
82 = h u m a n b e i n g
tance or detachment from them. They do not move us statim, “at once,”
“immediately”—instead there needs to be a process of mediation to make
them effective. There is a gap between apprehension and action, between
having a desire and being directed by that desire. This does not separate
us from our immediate sensitive appetite—it still always belongs to us.
But given a certain desire or fear or sense of anger we can do two things
before we act: (1) we can think more deeply about what is really the case
and (2) we can ponder more deeply what we really want. In both these
ways we are able to put the immediate situation and our immediate reac-
tions into a larger context. This context is discovered by our reason (whose
job is to make a larger sense of what we already know from principles we
already have), and this context is evaluated by our will (whose job is to
seek our most complete good in the light of the possibilities this large con-
text offers). It is the passivity of the sensitive appetite that marks it out—it
is moved by whatever is apprehended. The rational appetite, in contrast,
works out whether a particular thing apprehended leads to a more univer-
sal good.69 Quite often one particular thing may lead to many more uni-
versal goods, and many different particular things may lead to the same
more universal good. This is why, as we shall see, human beings are free to
determine what they seek.
In this account human beings are not completely caught up within the
momentum of their own seeking. It may seem a small thing for Aquinas
to state that we question our desires and fears. But this means that within
certain limits we question and therefore decide upon what our goals are
and what our own good is to be. Rational creatures, as Aquinas wrote in
the passage cited at the beginning of this chapter, “move themselves to an
end that they themselves propose.”70 As far as we know, this doesn’t hap-
pen with other animals. However sophisticated they are (and our appre-
ciation of their sophistication has increased enormously since Aquinas’s
time), their agency is limited. Even when they execute their own actions
and form them and seem to weigh up alternative paths they are still, in the
words of Stephen Brock, “adjusting a predetermined inclination (desire)
according to the perceived circumstances, in virtue of an equally predeter-
mined regulative principle (‘instinct’).” He continues:
The actual process of comparing one thing with another is the work of
reason. In answer to a suggestion that the will, like the sensitive appetite,
is necessarily moved by whatever the intellect apprehends (ST I.82:2obj3),
Aquinas writes:
The sensitive power is not a power which compares different things with each
other [non est vis collativa diversorum], as reason is, and it simply apprehends
some one thing. Therefore, according to that one thing, it moves the sensitive
appetite in a determinate way. But the reason is a comparison of several things
together [ratio est collativa plurium], therefore from several things the intellec-
tual appetite (that is, the will) may be moved, and not of necessity from one
thing [ex pluribus moveri potest appetitus intellectivus, scilicet voluntas, et non ex
uno ex necessitate].72
71. Brock, Action and Conduct: Thomas Aquinas and the Theory of Action, 38.
72. ST I.82:2ad3. 73. ST I.83:1c.
74. ST I-II.13:2ad3.
84 = h u m a n b e i n g
reason, therefore [a human being] acts from free judgment and can be in-
clined to various things. For reason in contingent matters may follow op-
posite courses [Ratio enim circa contingentia habet viam ad opposita].”75
This topic will form the subject of chapter 6. We can say briefly here that
reason allows us to hold together different goods without ordering them
before there is even a scale of ordering. We have to compare them not with
an external scale (which could only issue in one result) but with each other.
The decision to pursue one in preference to the others creates a scale on the
basis of which they are ordered. We could go to a restaurant or to the cin-
ema or to the circus, each one is actually possible, each one would be rea-
sonable. “Since the deliberating reason is disposed to opposite things, the
will can go to either [Quod ratio deliberans se habet ad opposita, voluntas in
utrumque potest].”76
Reason is a reflective power and rational agents can control their judg-
ments.77 “To judge about one’s own judgment belongs only to reason,
which reflects upon its own act and knows the relationships of the things
about which it judges and of those by which it judges.”78 This is why “the
root of all freedom lies in the reason [totius libertatis radix est in ratione
constituta].”79 Like other animals we discover goods and evils in the world
that will affect us in different ways and we notice our own instinctive in-
clinations and aversions to these. Yet our actual response to each situation
depends on which good we choose to seek and on how we choose to un-
derstand things. Intellect and will working together, as we shall see prop-
erly in chapter 6, allow us to determine our goals for ourselves. For this
reason our unfolding identity is in part a consequence and not simply a
cause of the choices we make about our goals. In other words, we form our-
selves.
Second, in common with all things, our identity develops over time as we
seek the perfection of our being. Furthermore, as creatures with a rational
appetite, and not just a sensitive one, the course of this development is up
to us, and we determine for ourselves which goal we shall seek and what
form our good will take. Our identity is over there in the future. At this in-
troductory stage it has been necessary to treat intellect and rational appe-
tite separately, and this makes it hard to appreciate how closely connected
their work is in the integrated life of the human being. We will go on to ex-
amine properly their interdependence as it manifests itself in the act of un-
derstanding (chapter 4) and in the act of choosing (chapter 6).
It might help to conclude this chapter by applying Aquinas’s account of
identity to two of Sartre’s examples. Aquinas has used the example of fear
to illustrate the role of both reason and will. The sheep flees the wolf as
soon as it is afraid; the human being, equally frightened, nevertheless waits
for the judgment of reason and the command of the will.80 We can com-
pare this with Sartre’s reformed gambler.81 Let’s say that this man is moti-
vated by a fear of gambling, which perhaps represents a wider fear of bank-
ruptcy or of failure. He is, paradoxically, reassured by this fear; he depends
on it and is defined by it. It keeps him safe. But then he realizes that he can
put this very fear in question. The atmosphere of the casino beckons to
him and he imagines himself beyond his fear in a paradise of riches and
adulation. His response will be determined by whichever plans issue from
his present thinking and desiring, and not simply by his initial instinctive
reactions. Fear does not rule him, it is ruled (or measured or weighed) by
him. His actions will depend on which measure he chooses.
Aquinas says as much in fewer words: we are not sheep. The sheep flees
the wolf at once because it is afraid.82 Aquinas’s human being, call him
the gambler, is different. When he is terrified by the “wolf ” (the roulette
wheel) Aquinas says that by applying “certain universal considerations” he
may calm down or stir up his fear.83 Perhaps he mulls over some univer-
sal considerations such as these: “Each time one goes to the table one has
a real chance of winning”; “One’s luck can increase as well as decrease”; “It
is possible to mortgage one’s house to pay one’s debts.” These indisputable
truths allow him to resize and overcome his fear. Or he can simply direct
his attention in a more focused way to the attractiveness of the goods he
seeks and in this way sidestep the fear: he remembers the adrenalin rush
as the wheel is spun; he thinks about the friendships he might make; he
dreams of a life of risk, rebellion, and recklessness and curses his com-
muter-belt mediocrity. These goods might attract him more than financial
security. By concentrating on them he avoids facing the fear of financial
ruin.
Let us say that he decides to gamble. The goods he now seeks (excite-
ment, friendship, rebellion) are also natural attractions caused by concu-
piscence: Aquinas doesn’t say that when we change our goals the will pulls
us away from our own natural desire. He writes elsewhere that “the man
who yields to concupiscence acts counter to that which he purposed at
first, but not counter to that which he wants now.”84 Yet by choosing his
new goal the gambler determines for himself what his good will be and
which identity will be formed. Sheep don’t do all this. In Aquinas’s scheme
the sheep represents those who are sincere for Sartre: those who want to
define themselves and their possibilities in terms of an unchanging nature
that would determine everything they did.
Some interpretations of Aquinas emphasize the naturalness of human
desires and underplay the responsibility we have to choose between them
and decide our individual goals. Anthony Lisska, commenting on Aqui-
nas’s teleology, writes the following:
An end is to be attained, not because of a subjective desire or wish on the part
of the agent, but because the end itself determines the well-functioning of the
human person. [.....] Nature has “determined,” as it were, the ends which lead
to the well-being of the individuals of the natural kind. “To have been deter-
mined,” however, means only that these particular ends are part of the develop-
ment of the individual’s essence.85
Aquinas would agree that possible ends are determined by nature (by con-
cupiscence, etc.), but he would add that the choice of one end from among
many is not determined by nature. Even those passages where he writes
84. ST I-II.6:7ad2.
85. Anthony J. Lisska, Aquinas’s Theory of Natural Law: An Analytic Reconstruction (Ox-
ford: Clarendon Press, 1996), 107.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 87
about natural and universal human ends need to be read very carefully. In
De malo 6c, for example, Aquinas distinguishes between habits and pas-
sions over which the will has some control, such as anger, and natural dis-
positions that are not subject to the will. If something appears good and
suitable because of a natural disposition, then “the will prefers it from nat-
ural necessity [ex necessitate naturali voluntas preeliget illud], as all human
beings naturally desire to be, to live, and to know.”86 But even these natu-
ral and universal goods do not move the will to choose them necessarily,
since—as Aquinas explains just a few lines before—apart from the good of
happiness, any good is capable of seeming less attractive when placed next
to another good, either because the reason judges that the other good is
objectively better, or simply because the person is enticed by thoughts that
make the other good seem more attractive.87
Sartre gives a notable description of the human act: “The act is always
beyond the essence; it is a human act only in so far as it surpasses every
explanation which we can give of it.”88 Aquinas would support this de-
scription insofar as Sartre means that the natural explanation of the attrac-
tiveness of alternative goods (as determined by the sensitive appetite) will
never be enough to explain why someone chooses one good rather than
another (through the rational appetite).
Another of Sartre’s examples can be read through the eyes of Aquinas.
A young man whose brother has recently been killed in the German of-
fensive is living in occupied France during the Second World War. He has
to make a choice: he can stay in France in order to care for his bereaved
mother or flee to England to join the Free French Forces.89 There are thus
two different ends (supporting a parent or fighting for one’s country) with
two different value systems (filial piety or patriotism). How does he de-
cide? He speaks a particular language, he lives in a particular country with
a particular culture, he has this character and this personal history, he has
these strengths and weaknesses and aptitudes and preferences. It is tempt-
ing to say that his decision will be determined by all these factors. He is
86. DM 6c [470–72].
87. DM 6c [441–67].
88. BN 35; EN 70/72.
89. Jean-Paul Sartre, ”Existentialism and Humanism,” in Jean-Paul Sartre: Basic Writings,
ed. Stephen Priest (London: Routledge, 2001), 33–34.
88 = h u m a n b e i n g
this person in these circumstances and therefore he will act in this way.
Aquinas recognizes this appeal to an essential, natural identity and quotes
Aristotle against himself in an objection to the possibility of human free-
dom:
Just as each one is, such does the end seem to him. But what kind of being we have
is not in our power [non est in potestate nostra aliquales esse], for this comes
to us from nature. Therefore it is natural to us to follow some particular end.
Therefore it is not because of freedom [Non ergo ex libero arbitrio].90
Aquinas agrees that we naturally desire our last end, in general, but in his
response to this objection he adds:
On the part of the body and its powers human beings may be such by virtue of a
natural quality, inasmuch as we are of such a temperament or disposition due to
any impression whatever produced by corporeal causes, which cannot affect the
intellectual part, since it is not the act of a corporeal organ. And such as we are
by virtue of a corporeal quality, such also does our end seem to us, because from
such a disposition a human being is inclined to choose or reject something. But
these inclinations are subject to the judgment of reason [Sed istae inclinationes
subjacent judicio rationis], which the lower appetite obeys, as we have said [cf.
ST I.81:3]. Wherefore this is in no way prejudicial to freedom [Unde per hoc lib-
ertati arbitrii non praejudicatur].91
So the many sensitive inclinations that arise from our nature and direct
us to certain goals do not cause us to act. It is reason that will determine
which goals we actually seek. We can apply this to our example. The young
Frenchman does have an identity. There are many defining features about
his life that make him who he is and motivate his actions. Yet this identity
does not help him determine what he will become in the future. He can’t
find the answer by looking into the person he thinks he is. He can con-
sider different things in the light of different ends. In this case he oscil-
lates between two types of thinking. He is attracted to both goals and he
recognizes that his identity could be defined in terms of either one. He
thinks about the needs of his country, then about the needs of his depen-
90. ST I.83:1obj5. Citing Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3:5, 1114b1. For an English version,
see Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 69.
91. ST I.83:1ad5.
i d e n t i t y i n a q u i n a s = 89
dent mother. He considers his own desire for vengeance against his oc-
cupiers, then his own love for his mother. He judges his situation in the
light of one’s duty to one’s country, then in the light of one’s duty to one’s
parents. His intellect is free to hold both options simultaneously in mind,
because they are both “abstract” possibilities that go beyond the immedi-
ate uninterpreted information he has from his sensitive apprehension. His
particular circumstances, in other words, do not trap him within a single
way of understanding those circumstances. The young man knows that his
future will depend on which good he chooses. His actions will depend on
which end he allows to become the object of his attention and the guid-
ing principle of his life. But a theoretical goal only becomes an actual goal
when he allows it to guide his thinking and when he allows himself to be-
come the person who is formed by this goal.
This example shows us that the facts of our life and nature do not fur-
nish us with a single scale of values against which we can make every de-
cision. Ethics is more than psychology, morality more than metaphysics.92
We have to acknowledge that our identity is insufficient and surpass it to-
ward a new one. We will only exist as acting persons through the end that
we set. Our actions depend on this unfolding identity and not on some
preestablished essence.
For Aquinas, we are fulfilled by what we choose to seek. We are what
we rationally desire. Our rational desire not only fulfills what we already
are, it also creates new possibilities for who we can become. We can change
the person we are, or it might be better to say that personhood lies in the
fact that we don’t have to be any particular person. We constitute ourselves
as persons through freely chosen human action, even though we are con-
stituted by other things in so many other ways (as we will see in chapter 6).
For Aquinas, human beings are becoming what they are not, and this be-
coming is not determined by what they are. The future comes to exist, in
some way, in their present, through their decision to orientate themselves
to this particular future. Our being as persons, our personal identity, de-
pends on a future that does not exist and which cannot be extrapolated
with any necessity from the present. Our being, in this sense, echoing Sar-
92. A fierce criticism of moral theories that claim to be based on a certain metaphysics of
human nature can be found in John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Claren-
don Press, 1980).
90 = h u m a n b e i n g
H u ma n U n d e r s ta n d i n g
Chapter 3
T h e S u b j e c t i v e N at u r e of O b j e c t i v e
U n d e r s ta n d i n g i n S a r t r e
Being-in-the-World
In part one we explored the way human identity is constituted
by the practical choices human beings make. In part three we
will look more closely at how these choices are freely made.
Here in part two we need to address a question that arises from
the ideas developed so far. There have been hints in the previ-
ous two chapters that our personal commitments color the way
we see the world, and that we only understand things in the
way that we want to understand them. Sartre’s being-for-itself
and Aquinas’s will seem to influence the way we interpret our-
selves and our circumstances. There seems to be a suggestion
that knowledge is subjective and that we can never grasp the
truth of things as they are in themselves. If this is the case, then
the choices we make will lack any objective foundation. Hu-
man beings make decisions about things, and if our perception
of these things itself depends on our decisions, then the whole
process will be hopelessly circular. Freedom will be a hollow
kind of creativity without any external points of reference. Hu-
man life, cut off from any roots in objective reality, will just be
a self-fulfilling fantasy, and a lonely one at that. So here in part
two we ask this question: How do Sartre and Aquinas maintain
that our understanding of the world is objective when it be-
longs to a human subject and when it in some way depends on
this human subject?
93
94 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
Sartre is convinced that there are no neutral facts about the world. Ev-
erything we experience is understood in terms of ourselves, our perspec-
tives, and our goals. This humanizing of the world, however, is paradoxi-
cally what allows the reality of the world to be revealed, since the world
can only be known if it is placed in a particular perspective. One notion
of objectivity (detached, inhuman, universal) is replaced by another (en-
gaged, human, specific). Objective truth, to put it another way, is not end-
lessly deferred and out of reach, it is continually discovered within the irre-
deemably subjective activities of human beings. This subjective objectivity
ensures that human decisions are based on an understanding of the world
as it is and not just as we want it to be. Freedom and “facticity” are insepa-
rable, and the concerns of both idealism and realism need to be taken into
account if philosophy is to give a faithful account of human experience.
If we want to appreciate the theoretical framework that makes sense of
this we will have to return to the opening sections of Being and Nothing-
ness. Sartre is trying to develop a phenomenological ontology. This means
that the foundation of his philosophy is concrete human experience. He
tries to make no assumptions about what lies “behind” this experience.
He wants to keep his focus on the experience and see what is happening
within it. Metaphysics may concern itself with why this experience arose
in the first place, what are its causes and grounds, but phenomenological
ontology stays within the experience itself.
Human experience is, nevertheless, complex—it cannot be described
in terms of a single principle.1 In the introduction to Being and Nothing-
ness Sartre scrutinizes our experience of phenomena in general, without
alluding to concrete human behavior, and finds that it must refer to the
correlative regions of being-in-itself and being-for-itself. We have touched
on these ideas in chapter 1. The unified, concrete experience we have is
“the relation” of these two “regions of being.”2 It is an “original bursting-
forth [un jaillissement primitif ]” which can’t be reduced to anything more
primary.3 Being-for-itself represents that aspect of openness to what is ex-
perienced. Being-in-itself represents that aspect of openness to what is ex-
perienced.
If we try to divorce these two regions from each other, we will lose touch
with them both. On the one hand, we never actually experience being-in-
itself isolated from all human context and cut off from any relationship
with us. What we experience is the phenomenon of this being, its place
within experience, its status as meaningful. On the other hand, we are
never directly conscious of our being-for-itself, we are only conscious of
our consciousness of other things, and in this way we are implicitly con-
scious that this consciousness is ours.
In the body of Being and Nothingness (part 1 onward) Sartre builds on
this highly abstract framework. He develops a term inherited from Hei-
degger and describes lived experience in terms of our être-dans-le-monde,
our “being-in-the-world.” We cannot experience being-in-itself, we can
only experience being as it appears to consciousness, being-as-it-is-in-the-
human-world, being as it is structured by our actions and our projects.
Nor can we experience our own consciousness in isolation from a con-
sciousness of something. The concrete world is the place where we start
and where we actually exist. It is not a construction pieced together from
two originally separate elements (a “pure” being-in-itself and a “pure” hu-
man consciousness), it is rather an original synthesis. We start by being-
in-the-world, and then we may speculate about the regions of being that
support this—our own being-for-itself and the being-in-itself of things.
The lived experience of acting human beings, which takes place in the
world, is the main subject of Being and Nothingness. The relationship be-
tween human engagement and the apprehension of being is at the center
of Sartre’s understanding of the world. Negation, for Sartre, is the consti-
tutive way in which things are revealed since they only take their place in
the world when we isolate them, go beyond them, and relate them to what
they are not. The world is the rising up of engaged human beings, the ne-
gation of being-in-itself by being-for-itself.
Sartre approaches this issue from different directions. He has a central
insight that is expressed in different ways: the world is human; objectivity
4. BN xxxvii; EN 28/28.
96 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
5. For these various influences, see Adrian Mirvish, “Sartre on Perception and the World,”
Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 14 (1983).
6. The German word Gestalt is roughly equivalent to the English form or shape.
7. See Wolfgang Köhler, Gestalt Psychology: An Introduction to New Concepts in Modern
Psychology (New York: Liveright, 1947), esp. 136–72.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n s a r t r e = 97
ing depends on the meanings we give to things through our purposes, but
he wrote that “meaning follows the lines drawn by natural organization.”8
So Sartre embraced “gestaltism” as a way of affirming the givenness
and otherness of the world. We find objects, it argues, as they are. He does
not, however, allow that these natural “figures” can be apprehended or un-
derstood outside the context of human choosing. The being (in-itself) of
each figure does not depend on the choice of the for-itself, but this being
is only encountered and revealed by the isolating power of the for-itself.
We could express it in this way: We find what is there, yet it is only there
through our finding.
Sartre argues that perceptual judgments depend in part on the direc-
tion of one’s interest and attention. Choice has a role in the simplest act of
perception. We choose to look at one thing rather than another, and dif-
ferent people looking in the same direction see different things. Each per-
ceived thing has to be isolated from the undifferentiated perceptive field
and viewed against it.9
In perception there is always the construction of a figure [une forme] on a back-
ground [un fond]. No one object, no group of objects is especially designed to
be organised as specifically either ground or figure; all depends on the direction
of my attention.10
jective form is lit up by the subjective attention, and the subject can only
attend to what is there. Sartre writes very simply that the relationship any
particular thing has with its background is “both chosen and given.”13 On
the one hand, we choose without any necessity to notice this thing, in the
pursuit of our interests, and to see it in relation to its background. “I am
free to look at the book on the table or at the table supporting the book.”14
On the other hand, the givenness comes from the relationship that things
really have with each other. We can’t change the “original distribution of
thises [distribution originelle des ceci]” that make up the world.15 It is an
unavoidable fact that at this moment the book and the table have a specific
relationship with each other. The decision to attend to one or the other of
these objects is only possible because of this original givenness.
There is a certain ambiguity here, and a number of questions remain
hanging: Are there any “natural” or universally acknowledged figures
whose emergence does not depend on the interests of particular individu-
als or groups? Do the figures exist as figures before the choice made? Sartre
is pulled in two directions. First, he is taking the side of realism and fighting
against the idealistic notion that things are constituted solely in terms of the
cognitive structures of the human subject.16 Second, he nevertheless wants
to affirm that perception and understanding are unavoidably human.
mediate practical use of them. It means that our broadest values and pur-
poses define the kind of objects we give our attention to. Our purpose may
simply be to understand something, or to contemplate something, or to
honor something, or to move past something—but we have to have at least
some reason for relating to it, some value we assign to our interaction with
it. There is a reciprocal relationship between human desire and the instru-
mentality we attribute to things.18 Sartre’s examples here are more con-
nected with sense perception and practical purposes, but he is making the
wider point that any kind of knowledge or understanding must be related
to some particular purpose, and ultimately to some overarching project—
even if that purpose is aesthetic contemplation or a desire to satisfy one’s
intellectual curiosity.
When Sartre writes that objects are revealed to us in “a complex of in-
strumentality [un complexe d’ustensilité],”19 he means that we only iden-
tify and understand something properly when we see how it works, how
it functions, how it fits into the dynamic context in which it is situated.
Things have a place in an active, unfolding world and not just in an ab-
stract map of sensible objects. The instrumental place that things occupy
only becomes apparent if we have some purposeful involvement in the
world. “Sense perception is in no way to be distinguished from the practi-
cal organization of existents into a world.”20 Everything refers, directly or
indirectly, to our purposes and so to ourselves as the center of these pur-
poses. There is always some relationship, however indirect, between what
things are and what we do; and there is always some relationship between
what we do and what we want.
Sartre puts it in this way: The place each thing has “is not defined by
ogy, trans. F. Kersten (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1982), 53. On the Heideggerian notion of equipment
(das Zeug: instrument, tool, gear), see Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Mac-
quarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford: Blackwell, 1962), 95–102, and translators’ footnote 1 on
97. The “readiness-to-hand” of an instrument cannot be discovered by looking “theoretically,”
we have to look with the sight of “circumspection” (looking around for something) and notice
what purpose the instrument is for. See BN 200; EN 236–37/250–51.
18. It’s important to be aware that the language of “instrumentalism” has particular nega-
tive connotations for some contemporary philosophers. Charles Taylor, for example, uses it to
refer to the loss of meaning and values that can occur in technocratic, consumerist societies.
Sartre intends something different. See Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of the
Modern Identity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 499–513.
19. BN 321; EN 361/385.
20. BN 321; EN 361/385.
100 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
a forest. They follow the same path at the same time, yet only one hears the
birdsong, only one sees the snakes, only one smells the flowers. They have
different fears, loves, instincts, hobbies, professions, etc., and these influ-
ence their perception. Even the “neutral” scientists in the group, who claim
to have a greater objectivity, have chosen their own particular object of in-
quiry, be it the humidity, the temperature, or the river formation. And if the
attention of all these people happens to converge on a single thing—say a
scream from the other side of the river, or a tree fallen across their path—
this convergence is inseparable from a convergence of their personal inter-
ests, and as soon as that interest wanes they will attend to other things. The
members of this party even notice different “things” about the same “thing.”
An animal darts in front of them and they notice its color or speed or size
or ferocity. There are innumerable properties to observe in any thing, and
our interests always determine which we attend to. As soon as things are
stripped of the meanings and references that purposeful human beings
have given them, they vanish into abstraction. Our interest is like a light
that illuminates things.25 The light is not what it illuminates, yet nothing
can appear without it.
Sartre returns to this relationship between objective fact and subjective
purpose in a later section of Being and Nothingness entitled “My Place.”26
Here, aided by his discussions of freedom, Sartre admits that there is an
“antimony.” On the one hand, “human-reality originally receives its place
[place] in the midst of things”—we find ourselves to be in a certain place
and we have to accept that. On the other hand, “human-reality is that by
which something such as place comes to things”—we give structure to an
otherwise chaotic collection of things and organize them into a place by
determining what they mean for us. In Sartre’s use of the term there can-
not be an abstract, nonhuman place, yet we “receive” our place without
manipulating the things we find.27
His response to this antinomy is not so much to offer a resolution as to
reinforce the necessity of this double truth. He revisits earlier arguments
and shows how there is never a pure contemplation of objects or a disin-
25. Joseph Fell applies this metaphor to Sartre’s account of instrumentality; see Joseph P.
Fell, Heidegger and Sartre: An Essay on Being and Place (New York: Columbia University Press,
1979), 74.
26. BN 489–96; EN 535–41/570–76.
27. BN 491; EN 536/571.
102 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
terested apprehension of data. Being there in that place is, for example, be-
ing near to something we remember or far from someone we love; being
there is being able to reach the teapot or read in the light from the win-
dow; being there is waiting for my discharge from the army in a hundred
and ten days; being there is being hidden from my enemies. These per-
spectives involved in “being there” are not additional meanings we give
to a situation after we have cast a neutral eye over the landscape, they are
part of the original data. Every aspect of place and time and environment
and situation is somehow conditioned by the way we exist beyond being,
by our freely chosen attitudes and plans and goals. “The future—a thrown-
forward future [un futur pro-jeté]—intervenes everywhere.”28
Try as we may to disentangle some independent data from our own
purposeful schemes, we always fail. What we are really doing is replac-
ing one human scheme with another. Sartre doesn’t mention the example
of science here, but one can see how even the movement to so-called sci-
entific objectivity (detached, uninfluenced by human need) is actually the
substitution of a more universal, more widely known purposeful scheme
for that of an individual or local one. To observe, for example, how light
reacts in an experiment reproduced in different laboratories throughout
the world is still to understand light in a perspective of human purposes.
There are reasons why these people are interested in light, why they exper-
iment in this way, why they notate their results in this technical language
and not another one, etc., and these reasons reflect their individual and
communal purposes. This does not in any way undermine the utility of the
scientific project, it simply reveals its true nature—which is to understand
the world in the light of a particular collective human purpose. There is
no neutral space where people act in a premoral way, there is no practical
thinking that avoids the question of purpose and the good. There are no
facts without values.29
30. The language of “perspective” recalls the perspectivism of Nietzsche and Ortega y Gas-
set. Frederick Olafson compares Sartre’s version of perspectivism with William James’s prag-
matism; see Frederick A. Olafson, Principles and Persons: An Ethical Interpretation of Existen-
tialism (Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press, 1967), 48–49.
31. BN 306–7; EN 345–46/368–70. 32. BN 316; EN 356/380.
33. BN 306; EN 346/369. 34. BN 307; EN 346/369.
35. BN 307; EN 346/369.
104 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
This object that we are is “the contingent upsurge of one orientation among
the infinite possibilities of orienting the world.”47 The specific orientation
of my world indicates a center that is myself. Sartre calls both the orien-
tation of the world and the center of orientation my body, and concludes
that my body is both coextensive with the world and at the same time “con-
densed into this single point which all things indicate.”48
51. For their views and their influence on Sartre, see Mirvish, “Sartre on Perception and
the World.”
52. BN 324 and footnote 3; EN 364/388 and footnote 1.
53. Sartre refers to Scheler at BN 330; EN 370/395.
54. BN 481; EN 527/561. Sartre borrows Bachelard’s term.
108 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
stitute the framework, the technique, and the ends in relation to which they will
manifest themselves as limits.55
Sartre is careful not to say that our free action constitutes the things
themselves or their limits. Instead it constitutes the framework, the tech-
nique, and the ends (le cadre, la technique et les fins) through which the
limits are revealed. A “technique” is the particular type of human endeavor
or cultural practice in which someone is involved. So here the difficulty of
the rock is only revealed because those dedicated to climbing (which is the
framework) want to scale the rock (to achieve this end) using their skills
and climbing equipment (which is their technique). In itself, the notion of
“difficulty” is meaningless, yet when we seek to climb the rock it reveals
itself “as it is (i.e., resisting or favorable).”56 There is no contradiction be-
tween creativity and discovery: each requires the other. “There is no obsta-
cle in an absolute sense, but the obstacle reveals its coefficient of adversity
across freely invented and freely acquired techniques.”57
Despite these nuanced passages about the resistance we meet when we
engage with the world, Merleau-Ponty still believed that Sartre gave too
little weight to the objective reality of the world and to our concrete being.
It is worth examining some of his criticisms in order to appreciate what
Sartre was really doing. Merleau-Ponty accepted that the central thesis of
intentionality was meant to preserve phenomenology from idealism. The
subject is not trapped within the structures of the mind since conscious-
ness is transparent to what is other than itself. But he drew attention very
early on to some dangers inherent in Sartre’s notion of transparency.58
Merleau-Ponty believed that Sartre held to a kind of Cartesian dualism
that did not allow for an “interworld”—a world between the transparent
subject and the impenetrable object, a world between one human subjec-
tivity and another.59 In this interworld things would carry a weight from
elsewhere, they would suggest and sometimes impose their own meanings.
The “flesh” of others and of the world would intrude into our compre-
hension more forcefully than Sartre allows. Without the interworld, con-
sciousness would be rootless and isolated.
Merleau-Ponty picks up Sartre’s example of fatigue, and agrees that it
is not an objective motive that causes us to halt on a journey. We have to
decide freely to give in to it. But there is nevertheless a kind of “sedimen-
tation” of our life; some attitudes have a “favored status” and become more
“probable.”60 Freedom presupposes a situation whose meaning we have not
chosen. Two passages express this insight very clearly.
We therefore recognize, around our initiatives and around that strictly individ-
ual project which is oneself, a zone of generalized existence and of projects al-
ready formed, significances which trail between ourselves and things and which
confer on us the quality of man, bourgeois or worker.61
The choice which we make of our life is always based on a certain givenness. My
freedom can draw life away from its spontaneous course, but only by a series of
unobtrusive deflections which necessitate first of all following its course—not
by any absolute creation. [.....] I am a psychological and historical structure, and
have received, with existence, a manner of existing, a style. All my actions and
thoughts stand in a relationship to this structure.62
These are penetrating criticisms, and if they are correct they will under-
mine Sartre’s philosophical project. The key question is this: Is the phenom-
enology of Being and Nothingness irreparably idealistic or does it already al-
low for the intrusion of an “interworld” into human consciousness?
Sartre’s answer is straightforward: There are many ways in which we
are already formed, many ways in which our actions depend on a momen-
tum and direction we have not freely given them, many occasions when
we participate without reflection in the projects of others. Yet all of these,
if they are to have any significance for us in our world, have to be given a
personal meaning in the light of our purposes and projects. We have to
make sense of them for ourselves. This is not a denial of the dense given-
ness of ourselves and of the world, it is the very way that we appropri-
ate this givenness and ensure that it does not sit unacknowledged on the
fringes of consciousness.
Knowledge Is Human
In this struggle to integrate the subjective influence of human perspective
and the objective givenness of the world Sartre is trying to integrate two
distinctive strands of phenomenology: the more personal-subjective phi-
losophy of Husserl and the more impersonal-objective philosophy of Hei-
degger. In Husserl’s phenomenology one’s first outlook on life is the natu-
ral attitude. With this initial attitude, Husserl writes, “I continually find the
69. Despite insisting that human life has its own momentum and direction, Merleau-Pon-
ty still gave the final word to freedom: “As long as we are alive, our situation is open, which im-
plies both that it calls up specially favoured modes of resolution, and also that it is powerless to
bring one into being by itself ”; see Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, 442.
70. BN 512–21; EN 557–65/594–603. 71. BN 515; EN 560/598.
72. BN 516; EN 561/598.
73. For further comments on this point, see chapter 5.
112 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
one spatiotemporal actuality to which I belong like all other human beings
who are to be found in it and who are related to it as I am. I find the ‘actu-
ality,’ the word already says it, as a factually existent actuality and also ac-
cept it as it presents itself to me as factually existing.” 74 This is not a world
merely of facts and affairs, it is at the same time a world of values, a world
of goods, a practical world. When we perform the epoche and “bracket”
this natural attitude we realize that these facts, values, and meanings are
dependent on the structures of understanding brought by the human sub-
ject.75 We still attend to the same “world,” to the same facts, values, and
meanings, but we no longer accept them in an unreflective way, we realize
that their force depends on their place in our subjective processes. Thomas
Busch writes that in Husserl’s epoche “objects, thus reduced to the status
of meanings for consciousness, are further grasped as constituted by the
meaning-giving acts of consciousness.”76 There are risks here which even
the most sympathetic phenomenologist such as Robert Sokolowski ac-
knowledges. This emphasis on subjective constitution leaves Husserl “with
the content of constitution as an unexplained residuum, a pure facticity
which escapes the principles of his philosophy.”77 This is why Sartre’s read-
ing of Heidegger in the late 1930s proved so timely. Heidegger’s Dasein re-
rooted him in the givenness of the world (the very givenness that attracted
him to Husserl in the first place). It gave him a corrective to Husserl’s sub-
jectivity, even though Sartre persisted quite consciously in using the more
subjective phrase réalité-humaine as a substitute for the impersonal Da-
sein.
Did Sartre’s project of integrating Husserl and Heidegger succeed? Was
he able to present a convincing picture of a subjective objectivity that pre-
serves both the human nature of experience and its objective foundations
in the world? Some commentators, such as Ronald Aronson, criticize him
78. Ronald Aronson, Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosophy in the World (London: Verso, 1980),
96–97.
79. It is interesting that in his serious and wide-ranging study Aronson makes hardly any
references (only three) to part 1 of BN, “The Problem of Nothingness” (which deals with the
structuring imposed by the for-itself through negation), and not one of these references con-
cerns negation.
114 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
80. Klaus Hartmann, Sartre’s Ontology: A Study of Being and Nothingness in the Light of
Hegel’s Logic (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1966), 135.
81. Fell, Heidegger and Sartre: An Essay on Being and Place, esp. 71–81.
82. On Sartre’s occasional references to a purer, more metaphysical conception of being-
in-itself, see Thomas W. Busch, The Power of Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in
Sartre’s Philosophy (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990), esp. 23–30. Busch believes
that the very notion of the in-itself is a muddled one “because Sartre fluctuates, in presenting
the notion, between a pure phenomenological ontology and a speculative metaphysics” (23).
83. See BN 619; EN 667/713.
84. BN 216–18; EN 253–55/268–71.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n s a r t r e = 115
itself and then knew the world in relation to itself and in terms of its own
understanding. But for Sartre “the for-itself does not exist in order subse-
quently to know [le pour-soi n’est pas pour connaître ensuite].”85 There is
no human subject that has knowledge. “Knowledge is nothing other than
the presence of being to the for-itself, and the for-itself is only the noth-
ing which realizes that presence [le pour-soi n’est que le rien qui réalise cette
présence].”86 Knowing is an absolute and primitive event, “it is the absolute
upsurge of the for-itself in the midst of being and beyond being [c’est le sur-
gissement absolu du pour-soi au milieu de l’être et par delà l’être].”87
The idealist position needs reversing (and therefore abandoning). It is
more accurate to say that we, through knowledge, are absorbed in being
than to say that the being of the world is trapped within the structures of
our knowing. There is only being, and the relation of the for-itself to the
in-itself is “a fundamental ontological relation.”88 The in-itself is affirmed
through the self-negation of the for-itself. This affirmation exists only for
the for-itself, but it is not in the for-itself, since it is an ek-stase, a being
present out there. In a later passage Sartre defends what he describes as
“something like an ontological conditioning of freedom,” “a kind of on-
tological priority [une préséance ontologique] of the in-itself over the for-
itself.”89 As Sartre writes in the conclusion to Being and Nothingness, the
for-itself has no reality except that of being the negation of being, and “its
sole qualification comes to it from the fact that it is the nihilation of an in-
dividual and particular in-itself and not of a being in general.”90 The ide-
alist dilemma (how to unite world and mind) is unnecessary. “Therefore
we have no business asking about the way in which the for-itself can be
united with the in-itself since the for-itself is in no way an autonomous
substance.”91
Sartre, in this light, grants to realism that being is present to conscious-
ness in knowledge and that “the for-itself adds nothing to the in-itself ex-
cept the very fact that there is in-itself; that is, the affirmative negation.”92
Although there are many ways in which being seems to be “structured”
by human experience, they all arise through negation and none of them
T h e S u b j e c t i v e N at u r e of O b j e c t i v e
U n d e r s ta n d i n g i n A q u i n a s
117
118 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
question of objectivity; or, to see it from the other side, the question of the
subject. (A) At the level of epistemology he wants to affirm that our un-
derstanding is inescapably human. The desire of the will influences ev-
erything. Our purposes and preferences determine when we understand,
whether we understand, what we understand, and how we understand.
Understanding is thoroughly subjective—this is what makes it personal.
Yet at the same time we understand only what is there and nothing more.
It is the intellect that understands, not the will, and it is the nature of the
intellect to be formed by the being of whatever is understood. So under-
standing is thoroughly objective as well as subjective. The emergence of
objectivity in fact depends on subjectivity. (B) At the level of action theory
and ethics Aquinas wants to affirm that the goods we seek, which deter-
mine our actions, are freely chosen by the human subject. No good (apart
from the final end) is so good that it cannot be seen in a different perspec-
tive. We can choose which perspective to take on each good, so that the
subjective attractiveness of the good depends on our choice, and our ac-
tions follow from this choice. Yet at the same time we can only be attracted
to what is actually a good, since it is the intellect alone that understands
what is good in this personal perspective.
In both epistemology and action theory Aquinas thus proposes a kind
of subjective objectivity. Objective truth is unveiled through its encoun-
ter with a purposeful subject, and the subject only grasps this truth in the
terms of its own subjective preferences. It is still, nevertheless, completely
objective. The truth, as Sartre says, is strictly human.1
At this stage the notion of subjective objectivity may seem unconvinc-
ing. In this chapter we will revisit Aquinas’s descriptions of human intel-
lect and will. Each has its own clear function. The richness of his account
comes from the fact that there is a reflexive aspect to every human act, so
that human beings know their own knowing and their own willing, and
they will each act of knowing and each act of willing. In this context, ob-
jectivity takes on a different meaning. The search for foundations is still
possible, but much more nuanced. It will help to bear in mind that this
rather technical-sounding discussion about intellect and will concerns
these broad questions of objectivity, subjectivity, and the nature of human
experience.
1. BN 218; EN 255/270.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 119
I will not pay much attention in this chapter to the differences between
Aquinas’s earlier and later writings on intellect and will because I believe
that these differences are not of great significance. There is an ongoing de-
bate about the development of Aquinas’s thinking.2 Odon Lottin proposed
that Aquinas moved from a kind of intellectual determinism (in De veri-
tate) to a more voluntarist conception of human action that highlighted
the dynamic freedom of the will (in De malo 6).3 This fits with R. A. Gau-
thier’s contention that during his second regency in Paris Aquinas under-
went some kind of personal conversion that affected his writing and miti-
gated an excessive intellectualism displayed in earlier texts. This change in
outlook could have been due to the growing influence of Augustine or to
the theological/political situation in Paris in 1270 when there were suspi-
cions that the Thomistic intellectualist position led to a denial of the free-
dom of the will.4 But Kevin Flannery, as I have already noted in the his-
torical introduction, through a textual comparison of De malo 6 and De
veritate 24:1, judges that the article in De veritate is a rewrite of at least
parts of De malo 6.5 This would make De malo 6 quite an early work. My
only concern here is to show how difficult it is to draw conclusions about
the development of Aquinas’s thinking in this area. I accept Daniel West-
berg’s conclusion that the differences are in emphasis rather than in mat-
ters of substance: There is a consistent picture of the interdependence of
intellect and will, a picture in which every action takes place for the sake
of a good that is both understood and desired; and the earlier writings—if
they are indeed earlier—pay great attention to the place of the will in the
exercise of human freedom.6
2. See Jean-Pierre Torrell, Saint Thomas Aquinas, Vol. 1: The Person and His Work (Wash-
ington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1996), 244–46; and Daniel Westberg,
“Did Aquinas Change His Mind about the Will?” The Thomist 58 (1994): esp 41–60.
3. See Odon Lottin, “Libre arbitre et liberté depuis saint Anselme jusqu’à la fin du XIIIe
siècle,” in Psychologie et morale aux XIIe et XIIIe siècles, vol. 1, 2nd ed. (Gembloux: J. Duculot,
1957), 11–389. Note that there is still a dispute about the dating of De malo 6 itself; see the His-
torical Introduction above, in the section “Aquinas: Historical and Intellectual Background.”
4. See James A. Weisheipl, Friar Thomas D’aquino: His Life, Thought, and Works (Wash-
ington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1983), 244–45; and Westberg, “Did
Aquinas Change His Mind about the Will?” 60.
5. Kevin L. Flannery, Acts Amid Precepts (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 2001), 247–49.
6. Westberg writes: “Free choice is a matter of choosing, on the part of both reason and
will, the bonum intellectum. This never changes in Thomas.” But in his later works “he came to
express more precisely that final causality had to do with the bonum aspect, and formal causal-
ity with intellectum”; see Westberg, “Did Aquinas Change His Mind about the Will?” 56.
120 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
It is worth making a final introductory note about the soul and its pow-
ers. Aquinas writes about the relationship that the human soul has with the
world. The soul (anima) in general, as we learned in chapter 2, is the pri-
mary principle of life for any living thing.7 A soul forms any living body.
It is the “shape” of each body insofar as it has this characteristic of being
alive about it.8 The human soul forms the human body. It is the “shape” of
the human body insofar as it is alive in a distinctively human way. So when
Aquinas writes that the soul relates or knows or wills we must not be mis-
led into thinking that some faculty is working of its own accord in isola-
tion from the life of the whole human being. Aquinas means that human
beings, insofar as they are acting in distinctively human ways, are doing
these things. It is not distinctively human to digest or snore or flee a pred-
ator—many other animals do these things. Yet it is distinctively human to
understand things and to act on the basis of this understanding.
In the same way, we must not treat intellect and will as if they were sep-
arately functioning substances or even biological individuals that assist the
soul in its thinking or acting, like talkative passengers in the backseat of
a car.9 Intellect and will are instead powers of the soul, which means that
they are the soul itself insofar as it is capable of acting in certain ways and
relating to certain objects.10 So to say that the intellect takes in or the will
goes out is simply to say that living human beings are doing these distinc-
tively human things. David Gallagher writes that “it is not the powers—
reason, will, appetite, etc.—which act, but the individual human person.”11
This is a holistic way of understanding the human being that still allows
one to analyze the distinct elements involved in human action.
7. ST I.75:1c.
8. ST I.75:5c.
9. Simon and Donagan warn against these dangers, without using this metaphor. See Yves
R. Simon, Freedom of Choice (New York: Fordham University Press, 1969), 97; and Alan Dona-
gan, “Thomas Aquinas on Human Action,” in The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philos-
ophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1982), 654.
10. See ST I.77:1.
11. David M. Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgment in Thomas Aquinas,” Archiv für
Geschichte der Philosophie 76 (1994): 276.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 121
Human beings thus relate to the world in two distinctive and comple-
mentary ways. Through the intellect they take in what is outside them.
This “bringing inside” is actually a way of describing the intellect as it “ex-
tends itself to what is outside it”—so there is no danger of forgetting that
knowledge is a relationship we have with things and not just an internal
possession of thoughts about things. Through the will human beings go
out in rem exteriorem, “toward the external thing.” Willing is a movement
that brings about a change in our active relationship with the world and
not just in our understanding. We involve ourselves, as Aquinas writes in
De veritate, with “the being that the thing has in itself ” and not just with its
being as it is understood.13
Human beings take things in through the intellect and go out to them
through the will; they think and they act; they understand the world and
they try to achieve things in this world. There seems to be a natural pro-
gression from understanding to willing, and in a number of places Aqui-
nas writes in a straightforward way about the dependence of the will on
the intellect. We touched on this topic in chapter 2. We share with all ani-
mals an ability to be moved by what we apprehend in our environment.
“An animal is able to desire what it apprehends, and not only that to which
it is inclined by its natural form.”14 The will depends, moreover, on reason
to supply its object.15 Three passages illustrate this point.
The will does not do the ordering, but tends to something as it is ordered by
reason. Consequently this word “intention” indicates an act of the will, presup-
posing the ordering of the reason as it orders something to the end.16
The goodness of the will depends properly on the object. Now the will’s object is
proposed to it by reason. Because the good as it is understood [bonum intellec-
tum] is the object of the will proportioned to it.17
If then we consider the movement of the powers of the soul on the part of the
object specifying the act, the first principle of motion is from the intellect, for in
this way the good as it is understood [bonum intellectum] moves even the will
itself.18
In this scheme it is the intellect that first understands what is good and
the will that consequently seeks it. There are so many fitting examples one
could imagine: A woman sees that a job advertised in the newspaper has
a high salary, so she puts in an application for the post. A man catches
sight of a particularly striking painting in a gallery, so he sits down to con-
template it. A child is learning to read, so her parents help her with her
homework. There are objective goods here—money, beauty, literacy—and
they have to be understood by the intellect before they can be sought by
the will. While there is certainly much more to acting than simply under-
standing, nevertheless we cannot desire or act unless we already have an
objective understanding of the goods before us:
The object of the intellect is more simple and more absolute than the object of
the will, since the object of the intellect is the very meaning of desirable good
[ipsa ratio boni appetibilis]; and the desirable good, whose meaning is grasped
by the intellect [cuius ratio est in intellectu], is the object of the will.19
14. ST I.80:1c.
15. Reason (ratio) and intellect are the same power in human beings, though they work in
different ways. Through intellect we apprehend intelligible truth; through reason we build on
this truth and connect it with other truths and so arrive at a deeper intelligible truth. See ST
I.79:8.
16. ST I-II.12:1ad3. 17. ST I-II.19:3c.
18. DM 6c [339–43]. 19. ST I.82:3c.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 123
It is difficult to translate this passage fairly, yet the main idea is clear. In
order for the will to be attracted to a good, the intellect must first take in
the fact that something is good and desirable [ipsa ratio boni appetibilis], it
must comprehend its ratio, its meaning.
The will, therefore, depends on the intellect. The intellect takes priority.
In ST I.82:4, however, Aquinas tries to look at the question in another way.
In the first articles of question I.82 Aquinas accepts that the will moves hu-
man beings toward their beatitudo (happiness), toward their perfect good
(art. 1), by seeking certain particular goods (art. 2), in response to the un-
derstanding that the intellect has of what is good (art. 3). Bonum enim intel-
lectum movet voluntatem, “the good which is understood moves the will.”20
Then, in article 4, Aquinas shifts to another level and asks whether the will
moves the intellect. At first sight this is a surprising and perhaps unnec-
essary question. One might think that Aquinas has already resolved the
question of the order of intellect and will. The will, he has already shown,
is the movement of human beings toward the good as it is presented by
the intellect. Now, strangely, Aquinas asks whether this process of under-
standing is itself something that we have to want. This is a reflexive ques-
tion about whether the act of the intellect, which furnishes the will with its
object, is itself something that we desire, something that we actively seek,
something for which we are responsible.
Reflexivity is a hugely significant issue, and it will allow us to return
to the subject of self-consciousness that we touched on in part one. It is
worth looking at ST I.82:4 in depth, together with the related articles DV
22:12 (“Does the will move the intellect and the other powers of the soul?”),
ST I-II.9:1 (“Whether the will is moved by the intellect?”), and certain pas-
sages in DM 6. The insights it provides might help us to answer some of
the questions that were left hanging at the end of part one: How are we
conscious of our consciousness of things? How are we present to our pres-
ence to things? How can we at one and the same time affirm and question
our identity and our understanding of the world?
The objections to the reflexive thesis of ST I.82:4 all revolve around the
problem of priority. I will paraphrase the three short arguments. Objection
1: It has already been established (in art. 3) that the intellect precedes and
20. ST I.82:3ad2.
124 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
moves the will by its understanding of the good. (In DV 22:12obj1 Aquinas
cites Augustine: “For nothing is loved or desired unless it is known.”)21 Ob-
jection 2: It is the nature of the will to move (the human being) after it has
been moved (by the good that is understood), and it is the nature of the in-
tellect to move the will (by understanding the good) on the basis of some-
thing that does not move (the apprehended good). In other words, there is
a nonmoving foundation to movement, a source of movement, which in
this case is the goodness of the object understood. In other words, the re-
ality of the world is what founds our understanding and therefore our de-
sires. Objection 3: Aquinas will not allow any room for some kind of un-
motivated, purposeless, irrational willing. The will is precisely the rational
appetite, and “we can will nothing but what we understand.”22 So if the will
does move us to understand, it must have a reason to do this, and so we
must already think that it is good to understand at this moment. This will-
ing (of the process of understanding) must be on the basis of some prior
understanding, by the intellect, of the goodness of this act of understand-
ing. This prior understanding would itself have needed willing, “and so on
indefinitely, which is impossible.”23 In other words, if willing is to be ratio-
nal, there must be at least some foundation in the intellect for the initial
act of willing.
All three objections argue that the priority of the intellect is essential
to the whole structure that Aquinas has been working to build. Without
this priority: (obj1) our understanding has no objective foundation in the
world, (obj2) our willing has no objective foundation in what is under-
stood, and (obj3) a vicious circle of understanding and willing is created
in which there is no beginning and no possibility of justifying any thought
or action.
Aquinas never renounces this principle that the will can only ever seek
what the intellect presents to it as good. The “end that moves” gives shape
and direction to the movement. In DV 22:12 Aquinas characterizes this end
as the ratio agendi, the ratio movendi: it is the reason for acting, the pattern
or meaning or sense of this particular movement. He clarifies this issue by
saying that the ratio agendi is “the form of the agent by which it acts.” This
form “is in the agent by way of intention,” through its reception by the in-
tellect, and “not according to the existence it has of its nature [non secun-
dum esse naturae].”25 The intellect, therefore, grasps the goal to be achieved
and presents it to the will, it praeconcipit (“conceives beforehand”) the ra-
tio of the end.
The second way in which one thing is said to move another thing is
this:
A thing is said to move as an agent, in the way that what causes an alteration
moves the thing it alters, and what pushes moves what is pushed [sicut alterans
movet alteratum, et impellens movet impulsum]. In this way the will moves the
intellect and all the powers of the soul.26
28. In ST I-II.9:1 and DM 6c “determination” and “specification” are synonymous and used
interchangeably. In ST I-II.10:2 Aquinas writes only of “specification.”
29. ST I-II.9:1c.
30. ST I-II.9:1c.
31. This is why Aquinas writes that the intellect is a power of the soul (which can be acting
or not acting) and is not to be identified with the essence of the soul (which simply is as long as
the human being is alive). See ST I.77:1.
32. ST I.82:4c.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 127
There are a number of points to note here. The will activates an act of
understanding but does not specify the content of the understanding. This
activation is for the sake of an end, which is the universal good that the
human being seeks, and so the activation is itself based on a prior under-
standing of the universal good. Yet there is not a vicious circle, since the
prior understanding of happiness that motivates the will is not the same as
the particular understanding which the intellect achieves now in this par-
ticular act of understanding.
A similar argument is put forward in DM 6:
But if we consider the movement of the powers of the soul on the part of the
exercise of the act, in this way the principle of motion is from the will. For the
power to which the principle end pertains always moves to act the power to
which pertains that which is for the end, for example the military art moves the
bridle-maker to operate. And in this way the will moves both itself and all the
other powers: for I understand because I will to, and likewise I use all the other
powers and habits because I will to do so.33
The faculties are not separate agents. Although we can identify the distinct
stages involved in this mutual determination of intellect and will, there is a
unified process taking place. David Gallagher explains it this way:
When we say, in a kind of shorthand, that the will moves the intellect or the in-
tellect moves the will, we always mean that the person voluntarily exercises his
capacity to know or that the person, through an act of knowing, determines
himself to choose one act or another.35
The exercise of the intellect’s act and the specification of the will’s act occur
together, as part of a single process with distinct aspects.
35. Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgment in Thomas Aquinas,” 276.
36. ST I.82:4ad1.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 129
So, in some respects, the will is an object for the intellect, and in other re-
spects, the intellect for the will. There is no suggestion, however, that one
consideration excludes the other. The simultaneous reflexivity of intellect
and will is a perpetual possibility, as Aquinas implies in the conclusion to
this reply, which repeats a thought from ST I.16:4ad1.
From this we can understand why these powers encompass each other in their
acts [hae potentiae suis actibus invicem se includunt], because the intellect un-
derstands the will to will, and the will wills the intellect to understand [quia in-
tellectus intelligit voluntatem velle, et voluntas vult intellectum intellegere]. In the
same way good is contained under truth, inasmuch as it is an understood truth,
and truth is contained under good, inasmuch as it is a desired good.38
When this same argument about the mutual influence of acts of intellect
and will on each other is referred to in ST I-II.17:1 Aquinas adds the fol-
lowing seemingly paradoxical conclusion: “The result is that an act of rea-
son precedes an act of will, and conversely [actum voluntatis praeveniri ab
actu rationis, et e converso].”39
These statements about reflexivity could not be clearer, but they raise the
question of what it means for something to act on itself. In ST I-II.9:3 Aqui-
nas addresses this question by asking how the will can move itself. He con-
cludes that in willing an end it can will the means to this end, although in
this case something that is actual (the will already willing the end) brings
about a new willing (the will willing the means) that was only potential,
and so the will does not move itself to move “in respect of the same” (se-
cundum idem).41 This clarification of a necessary order within the reflexive
activity of each power is what stops Aquinas’s claims descending into ab-
surdity; in chapter 6 we will look at the hierarchy of goods and truths that
stabilizes human action. Yet we should not shy away from that element of
40. DV 22:12c.
41. ST I-II.9:3ad1.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 131
circularity that haunts these discussions about reflexivity and which Aqui-
nas readily acknowledged:
Since there is in reflection a certain similarity to circular motion, in which what
is last in the movement is what was originally the beginning [Cum in reflexione
sit quaedam similitudo motus circularis in quo est ultimum motus quod primo
erat principium], we must so express ourselves in regard to reflection that what
was originally prior then becomes posterior.42
A final citation on this subject leaves no doubt about the reflexive pro-
cesses involved in something like choice:
Choice precedes use, if they be referred to the same object. But nothing hin-
ders the use of one thing preceding the choice of another. And since the acts
of the will react on one another, in each act of the will we can find both con-
sent and choice and use; so that we may say that the will consents to choosing,
and consents to consenting, and uses itself in consenting and choosing [volun-
tas consentit se eligere, et consentit se consentire, et utitur se ad consentiendum et
eligendum].43
These are huge claims, as radical as anything in Sartre, about the capac-
ity we have to take a view on ourselves and on our involvement with the
world. Aquinas seems to go even further than Sartre by stating that the in-
tellect can even reflect upon the essence of the soul (see above, DV 22:12c).
He proposes all this without any danger of dualism, without any sugges-
tion of a separate self.
What is the point of introducing this reflexive second level to the func-
tioning of the soul? Is it not enough for human beings to relate to the world
without relating to their own powers? What is the difference, for example,
between willing and willing to will, between knowing and knowing that one
knows? Why the duplication? The answer is that it will allow Aquinas to ex-
plain how human beings are free. If we apprehend our own involvement
with the world we can assess what we are doing and why we are doing it, we
can judge what we wish to understand and whether we want to act. Aquinas
believes that we have a presence-to-self through this presence to our acts of
intellect and will. Without this we cannot be free. His central contention,
42. DV 22:12ad1.
43. ST I-II.16:4ad3.
132 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
repeated time and again, is that human beings do not just take in the world
through knowledge and reach out to it through desire, we also know our
own knowing and desiring, and desire our own knowing and desiring.
Understanding, therefore, is an act of the intellect that only takes place
when it is wanted by the will. There are different levels to this. To under-
stand anything at all, to understand in general, we have to want to under-
stand in general, we have to want the intellect to function. To understand
this object, we have to want to understand this object. To understand this
aspect of this object, we have to want to understand this aspect of this ob-
ject. This never means that the will is determining the nature of what is
understood, since this formal determination is specified solely by the ob-
ject and apprehended by the intellect. Yet it means that whenever we un-
derstand anything we have to think that it is good to understand, and good
to understand this object, and good to understand this object in this way.
Each level of understanding is an act that needs willing, although the dif-
ferent acts may be implicitly willed in a single act.
There are many unresolved issues here, and I will leave most of them
hanging. I will return to the problems of circularity, priority, and the foun-
dation of our ultimate goals in chapter 6 on freedom. But one note needs
to be made at this stage about ST I.82:4ad3, which seems to undermine the
thesis I am presenting here, and indeed the arguments Aquinas has put
forward in the rest of the article. The third objection was concerned with
the infinite regress that seems to be established if the will moves the in-
tellect to understand, and if that very willing requires some prior under-
standing, and so on. Aquinas replies:
There is no need to go on indefinitely, but we must stop at the intellect as hav-
ing priority [sed statur in intellectu sicut in primo]. For some apprehension must
precede every movement of the will, whereas not every apprehension is pre-
ceded by a movement of the will [Omnem enim voluntatis motum necesse est
quod praecedat apprehensio, sed non omnem apprehensionem praecedit motus
voluntatis]. But the principle of counselling and understanding is an intellectual
principle higher than our intellect, and this is God [Sed principium consiliandi
et intelligendi est aliquod intellectivum principium altius intellectu nostro, quod
est Deus]—as Aristotle says in the Eudemian Ethics. And in this way he shows
that there is no need to proceed indefinitely.44
Taken out of context, the central phrase seems to deny the interdepen-
dence of intellect and will: “..... not every apprehension is preceded by a
movement of the will.”45 It appears to contradict Aquinas’s argument ear-
lier in the same article that, as far as the activation of the intellect is con-
cerned (per modum agentis), “the will moves the intellect and all the other
powers of the soul”; and that, as far as the powers include each other in
their acts, “the intellect understands that the will wills, and the will wills
the intellect to understand.”46 But the reply needs to be read carefully. It is
not at all clear in what respect the intellect has priority, or what kind of ap-
prehension is at issue here. Does Aquinas mean that sometimes the intel-
lect functions in isolation from the will, as if we have two distinct modes of
knowing (one willed, the other not); or two distinct objects of knowledge
(one kind willed, and the other not)? Such an interpretation would seem to
run counter to the body of the article and to the response to the first objec-
tion, and it would leave us with acts (of knowing) that were not truly hu-
man acts, in the terms set by Aquinas, since they would not include the ac-
tive involvement of the human person which is signified by the will.
Or perhaps there is some initial apprehension at the beginning of any
process of deliberation when a possible goal “comes to mind,” not because
we have decided to investigate it, but because of external circumstances or
because of the “internal” workings of our memory or imagination or sub-
conscious. Sometimes things just happen, sometimes thoughts just “hap-
pen,” and we have to determine whether to focus our attention on them
and pursue them, or whether to let them fall away. Eleonore Stump, in con-
sidering this third reply, gives the example of hearing the telephone ring
when one is immersed in another activity.47 We hear the telephone; we re-
flect on whether to answer it or not; and then we stop what we are doing
and go to answer it. There is no question of an infinite regress here, since
this particular process of decision making began with an unexpected event
45. It is striking how often this phrase is quoted in isolation as a kind of proof-text. See,
e.g., P. S. Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on the Will,” Review of Metaphysics 56
(2003): 845–46; and T. H. Irwin, “The Scope of Deliberation: A Conflict in Aquinas,” Review of
Metaphysics 44 (1990): 23–24, where Irwin refers to the passage, and concludes that “intellect is
prior to will and independent of it” (23), and that “the intellect operates independently of the
will and initiates the motions of the will” (24)—which seems to be drawing far too much from
Aquinas’s few words.
46. ST I.82:4c and ST I.82:4ad1.
47. Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (Abingdon, U.K.: Routledge, 2003), 282.
134 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
48. This interpretation would create a parallel with DM 6c (390–91), which tackles the ap-
parent circularity of willing and taking counsel, and concludes that the will must be moved “by
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 135
something external, by the impulse of which the will begins to will [ab aliquo exteriori, cuius
instinctu voluntas velle incipiat]”—namely, God.
136 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
our will could not be attracted to a particular good unless we were seeking
our greatest good through it. (1:7) All human beings share in this desire for
their own fulfillment, but they do not all agree about which good will sat-
isfy this ultimate longing. Some desire riches, some pleasure, others some-
thing else.
So all human actions take place for the sake of the ultimate good of the
one who acts. We can now combine this conclusion with the earlier con-
clusion that the functioning of the intellect is an act that must be willed.
This means that all our understanding has to occur within the framework
of our goals and desires. No understanding is neutral or passive, it never
just comes to us, even though the content of understanding comes from
the object. There is therefore always a personal stake in human under-
standing, it depends on a commitment to our final goal, and it only takes
place if we judge that understanding is a good that helps us achieve our fi-
nal goal. This has nothing to do with the distinction between the specu-
lative and the practical intellects.51 All acts of the intellect, speculative as
much as practical, are acts that have to be wanted and willed because they
are good and because they help us to achieve our final goal. Acts both of
the speculative and the practical intellect have to be judged (by the practi-
cal intellect) to be worthwhile.
Objective knowledge therefore requires the personal commitment of
the subject, and each single act of understanding has to be wanted as a
means to our happiness. In this sense our objective understanding of the
world reflects our subjective attitude to the world. Understanding is still
not in any way specified by the desires of the subject, but the fact that there
is any understanding at any moment is completely dependent on our deep-
est personal desire. Our desire to understand (or not) influences the way
the world is revealed to us, and different human worlds emerge, depend-
ing on the interest of the subject. This is true even before we take into ac-
count what our specific interests are. The measure of our interest as such
affects the world we allow ourselves to encounter. We can take an example.
Some tourists visit London together. One doesn’t want to learn anything
because he is tired from the journey; one hates learning because she as-
sociates it with dull school lessons; one is hungry for knowledge so he can
51. See ST I.79:11, where Aquinas explains that they are the same power directed either to
consideration of the truth or to operation.
138 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
use it to impress people at home; another wants to understand all she sees
in order to please the tour guide. They have different reasons for under-
standing or not understanding the world they are in, for exercising their
intellect. Their desire will determine whether they take in this world or
not, yet the world they take in will not depend on them at all. In this sense
the world that each of them discovers is a human world and depends com-
pletely on the ultimate goal that motivates them. David Burrell writes of
Aquinas’s view:
Knowledge or information can be assimilated only in the measure we have
sought it. This is not to say, of course, that we find only what we’re looking for!
We may well be surprised. But at least we have to be probing in the area which
yields the unexpected knowledge.52
So the will has to want each particular act of understanding. Put another
way, we can only understand something if we think it is good to under-
stand. It is vital to remember that it is the goodness of the act of under-
52. David B. Burrell, Aquinas: God and Action (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1979), 121.
53. ST I.82:4ad1.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 139
standing that is in question at this reflexive level, and not the goodness of
the object of understanding, which is determined by the being of the ob-
ject itself. The intellect alone discerns the goodness of a thing.54
54. We shall see in chapter 6 why a good object does not necessarily move the will even
when it is understood by the intellect.
55. ST I-II.10:2c.
140 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
Aquinas imagines that part of an object is hidden in shadow. Let’s say that
a bright scarf is carelessly placed in an open drawer, with one end dangling
out over the front. When we look at the end hanging in the light of the
room, we see it quite clearly. But if we peer into the back of the drawer we
can hardly see the scarf—its color and even its outline are indistinct in the
darkness and we cannot distinguish it from the gloves and T-shirts. Aqui-
nas wants to make a subtle distinction on which his whole philosophy of
freedom depends. There is a difference, he believes, between (A) not look-
ing at something and (B) looking at something without seeing it—even
though in both cases we fail to see the thing. In the first case, we turn our
gaze away from something. In the second case, we turn our gaze to a dif-
ferent part of the same thing, and this shift of attention means we are un-
able to see the object because of the nature of the object or of the circum-
stances.
This slightly strained analogy allows Aquinas to say that it is possible
for us to see an object in a different way, and even to see “something” dif-
ferent, even though we are looking at the same thing. We have different
56. The analogy is difficult to follow. Aquinas writes that the color of an object can be in
actu or not. The sense seems to be that the surface of an object can be illuminated and visible,
or in darkness and therefore invisible. I have translated the texts quite freely with this mean-
ing in mind.
57. ST I-II.10:2c.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 141
58. ST I-II.10:2c.
59. DM 6c [441–49].
142 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
We have here one of the most striking conclusions from the discussion so
far: Any other particular goods, insofar as they are lacking in some good, can
be regarded as nongoods. This is going to be the foundation of Aquinas’s
defense of freedom in chapter 6. It’s easy to think of examples. We look at a
cake and can consider either how tasty it is or how fattening it is; we inves-
tigate a new business venture and can consider either the benefits it could
bring or the financial risks it presents; we bump into a friend and can call
to mind either her past generosity or her past impatience. Our response in
each situation will be determined by the specific consideration we make,
and not just by the object in view. The important thing to realize is that in
each example the intellect can see both points of view. Both are true. Both
truths are specified by the object. It is as if there are two rival acts of the in-
tellect, two potential thoughts. But in fact they are both held at the same
time. Either truth can be set aside or approved by the will. When the will
does approve one truth it is not determining what is true, it is determin-
ing that a truth shall be noticed, by exercising a specific act of the intellect.
The will is not determining what is good, it is determining which aspect of
the good is understood. The reflexivity of the powers of the soul is essential
here, since the will is exercising and so controlling the act of the intellect
and not the specification of the good.
It is important to appreciate the significance of what Aquinas is doing
here. He is trying to find a third way between intellectualism and volunta-
rism. Let us take each of these in turn. (A) Intellectualism: If the specifica-
tion of the good depends solely on the object and our intellectual appre-
hension of that object, then the will must inevitably follow that good. It has
no leeway, it cannot reinterpret the good, since the intellect is formed by
the object alone. Intellectualism leads to determinism. (B) Voluntarism: If,
alternatively, the will can specify what is good without being bound by our
intellectual apprehension of the object, then we will certainly have more
control over our goals and our actions, but our desires will not be rooted
in the objectively apprehended reality of the world. Voluntarism leads to
irrationalism. (C) Aquinas’s Third Way: If, however, we can apprehend
with our intellect a single object but view that object in different ways, the
different views might attract or repel us in different ways. Intellectual de-
terminism is avoided, because we are freely choosing to see this aspect of
something rather than another aspect, and our actions will depend on our
willingness to attend to the goodness of one aspect or the other. Equally,
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 143
So the reason changes its consideration and in this way the will is brought
to seek a certain good. It is usually a bad thing, for example, to be cut open
with a knife, but the patient accepts this at the hands of the surgeon who is
trying to remove a tumor. The farmer wants to rejoice when it rains after a
long drought but he is sad that the school sports day is ruined. A child falls
into a surging river and a stranger hesitates on the bank, thinking alterna-
tively of the danger of jumping in and of the duty of helping. This does not
mean that human beings can change their final good, which is always the
complete perfection of happiness. The particular goods that we are reinter-
preting at any moment are always a means to our ultimate end. The neces-
sity of our final end is one element of Aquinas’s scheme that saves it from
circularity and absurdity. Yet in each example the particular good under
60. ST I-II.13:6.
144 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
consideration will only be appreciated and sought if the will wants to con-
sider it.
These two articles from Part I-II allow Aquinas to draw a startling con-
clusion. Every single particular good can be freely apprehended as not-
good, without compromising in any way the objectivity of good and the
openness of the intellect to truth. Every single particular good can thus be
willed or not willed, depending on the point of view we take on it.
is good to be interested in. They see different worlds, and the type of world
they see depends on the type of world they want to see, even though the ac-
tual building or clothes or time they discover is determined by the nature of
what they find in this world.
If they all look at the clock at the same time, will they see the same
time? Of course they will. But they will only look at the clock if they have
a reason to, and so their common discovery of a common time in a shared
world will only take place if their individual interests converge on the
same “object” (which is “the clock as timekeeper” and not just “the clock
as beautiful object”). This is true even if their reasons for wanting to know
the time are different. So the commonness of the time is not some neu-
tral reality that unites them despite their disparate interests—it only unites
them if their interests unite them around this common subject.
Is it possible for something to capture their attention and unite them
in a commonly understood world? Is it possible to take them outside the
realms of their personal interests? It might seem so, but this would be de-
ceptive. Say that a passing stranger screams and falls to the ground clutch-
ing her heart, and all three of them look to see what is happening. It’s true
that something outside their immediate interests has caught their atten-
tion, but it is not divorced from their wider personal interests. They have
an interest in paying attention to unexpected disturbances in public places
for the sake of their own safety, or a concern for their fellow human be-
ings, or a curiosity about the unknown. These interests are not impersonal
and they are certainly not universal. There may be others in the station
who don’t “notice” the sound of screaming for different reasons. Some may
have learnt to filter out inconvenient sounds, perhaps because of a deep
selfishness; others may have lived in a war zone, which made them im-
mune to signs of human suffering; others may have chosen to listen to mu-
sic on headphones with the express purpose of insulating themselves from
their environment.
Once they are looking toward the scene, the three are not united in
a neutral world that has startled them away from their personal worlds,
rather they are brought together by a common interest, which is to an-
swer the question “How shall I respond to this?” Suddenly they share the
same conception of what is good: “It is good to understand what has hap-
pened and decide how I should react.” We can only understand something
if we want to understand it. How do they react to the same situation? One
146 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
goes to help, another opens the newspaper, another pulls out a camera and
starts to take photographs. They see the same situation but their personal
interests determine which aspect of the situation they see: they see it from
different perspectives. This is stronger than saying that they interpret the
same thing in different ways. They actually see different things. One sees a
sick person who needs help; another sees a growing crowd of people that
might delay the train; another sees a journalistic scoop for a local news-
paper. All these things are true, they are specifications made by the object
and apprehended by the intellect, and in theory any human being could
understand the same truth. But in Aquinas’s scheme, we can’t understand
anything unless we think it is good to understand this thing, and unless we
are attracted to this way of understanding.
There are no neutral descriptions of what has happened. Even the
seemingly objective statement “This person has had a heart attack” is a
medical description that requires a commitment to a certain worldview.
If everyone in the station adopts the medical point of view and shares in
the interests of medics, then of course everyone can understand this de-
scription and enter this world. But there is no medical understanding
without a medical interest, and one could take alternative scientific view-
points on the same incident that would reflect different interests: acousti-
cians, for example, could study the sound of the scream, physicists the fall
of the body. In other words, there is no such thing as purely neutral knowl-
edge. Knowledge without an interested, attentive, motivated knower is not
knowledge at all.
The three characters in this example think and observe and act in dif-
ferent ways because their intellects consider a common object (the station,
the collapsed person) in different ways. This in turn depends on the fact
that the will commands the exercise of the intellectual act. Human beings
have to allow themselves to start thinking and to continue thinking along
a certain line of thought, even though the understanding itself is specified
by the object under consideration. This act of the will is the foundation of
all reasoning, and it saves Aquinas from an intellectual determinism that
would insist there is only one way in which a given object or circumstance
can specify our good.
The root of liberty is the will (which is where freedom lies [sicut subiectum]) but
it is the reason that is its cause. For the will can tend freely towards a variety of
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 147
things, because the reason can have various conceptions of good [voluntas libere
potest ad diversa ferri, quia ratio potest habere diversas conceptiones boni].61
61. ST I-II.17:1ad2.
62. See Norman Kretzmann, “Philosophy of Mind,” in The Cambridge Companion to Aqui-
nas, ed. Norman Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1993), 147–48.
63. Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgment in Thomas Aquinas,” 266.
148 = h u m a n u n d e r s ta n d i n g
better, under which aspect a particular action is judged, depends upon how the
will exercises the intellect’s act in its regard.64
Aquinas’s genius lies in the fact that he locates freedom in the reflexive
procedures that establish how the world is understood. Once this world is
established, with its presently understood goods, he never needs to argue
that the will asserts its “voluntariness” or “freedom” by going against what
it understands to be good. Aquinas preserves the twin foundations of a
“deterministic” intellectual specification of what is good and a “voluntaris-
tic” exercise of the particular consideration that allows this specification.
He holds onto his cake and eats it too.
All this begs a series of further questions: What is the reason for want-
ing to understand something in one way rather than another? What makes
the will approve of one intellectual perspective and so notice one good
rather than another? What, in other words, is the ultimate foundation of
willing and understanding that saves Aquinas’s system from circularity?
These questions bring us to the issue of freedom, which will be discussed
properly in chapter 6.
66. See, e.g., Weisheipl, Friar Thomas D’aquino: His Life, Thought, and Works, 250–54, and
Edward P Mahoney, “Aquinas’s Critique of Averroes’ Doctrine of the Unity of the Intellect,” in
Thomas Aquinas and His Legacy, ed. David M. Gallagher, Studies in Philosophy and the Histo-
ry of Philosophy (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 1994).
67. Thomas Aquinas, “De Unitate Intellectus Contra Averroistas,” in Sancti Thomae De
Aquino Opera Omnia, Iussu Empensaque Leonis XIII P. M. Edita, vol. 43 (Rome:Editori di San
Tommaso, 1976). For an English translation, see Thomas Aquinas, On the Unity of the Intellect
against the Averroists, trans. Beatrice H. Zedler (Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press,
1968), chapter 5, #112.
u n d e r s ta n d i n g i n a q u i n a s = 151
H u ma n F r e e dom
Chapter 5
F r e e d o m , C h oic e , a n d t h e
I n d e t e r m i nat io n of R e a s o n i n S a r t r e
1. BN 433; EN 477/508.
155
156 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
what we are doing in this act (even if we are doing other things at the same
time); we foresee a certain result (even if there may be other unforeseen
results too); and we try to bring about this result (even if we do not suc-
ceed). Sartre gives the example of an explosion at a quarry which was an
act (and not just an accident) because the worker “intentionally realized
a conscious project” when he set off the dynamite.2 He wanted to achieve
this end, unlike another worker who carelessly discarded a cigarette and
unintentionally set off another explosion. An intention involves an ac-
tive commitment toward an end, a first step toward its realisation (this is
what distinguishes it from a dream or a wish), even if it is not achieved.
The prisoner, by trying in some way to escape, learns that he has an inten-
tion and not a mere wish to escape.3 In this dynamic structure of inten-
tion there are always three inseparable aspects: (A) each act (B) has an end
(C) that refers to a motive.4 These aspects relate to the structure of tempo-
rality: (A) each act in the present (B) takes place for the sake of a future
(C) which makes sense of and fulfills a past.5 So this is the structure of in-
tention: motive-act-end.
Sartre dismisses the idea that human actions, in order to be free, need to
be without motives. Proponents of this view “can only end up by rendering
the act absurd.”6 We should note from the start Sartre’s opposition to a view
of freedom in which free acts are gratuitous and arise without explanation
and without reference to one’s convictions or values. He has more sympathy
with determinists who stress the role of prior motives and believe that acts
arise quite predictably if a certain person is in a certain situation. But the
problem with deterministic philosophies (and with much of our everyday
thinking) is that they reify motives. Motives are treated as brute, incontro-
vertible facts that drive the human being in a predetermined direction. De-
2. BN 433; EN 477/508.
3. BN 483–84; EN 529/563–64. John Atwell writes that “for Sartre it is not self-contradic-
tory to say ‘I intended to do X, but I didn’t do it’; but it is self-contradictory to say ‘I intended
to do X, but I didn’t do anything toward doing (i.e., accomplishing) X.’ ”; see John E. Atwell,
“Sartre and Action Theory,” in Jean Paul Sartre: Contemporary Approaches to His Philosophy,
ed. Hugh J. Silverman and Frederick A. Elliston (Pittsburgh, Pa.: Duquesne University Press,
1980), 72.
4. Here I use the English word “motive” to stand for the complex of objectively found mo-
tives (motifs) and subjectively felt motivations (mobiles) which seem to “cause” an action. The
distinctions are not important at this stage. See BN 446; EN 491/522–23.
5. BN 436–37; EN 480–81/511–12.
6. BN 437; EN 481/512.
f r e e d o m i n s a r t r e = 157
terminists extrapolate from these “psychic givens” and assume that there is
an unbroken continuity between the motive, the act, and the end.7 In deter-
ministic psychological theories, for example, Gustave Flaubert’s whole life
and work might be explained in terms of his innate ambition—as if the dis-
covery of this “ambition” left nothing else to be said.8
In Sartre’s eyes the fundamental mistake is to assume that “the moti-
vation provokes the act as the physical cause its effect.” In this false view
“everything is real, everything is full”; “motive, act, and end constitute a
‘continuum,’ a plenum.”9 This is the misconception we looked at in chap-
ter 1, where one’s identity and one’s values are taken to be indisputable fea-
tures of reality which generate a certain pattern of events. Sartre argues
that factual states of affairs cannot by themselves give rise to values that
would necessitate action. He exposes the contradictions inherent in a de-
terministic appeal to motives. He argues that since motives understood as
motives must be objects of our reflective consciousness, they must there-
fore be questionable. If we are reflecting on them, then we are able to hold
them at a distance, and their power automatically to direct our conscious
acts is nullified. This, once again, is the experience of anguish.
In Sartre’s view a motive is not discovered before the act, it is consti-
tuted by the act. In the formulation of each act, there is a necessary mo-
ment of negation. The agent must recognize an end, a “desideratum,” whose
counterpart is an “objective lack” or “négatité.”10 We must go beyond the de-
termined facts in front of us and decide what is missing and what could be
desired. The emperor Constantine, for example, as we saw in chapter 1, con-
ceives of the establishment of a new Christian city in the East of his empire
to counter the decadence of Rome. This decadence is only revealed to be a
lack that motivates if it is held up against a projected ideal. Nothing in the
city of Rome by itself actually constitutes a motive and prompts the projec-
tion of a new city. A motive lies in the realm of “nonbeing,” that is, it cannot
be discovered in the being of the world.
From the moment of the first conception of the act, consciousness has been able
to withdraw itself from the full world of which it is consciousness and leave the
level of being in order frankly to approach that of non-being.11
The possibility of a new city that does not exist is what reveals that the
old city is lacking something, and Constantine’s consciousness of this moti-
vation, his dissatisfaction with the decadence of Rome, is inseparable from
his projection of a new possibility. Before the new ideal came to mind the
“decadence” of Rome was just considered to be an ordinary and acceptable
part of urban life. Similarly, a worker in the oppressive conditions of early
nineteenth-century Lyon does not necessarily see his suffering as a motive
for action. He has no contemplative distance from suffering and cannot
understand it as good or bad—it just is. “To suffer and to be are one and
the same for him.”12 His suffering only becomes a motive when he is able
to envisage a better future that does not exist. The projection of an ideal
society achieved by revolution is what allows him to see that his present
situation is not what it could be. There is a double negation here: a future
that is not the present (and which cannot be extrapolated from the present
with any necessity) and a present that is not this future. Sartre draws two
conclusions, one about the act, another about the work of consciousness,
and these shed some light on his understanding of freedom:
(1) No factual state whatever it may be (the political and economic structure of
society, the psychological “state,” etc.) is capable by itself of motivating any act
whatsoever. For an act is a projection of the for-itself toward what is not, and
that which is [ce qui est] can in no way determine by itself that which is not.
(2) No factual state can determine consciousness to apprehend it as a négatité or
as a lack. Better yet no factual state can determine consciousness to define it and
to circumscribe it [as an isolated system].13
enced as a motive. “The motivation is understood only by the end; that is,
by the non-existent.”15
The peculiar status of the end is what preserves the whole scheme from
determinism. An end is something that influences the interpretation of
these circumstances even though it exists only in our intention and not in
reality. Circumstances produce results, not ends. Ends, on the other hand,
produce circumstances, or at least they change the relationship which the
circumstances have with the future. This effects a change in the meaning
and orientation of the circumstances themselves. Ends, values, motives,
and meanings are not found in the world but only in the understanding of
a being-for-itself that can conceive of a world beyond the world of imme-
diate experience.
Ends are not, as Sartre writes, ready made and prehuman, coming
“from God, from nature, from ‘my’ nature, from society.”19 Even the “im-
pulsive” decision to save one’s life and flee from mortal danger requires a
commitment to the value of one’s life, which is a commitment not every-
one chooses to make.20 The goal, however fixed it seems, is always chosen,
if it is a conscious intention that forms part of a human act. We cannot re-
ceive our ends, “either from outside or from a so-called inner ‘nature.’ ”21
If we are acting, if we are seeking to bring about a particular future, then
we must have at least some reflective awareness that this future is not fixed
and does not arise inevitably from our present. The fact that we can ask
“What am I doing? What am I seeking to achieve here?” shows that we are
conscious of the lack of necessity about our goal and our distance from it.
In Sartre’s scheme we can only act if we realize that the end is not given to
us in our present experience. The condition of intentional action is that we
are simultaneously aware of the end as a reason for acting and of the end
as a value that we freely choose to sustain. Human reality is unavoidably
aware of its role in choosing the ends that guide its activity. “It chooses
them and by this very choice confers upon them a transcendent existence
as the external limit of its projects.”22
Sartre does not imagine that we are always in the process of establish-
ing new ends. We are often doing things in the present that we decided
to do in the past. We often take for granted a prior motive.23 This is what
gives continuity to each human life. But if we are conscious of and present
to this motive, then like all intentional objects it becomes separated from
us by a nothingness. “It can act only if it is recovered; in itself it is without
force.”24 All motives, all values, all ends—however definitive we took them
to be in the past—need to have a value continually conferred on them in
the present. Their past meaning needs to be maintained in existence, or re-
jected, or appreciated in a new way. The end we choose now is absolutely
decisive for our interpretation of all that has influenced us in the past. The
French word sens is useful because it signifies both “meaning” and “direc-
tion.” Sartre writes that it is the meaning/direction of the past (which in-
cludes our past motives and values) that must be decided by us at each
moment. “I decide it precisely and only by the very act by which I pro-ject
myself toward my ends [je me pro-jette vers mes fins].”25
Sartre argues that ends are chosen even when we react to a situation in
what seems to be an impulsive, unreflective, emotional manner. Emotions,
for Sartre, are intentional—they make up part of our project and we allow
them to steer us toward freely chosen ends. It does not make a difference
for Sartre whether the end we project is grasped by the will in a deliber-
ated, reflective mode, or by the passions in an emotional, symbolic mode.
In both cases we are freely choosing how to respond to the world and to
go beyond it toward certain values.26 It does not matter whether we un-
derstand the reason for acting to be an objective motif (“motive”) discov-
ered in the facts of the world or a subjective mobile (“motivation”) lying in
our desires and emotions. Each reflects in its own way a value projected by
freedom.27 “Motives and motivations have only the weight which my proj-
ect—that is, the free production of the end and of the known act to be real-
ized—confers upon them.”28
Sartre believes that there “is” no single answer to the young man’s ques-
tion that sits out there in the world of being. The dilemma comes about
for the very reason that there are two incompatible answers that can arise
from the same circumstances. They are incommensurable. Each of them
is “right” in its own terms. The young man’s past does indeed recommend
a future of heroic patriotism, but also of heroic filial piety—and it cannot
in this case recommend both together. Each response would have a ratio-
nal and sufficient motive for the particular response it would motivate. Yet
neither has a greater right than the other to claim the attention of the man
and to become established as a cause of his actions. There are no cross-
project or metaproject reasons that would allow one to compare the two
fundamental options.
Sartre’s advice to the young man in Existentialism and Humanism is
to say, “You’re free, choose, that is, invent.”35 Choose whether to be a duti-
ful citizen or a dutiful son. Personality will be manifested in the priorities
that guide a life, and these priorities are seen here to be a consequence and
not a cause of one’s free decisions. With this word “invent,” inventer, Sartre
draws attention to the creative aspect of choice, which brings about what
would not have existed without the choice. It is an act of origination. Yet
it is also, as the Latin root of inventer (invenire) suggests, an act of discov-
ery, of meeting what is really there. Thomas Flynn explains that the origi-
nal choice at the heart of a decision is “criterion-constituting and hence is
without antecedent reason or necessity.”36 This is not far from Aristotle’s
idea that the reasonableness of any virtuous activity can be fully recog-
nized only from within the practice bounding it, to the eyes of one experi-
enced in and engaged in that activity.37 The active free choice establishes a
structure in which the components (motive-act-end) have a place. Every-
thing within the structure has a meaning, but there is no “external” mean-
ing that will justify the structure itself. “Thinking” cannot work out which
of many incompatible “ways of thinking” is the best. There must be a su-
prarational foundation for a given mode of rationality and action. It is in
this sense that Sartre characterizes choices as “absurd.” He is not just using
audacious language for its own sake.
Choice is not absurd in the sense in which in a rational universe a phenomenon
might arise which would not be bound to others by any reasons. It is absurd in
this sense—that the choice is that by which all foundations and all reasons come
into being [.....] . It is absurd as being beyond all reasons.38
Sartre believes that the “external” foundation of action lies in the ex-
istence of human freedom itself, and he identifies this with the very being
of the for-itself. Questions of action and personhood are inseparable. The
surpassing of identity we looked at in chapter 1 is what founds the totality
“motive-act-end.” “This ensemble is ultimately myself as transcendence; it
is me in so far as I have to be myself outside of me [c’est moi en tant que j’ai
à être moi-même hors de moi].”39 Freedom is not just one of many human
capacities that we happen to activate now and then, it is the “stuff ” (l’étoffe)
of one’s being.
So if we ask the question “Why did we do this rather than that?” or
“Why did we value this rather than that?” the answer refers us to the per-
son we are. And if we ask “Why, though, are we this person?!” there is no
answer beyond the fact that we are becoming this person through our ac-
tions. When Sartre was a conscript testing his ideas about freedom on his
fellow soldiers one of them gently reminded him that he must “take people
as they are,” and his impatient reaction was to say, “Yes, but I know in my
bones that people aren’t, they do.”40 Personhood, as we saw in chapter 1, lies
not in a substantial self that is a cause or explanation of the person, it lies in
the perpetual going beyond the self required by our consciousness of self.
Our human existence is more than our essence. There is nothing more fun-
damental to which we can refer. The only “explanation” for the shape of our
actions and our existence is the fact that our being-for-itself is an original
and irreducible event. It is the single thing (in our phenomenological ex-
perience) that is not caused by something else, because its nature is pre-
cisely to project itself beyond causes toward an end.
For the for-itself, to be is to nihilate the in-itself which it is [Etre, pour le pour-
soi, c’est néantiser l’en-soi qu’il est]. Under these conditions freedom can be noth-
ing other than this nihilation. It is through this that the for-itself escapes from
its being as it does from its essence; it is through this that the for-itself is always
something other than what can be said of it.41
Sartre thus returns to themes from the beginning of Being and Nothing-
ness. The intentional act that establishes the structure “motive-act-end” is
one with this unavoidable movement beyond identity that constitutes our
very being as self-conscious creatures. So for Sartre these are not different
areas of discussion. The intentional act itself, freedom, being-for-itself, and
the choice of ends are all one thing. The “unjustifiable” adoption of one
course of action is associated with the negation that takes place at the very
heart of human consciousness.42 Freedom is “equivalent to my existence.”43
Each intentional complex of action needs an external foundation, and this
is inseparable from the movement in which we go beyond the present and
relate it to a future that does not exist. We are free to act because we have
to deny our identity and choose how to reconstitute it. “Human reality is
free because it is not enough.”44 It is wrenched away from what it is.
Human beings are free because they are not self but presence to self [L’homme
est libre parce qu’il n’est pas soi mais présence à soi]. The being which is what it is
cannot be free. Freedom is precisely the nothingness which is been [est été] at
the heart of the human being and which forces human-reality to make itself in-
stead of to be. As we have seen, for human reality, to be is to choose oneself.45
So to the ultimate question “Why this choice, this end, this purpose in
life?” there is no answer. This choice, this end, this purpose is the person
who exists in this moment. There is nothing more fundamental to which
we can point. Any other explanation would deny the phenomenological
evidence, which shows that the choice of one’s ends and the constitution of
one’s identity are one with each other, and that they are originating, foun-
dational events that cannot be reduced to anything else. It is not true to
say, “She sought this thing because she is this kind of person.” Sartre would
instead say, “She is this kind of person because she is seeking this thing,”
or better still, “This person is the seeking of this thing; this human being is
the surpassing of this world for the sake of this end.” The choice and pro-
jection of one end, which determines the whole meaning of our life, is not
determined by an already existing personal identity—it is the person who
exists in this moment in relation to this end. There is no Bergsonian “deep
self ” (moi-profond) hidden away somewhere, distinct from the manifesta-
tion of the person that takes place through action.46 Even though Sartre
paid more attention in his later works to the practical limits of freedom
and the influence of one’s environment on the formation of the self, he
never lost this basic philosophical conviction that we determine our being
by going beyond what we are. Ronald Aronson summarizes Sartre’s thesis
in this phrase: “We make ourselves from what has been made of us.”47 In
other words, it is not enough just to be ourselves: we have to adopt our-
selves and take responsibility for who we are becoming. There “are” no
ends; they are not out there waiting to be discovered.
In the search for explanations, there is nowhere further back to go than
the original choice of ends that takes place when we become aware of the in-
conclusiveness of the present. It is foundational and self-constituting since it
is precisely the response we have to make to the insufficiency of all previous
foundations. To put it in a slightly different way: Our free response to the
foundations we discover becomes foundational for the future. A phrase that
became an existentialist slogan (“existence precedes essence”) only makes
proper sense in the context of Being and Nothingness. Sartre refuses to grant
that descriptions of essence can ever account for the freely projected exis-
tence of human beings, where “essence” stands for all that is and “existence”
stands for the dynamic orientation of all that is to what it is not.48
dom and still suggest that there is some kind of overarching meaning to
each human life?
It might be helpful to consider one example of voluntaristic thinking
from the history of philosophy and see how far Sartre’s thinking is from
this. Servais Pinckaers describes the “freedom of indifference” that is pro-
posed by traditions influenced by William of Ockham.52 He contrasts this
voluntaristic view of freedom with a “freedom for excellence” proposed by
Aquinas. For our purposes it doesn’t matter whether Pinckaers is fair to
Ockham or not (or to Aquinas). I am using his presentation of voluntarism
to provide a contrast with Sartre’s position.
“Freedom of indifference” drives a wedge between freedom and rea-
son. Ockham argues that freedom resides in the will, which can respond
to the conclusions of reason by accepting them or rejecting them. Freedom
is an indetermination or a radical indifference in the will regarding con-
traries. Actions are produced in a wholly contingent way without having
any necessary orientation to the good as it has been understood by reason.
Love for the good and rational desire are replaced by a self-determining
domination. Freedom chooses without reference to one’s ultimate goal in
life or to one’s past actions. Decisions take place in an isolated present mo-
ment, disconnected from each other. Pinckaers explicitly mentions Sartre
as a figure who stands (perhaps unconsciously) in this voluntaristic tradi-
tion, although one suspects that he does not know Sartre’s work well.53
There is an order in the voluntaristic system described by Pinckaers.
First we understand the world and ourselves, and then we choose how to
act. The will functions in a context determined by reason and it chooses
whether to accept or reject the good that reason proposes. Freedom deter-
mines what we do, but it does not determine how we think about things or
how we understand the world—it takes this understanding from the rea-
son. If the will chooses against a value assigned by reason, this is not be-
cause the will values this “countervalue,” since it is only the reason that can
judge that something is valuable. There can be no reason for choosing the
52. Servais Pinckaers, The Sources of Christian Ethics, trans. Sr. Mary Thomas Noble (Ed-
inburgh: T & T Clark, 1995), 330–42.
53. Ignatius Eschmann is another reputable Thomist who uses Sartre as a voluntarist foil
against which he can set the more rational ethics of Aquinas; see Ignatius Theodore Eschmann,
The Ethics of Saint Thomas Aquinas: Two Courses (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval
Studies, 1997), 53.
170 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
countervalue—it is precisely what is against reason and what does not fit in
to a rationally established order of values and goals. This is all quite differ-
ent from Sartre. I will summarize some of the features of Sartre’s scheme
that contrast with the voluntarism described by Pinckaers, and then I will
give some examples from Being and Nothingness.
(A) For Sartre, choices about action are always comprehensible in the
light of what we understand to be good. We can only do what we under-
stand to be worthwhile and valuable. In this sense the “will” (in the lan-
guage of Ockham) is tightly integrated with the “reason” and cannot go
against its conclusions. Motive, act, and end make up an unbreakable com-
plex of reasons, actions, and values that refer to each other and depend
on each other. If someone is capricious or an action gratuitous then that
person, according to Sartre, has not acted freely. There is no such thing
for Sartre as an arbitrary human action, one without a motive or an end—
although there are many things we do accidentally (or incidentally) for
which our freedom is not responsible. This is therefore quite different (to
take another example of voluntarism) from Kierkegaard’s teleological sus-
pension of the ethical, where obedience to God’s particular commands can
take someone outside the sphere of the ethical and into an activity that is
at odds with one’s system of understood moral values.54 Kierkegaard and
Ockham allow the will to move against the recommendations of reason—
creating what could be called a nonethical freedom, or alternatively an ir-
rational ethic. Sartre’s human being has to be ethical. In his scheme we have
to live for values that are comprehensible and make sense of our life.
(B) The freedom that founds an intentional complex does not func-
tion within the reasoning determined by this complex—it is “prior” to it.
This is why freedom cannot go against reason. It is, rather, the foundation
of one line of reasoning. In the moment of choice there are no necessary
goals proposed by a rational assessment of our situation, so freedom is not
moving against any rational recommendations. It is not indifferent to “the”
good that is understood, because in the moment of choice there are no ra-
tionally persuasive values to which it can be indifferent. As we discovered
in chapter 3, the subjective involvement of human beings is what allows
the objective truth about the world to be revealed. There can be no reasons
54. See Frederick A. Olafson, Principles and Persons: An Ethical Interpretation of Existen-
tialism (Baltimore, Md.: John Hopkins University Press, 1967), 28–30.
f r e e d o m i n s a r t r e = 171
with two other unsatisfactory alternative explanations. (i) Motives are fixed
and determine our actions completely. We cannot act otherwise and so we
are not free. (ii) Free acts are those that go against our motives, that is, they
are irrational and gratuitous. Sartre describes a third way in which we have
a choice because we can allow ourselves to be moved by different motives,
by changing the understanding and values we have, and by becoming a
different person. We do not go against reason, we refound it. We rethink
reason itself. To put it another way: We can act differently because we can
adapt, expand, and transform our rationally appreciated desires. We are
free to do something different because we are free to be someone different,
and in this way the free act is always integrated with our understanding
and our rational goals and our identity. This is far from voluntarism.
It still begs the question, of course, of whether this choice to allow
oneself to be moved by different motives is a fully rational choice. Sartre
would say that this very question misses the point: The decision to let our-
selves be guided by certain motives is the very thing that allows us to be
rational; it is the foundation of rationality. There is no abstract set of rea-
sons lying outside our intentional frame of reference. We can only reason
in a particular way because we have experienced, perhaps only in anticipa-
tion, the inner logic of this choice, and been attracted by this logic. Why
do I choose to do this? Because I want to; because it makes sense; because
it is reasonable. That’s all there is to say. And if someone then asks, “Ah,
but why do you to choose to do this rather than something else?” I still
give the same answer: Because I want to; because it makes sense; because
it is reasonable. I don’t have to say, I choose this because it makes more
sense than the alternatives—since that answer only becomes true once I
have chosen it. They all make sense, that’s why I have to choose. The fact of
choosing then becomes a part of what allows us to make sense of what we
have chosen, not as an additional reason, but as the act that brings to light
the reality of this intentional path.
I know that the other courses of action are also reasonable (in different
ways). Acts are free, and once they are unfolding they make perfect sense
in the light of our motives. So acts are never gratuitous. The gratuitousness
is now moved to a different level, to that of the person, of the being of the
human agent. The reason why this person is this person lies in his or her
being, which is identical with the choice one makes about one’s existence.
To be a human being is to be free to be who one chooses to be (within
174 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
We could say that for Sartre we establish the form of our existence but
not the fact of our existing. Human beings do not create their whole be-
ing from nothing, and in this sense they share in the unjustifiability and
incomprehensibility of everything: “By this being which is given to it, hu-
man reality participates in the universal contingency of being and thereby
in what we may call absurdity.”65
there is no steady line of continuity. Only when he chooses and acts does
the vow take its place in a temporal succession of meaning. If he walks
away from the casino, the vow becomes the source of that resolution that
keeps him away. If he enters the casino, the vow becomes a pointless mo-
ment of heroism in a life otherwise wholly given to gambling. The action
in the present fixes and orientates the event in the past.
The important point to grasp is that before he acts, when he experi-
ences the anguish of having to choose, the vow has no fixed meaning. It is a
memory without force, an event without significance, and it has no mean-
ingful place in his personal history. This changes when he acts—however
he acts. By giving it meaning (in the present) he gives it a secure place
in his past. So temporality is established by and not broken by the unjus-
tifiable upsurge of the present choice. Consciousness is not a succession
of instantaneous moments isolated from each other—it is the foundation
of temporality. To be conscious is to allow an understanding of oneself to
emerge in a framework of time. Sartre puts this beautifully: To choose our-
selves is “to cause a future to come to make known to us what we are by
conferring a meaning on our past.”69 Our orientation to a future allows us
to unify the self that is seeking this future. We are “self-creating selves,”
as Phyllis Sutton Morris puts it, where the created self (who we are in the
light of our past) is formed by the creating self, which is nothing other
than the conscious bodily agent acting in the present.70
The original choice continually made in the present is in one sense an
unjustifiable foundation for all temporality, just as the act founds the mo-
tive and end. Yet in another sense the choice, no matter how radical and
spontaneous, is always an essential part of a reinterpreted temporal pro-
gression. This is why it is impossible to isolate a “new” choice from the
life it manifests. Freedom always has the two faces of sheer originality and
plodding necessity. A “new” choice, for example, is certainly an integral
part of the newly begun totality—it explains the direction of the future.
It is less obvious, but equally true, that the new choice necessarily deter-
mines itself “in connection with the past which it has to be.”71
Whatever the decision, we have to understand it in terms of our past,
69. BN 465; EN 510/543.
70. Phyllis Sutton Morris, “Self-Creating Selves: Sartre and Foucault,” American Catholic
Philosophical Quarterly 70, no. 4 (1996).
71. BN 466; EN 511/545.
f r e e d o m i n s a r t r e = 177
even if the new decision makes us realize how wrong we were before. Our
new “rightness” is a correction and in some ways a culmination or fulfill-
ment of the “wrongness” that guided us in the past. If we do something
completely unconnected with our past identity, without any reference at
all to what went before, this is not freedom—we call it madness or am-
nesia. The radical, unjustifiable choice has to justify itself and interpret
itself in the perspective of the past. Whether we fight the enemy or flee,
remain in our marriage or leave, eat the chocolate or diet, work for a mul-
tinational corporation or travel the world—in each case we will under-
stand the choice in terms of the past and see our past as building up to it
and explaining it. In each case the immediacy of the present choice, which
seems to shatter all continuity, is actually the very moment that establishes
continuity. Even the many “noncrisis” things that we do without much re-
flection—feeding our children, traveling to work, watching the TV—are
original choices, in the sense that they perpetuate and reestablish for the
present a specific temporal project (that is already under way). We give
them our implicit consent, and there is always an implicit possibility of not
doing them.
If we make a radical change, then the decision to change is what gives
new meaning even to the past choice that is rejected. The new choice is
“on principle, a decision to apprehend as past the choice for which it is
substituted.”72 This is why it is a grave misunderstanding to think that Sar-
tre’s view of original choice implies a series of discontinuous changes and
arbitrary repudiations of one’s past. A “new” choice is not “a global flip-
flop,”73 nor a wild, empty leaping of the will away from one’s established
personality and one’s present reasoning.74 Consciousness takes the past as
an object and “evaluates it and takes its bearings in relation to it.”75 Sartre
later puts this in a succinct phrase: “It is the future which decides whether
the past is living or dead.”76
Every memory is an interpretation and a certification. An event as un-
controversial as a childhood illness depends on a thousand present proj-
ects to sustain it. Sartre’s memory of having whooping cough as a four year
old depends on his commitment to a social order that uses a certain calen-
dar, to the trustworthiness of the adults who recounted it, to the medical
science that defines the condition.77 We could object that there is simply a
brute fact lodging in his memory. Sartre would say that we cannot get at
this fact—cannot select it, locate it, describe it, understand it—without the
structures of interpretation provided by our present commitments. This
doesn’t mean that we can always control which memories come to mind
and when they do (although our consent is often more important than we
admit). It does mean that whatever the memory is, it must be understood
in the light of our projects. We could also object that this overarching so-
cial order is not something one can realistically opt out of. A young boy
like Sartre brought up in early twentieth-century France did not have the
option of dating his birth by the Egyptian or Mayan calendar. Sartre would
still say that we are giving assent to the pervasive social order, and align-
ing our personal project with the larger social one, even if there are not
many live alternatives. We may not be responsible for the values of our so-
ciety, but we are complicit in them. It is worth remembering that all soci-
eties have had those who have chosen to reject aspects of the social order
through voluntary exile or rebellion.
Phyllis Sutton Morris suggests that for Sartre remembering is remem-
bering-as. In this respect he agreed with the Freudians in saying that a
principle of selection operates in memory. Yet for Sartre the principle is
one with our present projects, it is not some hidden influence determining
us despite ourselves. His phenomenology of freedom is not divorced from
psychology. Morris writes: “We are not, then, at the mercy of the past, and
we cannot excuse present actions on the basis of inexorable memories of
the past.” Sartre’s discussion of memory “is directed against those psycho-
logical determinists who would claim that memories of the past compel or
coerce present action and that men are therefore not responsible for their
acts.”78 Nevertheless, we have to keep reminding ourselves that the influ-
ence of a past that is given meaning by our project in this way is real, it ex-
ists in the past and not just in the imagination of the one who acts, it is
what the agent discovers.79
So our free acts in the present structure our past and our future and
allow us to interpret them. Sometimes these acts reinforce our previous
interpretations. Sometimes a new way of acting gives rise to a new inter-
pretation—which is still, nevertheless, in continuity with one’s past. “Con-
version” is Sartre’s preferred word to stand for the radical modification of
one’s project that brings about a new continuity. A converted atheist is not
simply a believer, “he is a believer who has denied atheism for himself,
who has turned the project of being an atheist into an aspect of the past in
him [qui a passéifié en lui son projet d’être athée].”80 His previous atheism
is not simply ignored, it becomes a part of his new religious story. His re-
ligious conversion—far from being capricious—makes perfect sense when
set against the atheist background. Sartre is at his most eloquent when he
points to some of the great conversions in literature: Gide’s Philoctetes
casts off his hate, Dostoyevsky’s Raskolnikov decides to give himself up.
These extraordinary and marvellous instants when the prior project collapses
into the past in the light of a new project which rises on its ruins and which as
yet exists only in outline, in which humiliation, anguish, joy, hope are delicately
blended, in which we let go in order to grasp and grasp in order to let go—these
have often appeared to furnish the clearest and most moving image of our free-
dom.81
tentions from fantasies. It also makes it possible for us, within a given proj-
ect, to find objective foundations for that project. Mountain climbing, for
example, makes no sense without mountains, and only when we decide to
climb will we discover if a given obstacle is climbable or not.85
In Being and Nothingness Sartre discusses the various forms of facticity
under five headings: one’s place, past, environment, fellow human being,
and death.86 These are some of the richest sections of the work. The weight
of facticity appears in many forms. Climate, earth, race, class, language,
history, heredity, childhood, habits, and the small and great events of life
all press in and form us.87 One of the most indisputable facts confronting
human beings, mentioned in an earlier section of Being and Nothingness,
is the biological unity of each human organism, our “shocking solidarity
with the foetus.”88
Sartre therefore recognizes that we appear to be made more than to
make ourselves.89 He goes on to argue, however, that the factual limits of
our actions are not limits to existential freedom, they actually make free-
dom possible, since freedom is the way we go beyond all that is to a not-
yet-existing end. “Only the ensemble of real existents can separate us from
this end—in the same way that this end can be conceived only as a state
to-come [état à-venir] of the real existents which separate me from it.”90
Being-for-itself is the negation of these “real existents.” It depends on
them. “There can be a free for-itself only as engaged in a resisting world.”91
So freedom is nothing without our presence to the facticity of existence.
Given this facticity, we can notice three ways in which the “absoluteness”
of human freedom is qualified.
First, freedom is an essential aspect of conscious human life, but it is
not the whole of human life. There is more to the human being, to human
reality, than being-for-itself. It is actually only one element of an original
synthesis. Human reality is the negation and reconstitution of a particu-
lar being-in-itself, through the presence to self of being-for-itself, in a total
context of one’s being-in-the-world—with an awareness of one’s being-for-
others.92 This is what saves Sartre from a rootless freedom that would have
We should note that Sartre does not say that practical success is not im-
portant in itself (he cared deeply about practical matters), he says that it is
not important to freedom. In other words, we are still free even if we fail
to achieve our ends. We should also remember that the self-determination
of our wanting is strictly limited by our situation, since “choice” in Sar-
tre’s technical language means undertaking a project and not just dream-
ing about an alternative reality.97 Sartre never implies that human beings
can conjure up any project they like for themselves, irrespective of their
past, their personality, their commitments, their actions. A single sentence
that encapsulates Sartre’s thinking about the contingent limits of freedom
could be the following: “To be free is not to choose the historic world in
which one arises—which would have no meaning—but to choose oneself
in the world whatever this may be.”98 Historic world stands here for that
immensely complex set of facts and circumstances that constitutes one’s
present reality. It all has to be accepted and surpassed, affirmed and de-
nied.99 Sartre gives the example of the prisoner.
We shall not say that a prisoner is always free to get out of prison, which would
be absurd, nor that he is always free to long for release, which would be an irrel-
evant truism, but that he is always free to try to escape (or to get himself liber-
ated); that is, that whatever his condition may be, he can project his escape and
teach himself the value of his project [il peut pro-jeter son évasion et s’apprendre
à lui-même la valeur de son projet] by beginning some action.100
One can see why Sartre had such an ambiguous relationship with the
structuralism that became popular in French philosophy. He insisted as
much as anyone on the impossibility of encountering unmediated facts
and on the omnipresent influence of human structures. But his other two
convictions are inseparable from this. First, he is convinced that the objec-
tive reality of the world is revealed through these structures and claims its
rightful meaning within them. Second, he is convinced that the structures
are not static, they are constructed and kept in being only through the pur-
poseful activity of human beings as they go beyond what they encoun-
ter. In other words, Sartre believed in truth and freedom as well as struc-
ture, and far from thinking that these were threatened by the constraints
of structure he believed that all three concepts depended on each other for
their significance. Many years after Being and Nothingness he wrote: “There
is no doubt that structure produces behaviour. But what is wrong with rad-
ical structuralism [.....] is that the other side of the dialectic is passed over
in silence, and History is never shown producing structures.”105
The question of structures relates to the broader question of the re-
lationship between individual freedom and human culture. There is no
doubt that Sartre paid more detailed attention to cultural factors in his
later works, where the concept of the vécu (“lived experience”) becomes
central.106 Influenced by figures such as Freud, Lacan, and Marx, he is
much more aware of the opaque forces of family and history that structure
a human life. “A simple formula would be to say that life taught me la force
des choses—the power of circumstances.”107 Yet Sartre does concern him-
self with the subject of culture in Being and Nothingness. The long section
entitled “Freedom and Facticity: The Situation” is a philosophy of culture
in all but name.108 Sartre analyzes the numerous ways in which the reality
of the world is mediated to us through humanly constructed frameworks.
As I have already suggested in my introduction, the formal relationship
between facticity and freedom remains fundamentally the same in his ear-
lier and his later work, and there is a change of emphasis and tone rather
than a new philosophy. In later years Sartre defines freedom as “the little
movement that makes of a totally conditioned social being a person who
does not return in its entirety what he received from his conditioning.”109
110. Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique de la Raison Dialectique, Vol. 1: Théorie des Ensembles Pra-
tiques, Bibliothèque des Idées (Paris: Gallimard, 1960), 67–68 and 158.
111. Gregory McCulloch, Using Sartre: An Analytical Introduction to Early Sartrean Themes
(London: Routledge, 1994), 66–69.
112. Morris, Sartre’s Concept of a Person: An Analytic Approach, 117.
113. See his description of the inferiority complex at BN 459; EN 504/537.
f r e e d o m i n s a r t r e = 187
dom lies in the necessity of taking a view on these limitations and not on
the possibility of overcoming them. Someone confused, broken, seemingly
powerless—if the person is conscious—has to choose how to understand
his or her state and how to respond to it, as much as those who are in the
full possession of their powers.
This brings us to the “hard” version of the question about whether
freedom can be taken away. Sartre seems to suggest that even in situations
of grave oppression human beings are still free. Whatever the “coefficient
of adversity” it is “senseless to think of complaining since nothing foreign
has decided what we feel, what we live, or what we are.”114 This is the point
at which, according to Herbert Marcuse, his treatise on human freedom
reaches the point of self-abdication. Marcuse writes:
If philosophy, by virtue of its existential-ontological concepts of man or free-
dom, is capable of demonstrating that the persecuted Jew and the victim of the
executioner are and remain absolutely free and masters of a self-responsible
choice, then these philosophical concepts have declined to the level of a mere
ideology, an ideology which offers itself as a most handy justification for the
persecutors and executioners—themselves an important part of the “réalité hu-
maine”. [.....] The free choice between death and enslavement is neither free-
dom nor choice, because both alternatives destroy the “réalité humaine” which
is supposed to be freedom. [.....] Behind the nihilistic language of Existentialism
lurks the ideology of free competition, free initiative, and equal opportunity.
Everybody can “transcend” his situation, carry out his own project: everybody
has his absolutely free choice.115
ing. Sartre recognizes that this is an absurd proposition. But what would it
mean to say that the oppressed have no freedom, no choices to make, no
possibility of interpreting the weight of their situation?
The main argument of Being and Nothingness is phenomenological.
Sartre points to the experience of oppression. He will not admit that this
forms a category of experience outside the intentional structures analyzed
in the early parts of the work. It is a fact of experience that the oppressed,
if they are conscious human beings, have to face their experience and work
out what it means and how to react to it. Being-for-itself has to see beyond
the brute givenness of the circumstances and ask what it means in the light
of a freely chosen end. The oppressed, as much as their oppressors, suffer
from anguish and have to ask: Who am I? What is important to me? What
shall I do?
Many people are indeed so brutalized that they are unable to think and
choose—they lose their “existential” consciousness even though they are
technically “conscious” and still awake. They can be overcome with fear
or pain and respond solely through a kind of animal instinct. They can be
drugged into oblivion. They can lose their “presence to self ” just as we do
when we sleep. Many, tragically, are killed. But if they are aware of their ex-
perience, then they have to interpret it and respond to it—this is an exis-
tential fact that Sartre will not let go of. Whatever their concrete circum-
stances, they have at least some choices to make, some moments when they
realize that an action or an attitude is not determined and is “up to them.”
In the very narrow confines of their historical situation, all human beings
have to decide to some small extent how they will act in the circumstances
they inhabit, how they will form the form of life that has been given to
them. Sartre is not suggesting that people can escape their lives, he simply
believes that all people have some personal responsibility for how their life
is lived. Existential freedom cannot be a product of education or opportu-
nity, it is part of the human condition, however terrible the material condi-
tions in which one lives.
It is also a historical fact that the oppressed have always interpreted
their oppression in different ways, and these interpretations have led to
vastly different responses. However terrible their oppression, some have
fought openly, some have engaged in subterfuge, some have accepted their
lot silently, some have collaborated behind the scenes, some have joined
the ranks of the oppressors. Anyone who has seen a documentary such as
f r e e d o m i n s a r t r e = 189
Le Chagrin et la Pitié, about the Nazi occupation of France, will have been
struck by the variety of responses chosen by free human beings in the face
of a situation of terrible oppression.117 Sartre knew as well as anyone that
violent circumstances can take away the practical freedom of entire peo-
ples, yet he didn’t balk from describing the heightened sense of responsi-
bility each person faces in these circumstances.
There is also a metaphysical or anthropological argument implicit in
Being and Nothingness that Sartre doesn’t quite spell out—one that has po-
litical consequences. If we accept that the oppressed have had their onto-
logical freedom taken away from them, then what is there left to defend
in their lives? There is no project, no freedom, no presence to self, and
there is consequently no recognizable human being to harm, no right to
be defended, no dignity to be preserved. The reason we recoil at injustice
and oppression, even when someone seems to have had the very human-
ity crushed out of him, is because we believe there is still a trace of human-
ity present, a life to be lived. Sartre expressed this in a later essay when he
took issue with a Marxist conception of political liberation that assumes
that structural changes can take away (and restore) the inherent freedom
of human consciousness.
But, say the Marxists, if you teach man that he is free, you betray him; for he no
longer needs to become free; can you conceive of a man free from birth who de-
mands to be liberated? To this I reply that if man is not originally free, but de-
termined once and for all, we cannot even conceive what his liberation might
be.118
117. Le Chagrin et la Pitié [documentary film], written by André Harris and Marcel Oph-
üls, directed by Marcel Ophüls (1969).
118. Jean-Paul Sartre, “Materialism and Revolution,” in Literary and Philosophical Essays
(New York: Collier, 1962), 244.
190 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
second sense, (2) condemn those who render them unfree in this sense, (3) en-
courage them to become free in this sense, and (4) help them to do so.119
120. Ray Davison, “Sartre Resartus: The Circuit of ‘Ipséité’ from London to Clermont Fer-
rand. ‘L’être et le néant’ at 50,” Journal of European Studies 24 (1994): 154.
Chapter 6
F r e e d o m , C h oic e , a n d t h e
I n d e t e r m i n at io n of R e a s o n
i n Aqu i nas
1. BN 443; EN 488/519.
192
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 193
nature is more solidly established, choices are more rational, and ends are
more accessible. In his view, all human beings seek a common goal, which
is determined by their nature. He calls this goal the finis ultimus (“the last
end”) or beatitudo (“happiness”). We are free to choose how we reach this
goal, and we have many short-term goals that allow us to achieve it, but we
have no say in the nature of the final end itself.
Unlike Sartre, therefore, it may seem that Aquinas has a very restricted
view of freedom. Our deepest desire is imposed upon us, our ultimate goal
is determined for us, and freedom extends only to “technical” questions
about which “means” we can employ to get there. It’s as if we are ordered
to visit London and given the choice of whether we take the train or the
bus, or forced into a marriage and invited to select which color wallpaper
will go in the dining room. This seems a far cry from Sartre’s liberté, which
is a completely undetermined decision to form a unique personal iden-
tity by pursuing a freely chosen set of purposes. For Sartre we are artists
and visionaries—responsible for ourselves and for our world. For Aqui-
nas, it seems, we are bureaucrats and managers—responsible for fulfilling
the tasks we have been given, perhaps with some originality or aplomb, but
without much room for maneuver.
In reality, however, the scope Aquinas gives to human freedom is al-
most limitless, and is certainly as wide as Sartre’s. This is because the final
end we seek is the good in general, without any further specification; it is
happiness in principle, without any further conditions. “Under the good in
general are included many particular goods, to none of which is the will
determined.”2 We don’t just choose the means to an already established
end, we also choose the particular form that this end takes for us. We can-
not seek good or happiness in general without making a particular choice
to seek a particular type of good. In this sense the concrete goal that we
seek, the good that embodies our perfect happiness, is completely up to us.
Aquinas, like Sartre, believes that the constitution of practical goals always
depends on human freedom.
The first point to make in this chapter is about the scope of human
choice. Despite what is often assumed, Aquinas believes that we have to
choose all of our ends—except the final one. It’s easy to miss this and over-
emphasize other aspects of Aquinas’s thought. He writes so clearly about
2. ST I-II.10:1ad3.
194 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
the necessity of seeking the final end, and about the instinctive needs and
desires of our human nature, that one could get the impression that the
scope he gives to human choice is minimal. Yet he also states that within
the circumstances of our life we are completely free to determine which
particular goods we seek and which particular form our final end will take.
We freely determine, therefore, who we are, since our identity depends on
what we seek to become through seeking our end.
Having established the scope of human choice, the main argument of
this chapter then concerns the act itself of human choosing. Aquinas says
that choices are made by the will and reason working together. The will ac-
cepts and affirms one possible line of reasoning. This is because in practical
matters the reason is often undetermined since it arrives at many simulta-
neous conclusions. All these conclusions derive from the objective circum-
stances of the world; each one would give rise to a different rationally jus-
tified course of action; yet only one can be acted upon, and sometimes the
reason cannot decide between them. We have to decide to follow one con-
clusion by actively accepting the reasonableness of one single course of ac-
tion with our will. This is why a choice is always rational and personally
willed—which is what makes it free. Human beings seek (through the will)
a good (understood by intellect and reason)—the two elements of choice
are inseparable, yet they are also distinct. In this way we freely constitute
our own identity since we are the concrete seeking of one way of life.
It is vital to keep in mind the meaning of the technical vocabulary used
throughout this chapter, as it was explained in chapter 2, so that the full
significance of Aquinas’s vision of the human being becomes clear. When
he writes about “intellect” and “reason,” he is referring to our openness as
human beings to other things. Understanding makes us present to other
things and one with them. Through understanding we go beyond ourselves
and our interests and share in the reality of other things. We are trans-
formed by them and in some sense we take on their identity. We are inter-
nally displaced so that we have a center outside ourselves. When Aquinas
writes about “will” he is referring to our ability to go beyond ourselves in
a further way. Whenever we act we are seeking to attain a good thing or
to bring about a good situation. This means that we recognize an insuffi-
ciency about the present state of things and want to transform our situa-
tion into something that it is not. The good situation we want to produce
is precisely something that does not yet exist and that could exist. Even in
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 195
the most insignificant willed action we therefore re-create the world and
take it beyond what it is. At the same time, to seek a good thing is to seek
our own good through the achievement of that good thing. We recognize
that our own being is not complete, not sufficient, and we seek a perfection
for ourselves that we do not yet have. This means that we are transforming
ourselves into what we are not and creating a new identity through our ac-
tivity. So there are various levels of identification, transformation, and re-
creation associated with the philosophical vocabulary of Aquinas.
Now, in this chapter, we will see how all the goods that human beings
seek (apart from the final one) are freely chosen. This means that at ev-
ery level the transformation and re-creation of our identity is completely
up to us. We freely determine what we are (through understanding), what
will become of the world (through actively seeking the good), and who we
are becoming (through actively seeking our own perfection in this good).
These are the radical conclusions Aquinas comes to, and they are easily
masked by the language. Throughout this chapter it will help to bear in
mind these large ideas which form the background to many apparently
simple words: intellect, reason, will, etc.
A final introductory note about language. As has been mentioned in
the historical introduction, contemporary English-speaking philosophy
tends to discuss questions of human freedom and action under the head-
ing “freedom of the will.” Aquinas inherits a tradition that refers to simi-
lar issues under the heading liberum arbitrium, which is preserved in the
contemporary French le libre arbitre.3 The Latin does not contain the word
“will,” voluntas. It was a matter of debate whether the will was free, or the
reason, or some other faculty, or none at all.4 For these reasons it seems
prejudicial to the debate to continue using the traditional translation of
“free will” for liberum arbitrium. Various alternatives have been suggested
and used: “free choice,” “free judgment,” “free decision.”5 I have chosen
3. The term goes back to classical literature and legal formulations where it indicates the
“power to decide” or “freedom of action.” See Daniel Westberg, Right Practical Reason: Aristo-
tle, Action, and Prudence in Aquinas (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), 81–82; and Charles H.
Kahn, “Discovering the Will: From Aristotle to Augustine,” in The Question of “Eclecticism”:
Studies in Later Greek Philosophy, ed. John M. Dillon and A. A. Long (Berkeley and Los Ange-
les: University of California Press, 1988), 250.
4. See J. B. Korolec, “Free Will and Free Choice,” in The Cambridge History of Later Medi-
eval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan Pinborg (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1982), 630–34.
5. See Westberg, Korolec, and also Timothy Suttor in Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theo-
196 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
to use the single word “freedom” to stand for the Latin phrase.6 This is
not just to create a convenient parallel with Sartre’s language. Liberum ar-
bitrium is often used by Aquinas as a synonym for libertas (see, e.g., ST
I.83:1ad3). “Freedom” is an English term that can stand for both, and us-
ing it helps us to see that Aquinas is interested in a range of philosophical
concerns that go beyond what might be suggested by a translation such as
“free judgment.” Like the Latin phrase, it leaves open the question of how
the human being is free and where that freedom lies; it emphasizes neither
an intellectual nor a volitional interpretation; and it indicates the subject of
the argument and not its conclusion. I hope this will facilitate the develop-
ment of ideas in this chapter.7
logiae, ed. Thomas Gilby, 60 vols. (London: Blackfriars: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1963ff), vol. 11,
237, footnote a.
6. See, e.g., Timothy McDermott’s usage in Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae: A Con-
cise Translation, ed. Timothy McDermott (London: Methuen, 1989), 128–29.
7. This does not rule out the fact that there are other senses of freedom for Aquinas that lie
outside the range of meanings included in liberum arbitrium and libertas, such as the free will
(libera voluntas) that inclines us to our final end, even though it excludes any choice and in-
volves a kind of natural necessity. Cf. DV 24:1ad20.
8. ST I.81:2.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 197
to our human nature and to flee what is hurtful to it—this is our concupi-
scible appetite (appetitus concupiscibilis). We also want to defend ourselves
against things that thwart these aims—this is our irascible appetite (appeti-
tus irascibilis). We are bodily creatures, and our bodiliness takes a particu-
lar form that we have not chosen and that is constantly influenced by other
bodily influences outside our control.9 This bodiliness gives each of us a
certain inherent temperament (complexio) or disposition (dispositio) that
colors the way we see things and inclines us toward certain goals.10 We
also have various acquired habits and passions that incline us to one thing
or another. And whether we like it or not, as Aristotle has pointed out,
hearts beat and genitals stir—as if they were independent creatures with
their own principle of life guiding them.11
Human beings are enmeshed in a great web of forces and causes that
determine everything from the global environment to the quirks of our in-
dividual physiologies. These forces are represented in medieval cosmology
by the movement of the heavenly bodies, motus coelestis corporis.12 This
cosmology allows thinkers like Aquinas to propose a sophisticated and
contemporary-sounding view of our ecological situatedness. These diverse
influences stir us in numerous ways. Aquinas gives the simplest example:
“When it gets cold, we begin to wish to make fire.”13 He even allows for
what we would now call a kind of genetic determinism when he describes
the conception of a child through the union of “the semen and the matter
of the one conceived.”14 This genetic mixing is part of what ensures that
the soul “is in some sense made prone to choose something inasmuch as
the choice of the rational soul is inclined by the passions.”15
We are determined furthermore by the paucity of practical options
available to us at any moment.16 However radical the notion of “choice”
seems, it can only be about possible things—things that can realistically
be achieved through our actions. And even the actions we undertake with
some realistic hope of success may be frustrated from the very beginning.17
We may wish various things, but as soon as we try to command one of our
powers to act, “the will can suffer violence, as regards the commanded acts
of the will, insofar as violence can prevent the exterior members from ex-
ecuting the will’s command.”18
All of these influences contribute to our “facticity” for Aquinas; we are
always already “in situation.” These Sartrean phrases are entirely appropri-
ate here—they emphasize the extent to which we are made in Aquinas’s
philosophy. We seem so unfree. Numerous influences press upon us from
without and from within, and human life seems thoroughly determined by
forces over which we have no control.
There is another way, however, in which we have a great deal of control
over our lives. Aquinas does not just describe our human nature, he goes
on to explain how this nature is under reason. We have to respond to our
determined nature and decide what we will make of ourselves. We have to
respond to our determined situation and decide what we will make of it.
The irascible and concupiscible appetites are subject to reason and will.19
The instinctive assessment we make of what is best, an assessment that all
animals are able to make through their estimative power (vis aestimativa),
is itself “naturally guided and moved according to universal reason” as it
“directs the sensitive appetite.”20 So we are not just driven by our instincts,
we also direct them according to our deepest understanding of what is true
and what is good. This kind of directing, as we shall see as this chapter de-
velops, depends on the freedom of the individual agent.
The rational appetite is completely undetermined as regards the con-
crete goods that it seeks.21 This is the disconcerting heart of Aquinas’s ac-
count of the will. We freely choose which goods will perfect our life and
give it purpose. We are obliged to find our perfection in something (which
is what it means to seek the universal good), yet there is no necessity for us
to find our perfection in anything in particular.22 Aquinas is unambiguous
about this. In a question about the will in the Summa he writes: “As the ca-
pacity of the will regards the universal and perfect good, its whole capacity
is not subjected to any particular good [non subiicitur eius possibilitas tota
alicui particulari bono].”23 When discussing the manner in which we will
in Part I-II he states: “Under good in general are included many particu-
lar goods, to none of which is the will determined [ad quorum nullum vol-
untas determinatur].”24 This is despite the fact that in the body of the same
article he argues that various particular goods are naturally wanted by the
will insofar as they “belong to the willer according to one’s nature” and
“relate to [one’s] natural well-being [respiciunt consistentiam naturalem].”25
The fact that there is a kind of spontaneous desire for what is naturally
beneficial does not mean that the will actively seeks these objects with any
necessity.26 There is not a single particular good to which the whole hu-
man being is naturally, necessarily directed with some kind of integrated
wanting. So although it seems that there are many natural human ends, in
fact there is no natural end for the person. It is not enough for us to want
a good, we have to choose to make that good a part of the universal good
to which we are directing ourselves—it has to become an embodiment of
our deepest desire.
Sometimes, for example in DV 22:5c, Aquinas suggests that human
beings necessarily will some goods, such as life or knowledge, because they
have a necessary connection with our final end. Yet in a parallel question in
Part I of the Summa, which is composed later than De veritate, he is much
more cautious. He still believes that some goods have a necessary connection
with happiness and with our adherence to God, in whom alone true happi-
ness consists. But he recognizes that we can be ignorant of these connec-
tions, and for this reason there are no goods at all that human beings have
to will. “Yet until through the certitude of the Divine Vision the necessity
of such connection be shown, the will does not adhere to God of necessity,
nor to those things which are of God [Sed tamen antequam per certidudinem
divinae visionis necessitas huiusmodi connexionis demonstretur, voluntas non
ex necessitate Deo inhaeret, nec his quae Dei sunt].”27 The parallel between the
two passages is not exact, but there is certainly a refusal to allow that in this
present life there are any particular goods that are necessarily willed.
The extraordinary thing about human beings is not that we are unin-
fluenced by our nature or our environment, but that we have to determine
for ourselves how to respond to the sum total of these influences. However
many things form us, we are still capable of asking “What is happening?
What do I want? What shall I do?” It is true that the sensitive appetite con-
tinually influences us: We naturally want to eat, to talk, to discover things,
to be warm, to play, to have families, etc. These things are human goods, and
we often seek them without much reflection, like a moth seeking light or a
lion chasing a gazelle. Yet we have an additional ability to question these in-
stinctive goods and to make our own priorities among them. This process
presupposes an extraordinary ability not to identify with our natural desires
and not to identify with the “person” who seeks these goods. At one and the
same time we recognize (i) that we are this person who does want these
things, and (ii) that we could be a “different” person who would want other
things. If we question one of our present goods (this meal, this job, this hol-
iday, this family), we are necessarily questioning the person who is seeking
these goods—since a good is precisely something desired for the sake of the
perfection of the one who seeks it. To question the good is to question one-
self. This is the deepest significance of the rational appetite.
Animals, of course, have priorities. One desire may override another.
A bird, for example, might refrain from swooping down on the crops if
it knows that the farmer has a gun, in which case self-preservation takes
priority over being fed. Yet the peculiar thing about human beings (and
other creatures with rational appetite) is that we decide how the priorities
are set, we decide for ourselves what is most important.28 We can find our
perfection in different ways in different goods, and the good we eventually
27. ST I.82:2c.
28. See John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 90–
95, on the difficulty of prioritizing natural goods. For an excellent discussion of the relation-
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 201
seek is up to us. Animals have to work out how to get the goods they al-
ready seek and so how to perfect the creatures they already are; human be-
ings have to work out which goods to seek and in that way work out which
persons we will allow ourselves to be.29 This is what it is for human nature
to be under reason.
ship between particular goods and the final end of the person, see R. Mary Hayden, “Natural
Inclinations and Moral Absolutes: A Mediated Correspondence for Aquinas,” Proceedings of
the American Catholic Philosophical Association 64 (1990).
29. In this sense, for Aquinas as for Sartre, existence precedes essence, since the identity
we are coming to have (our “essence”) depends on the free response we make (our “existence”)
to what has determined us.
30. ST I-II.13:3c. 31. ST I-II.13:3c.
32. DV 24:1ad19.
202 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
vel tales], since what one is like is given at birth and it depends, as some main-
tain, upon the arrangement of the stars. It is therefore not in our power to ap-
prove this or that end.33
33. DV 24:1obj19. Citing Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3:5, 1114b1. For an English version,
see Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1985), 69.
34. DV 24:1ad19.
35. ST I-II.1:7c. Thomas Gilby’s translation distinguishes between what happiness means
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 203
On the one hand, the idea of happiness is something all human beings
seek, since we all want to be fulfilled. Aquinas expresses the same point in
a later question: “To desire happiness is nothing else than to desire that
one’s will be satisfied, and this everyone desires” (ST I-II.5:8c).36 It is essen-
tial to note that in Aquinas’s view this is the only thing that we necessarily
seek by nature. On the other hand, human beings are not all agreed about
“the thing in which the idea of the last end is found [id in quo finis ultimi
ratio invenitur],” about “where” the last end is found. Just as we seek our
good in different ways, in different particular goods, so we do not all agree
about which particular thing will perfect us. There is a radical indetermi-
nation about human desire.37
So the fact that we are all necessarily seeking happiness does not deter-
mine for us what thing we actually seek, what the last end is for us. Happi-
ness can take many different forms. In this first question of ST I-II Aqui-
nas is not judging the respective worth of various possible final ends. He
doesn’t say “some people desire riches as their final end (but they are wrong
.....)” or “some desire pleasure (yet this is only part of the story .....)”—these
issues follow in question 2. Here in ST I-II.1 Aquinas is writing about the
nature of human action and its orientation to an end. Aquinas believes that
those who desire riches or pleasure as their consummate good are seek-
ing to be perfected through these goods. The purpose and direction of our
whole life is determined by the end we seek—whatever that may be.38 In
the sed contra to ST I-II.1:5 he writes, “That in which human beings rest as
in their last end, is master of their affections, since they take from that the
rule of their whole life,” and he applies this to gluttons who make the satis-
faction of their belly the dominating end of their whole existence.39 Once
again, Aquinas is not at this stage making moral judgments about human
choices, he is simply noting that we can seek different ends and choose to
and that in which it is realized, and he comments that this is the difference between “the idea
of happiness and the happy-making thing; approximately happiness in the abstract and in the
concrete.” See Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, vol. 16, footnote b, 27.
36. ST I-II.5:8c.
37. It could be instructive to translate finis ultimus as “a last end” rather than “the last end.”
The indefinite article would remind us that in seeking these particular things we are seeking an
end, our end, and not “that end” which everyone else has.
38. This does not mean that all particular ends are equivalent nor that all human beings
are able to find happiness in the ends they seek. See ST I-II.5:8.
39. ST I-II.1:5 sed c.
204 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
for ourselves. Aquinas believes that we are sources and centers of our ac-
tivity. Our life is our own and that is why we are held responsible for it.
When searching for the explanations and causes behind human behavior
there is nowhere further back to go than the existence of the human being
in question. However many external and internal factors influence the ac-
tion, it is impossible to leave out this aspect of personal commitment that
gives a center to the action and makes it human. Human actions ultimately
refer to and derive from the integrity of this individual human being. We
can now investigate the nature of this freedom that allows human beings
to make decisions about goods and ends.
46. Good pieces that comment on these questions include Gallagher, “The Will and Its
Acts (Ia Iiae, Qq. 6–17)”; Alan Donagan, “Thomas Aquinas on Human Action,” in The Cam-
bridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny, and Jan
Pinborg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982); Westberg, Right Practical Reason: Ar-
istotle, Action, and Prudence in Aquinas; and John Finnis, “Object and Intention in Moral Judg-
ments According to Aquinas,” The Thomist 55 (1991).
47. ST I.83:1c.
206 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
freedom is. It is the fact that the human being, unlike other animals, “acts
from free judgment and retains the power of being inclined to various
things [potens in diversa ferri].”48 Freedom is thus our ability to seek dif-
ferent things because we can think about things in different ways. Actions
are concerned with contingent, concrete matters, and “in such matters the
judgment of reason may follow opposite courses [ad diversa se habet], and
is not determinate to one. And forasmuch as human beings are rational is
it necessary that they be free.”49
Aquinas takes up the definition of “what is free” (liberum) from Aris-
totle’s Metaphysics, cited in the third objection of the same article. “What is
free is sui causa” (“cause of itself ” or “self-determining”).50 He clarifies this
in his response. “Freedom is the cause of its own movement, because by
their freedom human beings move themselves to act.”51 These themes are
repeated in the first question of Part I-II, and one citation brings them to-
gether very succinctly: “Those things that have reason, move themselves to
an end, because they have dominion over their actions through their free-
dom, which is the faculty of will and reason.”52
These, then, are some of the ideas associated with freedom: a judg-
ment that is not determined, the ability to seek different things, the inde-
termination of reason, having control over one’s actions, self-movement,
self-determination. In the third article of ST I.83 Aquinas makes more ex-
plicit what is at the heart of each of these characterizations of freedom:
choice. “The proper act of freedom is choice [electio]: for we say that we
are free because we can take one thing while refusing another, and this is
to choose.”53
Now two things concur in choice: one on the part of the cognitive power, the
other on the part of the appetitive power. On the part of the cognitive power,
deliberation [consilium] is required, by which one thing is judged [diiudicatur]
to be preferred to another; and on the part of the appetitive power, it is required
that the appetite should accept the judgment of deliberation.54
So there are two elements to any choice: a rational preference and a will-
ing acceptance. Choice always involves a double movement: it is (i) judg-
ing what is to be preferred and (ii) accepting the judgment. Or to put in an-
other way, it is the unified movement of allowing the judgment of preference
through its acceptance. It seems, to put it crudely, as if the cognitive power
first does all the hard work of determining what is best to do, and then the
will just rubber stamps this. We should not, however, be misled by the de-
scription of this sequence. It does not imply that the “choice” of which path
to follow is made solely by the judgment of deliberation, as if the intellect
can always provide us with sufficient reason to prefer one course of action
rather than another, and the will simply ratifies this irrefutable judgment.
Aquinas is insistent that choice is a function of the cognitive and appetitive
powers working together, and nothing is actually chosen unless the will ac-
cepts what is understood to be preferable. His reply to the second objection
is highly nuanced.
Judgment [iudicium] is a sort of conclusion and termination of deliberation
[consilium]. Now deliberation is terminated [determinatur], first, by the sen-
tence [sententia] of reason; secondly, by the acceptance of the appetite: whence
the Philosopher says in Ethics 3 that, “having formed a judgment by delibera-
tion, we desire in accordance with that deliberation.” And in this sense choice
itself is a kind of judgment [quoddam iudicium] from which freedom [liberum
arbitrium, “free decision”] takes its name.55
At first sight this text might seem to confirm the sequential descrip-
tion of understanding and willing introduced in the body of the article: the
will (inevitably) follows the reason. Yet two enormously important qual-
ifications are made here. First, deliberation, which might seem to be an
independent rational process, is not in fact “terminated” or “determined”
(determinatur) without the intervention of the will. In one sense it is still
true to say that the reason determines the final deliberation, since (if the
deliberation takes place) there is nothing apart from the sentence of rea-
son for the will to accept. But on the other hand, without the conclud-
ing acceptance of the will, there is no deliberation, and the reason remains
ineffective. In this sense, it is possible to say that the will determines the
deliberation, since it determines whether any particular judgment of rea-
56. ST I-II.13:1c.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 209
of rational necessity involved for anyone who is thinking properly. But the
whole point is that we have to make choices when one option is not obvi-
ously better, when numerous options all make sense, and when each one
could reasonably be chosen. John Finnis emphasizes this and is highly crit-
ical of theories that might obscure the fact that for Aquinas choice is be-
tween rational, viable alternatives. “Any deliberation which ends in choice
must have yielded, not one judgment affirming the choiceworthiness of an
option awaiting adoption by the will, but (at least) two judgments.”57 Aqui-
nas makes this clear in the following article when he repeats what we have
already learnt, that the will, unlike the sensitive appetite shared with ani-
mals, is “indeterminate in respect of particular goods.”58
Since choice is the taking of one thing in preference to another it must of ne-
cessity relate to several things that can be chosen [necesse est quod electio sit re-
spectu plurium quae eligi possunt]. Consequently in those things which are alto-
gether determinate to one there is no place for choice.59
Kevin Flannery draws attention to the fact that for Aquinas, and not
for some of his neo-Scholastic interpreters, there is still a choice to make
even after the intellect has made all the judgments that it can:
If the process of practical reasoning truly leads to choice [electio], at the thresh-
old of choice, there must yet exist options among which the agent chooses. The
scholastic ordered pairings consilium-consensus/iudicium-electio suggests that
the job of voluntas is to deliver propulsion (by consensus and electio) to what
is decided only in intellect (consilium and iudicium). The genuinely Thomistic
order, on the other hand—consilium, iudicium, consensus, electio—makes it ap-
parent that the entire moral agent is present right at the very threshold of going
into action.60
57. Finnis, “Object and Intention in Moral Judgments According to Aquinas,” 5–6.
58. ST I-II.13:2c.
59. ST I-II.13:2c.
60. Kevin L. Flannery, Acts Amid Precepts (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 2001), 163.
210 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
61. ST I.83:1c.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 211
This is a huge claim—that any concrete thing at all can always be seen as
good in one way, or as not good. Choice is not just about those rare mo-
ments when we stand before two finely balanced and incompatible options.
Aquinas says that we can always see more than one way of acting, because
we can always see an aspect of good and an aspect of bad in any option, and
therefore we can always discover reasons for doing it and reasons for not
doing it. It is part of the nature of reason for Aquinas that it can observe
present reality in different ways. The world has multiple possible meanings.
The particular situations we encounter always and necessarily give rise to
more than one conception of what is good, more than one practical option,
more than one possible future. It can’t be emphasized enough that it is rea-
son that does this. Reason discovers that there is no necessity about any sin-
gle interpretation of the good—this is not because of a failure of reason.
Aquinas addresses this question of necessity in the same article (13:6).
The second objection is very forceful, and he accepts its argument: If there
is a necessity about the prior judgment of reason, then it seems there will
be a necessity about the choice. In other words, if we have to think that
something is good, then we will inevitably choose it. In the body of his re-
ply he restates his central contention. “The human being does not choose
of necessity. And this is because that which is possible not to be, is not
of necessity [quod possibile est non esse, non necesse est esse].”63 In other
words, we can choose, without necessity, because of the possible not-being
62. ST I-II.13:6c.
63. ST I-II.13:6c.
212 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
of the options. What makes them options is their conditionality, the fact
that they could be and therefore that they are not, the fact that they do not
come about as a necessary consequence of the being of the world that is.
“Being” (the reality of the present situation) gives rise to “nonbeing” (the
possible futures that are not yet determined) through the mediation of rea-
son. The element of negation is as important for Aquinas as it is for Sartre.
When we face a choice we face options that precisely do not exist, they do
not flow out of the present constitution of the universe with any necessity.
These options have to be made to be through the choice, and that is why it
is not possible for there to be any necessity in the reasoning involved in a
choice. David Gallagher writes about how important it is for Aquinas that
human beings are free to understand things in different ways and not just
free to act:
Does the agent have control over how the options appear? This question cuts
to the heart of the matter. If we say that choice and action depend upon how
various goods appear to a person, and if a person does not control how these
goods appear, then the person’s action will not truly be free—able to be other-
wise—nor will the person be morally responsible for it. If goods simply appear
to an agent as they appear, then to characterize the will as rational appetite leads
us into a form of psychological determinism, a determinism incompatible with
freedom and responsibility.64
Gallagher explains that for Aquinas the agent exercises control over the
very act of reason that governs his or her choice. “How objects appear, in
terms of good or evil, is not simply a question of those objects taken inde-
pendently of a particular agent, but rather depends in large measure on the
agents themselves.” An agent’s “contribution” to the appearances is always
to some extent voluntary or willed.65
Aquinas’s specific replies to the first two objections of ST I-II.13:6 con-
tain two remarkable glosses on the nature of the type of reasoning that
takes place in practical judgments. The first response runs:
The conclusion does not always of necessity follow from the principles, but only
when the principles cannot be true if the conclusion is not true. In like man-
64. David M. Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgment in Thomas Aquinas,” Archiv für
Geschichte der Philosophie 76 (1994): 248.
65. Ibid., 249.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 213
ner, the end does not always necessitate in the human being the choosing of the
means, because the means are not always such that the end cannot be gained
without them; or, if they be such, they are not always considered in that light.66
One end can be achieved in different ways. One set of principles can lead
the reason to a number of different conclusions. The reason by itself can-
not “decide” which of these reasons is to be followed, because they are all
reasonable. The second response adds:
The reason’s decision or judgment of what is to be done is about things that are
contingent and possible to us. In such matters the conclusions do not follow
of necessity from absolutely necessary principles [non ex necessitate sequuntur
ex principiis necessariis absoluta necessitate], but from principles necessary only
given a condition [sed necessariis solum ex conditione]; as, for instance, “If he is
running, he is in motion.”67
So in these cases when there are many legitimate conclusions, multiple fu-
tures, the only way that a single conclusion is reached is when a condition
is inserted that turns the principle into the kind of principle that requires
a single answer. In other words, we have to create the conditions in which
one conclusion will make sense.
Let’s say that a woman has to choose whether to take option A or option
B in order to achieve the goal X. Let’s accept that these are viable options,
they arise from the reality of her situation and the possibilities available to
her. X is the end, the guiding principle, which serves as the principle in a
practical judgment. Perhaps she wants a salary and has to choose between
being a teacher or a car mechanic; perhaps she wants a holiday and has to
choose between traveling to Brighton or Bournemouth. She already knows
that both options (A and B) lead to X—this is the very reason she has a di-
lemma. If she chooses A, all the specific benefits of A will accrue (together
with the goal X); if she chooses B, all the specific benefits of B will accrue
(together with the goal X). She cannot come to an unconditional conclu-
sion on the basis of reason alone. She can only conclude that A is the cor-
rect conclusion if she first decides to build the conditions of A into the
very principle X from which she is trying to derive A. A will be the con-
clusion that derives from her desire for X only if she sees the problem (and
66. ST I-II.13:6ad1.
67. ST I-II.13:6ad2.
214 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
Aquinas could not be clearer here about the remarkable fact that we can
approve of and consent to many options at the same time. “Since each of
these meets with approval, consent is given to each [dum quodlibet placet,
in quodlibet eorum consentitur].” In these cases the reason alone is not able
to find a preference. In fact, a preference is not something that is found,
it is made or given to one option by choosing or in the very choosing (eli-
gendo).
The similarities with Sartre’s understanding of freedom are striking. A
reasoned analysis of the situation produces many possible courses of ac-
tion. None of them arises from the facts before one with any inevitability,
none of them makes a claim on us with any necessity. Reason alone is insuf-
ficient for determining our ends. The characters in Being and Nothingness
are confronted with many options: to gamble or to walk away, to continue
the journey or to give up, to suffer in silence or to rebel. They are aware
that nothing determines the future for them—nothing about themselves
or their situation. The totality before them gives rise to alternative possible
outcomes. They have to go beyond this totality and freely project them-
selves into a specific future that is not determined. They determine it for
themselves by choosing to act for one good out of many possible goods.
They allow themselves to be motivated by one set of reasoning by acting
for a specific end, and this free choice to seek one end is what gives le-
68. This is one reason why Yves Simon insists that the key to Thomistic freedom is super-
determination and not indetermination; see Yves R. Simon, Freedom of Choice (New York: Ford-
ham University Press, 1969), 152–53.
69. ST I-II.15:3ad3.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 215
gitimacy to this specific set of reasons. They can do this because they are
not trapped within being-in-itself. Their being is to exist beyond being as
being-for-itself. In Aquinas’s scheme it is reason that allows us to see the
alternative possibilities for good within being, and the will that allows us
actively to project ourselves toward one of these possibilities. The reason
liberates us from necessity and the will re-creates a kind of conditional ne-
cessity that is based on the freely chosen end.
In the view of both Aquinas and Sartre, we are free to act (in one way
rather than another) because we are free to reason and to understand the
good (in one way rather than another). An English phrase captures this
nicely: the act of choosing is often called “making up one’s mind.”70 The
judgment of preference takes place in the very choosing, and one’s will is
one’s capacity to shape oneself by responding to reasons.71 This means that
in their choices human beings are freely deciding how they will under-
stand the world, what they will prefer, and where their lives are going. We
should note that Aquinas’s account of choice, like Sartre’s, does not just ap-
ply to those dramatic “Moments of Decision” when we hesitate before an
agonizing dilemma that will determine the direction of our life and the
quality of our character.72 Whenever an action is “up to us,”73 whenever we
could have done otherwise, we then have to choose to do it. Both the sea-
soned Mafia hit man and the loyal charity worker may go about their busi-
ness without much reflection or hesitation, but they are still freely choos-
ing to do their work and fully responsible for it. They could have done
otherwise, if only by not acting.
Aquinas connects the fact that there are alternative contingent solu-
tions to practical dilemmas with our ability to deal with universals. Hu-
man knowledge is not tied to particular, material things, and for this rea-
son we can—as it were—direct and apply our ideas to various things by our
free choice. If an architect had only a particular material form of a house
in mind, one that was already individualized, then he would not be able to
70. See Joseph M. Boyle, Germain Grisez, and Olaf Tollefsen, Free Choice: A Self-Referen-
tial Argument (South Bend, Ind., and London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1976), 13.
71. See John Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political, and Legal Theory (Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1998), 66–70.
72. See Flannery, Acts Amid Precepts, 162–66. The examples that follow are based on Flan-
nery’s.
73. See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 3:5, 1113b6.
216 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
build any other type of house, since there would be only one concrete idea
determining his thinking and motivating his actions. (For example, if an
architect were using some off-the-shelf plans for a three-bedroomed, two-
story house made of wood and glass that had already been constructed a
hundred times.) But architects usually start with universal forms (e.g., “a
family home,” “an office block”) that can be realized in different concrete
ways. Aquinas explains this in De malo 6:
An intellectual form is a universal, under which many things can be compre-
hended [Forma intellecta est universalis, sub qua multa possunt comprehendi].
Hence, since acts are concerned with singulars, among which there is none that
is equal to the potentiality of the universal, the inclination of the will remains
indeterminately related to many things [remanet inclinatio voluntatis indeter-
minate se habens ad multa]; for example, if an architect conceives the form of a
house in a universal, under which houses of different shapes are comprehended,
his or her will can be inclined to build a house that is square or circular or of
some other shape.74
The same building analogy is used in a question about the divine will in De
veritate, but here Aquinas connects the universality of human reason not
only with the architect’s ability to embody universal ideas in different par-
ticular ways, but also with the architect’s ability to decide whether to build
the house or not.
Because the form of the house in the mind of the architect is the idea of the
house taken absolutely [ratio domus absoluta], of itself not disposed any more
to existence than to non-existence or to existence in one particular way rather
than in another [magis ad esse quam ad non esse, nec ad sic quam ad aliter esse],
as far as the accidental features of the house go, the architect’s inclination in re-
gard to making the house or not remains free.75
Once again, the future is not determined by the being of the present. The
ratio absoluta of the house is not disposed more to existence or to nonex-
istence, nor to one kind of embodiment rather than another. So knowl-
edge gives us an indifference to being, an ability to decide whether some-
thing shall be or not be. The fact that we can abstract immaterial forms
74. DM 6c [287–96].
75. DV 23:1c.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 217
and think about things in general is what allows us to go beyond the total-
ity of the present and envisage what does not have to be, which is another
way of saying that we envisage what could be. Possibility and the condi-
tional tense only emerge through this process of stepping back from con-
crete being (making a deeper sense of it, through knowledge) and stepping
forward beyond concrete being (seeing the possibilities, through practical
reasoning about human action). We don’t just know that the future is open
and undetermined—it is our knowledge that makes the future undeter-
mined. Human knowledge introduces the potential being of multiple hu-
man actions through the actual nonbeing of the single understood form.
Our ability to deal with universals which do not exist in concrete reality is
what frees us from necessity and determination. Alan Donagan summa-
rizes Aquinas’s view in this way:
[Freedom] is wholly a matter of the non-necessity of any judgment a man can
arrive at by his natural powers as to the goodness of an end or the suitability of
a means. Even when will seems to fly in the face of intellect, there is always a
(foolish, perhaps vicious) judgment which directs it.76
tion we can investigate this movement of the will that concludes the act of
choice.
Aquinas touches on the activating power of the will in a number of ar-
ticles, some of which we have looked at in chapter 4. The will as an effi-
cient cause [per modum agentis] moves the intellect and all the powers of
the soul, “because wherever we have order among a number of active pow-
ers, that power which regards the universal end moves the powers which
regard particular ends.”78 With respect to their exercise, the will moves the
other powers of the soul to their acts, “for the end and perfection of ev-
ery other power is included under the object of the will as some particu-
lar good,” and the will moves the other powers to their particular ends as it
seeks the universal end.79 As to the exercise of its act, “no object moves the
will necessarily, for no matter what the object be, it is in one’s power not
to think of it, and consequently not to will it actually.”80 This is true even
of the universal good of happiness, because a person “is able not to will to
think of happiness at a certain moment, since even the very acts of the in-
tellect and the will are particular acts.”81
ST I-II.10:2 contains perhaps the most unambiguous description of the
decisive role of the will in determining human action. The question con-
cerns whether the will is moved by its object of necessity. Aquinas writes:
If the will be offered an object which is good universally and from every point
of view, the will tends to it of necessity, if it wills anything at all; since it cannot
will the opposite. If, on the other hand, the will is offered an object that is not
good from every point of view, it will not tend to it of necessity. And since lack
of any good implies some non-goodness [quia defectus cuiuscumque boni habet
rationem non boni], consequently, that good alone which is perfect and lacking
in nothing, is such a good that the will cannot not-will it: and this is happiness.
Whereas any other particular goods, in so far as they are lacking in some good,
can be regarded as non-goods [alia autem quaelibet particularia bona, inquan-
tum deficiunt ab aliquo bono, possunt accipi ut non bona]: and from this point of
view, they can be set aside or approved by the will, which can tend to one and
the same thing from different points of view [quae potest in idem ferri secundum
diversas considerations].82
We can notice the following points: (A) If the will is actually in the pro-
cess of willing, then it is not free not to seek the perfect good in happiness.
So there is a general necessity about willing our final end. (B) Apart from
the perfect good, absolutely any other good at all can be viewed as good or
as not good. In other words, even though Aquinas insists that the object
specifies the act and the reason determines what is good, nevertheless the
object and the reason alone can never “specify” which specification of the
good will motivate the act. Reason supplies too much information—it can
never present the will with a single, indisputable possible good (apart from
the perfect end). (C) Particular goods can be either set aside or approved
by the will (possunt repudiari vel approbari a voluntate). This is crucial.
Even though Aquinas sometimes simplifies his account and suggests, as
we have seen, that the cognitive power alone (through deliberation) judges
what is preferable,83 nevertheless deliberation itself is not terminated with-
out the acceptance of the will,84 and a preference cannot be given without
the affirmation of the will that closes choice.85 (D) When the will sets aside
or approves a particular object, when it accepts one good rather than an-
other, this is because it sets aside or approves of a point of view which is
reasonable, which is one legitimate way of understanding this object. So
the will is not going against reason; rather the will is selecting one reason
from among many. The act is still specified solely by the goodness of the
object as presented by reason. It is the object that moves and determines
the act as its specifying principle, the object that makes it this act and not
another.86
In a passage from De malo 6 Aquinas gives three factors that might
incline the will to consider a good in one way rather than another, three
“reasons” why we might take one point of view on an issue rather than an-
other:
That the will is drawn to that which is presented to it more according to this
particular condition rather than another, can occur in three ways. In one way,
inasmuch as one condition is of greater weight [in quantum una preponderat],
and then the will is moved according to reason; as, say, when a person prefers
The three factors that might influence my will are thus: (i) the objective
importance of the options before me (their “weight”); (ii) my particular
situation insofar as it influences my way of thinking (where this situation
includes what is happening in my inner life as well as the world in which I
exist); and (iii) my character. I might buy a cake either because I am hun-
gry and need some nourishment; or because [externally] I happen to be
walking past a shop with an enticing advertisement for cakes outside; or
because [internally] I am daydreaming about a cooking program I saw on
television; or because I am gluttonous and want to satisfy my gluttony.
Aquinas says that only in the first case is the will moved according to
reason. This fits with our everyday assumptions—that when we are be-
ing enticed by advertisements, or swayed by external pressures, or driven
by a particular character trait, we are not being completely rational. But
this has to be read carefully. Aquinas does not mean that in the other two
cases the option chosen is not rational. He has already explained that the
very reason why we can consider something to be good and still decide
not to will it is that other things, at the same time, can also be considered
good or fitting. With regard to any good (apart from the complete good
of happiness), “a person will be able to will its opposite, even while think-
ing about it, since perhaps it [the opposite] is good or fitting according
to some other particular consideration; as, for instance, what is good for
health is not good so far as enjoyment is concerned, and so on in regard to
other things.”88 So even when, against the objective advice of reason, the
will considers a lesser good, and inclines to that instead, it is still some-
87. DM 6c [450–467]; quoting Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3:5, 1114a32–b1.
88. DM 6c [444–49].
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 221
89. DV 22:15c.
222 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
Once again it must be emphasized that the reason is not proposing a single rea-
sonable plan of action that is automatically approved by the will. Sometimes al-
ternative plans of action cannot be ordered by the reason, they are all equally
reasonable, and the reason “puts them next to one another” (conferre). Some-
times the reason puts one plan before the others (praeferre)—but without los-
ing sight of the viability and reasonableness of the alternatives. In neither case
is the will obliged to prefer one alternative as ground for action (ad operandum)
rather than another. The inclination of the will to one rational plan, which is
the ultimate cause of action, is not necessarily determined by the order given by
reason. There couldn’t be a clearer statement of the determining influence of the
will. Aquinas’s own words, however, could mislead us here. When he writes that
the will does not of necessity follow reason he means here that it does not follow
the ordering (praeferre) which reason gives among rival plans. It still, however,
follows the reasonableness of the chosen option. As he goes on to say, choice is
always an act of the will in relation to reason, and the option preferred by the
will is always therefore a reasonable one that has been proposed (even if it is a
lower ranking proposal) by reason.
Stephen Brock draws attention to the role of the will in making the
preference.90 When we reason about possible actions, “it can happen that
both “measure up” and that neither is a clear winner.” If taking one ex-
cludes the other, then the decision is simply “up to you.”
You refuse one when all conditions needed for your accepting it are present,
and you accept the other when all conditions needed for refusing it are pres-
ent. [.....] The will moves toward one thing despite a sufficient attraction toward
something excluding it; this is a choice, a taking one thing in the face of an-
other, a preference. This is not at all to say that the choice is not informed by a
judgment. The chooser must have formed a judgment declaring the preferabil-
ity of what he chose. Only, he also formed a judgment declaring the preferabil-
ity of the alternative he rejected. Nor are these two separate judgments; it is one
judgment, declaring one alternative preferable in some respect, and the other
preferable in another respect.91
So there are multiple practical truths, multiple possible acts, which all
make sense in different ways. Let’s call them different lines of reasoning.
Reason cannot decide between them, since reason is the very faculty that
has brought them to light. It is up to the will to prefer one way of reason-
ing and acting. This is free choice. It is simply the way that we activate a
reason. Note that it does not involve an additional, alternative, nonrational
apprehension of good. Stephen Brock puts it this way:
[The will is not] an additional source of objects or specificatory principles, out-
side or apart from those given by the intellect. Rather, the will plays a role in the
determination of its object precisely by playing a role in the process by which
the intellect comes to provide it with an object.92
The will is not determining what is good (the reason does this), it is de-
termining that one way of looking at one good should be activated, that
one project be followed. The only reason for doing X is X itself—as judged
by the reason. The movement of the will is necessarily in accord with the
good as it is presented by reason, but the movement itself is not caused by
the understanding of the good—it is caused by, indeed it is, the will’s very
attraction to this good. A choice is rational, indeed there is no such thing
as an irrational choice (since it must be between reasonable options)—yet
a choice is not rationally made.
The will, for Aquinas as for Sartre, is not against reason, it is what es-
tablishes it as something with practical relevance. The exercise of the will
is what gives momentum to the reasonableness of one way of reasoning,
which up to this moment had only a theoretical power. Why did we go to
the cinema instead of the bowling alley? Eat Italian instead of Mexican?
Talk about football instead of politics?
On the one hand, the action brings about its own explanation—we act
for the objective good sought. The only reason for eating Italian food is
because Italian food is good. But why do we not follow other reasons? Be-
cause of the reasonableness of the reasons that we do choose. There are no
further reasons to put into the equation. This is not voluntarism, for the
simple fact that the movement of the will toward this good is explained by
the objective rationality of the good in question. The fact that other goods
could also have been reasonably chosen does not alter this.
95. Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989), 510.
96. This idea of autonomy in Aquinas is brought out in Martin Rhonheimer, Natural Law
and Practical Reason: A Thomist View of Moral Autonomy (New York: Fordham University
Press, 2000), see esp. viii and 143.
226 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
for the agent about to decide, nor for the philosopher trying to analyze
the prehistory of the agent’s eventual decision, since both the agent and
the philosopher are trying to investigate the same thing. Choosing brings
about an answer that did not exist before, except as one possibility among
many. The recurring demand for more philosophical clarity here is under-
standable but misplaced, since it denies the very fact of freedom. The in-
quisitive philosopher is always trying to collapse this “future” choice into
the determinations of the past and present. But once again, the disconcert-
ing heart of Aquinas’s view is that the present, as it is understood by rea-
son, is not enough (because reason is undetermined), or rather it is too
much (because reason sees alternative possibilities), and it can only be de-
termined by an unanticipated movement of the will in the future choice—
which will still be perfectly explicable in terms of the end that is actually
chosen.
97. See, e.g., Jeffrey Hause, “Thomas Aquinas and the Voluntarists,” Medieval Philosophy
and Theology 6 (1997); P. S. Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on the Will,” Review
of Metaphysics 56 (2003); and Robert Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2002), esp. section 7.4, 221–33.
98. It is almost impossible not to use the words “voluntarist” and “intellectualist” when
discussing these arguments since these are the labels used in the literature to characterize ri-
val interpretations. So I reluctantly adopt these terms in this discussion. But one of the main
points of my own position is that even though Aquinas is not an intellectualist, this does not
make him a voluntarist, insofar as the good eventually chosen is always completely specified
solely by the intellect.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 227
tive. But at least I can point out some of the shortcomings of some these
other approaches.
Jeffrey Hause argues that Aquinas is a thoroughgoing intellectualist:
On Aquinas’s view, the will cannot, by any innate capacity, direct the intellect’s
attention, keep the intellect from issuing judgments about what one ought to
do, or keep itself from willing what the intellect has determined what one ought
to do. Nor can it select one from among a variety of alternatives unless the intel-
lect has first settled on that one as the alternative to be pursued. Which, if any,
of a set of objects the will wills, and whether it wills anything or nothing at all,
depends not on any voluntaristic capacity of the will, but on how the intellect
judges the object in question.99
its evaluations. [.....] The will always chooses in accordance with reason’s
decisions, and it always executes those decisions in accordance with rea-
son’s commands.”103 He pays too little attention, however, to the passages
where Aquinas explains that the reason is not always fully determined, and
that sometimes it finds that different options are equally preferable, or it
finds that the will rejects its rational priorities (and inclines to an object
that is good in another rational way).104
In this respect, Hause’s interpretation of ST I-II.13:6ad3 betrays his own
intellectualist inclinations. The question is about whether we choose out
of necessity or freely. The third objection proposes that a choice cannot be
free because from several objects we will necessarily choose whichever ap-
pears to be best. Aquinas replies (in Hause’s translation):
If two things are proposed (to the will) which are equal in one respect, nothing
prevents our considering in one of them some quality which makes it stand out,
and (so nothing prevents) the will’s being inclined to the one rather than to the
other.
ous things are available, and one seems to be best, we still do not choose
out of necessity, because the reason can consider different things to be su-
perior in different ways. It is about the indetermination of reason, and the
fact that the will is free to move in different directions precisely because
the reason has not come up with any necessary conclusions, and is still
capable of entertaining various alternative considerations. The will is not
determined by the reason here; it is the will that “determines” which of
the many possible rational determinations will prevail. This is why, to re-
turn to the third objection, a hungry man can choose one appetizing dish
rather than another; it is also why he can choose what does not appear to
be best (eminentius apparet), and eat the tablecloth, or not eat at all.
P. S. Eardley, another interpreter in the “intellectualist” line, presents
a fair summary of David Gallagher’s argument that for Aquinas, when an
object and an act can be considered by the reason in different ways, it is the
will that controls which consideration will take priority, independently of
a prior determination of reason.106 Eardley argues that this view, however,
should not be attributed to Aquinas, but that it fits more with the teaching
of Giles of Rome, one of his pupils.
On Thomas’s account, the will can never act independently of a prior judgment
of reason, either as regards exercise or as regards specification. If the will desires
one object over another, this is because reason has apprehended it as better and
specified or determined the will’s act accordingly. Furthermore, whether or not
the will exercises its act or the other powers of the soul is also determined by a
prior act of the intellect.107
Yet Eardley provides very little evidence for rejecting Gallagher’s con-
clusions. He appeals once to Hause, without referring to his actual argu-
ments.108 And, in another place, like Hause, he accepts hypothetically the
main thrust of the “voluntarist” argument, only to insist that a thorough-
going intellectualism would nevertheless lie behind it: “Even if the will has
the ability to control how the object is ultimately regarded by the intel-
106. P. S. Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on the Will”; commenting on Da-
vid M. Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgement in Thomas Aquinas,” Archiv für Geschichte
der Philosophie 76 (1994).
107. P. S. Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on the Will,” 846.
108. “Aquinas cannot, as Gallagher would have it, be considered a voluntarist as regards
the self-motion of the will. Rather, as Hause has shown, he should be regarded as a thorough-
going intellectualist”; see Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on the Will,” 847.
230 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
lect, nonetheless, any such act has to have been itself determined by a prior
judgment of the intellect.”109 The evidence for this statement is the pas-
sage from ST I.82:4ad3, which I have already discussed in chapter 4 (“[But]
not every apprehension is preceded by a movement of the will”).110 What-
ever Aquinas is doing in this difficult passage, he is certainly not talking
about prior judgments of the intellect which might control how the will
then controls the considerations made by the intellect.111
Eardley continues his interpretation with a misreading of ST I-II.9:4.
Aquinas writes that “even with regard to its being moved to exercise its act,
it is necessary to posit that the will is moved by some external principle.”112
Eardley writes that “such an ‘external’ principle is deliberation (consilium),”
and uses this understanding to conclude that “the intellect both determines
whether the will should elicit an act or not and also what it should will.”113
But the “external principle” referred to in this article is quite clearly not
consilium—it is instead God. In the body of the article Aquinas explains
that we can only come to will the means to an end through a process of de-
liberation, and that this process of deliberating and willing cannot stretch
back indefinitely; and for this reason the original willing of the will must
come “by the impulse of some exterior mover [ex instinctu alicuius exterio-
ris moventis], as Aristotle concludes in a chapter of the Eudemian Ethics.”114
So the reference is to the transcendent cause of our willing, which lies in
God, and not to any particular (intellectual) principle within us. The refer-
ence to the Eudemian Ethics makes this very clear.115
Robert Pasnau gives a spirited intellectualist reading of various Thomis-
tic texts.116 The main problem is that by the end he loses spirit himself, and
becomes uneasy about the deterministic implications of this reading, and
about whether such implications are really true to Aquinas. He believes
that Aquinas’s theory of free decision is compatibilist, and gives two sub-
109. Ibid., 845.
110. See the section “Reflexivity of Intellect and Will.”
111. See my comments on this passage in chapter 4 above, in the section “Reflexivity of In-
tellect and Will.”
112. ST I-II.9:4c; Eardley’s translation, in P. S. Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of
Rome on the Will,” 845–46.
113. P. S. Eardley, “Thomas Aquinas and Giles of Rome on the Will,” 846.
114. ST I-II.9:4c.
115. Eudemian Ethics 7:14, 1248a18ff.
116. Robert Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 2002), esp. section 7.4, 221–33.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 231
117. Ibid., 221. In my understanding, Aquinas could certainly not support the first state-
ment because a lack of necessity in freedom is one of his constant refrains; but he could pos-
sibly support the second statement because he does not say that freedom is uncaused or un-
determined, since the intellect always determines the object of free decision (so the act itself
is never undetermined), and since freedom does not exclude various kinds of causes (e.g., the
transcendent cause of our natural desire for happiness).
118. Pasnau’s translations; ibid., 224 and 227.
119. Ibid., 228–29.
120. Ibid., 229.
121. Thomas J. Loughran gives a sophisticated defense of Aquinas’s apparent compatibilism
in his “Aquinas, Compatibilist,” in Human and Divine Agency: Anglican, Catholic, and Luther-
an Perspectives, ed. Michael F. McLain and Mark W. Richardson (Lanham, Md.: University
Press of America, 1999). He argues that what makes acts of human intellect and will contingent,
rather than necessary, even when they are determined by a full set of causal antecedents, is the
fact that the antecedents themselves are contingent, and that they are beyond the grasp of the
agent. In other words, our acts are fully determined, but because the contingent determining
232 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
How—the libertarian asks—could we then be free? The compatibilist has no de-
fense against this line of attack, other than to suggest that it is a mistake to sup-
pose ourselves so in control of our choices. It just is true that the causes of our
actions extend beyond our reach.122
This kind of response, Pasnau admits, seems to run against Aquinas’s re-
peated insistence that the movement of the will is in no way necessary.
He finds “hints” that Aquinas understands necessity in a way weaker than
libertarians would want; and then suggests that human beings are only
subject to a “conditional necessity” that results from the contingent cir-
cumstances of our environment and our history: “Given the entire state of
the universe, including an individual’s higher-order beliefs and desires, a
certain choice will inevitably follow”; “Human beings must make certain
choices, given (a) their natures, (b) the surrounding circumstances, and
(c) their higher-order beliefs and desires.”123 Pasnau finishes this section in
a slightly wistful manner:
It would be absurd to deny that animals do, in some sense, determine their
own actions. It would be equally absurd to deny that we determine our own ac-
tions, in a fundamentally deeper way. Perhaps we too do not escape the chains
of causal necessity. But if we are determined, we are determined by our own be-
liefs and values, not simpy by the brute design of nature and the happenstance
of events. This difference, for Aquinas, makes all the difference.124
forces are so diffuse and beyond our comprehension, we understand ourselves to be acting in-
dependently and without necessity. “Human beings experience independence from any mea-
sure of the causal antecedents to choice which they can comprehend” (15).
122. Robert Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 231.
123. Ibid., 232.
124. Ibid., 233.
125. Loughran draws the same conclusions. “The compatibilist model leaves human be-
ings with exactly the measure of independence from proximate causal orders which reflec-
tion on human experience reveals [.....] . But that independence from proximate causal orders,
freedom from necessity in that sense, in no way implies independence from the entire order
of created causality.” He goes on to acknowledge that, for libertarians, this kind of freedom
“will seem plainly insufficient to preserve freedom; worse, it seems irrelevant”; see Thomas J.
Loughran, Human and Divine Agency, 18.
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 233
Self-movement belongs properly to the will and not to the intellect, since
the intellect is moved by the will to act, “but the will is not moved by an-
other power but by itself.”131 The idea of self-movement implies that the
fact of movement has no cause outside the occurrence of the movement it-
self. Aquinas states that “freedom is the cause of its own movement [causa
sui motus], because by one’s freedom one moves oneself [seipsum movet] to
act.”132 There is a kind of “immanent” operation here, which must, as Ste-
phen Brock explains, “be an activity which is immediately and simultane-
ously able to effect either one thing or its contrary.”133 It is no exaggeration
to say that self-movement is a kind of self-creation, since the self is consti-
tuted by its ends, and we choose our ends and therefore our self by moving
ourselves toward them.134
on this question of the will’s self-movement, De malo 6 is particularly
helpful.135 Aquinas is writing about the exercise of the act (i.e., whether an
end that is already understood by the reason in a particular way will actu-
ally be pursued), rather than the specification of the act (i.e., whether an end
will be understood by the reason in one way rather than another).136 He ex-
plains that “the will is moved by itself [voluntas movetur a se ipsa]: for just
as it moves the other powers, so also does it move itself [se ipsam movet].”137
He recognizes that this seems to imply a contradiction, since moving some-
thing normally involves one thing that is not in motion being moved by
another thing that is in motion. How can the will be both not in motion
and in motion at the same time? He writes that in this case the will is not
“both in potency and in act with regard to the same thing.”138 For just as
our knowledge of one thing leads us on an investigation that results in some
new knowledge, so the fact that we already will one thing (such as health)
leads us to will another thing (such as the taking of some medicine).
131. DM 6ad10.
132. But this doesn’t exclude God being the first cause of our freedom; see ST I.83:1ad3 and
below.
133. Brock, Action and Conduct: Thomas Aquinas and the Theory of Action, 40, footnote 79.
134. This does not mean, as we shall see below, that the will is without a transcendent
cause that explains its original ability to move.
135. See DM 6c [360–415].
136. But it is important to remember that the will’s control over the exercise of an act also
has some bearing on the act’s specification, since any specification depends on a particular act
of the intellect that itself needs activating.
137. DM 6c [361–63].
138. DM 6c [364–65].
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 235
To the suggestion that an external principle behind the will brings with
it some kind of coercion, Aquinas replies: “The will contributes something
when it is moved by God, for it is the will itself which acts [ipsa enim que
operator], although moved by God.”145 God makes the will to be what it is,
which is an inclination to happiness that can be embodied and fulfilled in
many different ways—and the decision about which way depends on the
human person and not on God. In a discussion of what happens when
the will makes a new choice, he writes that this change is effected by two
movers, “insofar as the will itself moves itself to act and insofar as it is also
moved by an external agent, namely God [in quantum ipsa voluntas movet
se ipsam ad agendum et in quantum etiam movetur ab alio exteriori agente,
scilicet Deo].”146 There is no contradiction for Aquinas between our radical
dependence on God as the transcendent foundation of our freedom, and
the radical independence of that freedom insofar as it allows us to deter-
mine our goals and thus constitute ourselves. To be human is to have the
possibility of creating a future that has not been predetermined; it is to go
beyond the bounds of necessity.
In ST I-II.6:1 Aquinas relates the possibility of the will’s self-movement
more specifically to knowledge of an end. He writes that a stone does not
move itself downward, even though the principle of this movement is in-
trinsic to the stone (and we might therefore be tempted to say that through
its own heaviness the stone thrusts itself downward). “But those things
which have a knowledge of the end are said to move themselves because
there is in them a principle by which they not only act but also act for
an end.”147 Irrational animals have an imperfect knowledge of their end
and consequently their acts have a kind of voluntariness [voluntarium]. Yet
these animals apprehend the end “without knowing it under the aspect of
the end, or the relationship of an act to an end.”148 Aquinas continues:
Perfect knowledge of an end goes with voluntary activity in its complete sense;
inasmuch as, having apprehended the end, a human being can, from deliberat-
ing about the end and the means thereto, be moved, or not, to gain that end.149
150. Cf. ST I-II.13:3c, where Aquinas explains how the end in one operation can be a means
to bring about a further end.
151. ST I-II.6:2ad2.
152. David B. Burrell, Aquinas: God and Action (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1979), 128. There is no space here to discuss the huge topic of character in Aquinas.
It is enough to say that even though character (habitus) can become a principle of human ac-
tions (see ST I-II.49:3), it develops as a consequence of human actions (see ST I-II.51:2–3). There
238 = h u m a n f r e e d o m
comes through choosing this goal did not exist before the choice was made.
The human person is the one who creates oneself through seeking specific
goals. The choice itself is self-constituting. David Gallagher formulates this
in a startling way:
The judgment of choice which determines the will’s motion arises in the choice,
a choice which occurs only when it is willed. Hence the will influences, in the
act of choice, the very judgment it follows in that act.153
is a feedback effect in which actions produce dispositions and dispositions produce actions. The
ultimate foundation of the process lies in the individual choices that produce action.
153. Gallagher, “Free Choice and Free Judgment in Thomas Aquinas,” 256.
154. Ibid., 276.
155. In a passage about how one can attribute the activity of parts of a substance to the ac-
tivity of the whole, Aquinas writes: “We may therefore say that the soul understands, just as
the eye sees; but it is more correct to say that the human being understands through the soul
[homo intelligat per animam]” (ST I.57:2ad2).
f r e e d o m i n a q u i n a s = 239
how to understand or what to seek. Our reason has discovered that there
is no single objective way of understanding things, no single set of nec-
essary goals. We are paralyzed. Then, at the moment of choice, our will
approves of one specific way of understanding things by actually seeking
one specific good. The will as it brings about one possible way of under-
standing things constitutes the freedom of the acting person. We go beyond
the indeterminate world of possibility and create a single determined fu-
ture through action. So our identity, which is constituted in relation to the
goods that we actually seek, is established. We become sure of who we are
by crystallizing one way of understanding the world and our self, and ori-
entating our whole being to this good. We create ourselves by seeking this
form of perfection in this good.
So the undertaking of one project (understanding in this way, desir-
ing in this way, being this person) is the self. There is no other “self ” that
exists outside or before the willing of one goal, as its cause or explanation.
There is no “deep self ” that is a prior foundation for the choice we make
of one project from among many. We constitute ourselves through our
free choices. Our goals constitute our personhood, yet they are themselves
constituted by the person we choose to be. Even if we never reach the goal
in the future, an identity is still created in the present. What matters is the
direction in which we are actually moving and our personal understand-
ing of the significance of that direction. We are a longing, a direction, a
project—not a finished product. To be human is to be in via, to be on the
way. To be free is to choose the way, and in choosing the way, to choose the
end at which we hope to arrive.
Part Four
H u ma n F u lf i llm e n t
Chapter 7
T h e P o s s i b i l i t y o f H u m a n H a pp i n e s s
in Sartre
243
244 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
1. ST I.II.2:1c. See the translations in Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers
of the English Dominican Province, 5 vols. (Westminster, Md.: Christian Classics, 1948) and
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, ed. Thomas Gilby, 60 vols. (London: Blackfriars/Eyre &
Spottiswoode, 1963ff) (which curiously uses “happiness” in the text and “beatitude” in some of
the headings).
2. BN 90; EN 127/134.
3. The Prologue to Part II, for example, sets the whole question of the nature of the human
being in a theological context: The human being “is made in God’s image” (factus ad imaginem
Dei), and Aquinas only treats of God’s image here because he has already spent the 119 ques-
tions of Part I treating, broadly speaking, of God himself.
h ap p i n e s s i n s a r t r e = 245
4. BN 194; EN 230/244.
5. BN 626; EN 674/720, manquée can mean both “failed” and “missing.”
6. BN 101; EN 138/146.
246 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
surge of the negation of its being-in-itself. “What the for-itself lacks is the
self—or itself as in-itself [Ce que le pour-soi manque, c’est le soi—ou soi-
même comme en-soi].”7 Sartre’s anthropology flows out of his phenomenol-
ogy. To be human is to exist in-between two poles as a “lived relation [rap-
port vécu]”: these poles are the present facticity of being-in-itself and the
future ideal of the in-itself-for-itself. “Human beings are neither the one
nor the other of these beings, since there is no sense in which we are. We
are what we are not and we are not what we are.”8 In other words, it is a
constitutive part of our nature to consider and seek a perfection that we do
not yet have (“we are what we are not”), and it is a constitutive part of our
nature to be conscious of a lack of complete identification with who we are
now (“we are not what we are”).
Sartre writes about the ideal of self-coincidence in a number of ways.9 It
is “the impossible synthesis of the for-itself and the in-itself ” which would
“preserve within it the necessary translucency of consciousness along with
the coincidence with itself of being-in-itself.”10 He identifies the ideal with
value insofar as the values we seek are precisely things that do not exist,
things that define the persons we wish to become. Value is the “beyond”
that draws us out of ourselves toward a future self that does not exist.11 Sar-
tre writes about “value taken in its origin, or the supreme value,”12 which
bears a great similarity to the universal good in Aquinas. It is not the par-
ticular good sought but the good as good for us: the fact that a good allows
us to surpass ourselves and constitute ourselves in relation to a perfection
we have not yet achieved. The supreme value is the underlying fulfillment
of the self that we seek as we seek particular values, “the absolute being of
the self with its characteristics of identity, of purity, or permanence, etc.,
and as its own foundation.”13 Beauty represents for us this ideal state of ful-
fillment.14 Yet even beauty is apprehended only as an absence that haunts
the imperfection of the world. We can only realize the beautiful through
our imagination, which grasps the ideal but simultaneously recognizes the
unreality of what is imagined.
The ideal is “an unrealisable totality which haunts the for-itself and
In the play In Camera Garcin remarks, “I died too soon. I wasn’t al-
lowed time to carry out my acts.” To which Inès replies, “One always dies
too soon—or too late. And yet life is over with, finished; the deed is done
and you must add it all up. You are nothing other than your life.”21
Many aspects of the dilemma of ontological unhappiness are played
out in human relationships.22 “The look” (le regard) of “the other” (autrui)
confers on our being a kind of objectivity and allows us to observe our
freedom from the outside.23 “I see myself because somebody sees me.”24 In
the eyes of the other our projects and identities, which are so precarious,
take on a certain stability and seem like essential features of our being. Our
recognition of the subjectivity of the other gives us an unreflective experi-
ence of our own objectivity, and for a moment takes away the anguish of
having to go beyond what we are. Objectification in itself is not necessar-
ily negative, even though Sartre illustrates it by describing experiences of
shame (la honte).25 Shame can be an authentic attitude because it allows us
to apprehend our nature as an object.26 “Pride” (la fierté), however, is yet
another form of bad faith. In pride we resign ourselves to being only what
20. BN 538–39; EN 583/623.
21. Jean-Paul Sartre, Huis Clos and Other Plays (London: Penguin Books, 2000), 221; origi-
nal French text in Jean-Paul Sartre, Huis Clos (London: Routledge, 1987), 93.
22. See BN 252–302; EN 292–341/310–64. 23. BN 259–65; EN 298–304/316–23.
24. BN 260; EN 299/318.
25. See BN 221–23 and 259–61; EN 259–61/275–77 and 298–300/316–18.
26. BN 290; EN 330/351.
h ap p i n e s s i n s a r t r e = 249
we are and take refuge from freedom in this objectified being.27 An au-
thentic response to shame is not pride but l’orgueil, which is perhaps best
translated as “assertiveness” rather than “arrogance” (or again “pride”),
since it means simply the reaffirmation of our freedom and the consequent
objectification of the other’s subjectivity.28
The two defining characteristics of human relationships emerge from
these primary phenomenological experiences. In Being and Nothingness the
words “amour” (love) and “le désir” (desire) are given technical meanings
that should be distinguished from their everyday ones. Through l’amour we
seek to become the object of the other’s freedom, so our freedom becomes
more and more alienated. This is why Sartre relates his concept of love to
masochism, because it holds a passive face to the subjectivity of the other.29
Through le désir we seek to turn the other into an object and to possess the
other’s freedom. This is why Sartre’s concept of desire is related to sadism,
because we use our own subjectivity to take hold of the other.30 Love allows
us to be appreciated for who we are—which limits our freedom; and desire
allows us to appreciate who the other person is—which restores our own
freedom, but restricts our ability to experience being loved. We oscillate be-
tween loving and desiring the other.
The failure to construct harmonious, stabilized relations, which is such
a notable feature of Sartre’s philosophy, is actually a guarantee that each
person in the relationship is free. If we love others as persons then there is
always the possibility that their freedom will take us by surprise. This cre-
ates conflict. We can appreciate whatever objective face they show in the
present, but this is quite different from objectifying them and denying that
they are free to change this face. The fact that others do not always fit with
our expectations is a sign that we are relating to their freedom as well as
to their identity. Conflict in a relationship is, for Sartre, a positive sign that
two people have not turned themselves or each other into objects that can
be possessed and manipulated.31 Just as we can never find perfect happi-
ness in a stabilized in-itself-for-itself, so we can never find perfect happi-
ness with another. The lack of perfect harmony in any human relationship
is, strangely, a sign that the relationship is still alive.32
God is for Sartre the ideal of securely having an identity and freely found-
ing it at the same time. The fundamental project of human beings is to be
God. “To be human means to reach toward being God; or, if you prefer,
the human being fundamentally is the desire to be God.”35 We desire to be
“consciousness become substance, substance become the cause of self, the
Human-God [la conscience devenue substance, la substance devenue cause
de soi, l’Homme-Dieu].”36
Sartre adopts, for his own phenomenological purposes, the religious
vocabulary of the Judeo-Christian culture in which he stood. This tradi-
tion recognized the transcendent possibility of a being who can be both
perfectly free and perfectly fulfilled, beyond himself and in possession of
himself, ecstatic and recollected. At the same time Sartre insists that such
a being, in the terms of his phenomenological ontology, by definition can-
not exist. This is because consciousness and freedom are inextricably as-
sociated for Sartre with distance, negation, doubt, lack, and incompletion.
Consciousness always involves an openness to what one is not, an aware-
principles: No matter how strongly we love others, if we love them solely for who they are now,
this is an act of bad faith, since it restricts them to their present identity. If we love them as per-
sons we will love them for who they could be and not just for who they are, which is to love a
future self that could arise from the freedom of the one loved. Part of loving others in the pres-
ent is the desire to love whoever they will become through their free choices. So long-term
commitment to a relationship is not an additional factor we might give in the future but an es-
sential element of loving a person now in the present.
33. There is an excellent assessment of the relationship between Sartre’s theology and his
phenomenology by Frederick J. Crosson, “Intentionality and Atheism: Sartre and Maritain,”
The Modern Schoolman 64 (1987). See also James McLachlan, “The Theological Character of
Sartre’s Atheology in ‘Being and Nothingness,’ ” Epoche 5, nos. 1–2 (1997).
34. BN 90; EN 126/133. 35. BN 566; EN 612/654.
36. BN 575; EN 621/664.
h ap p i n e s s i n s a r t r e = 251
37. Note the brief foray into metaphysical speculation at BN 619–25; EN 667–73/713–20.
38. Frederick Crosson speculates about how Sartre’s view of consciousness might allow
for a conception of God in which he would know himself (and all things as they participate
in his infinite being) through a completely actualized and timeless self-consciousness, without
there being any duality or knowledge of himself as object. There could be some kind of self-
coincidence and completion that would not destroy consciousness. In other words, the ab-
sence of self-identity and substantiality which Sartre knows to be a condition of temporal hu-
man consciousness may not be a condition of all consciousnesses. See Crosson, “Intentionality
and Atheism: Sartre and Maritain,” 156–60.
39. BN 615; EN 662/708.
252 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
happy. “Human reality is suffering in its being” because “it could not attain
the in-itself without losing itself as for-itself.” It is therefore “by nature an
unhappy consciousness with no possibility of surpassing its unhappy state
[par nature conscience malheureuse, sans dépassement possible de l’état de
malheur].”40 A “constant disappointment” accompanies every momentary
achievement. We ask ourselves “Is it only this? [n’est-ce que cela?]” and an-
other horizon of possibilities immediately opens out.41 The disillusion, we
should remember, is not connected with circumstances, it is an “ontologi-
cal disappointment.”42
Even a sympathetic critic like Frederick Olafson found these conclu-
sions too pessimistic and wished that Sartre had recognized that some hu-
man lives seem more disappointing and disappointed than others.
There is, after all, a distinction between lives that are crowned by achievement
and those that issue in frustration and failure, and this is a distinction that is
surely relevant to the business of making out—however difficult that may be—
whether a man is happy or not.43
I think that Olafson misses the point of Sartre’s argument. Sartre does
not deny that human beings can find some satisfaction in their achieve-
ments, nor does he deny that some lives are full of success and some full
of failure. He simply draws attention to the continual necessity of mov-
ing on. Any achievement becomes part of our facticity—we have to take
a view on it, interpret it, and project ourselves beyond it toward a future
goal. If we cling to it and define ourselves in terms of it, then it diminishes
our freedom and becomes an aspect of bad faith. Yet if we see beyond the
achievement (and admit that we are not yet fully happy), then the achieve-
ment becomes part of our unfolding identity and we preserve our freedom
and openness to the future. Unhappiness, as a manifestation of our con-
stant going beyond the present, is the guarantee that we are still conscious,
desiring human beings.44 There are less pessimistic ways of expressing the
less than complete happiness. There is no need to argue that human beings should seek certain
goods, or should seek the good of others. Ethics simply needs to start with the nature of human
desire and human freedom.
45. See Christina Howells, Sartre: The Necessity of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1988), 44–45 and 198–99; and Jean-Paul Sartre, Cahiers Pour Une Morale (Paris:
Gallimard, 1983), 450–53, translated as Jean-Paul Sartre, Notebooks for an Ethics, trans. David
Pellauer (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1992), 435–39.
254 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
reprise de l’être) that would take us beyond the categories of good and bad
faith.46 A radical conversion might lead to “an ethics of deliverance and
salvation.”47 The activity of play releases us from the spirit of seriousness
and allows us to appreciate our own subjectivity.48 Through existential psy-
choanalysis our freedom might become more conscious of itself and might
be able “to take itself as a value as the source of all value.”49
There is no space here to dwell on these provocative suggestions,50 nor
to delve into the notebooks that represent Sartre’s own attempts to take
these issues forward and open up further avenues for exploration.51 I want
to make just one point here, which is that however much Sartre’s thought
develops in his later works, however much nuance he adds, he never puts
in question the essential conclusions of phenomenological ontology made
in Being and Nothingness.His enigmatic references to authenticity and con-
version do not represent a repudiation of the basic ontology of freedom
mapped out in Being and Nothingness.52 He continues to hold in his later
work that we are fundamentally incomplete beings. We have an identity
(as “being-in-itself ”); we are present to this identity and have to go beyond
46. BN 70, footnote 9; EN 106/110, footnote.
47. BN 412, footnote 14; EN 453/484, footnote. Cf. BN 627; EN 675/721.
48. BN 580–81; EN 626–27/669–70. 49. BN 627; EN 675/722.
50. For some helpful interpretations of what Sartre might have meant, see Francis Jean-
son, Sartre and the Problem of Morality, trans. Robert V. Stone (Bloomington: Indiana Uni-
versity Press, 1980), esp. 208–19; Hazel E. Barnes, An Existentialist Ethics (New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 1967), esp. 55; Juliette Simont, “Sartrean Ethics,” in The Cambridge Companion to Sar-
tre, ed. Christina Howells (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), esp. 180–84; How-
ells, Sartre: The Necessity of Freedom, esp. 24–25; David Detmer, Freedom as a Value: A Critique
of the Ethical Theory of Jean-Paul Sartre (La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1988), esp. 107–23; Thomas
W. Busch, “Sartre’s Use of the Reduction: Being and Nothingness Reconsidered,” in Jean-Paul
Sartre: Contemporary Approaches to His Philosophy, ed. Hugh J. Silverman and Frederick A.
Elliston (Pittsburgh, Pa.: Duquesne University Press, 1980); and Thomas W. Busch, The Power
of Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in Sartre’s Philosophy (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1990), esp. 30–39.
51. Sartre, Cahiers Pour Une Morale, translated as Notebooks for an Ethics. See Thomas C.
Anderson, Sartre’s Two Ethics: From Authenticity to Integral Humanity (Chicago: Open Court,
1993).
52. Sartre himself famously referred to his work of 1943 as “une eidétique de la mauvaise
foi,” an eidetic or presentation of bad faith. He is not, however, rejecting the phenomenologi-
cal picture of the human being proposed in BN. The context of the phrase makes it clear that
he is comparing unfavourably his own theoretical and abstract phenomenology with Merleau-
Ponty’s more empirical studies of the concrete and often inhuman forces that actually shape
history. With hindsight he is criticizing his own analysis of the human situation for being de-
tached and insufficient, and not for being wrong. See Jean-Paul Sartre, Situations IV (Paris:
Gallimard, 1964), 196 and footnote.
h ap p i n e s s i n s a r t r e = 255
it (as “being-for-itself ”); and we seek a freely chosen future identity (in
“being-in-itself-for-itself ”).
Human beings cannot renounce this fundamental desire to be God, to
attain completion, without renouncing ourselves. We avoid this necessity
of going beyond ourselves and constituting ourselves in relation to an ideal
future. There may be additional attitudes we can adopt within this quest,
there may be further inferences we can draw from this quest, there may be
the possibility of turning the exercise of freedom into a goal, or of accept-
ing that the ultimate goal will never be reached—but Sartre never implies
that we can abandon this quest altogether. The refusal to rest satisfied, the
constant push beyond, over the horizon, is all that human beings can hope
for—at least by their own resources. Consciousness is not only conscious-
ness of not being what is present and having to be what is future (which is
where Sartre began), it is also consciousness of never being able to be this
future. This is the most profound sense of being human.
Chapter 8
T h e P o s s i b i l i t y of H u m a n
H a ppi n e s s i n A q u i n a s
1. ST I.79:8c. 2. ST I.79:8c.
3. ST I-II.3:4c. 4. ST I-II.11:1c.
5. ST I-II.11:1ad3.
256
h ap p i n e s s i n a q u i n a s = 257
This notion of rest and enjoyment may seem to undermine the cen-
tral argument of this book. I have been suggesting that intellect and will
function for Aquinas in a similar way to Sartre’s consciousness and being-
for-itself. We are by nature open to what we are not (through intellect)
and striving to become what we are not (through will), and our identity as
human beings consists in a perpetual going-beyond ourselves toward an-
other identity that does not yet exist, toward our future perfection. When-
ever we seek a particular good, we are seeking our own good, which is pre-
cisely our being insofar as it does not yet exist.6 Even if the good we seek
is simply the preservation of what we already have (like health or friend-
ship), there is still a sense in which this preservation of our being in the fu-
ture is something we do not yet have, which is the very reason why we are
seeking it. Our being is necessarily fractured by the decentering that intel-
lect and will bring about.
If in fact we can reach this perfection and actually be happy with it, if
we can possess an identity without having any distance from it, if we can
halt this constant movement beyond, then the picture I have presented of
Aquinas’s human being is false. For Sartre, to be human is to go beyond
what we have and what we are. For Aquinas, it seems, we can at some point
rest content with what we have and what we are; in Sartre’s terms, we can
reach a state of becoming pure being-in-itself. Rest, possession, enjoyment,
satisfaction: these are concepts that would indicate to Sartre the dark night
of identity and the dissolution of consciousness. With these questions in
mind we can examine the extent to which Aquinas thinks that we can and
cannot be happy in this life.
Happiness, beatitudo, as we saw in chapter 6, is the satisfaction we
hope to find when we reach our final goal and attain the perfection we
have longed for. We can want many different things at the same time, large
and small, yet at any one moment there must be a deepest desire that moti-
vates us, an overriding goal that functions as an organizing principle to our
actions, one which we long for as our “perfect and fulfilling good [bonum
perfectum et completivum].” 7 Happiness is the perfect good, “which satis-
6. This is true even when our attention is directed away from ourselves to the good of oth-
er people or other things, since our desire is still personal and part of what we wish our own
life to be about. See the discussion of “the good” in chapter 2 above.
7. ST I-II.1:5c.
258 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
fies the appetite altogether, else it would not be the last end, if something
yet remained to be desired.”8 If we find the ultimate good we are seeking
and fulfill our desire, then we will be happy.
Aquinas makes three important distinctions as he writes about happi-
ness.9 The first, which we have already come across, is between the general
meaning of the last end (the ratio of the last end, the last end as such) and
the particular object we are seeking as our last end (“the thing in which
the last end is found [id in quo finis ultimi ratio invenitur]”).10 We all seek
our last end as such, we all want to be happy and to find fulfillment in our
perfect good. Yet we don’t all agree on how to be happy, on where we will
find that fulfillment. The second distinction is between beatitudo imper-
fecta and beatitudo perfecta.11 Imperfect or incomplete happiness is sim-
ply happiness to the extent that we can find it in this life: it is “that which
is had in this life [quae habetur in hac vita].” Perfect or complete happi-
ness “consists in the vision of God.”12 Only perfect happiness “attains to
the true notion of happiness,” while imperfect happiness “does not attain
thereto, but partakes of some particular likeness of happiness [participat
quandam particularem beatitudinis similitudinem].”13 The third distinction
is between possessing an end imperfectly, “only in intention,” and possess-
ing an end perfectly, “not only in intention but also in reality [in re].”14 The
8. ST I-II.2:8c.
9. For the historical background to Aquinas’s discussion of happiness and for an account
of some of the influences on him, see Georg Wieland, “Happiness: The Perfection of Man,” in
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy, ed. Norman Kretzmann, Anthony Kenny,
and Jan Pinborg (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982).
10. ST I-II.1:7c. See the discussion of the indetermination of ends in chapter 6 above.
11. The theological distinction goes back to William of Auxerre, died 1231; see Wieland,
“Happiness: The Perfection of Man,” 679. Aquinas uses it to develop some unresolved themes
in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, where, for example, worldly happiness is subject to fortune,
and contemplation, although the best activity of the human being, is also something beyond
human attainment. See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis, Ind.:
Hackett, 1985), 10:7, 1177b26 to 1178a6; and Anthony Kenny, “Aquinas on Aristotelian Happi-
ness,” in Aquinas’s Moral Theory: Essays in Honour of Norman Kretzmann, ed. Scott MacDon-
ald and Eleonore Stump (Ithaca, N.Y., and London: Cornell University Press, 1998), 24. An-
thony Celano argues convincingly that in formalizing these distinctions Aquinas draws out the
implications of Aristotle’s ethics without betraying his thought; see Anthony J. Celano, “The
Concept of Worldly Beatitude in the Writings of Thomas Aquinas,” Journal of the History of
Philosophy 25 (1987).
12. ST I-II.4:5c.
13. ST I-II.3:6c.
14. ST I-II.11:4c.
h ap p i n e s s i n a q u i n a s = 259
will can thus have a true but imperfect enjoyment of the last end even be-
fore it reaches it, through its active striving toward this goal.
Aquinas writes with great simplicity in ST I-II.5:3 that “perfect and true
happiness cannot be had in this life [perfecta autem et vera beatitudo non
potest haberi in hac vita].”15 This statement alone should puzzle us. On the
one hand, the whole point of human life is happiness. On the other hand,
Aquinas now insists, we can never find true happiness in this life. Aquinas
believes that human beings by their very nature cannot find perfect hap-
piness in this life—the “rest” we can achieve is never total. As bodily crea-
tures who exist in time and who have an infinite desire to understand and
be fulfilled, we can never find the final rest we are searching for in this life.
This is not because of some circumstantial difficulty or personal weakness,
it is because of our nature as temporal creatures with intellect and will.
Aquinas agrees with Sartre that the perfection human beings naturally de-
sire, being-in-itself-for-itself, is a self-contradictory synthesis that cannot
be attained in this life. Whether it is possible for us to attain another kind
of life, beyond time, is a separate question to which we will return later.
21. ST I-II.2:8ad3.
22. ST I-II.11:3c, referring to De Trinitate, 10:10.
23. ST I-II.11:3c.
262 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
24. ST I-II.11:3c.
25. BN 501, see 501–4; EN 546/582, see 546–49/582–85.
26. ST I-II.5:3c.
27. ST I-II.5:4c.
h ap p i n e s s i n a q u i n a s = 263
This lack of stability, and the anxiety that follows with it, are a necessary
part of temporal existence. Aquinas writes that vicissitudes such as these
are “for such things as are subject to time and movement.”28
Even if we could somehow reach an infinite good in this life, and pos-
sess it without fear of ever losing it, there is still a final reason why perfect
happiness would be beyond us. Aquinas writes in ST I-II.3:2 that insofar
as happiness is a created reality in us it must involve our own activity (op-
eratio). Happiness, in other words, is not just something that happens to
us. Part of our fulfillment is to be actively involved in that fulfillment.29 It
is not enough for us to be alive, we want to be actively living.30 But in this
present life human activity can never be unified or continual.31 We have to
act in time, in the present, moment by moment, and therefore our activity
is necessarily fragmented. Although contemplation of the truth is an ac-
tivity that has more unity than an active life occupied with many things,
Aquinas is realistic about the fact that even this has to be interrupted by
sleeping and doing other things. So we can never act now in a way that en-
sures that all our future activity will be part of (or even consistent with)
this present act. We cannot collapse the future into the present and take
possession of a total, everlasting happiness. This is another example of how
our failure to be happy relates to our nature and not to certain unfortu-
nate circumstances. We are beings who operate progressively in time, and
we cannot unify this activity and bring it to completion in one integrated
movement.
For the many reasons outlined in this section, Aquinas is convinced
that human beings cannot find perfect happiness in this life. We should
not lose sight of the force of this conclusion. Aquinas does not say that per-
fect happiness in this life is a difficult achievement, one that is too much
for us in practice, and that we therefore need God’s help to find it. Instead
he says that perfect happiness in this life is in principle an impossible idea.
It would contradict our very nature to find perfect happiness. Human life
itself is fragmented and we have only a precarious hold on ourselves. We
are temporal creatures whose nature is to look beyond the present to the
28. ST I-II.5:4c.
29. ST I-II.3:2c.
30. Life involves the being of the living thing (esse viventis) and also the activity of the liv-
ing thing (operatio viventis); see ST I-II.3:2ad1.
31. ST I-II.3:2ad4.
264 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
future, to the good we do not yet possess, to the person we have not yet
become. Human beings in time are always seeking a further good. Aqui-
nas is absolutely insistent on this point. The temporal goods we seek are
necessarily insufficient and necessarily unstable. We have an infinite and
therefore insatiable desire to have more and to know more, and we know
that everything we do lay hold of will eventually pass. Aquinas has no con-
ception of what it might be like for human beings to achieve their perfec-
tion in this life. A perfectly happy human being could bear no resemblance
to the human beings that we know. Temporal human perfection is self-
contradictory because it would mean that we had finally become all that
we could be, which would be a kind of not-being-human. Aquinas be-
lieves, for the same reasons as Sartre, that perfect human happiness is im-
possible in this life because it would mean the end and not the fulfillment
of the human life that we know.
32. ST I-II.2:8c.
h ap p i n e s s i n a q u i n a s = 265
finite good.33 The universal good, however, that alone can satisfy our will,
is not just a theoretical synthesis for Aquinas, it must also be a real possi-
bility, and he argues from the nature of our desire for the universal good to
the possibility of our finding it. In Aquinas’s understanding, it makes per-
fect sense to say that the existence of a desire or capacity is enough to es-
tablish that the desire or capacity could in principle be fulfilled (although
it may in the circumstances not be fulfilled). Similarly, the existence of
any potentiality is enough to establish that the potentiality could in prin-
ciple be actualized (although it may in the circumstances not be actual-
ized). Desire and potentiality are by definition aspects of a thing insofar
as it relates to the fullness of being it could have. They signify a relation-
ship with the perfection that is due to, appropriate to, and possible for this
being.34 This is the metaphysical background that allows Aquinas to state
with great simplicity:
Happiness is called the attainment of the perfect good. Whoever, therefore, is
capable of the perfect good can attain happiness. Now, that human beings are
capable of the perfect good, is proved both because their intellect can appre-
hend the universal and perfect good, and because their will can desire it. And
therefore human beings can attain happiness.35
33. ST I-II.2:8ad3.
34. Cf. ST I-II.18:1c, where some things are said to lack the fullness of being “due to them”
(eis debitam).
35. ST I-II.5:1c.
266 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
inane].”36 It is true that he first gives a theological reason for this, and states
bluntly that it is “opposed to the faith” to suppose that the created intel-
lect cannot find happiness in the vision of God, or can find it in something
else.37 Yet we should note that the argument from natural desire is explic-
itly given as an additional nontheological reason for thinking that the cre-
ated intellect can see the essence of God.38
Aquinas makes a similar argument in the body of ST I-II.3:8, this time
without the appeal to faith. He writes that our curious intellects, which
wonder incessantly about causes, cannot be satisfied with knowing that
God exists as First Cause, since we want to know what he is and reach “the
very essence of the first cause.”39 Final and perfect happiness must there-
fore consist in nothing less than the vision of the Divine Essence.
Aquinas thus shows not only that we are capable of perfect happiness
but that we can find this in God alone. Once again, I want to insist that
there is a philosophical argument here that makes sense without the sup-
port of faith or religious revelation. Of course Aquinas never steps out-
side of the theological framework of the Summa, and he draws continually
on biblical and theological resources. But he also recognizes that a philo-
sophical investigation into the nature of human longing would necessar-
ily lead one to the idea of God. God is the universal good and the First
Cause of all things who must exist if our infinite desire for happiness and
for understanding are not to be in vain. Human desire necessarily points
to God. Right at the beginning of the Summa Aquinas writes that we can
be brought to an initial, imprecise conception of God by reflecting on the
nature of human desire:
To know that God exists in a general and confused way is implanted in us by na-
ture, inasmuch as God is the happiness of human beings. For we naturally desire
happiness, and what is naturally desired by us must be naturally known to us.
This, however, is not simply speaking to know that God exists [non est simplic-
iter cognoscere Deum esse], just as to know that someone is approaching is not
the same as to know that Peter is approaching, even though it is Peter who is ap-
proaching; for many there are who imagine that our perfect good which is happi-
ness, consists in riches, and others in pleasures, and others in something else.40
disappeared. The problem is not so much the contradiction; indeed, the postmodern instinct
is to rejoice in such contradictions. The real problem is that this account does not do justice
to the existential experience. Our actions betray our deepest understanding of what is real and
what we understand to be actually possible. We act not just “as if ” the ideal were achievable.
We act, instead, for or toward an ideal; thoroughly committed to achieving it; orienting our
minds, our bodies, our plans, our energies, our whole lives around this ideal. It is not enough
to insist that we don’t “really” believe in it when everything connected with our own reality is
constituted by it.
44. Gianfranco Basti, Filosofia Dell’uomo (Bologna: Edizioni Studio Domenicano, 1995),
293–96.
45. ST I.2:1ad1.
h ap p i n e s s i n a q u i n a s = 269
46. This refusal might also provide a “reason” for changing projects, for conversion, which
was so lacking in chapter 5 because of the incommensurability of alternative projects. If we rec-
ognize that our desire is always to go further than the present goal we have set ourselves, then
this will give us a reason for choosing a new goal if it has more and richer possibilities. The
only bad choice, the only “sin,” is not wanting to be happy enough, or not wanting enough to be
happy. It is resigning ourselves to a limited good, a limited vision of the self, when a greater
good beckons.
270 = h u m a n f u l f i l l m e n t
Essence “surpasses the nature not only of human beings, but also of ev-
ery creature” and “neither human beings, nor any creature, can attain final
happiness by their natural powers.”47 “It is impossible that it be bestowed
through the action of any creature: but by God’s work alone is the human
being made happy [homo beatus fit solo Deo agente], if we speak of perfect
Happiness.”48
Aquinas states two conclusions with absolute clarity, and he is able to
reach these conclusions without appealing to revelation (even though at
various points he also draws on revelation): (i) Human beings, by their
very nature as creatures of intellect and will, desire a perfect happiness that
cannot be found in this life. This perfect happiness can only be found in
union with God, since there is no end to our seeking in this life, and God
alone is the universal good that can entirely satisfy our will.49 (ii) Union
with God, the vision of God’s essence, surpasses the very nature of every
creature including the human being. All creaturely knowledge falls short
of the vision of the Divine Essence, “which infinitely surpasses all created
substance. Consequently neither human beings, nor any creatures, can at-
tain final happiness by their natural powers.”50
These two conclusions create a paradox. The perfect and crowning
good, to which we naturally tend, cannot be reached naturally. The vision
of the Divine Essence, which is absolutely necessary if we are to be happy,
is beyond our natural powers. Put very simply: we have a natural desire
for God that cannot be naturally fulfilled. This is no stranger than Sartre
writing that the goal we all strive toward (being-in-itself-for-itself) is at
the same time an impossible ideal, one that is by definition unachievable
because it would involve the dissolution of consciousness and being-for-
itself.
Denis Bradley gives a very helpful account of Aquinas’s position in his
book Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good, drawing on texts beyond the
few we have been looking at in ST I-II. Bradley writes that the thrust of
Aquinas’s philosophical thinking about “the natural endlessness of human
nature” leads to an aporia. As philosophy, it cannot rest satisfied with the
idea that human nature can find some natural fulfillment in this life, yet as
51. Denis J. M. Bradley, Aquinas on the Twofold Human Good: Reason and Human Happi-
ness in Aquinas’s Moral Science (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press,
1997), xiii.
52. Ibid., 514.
53. Recent debate was provoked by the publication of Henri De Lubac, Surnaturel: Études
Historiques (Paris: Aubier, 1946). For an excellent discussion of some contemporary views, see
Benedict M. Ashley, “What Is the End of the Human Person? The Vision of God and Integral
Human Fulfillment,” in Moral Truth and Moral Tradition: Essays in Honour of Peter Geach and
Elizabeth Anscombe, ed. Luke Gormally (Blackrock, Co. Dublin: Four Courts Press, 1994).
54. In Scholastic philosophy and theology “supernatural” simply means what is above or
beyond nature, what is beyond the unaided powers of any creature—it has nothing to do with
spooks or spells (which, as created things, might be quite “natural”).
h ap p i n e s s i n a q u i n a s = 273
Just as nature does not fail human beings [referring to homo] in things that are
necessary, although it has not provided them with weapons and clothing, as it
provided other animals, because it gave them reason and hands, with which
they are able to get these things for themselves; so neither did it fail human
beings in things that are necessary, although it did not give them the means
by which they could attain happiness [quamvis non daret sibi aliquod princi-
pium quo posset beatitudinem consequi]: since this is impossible. But it did give
them freedom, with which they can turn to God, so that he may make them
happy [Sed dedit ei liberum arbitrium, quo possit converti ad Deum, qui eum fac-
eret beatum]. “For what we are enabled to do by our friends, we ourselves, in a
sense, are able to do,” as it is said in Ethics 3.55
So it is our part of our nature not only to seek happiness but also to have
the ability to ask for what we cannot find through our own efforts. It is part
of our nature not only to be frustrated but to find a way out of our frustra-
tion. The fact that the achievement of happiness can only be a supernatural
gift from God does not mean that our desire or request for it needs some
supernatural cause. We can ask God to allow us to share in this way of life,
and perhaps he will grant it to us.
55. ST I-II.5:5ad1, citing Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3:3, 1112b27. For an English version,
see Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 63.
C o n c l u s io n
1. Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), esp. 495–521. See also Taylor’s
The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991).
2. This is my analogy and not Taylor’s.
275
276 = c o n c l u s i o n
ies of this world. These are some of the issues that Aquinas and Sartre are
grappling with. They both argue, in answer to Charles Taylor, that it is pos-
sible to take one’s place in a public moral order without self-alienation as
long as there is a personal appropriation of that order; that a proper objec-
tivity can be discovered only through a creative subjective commitment;
that personal freedom requires a recognition and acceptance of the cir-
cumstances that condition one; that one’s identity is both inherited and
chosen, formed and fluid, open to fulfillment and haunted by the threat of
disintegration.
The main aim of this study has been to show that despite their signif-
icant differences there are profound similarities in the way Aquinas and
Sartre understand the questions of human freedom, personal identity, and
the possibility of perfect happiness in this life—similarities that are unac-
knowledged or assumed to be nonexistent by most scholars. I hope I have
achieved this aim to some degree, and established that there is a common
approach to the way in which these questions are framed and answered.
A secondary aim of this study, often more implicit than explicit, has been
to show that there is much value in this common Thomistic-Sartrean ap-
proach, and that it sheds a great deal of light on some of the philosophical
issues facing us today.
For just a moment I want to set aside their differences, and present
a view of what it means to be a human being as if it came from a single
Thomistic-Sartrean pen, a view that has emerged from the four parts of
this study. This will act both as a conclusion to my study and as an invita-
tion to consider the implications of this vision of the human being.
In part one, it became clear that human beings both have an iden-
tity and go beyond it. We identify with our thoughts and feelings and val-
ues, with our circumstances, with the totality of our experience. There is
an immediacy about our presence to the world. We share in the being of
other things. Yet at the same time we are conscious of this experience and
are therefore distant from it. We are aware of our own incompletion. We
have questions, dilemmas, and moments of existential and moral anguish.
Nothing can completely determine for us the meaning of the world or the
direction of our life.
There is a fundamental lack within the present that paralyzes our
thought and action. We have to go beyond all that we are and conceive
of a future that will make sense of the present. We have to act for an end
278 = c o n c l u s i o n
that does not yet exist and orientate ourselves to this goal. In this way we
make sense of the world and give meaning to our life. The human person
is neither the present static identity nor the intangible future goal. We are
constituted, rather, by this freely chosen relationship between identity and
end. Personhood, therefore, necessarily involves both the facts that deter-
mine us and the movement beyond these facts to the one we seek to be-
come. It involves essence and existence, self-possession and dispossession,
introspection and ecstasy, present and future, the real and the ideal, the
indicative and the conditional. It involves what is true and what could be
good. We constitute ourselves by accepting who we are and moving be-
yond this.
In part two, it was shown that there is an objective and a subjective as-
pect to all human understanding. In one sense, our understanding is deter-
mined by the being of whatever object is understood. We need to be trans-
parent and responsive to the reality of the world. Everything we encounter
has an independence, a weight, and we cannot manipulate the facts of our
experience. If we make unrealistic plans or propose false interpretations of
the world, we are checked and even constrained by the resistance things
show.
In another sense, however, our understanding depends completely on
our personal involvement in the world. We can’t understand anything un-
less we take an active interest in it. Everything is seen from a certain per-
spective and understood in terms of the language and categories of the
one who understands. These categories are inseparable from the values of
those who use them, since all understanding embodies the lived priorities
of the individuals and groups who choose to understand. These categories
also make possible certain kinds of desires, since we can only desire what
we understand to be worthwhile. So desire, understanding, and purpose-
ful activity interconnect and unavoidably influence each other. Neverthe-
less, the element of circularity diminishes neither the objectivity of truth
nor the personal nature of desire. The truth is human, and objectivity is
always grasped through the subject. Knowledge is impossible without hu-
man commitment, and this commitment is impossible without an under-
standing of what we are like and what the world is like.
In part three, it was concluded that at any one moment, if we take into
account all the relevant facts at our disposal, there are always different ways
of looking at any situation, different reasons for acting, different goals we
c o n c l u s i o n = 279
can pursue. Any of them would make sense of the objective understanding
we have of the world. We are free to act because we are free to think about
things in different ways. Uncertainty is the starting point of deliberation,
choice, and responsibility. We have to choose from the different possible
goods before us and project ourselves into a single future. In this way we
choose which person we will become. From the plethora of potentially sig-
nificant motives, we make some motives real by acting for them. Within
the constraints of our circumstances, we choose to live in one way rather
than another.
Freedom thus depends on two things: on accepting the limits of one’s
situation, and on reinterpreting these limits in the light of a particular fu-
ture. We have to accept our beginning and choose our end. Our actions are
not determined by our being, since our being is open-ended and ambigu-
ous. Our being, rather, is determined by our activity, as we project our-
selves toward a future self that does not yet exist. We decide the mean-
ing of our life and the priorities that will give it shape. For these reasons,
the person we are aiming to become is more significant than the person
we are. We constitute ourselves through our free choices, even though this
very freedom is something we have not chosen and something we cannot
disown.
In part four, it was shown that within each particular desire there is
a deeper and more universal longing for completion and perfect fulfill-
ment. Human beings do not just want to travel, we also want to arrive. We
are frustrated that our understanding is limited, our possessions insuffi-
cient, and our identity insecure. In other words, we want to be happy. So
we chase after an ideal moment in the future when desire as such will be
fulfilled and when we will finally become the person we wish to be. This
moment never comes because desire is infinite and self-coincidence im-
possible. Even though we create an identity through our free choices, and
may find a certain stability and satisfaction in recommitting ourselves to
that identity, we still have a distance from ourselves. We always see a future
opening up before us. We have some transitory experiences of happiness,
but perfect happiness eludes us and is in principle impossible to achieve in
the life that we know.
So for both Aquinas and Sartre, we are fragmented persons, internally
displaced, perpetually in exile from ourselves. This prospect both liberates
and terrifies us. We can try to escape the dilemma by pretending that we
280 = c o n c l u s i o n
Works by Sartre
Sartre, Jean-Paul. The Age of Reason (London: Penguin Books, 2001).
———. Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontol-
ogy, translated by Hazel Barnes (London: Routledge, 1958).
———. Cahiers pour une Morale (Paris: Gallimard, 1983).
———. “Cartesian Freedom.” In Literary and Philosophical Essays
(New York: Collier Books, 1962).
———. Critique de la Raison Dialectique, Vol. 1: Théorie des ensembles
pratiques, Bibliothèque des Idées (Paris: Gallimard, 1960).
———. L’être et le néant: Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique (Paris:
Gallimard, 1943).
———. L’être et le néant: Essai d’ontologie phénoménologique, édition
corrigée avec index par Arlette Elkaïm-Sartre (Paris: Gallimard,
1996).
———. “Existentialism and Humanism.” In Jean-Paul Sartre: Basic
Writings, ed. Stephen Priest (London: Routledge, 2001).
———. L’Existentialisme Est un Humanisme (Paris: Gallimard, 1996).
———. Huis Clos (London: Routledge, 1987).
———. Huis Clos and Other Plays (London: Penguin Books, 2000).
———. L’Imaginaire (Paris: Gallimard, 1986).
———. “The Itinerary of a Thought.” In Between Existentialism and
Marxism (New York: Pantheon Books, 1974).
———. Lettres au Castor, vol. 1 (Paris: Gallimard, 1983).
———. “Materialism and Revolution.” In Literary and Philosophical
Essays (New York: Collier, 1962).
———. Notebooks for an Ethics, trans. David Pellauer (Chicago and
London: University of Chicago Press, 1992).
———. The Psychology of the Imagination (London: Routledge, 1972).
———. Situations I (Paris: Gallimard, 1947).
———. Situations III (Paris: Gallimard, 1949).
———. Situations IV (Paris: Gallimard, 1964).
———. Situations IX (Paris: Gallimard, 1972).
———. La transcendance de l’ego: Esquisse d’une description phénomé-
nologique (Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin, 1972).
———. The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Con-
281
282 = b i b l i o g r a p h y
sciousness, trans. Forrest Williams and Robert Kirkpatrick (New York: Hill &
Wang, 1957).
———. The Words, trans. Bernard Frechtman (New York: Braziller, 1964).
Works by Aquinas
Aquinas, Thomas. Commentum in quatuor libros Sententiarum Magistri Petri Lom-
bardi, in Sancti Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris angelici ordinis predicatorum Opera
omnia ad fidem optimarum editionum accurate recognita, vols. 6–7 (Parma: ty-
pis Petri Fiaccadori, 1856–1858).
———. De potentia. In Quaestiones disputatae, vol. 2, ed. P. Pession (Turin/Rome:
Marietti, 1953).
———. “De Unitate Intellectus Contra Averroistas.” In Sancti Thomae De Aquino
Opera Omnia. Iussu Impensaqu Leonis XIII P. M. Edita, vol. 43 (Rome: Editori
di San Tommaso, 1976).
———. The Disputed Questions on Truth, trans. Robert W. Mulligan, James V. Mc-
Glynn, and Robert W. Schmidt, 3 vols. (Chicago: Henry Regnery Company, 1952).
———. On Evil, trans. Jean Oesterle (South Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame
Press, 1995).
———. On Evil, trans. Richard Regan, ed. Brian Davies (New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 2003).
———. On Human Nature (Indianapolis, Ind./Cambridge: Hackett, 1999).
———. On the Unity of the Intellect against the Averroists, trans. Beatrice H. Zedler
(Milwaukee, Wis.: Marquette University Press, 1968).
———. Sancti Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici Opera Omnia. (Rome: 1882– ).
[“Leonine” edition].
———. Selected Philosophical Writings, trans. Timothy McDermott (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1993).
———. Summa Theologiae, ed. Thomas Gilby, 60 vols. (London: Blackfriars/Eyre
& Spottiswoode, 1963ff).
———. Summa Theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province,
5 vols. (Westminster, Md.: Christian Classics, 1948).
———. Summa Theologiae: A Concise Translation, ed. Timothy McDermott (Lon-
don: Methuen, 1989).
Other Works
Ackrill, J. L., ed. A New Aristotle Reader (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987).
Anscombe, G. E. M. Intention. 2nd ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 2000).
290 = b i b l i o g r a p h y
Aristotle. De Motu Animalium, trans. Martha Craven Nussbaum (Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press, 1978).
———. The Metaphysics: Books I–IX, ed. G. P. Goold, trans. Hugh Tredennick, The
Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1933).
———. Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1985).
Balthasar, Hans Urs von. “On the Tasks of Catholic Philosophy in Our Time.” Com-
munio 20 (1993).
Bauman, Zygmunt. Intimations of Postmodernity (London: Routledge, 1992).
Bell, David. Husserl (London and New York: Routledge, 1990).
Bourke, Vernon J., Will in Western Thought: An Historico-Critical Study (New York:
Sheed & Ward, 1964).
Boyle, Joseph M., Germain Grisez, and Olaf Tollefsen. Free Choice: A Self-Referen-
tial Argument (South Bend, Ind., and London: University of Notre Dame Press,
1976).
Caputo, John D. “The End of Ethics.” In The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, ed.
Hugh LaFollette (Malden, Mass., and Oxford: Blackwell, 2000).
Crisp, Roger, and Michael Slote, eds. Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1997).
De Lubac, Henri. Surnaturel: Études Historiques (Paris: Aubier, 1946).
Donagan, Alan. Choice: The Essential Element in Human Action (London: Rout-
ledge & Kegan Paul, 1987).
Finnis, John. Fundamentals of Ethics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).
———. Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980).
Gaita, Raimond. A Common Humanity: Thinking about Love and Truth and Justice.
2nd ed. (London and New York: Routledge, 2002).
Harris, André, and Marcel Ophüls. Le Chagrin et la Pitié [Documentary film], di-
rected by Marcel Ophüls (1969).
Harvey, David. The Condition of Postmodernity (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989).
Heidegger, Martin. Basic Writings (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1993).
———. Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Oxford:
Blackwell, 1962).
Husserl, Edmund. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology, trans.
Dorion Cairns (The Hague, The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1960).
———. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Phi-
losophy. Book 1: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology, trans. F. Kersten
(The Hague, The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1982).
Kahn, Charles H. “Discovering the Will: From Aristotle to Augustine.” In The Ques-
tion of “Eclecticism”: Studies in Later Greek Philosophy, ed. John M. Dillon and
A. A. Long (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1988).
Kerr, Fergus. Immortal Longings (London: SPCK, 1997).
Köhler, Wolfgang. Gestalt Psychology: An Introduction to New Concepts in Modern
Psychology (New York: Liveright, 1947).
Kotva, Joseph J. The Case for Christian Virtue Ethics (Washington, D.C.: George-
town University Press, 1996).
Lacan, Jacques. Écrits: A Selection, trans. Alan Sheridan (London: Tavistock, 1977).
b i b l i o g r a p h y = 291
Lear, Jonathan. Happiness, Death, and the Remainder of Life (Cambridge, Mass., and
London: Harvard University Press, 2000).
Levinas, Emmanuel. “Martin Buber and the Theory of Knowledge.” In The Levinas
Reader, ed. Seán Hand (Oxford and Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell, 1989).
Lottin, Odon. “Libre arbitre et liberté depuis saint Anselme jusqu’à la fin du XIIIe
siècle.” In Psychologie et morale aux XIIe et XIIIe siècles, Vol. 1, 2nd ed. (Gem-
bloux, France: J. Duculot, 1957).
MacDonald, Paul S., ed. The Existentialist Reader: An Anthology of Key Texts (Edin-
burgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2000).
MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue. 2nd ed. (London: Duckworth, 1985).
McCabe, Herbert. Law, Love and Language (London and Sydney, Australia: Sheed
& Ward, 1968).
McDowell, J. “Virtue and Reason.” The Monist 62 (1976).
McInerney, Ralph. The Very Rich Hours of Jacques Maritain: A Spiritual Life (South
Bend, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2003).
Merleau-Ponty, M. Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1962).
Midgley, Mary. Beast and Man: The Roots of Human Nature (London: Methuen,
1979).
———. “The Objection to Systematic Humbug.” Philosophy 53 (1978).
Mihalich, Joseph C. Existentialism and Thomism (New York: Philosophical Library,
1960).
Murdoch, Iris. The Sovereignty of Good (London: Routledge, 2001).
Norris, Christopher. The Truth about Postmodernism (Oxford and Cambridge,
Mass.: Blackwell, 1993).
Popper, Karl R. “Epistemology without a Knowing Subject.” In Objective Knowledge,
an Evolutionary Approach (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979).
Simon, Yves R. Freedom of Choice (New York: Fordham University Press, 1969).
Sokolowski, Robert. The Formation of Husserl’s Concept of Constitution (The Hague,
The Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1964).
Stoker, Michael. “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories.” In Virtue Ethics,
ed. Roger Crisp and Michael Slote (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
Taylor, Charles. The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 1991).
———. “Explanation and Practical Reason.” In Philosophical Arguments (Cam-
bridge, Mass., and London: Harvard University Press, 1995).
———. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1989).
Wippel, John F. “The Condemnations of 1270 and 1277 at Paris.” Journal of Medieval
and Renaissance Studies 7 (1977).
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Notebooks, 1914–1916, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe, 2nd ed.
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1979).
Wolf, Susan, “Moral Saints.” In Virtue Ethics, ed. Roger Crisp and Michael Slote
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).
index
293
294 = i n d e x
Busch, Thomas, 17–18, 34, 36, 112 De principiis naturae (Aquinas), 7
Buzz Lightyear, 275 Derrida, Jacques, 42
Descartes, René: influence on Sartre, 14,
Camus, Albert, 168 45n96
cause, in Sartre, 31, 45–46 desire, 75, 249, 259–60; and instrumental-
Caws, Peter, 17, 42 ity, 98–102
Chagrin et la Pitié, Le, 189 determinism: and compatibilism, 147–48;
character, 237; effect on will, 220 in early Aquinas, 119; indeterminism
Chartier, Emile August (Alain), 13 in Sartre, 160–62; and intellectualism,
choice: in Aquinas, 131, 205–9; examples 142–43; rupture of, 26–31, 32; weaknesses
of, 84–90; and freedom, 143–44; non- in, 156–57
necessity of, 211–25; rationality of Detmer, David, 189–90
choice, 168–74; in Sartre, 163–68 De trinitate (Boethius), 7
Christ, 5-6; in Sartre, 251 De unitate intellectus (Aquinas), 3–4
Cicero: in Aquinas, 6 De veritate (Aquinas): historical back-
circuit de l’ipséité, le, 54–57 ground, 4
cliff walker, 26–28, 52 Dieu. See God
coefficient of adversity, 107–9, 187 Dilman, Ilham, 57
cogito, 14, 39 Dionysius, Pseudo-, 79
commitment: as ethical ideal, 249n32 Dominicans: Aquinas and, 5; on freedom,
communism: and Sartre, 179 2; Le Saulchoir, 9
compatibilism, 147, 230–33 Dostoyevsky, Fyodor, 179
conscience, la. See consciousness doubt, 46
conscience (de) soi. See self-consciousness dualism, 39, 41
consciousness: emptiness/transparency of,
35, 108–9; positional, 33–34; in Sartre, Eardley, P. S., 229–30
32–37, 52, 103; transcendence of, 34. See École Normale Supérieure, 11, 13
also self-consciousness Edie, James, 18
concupiscible appetite, 81 Ego: in Sartre, 17, 25, 55; transcendent, 36;
consilium. See deliberation transcendental, 36–37, 73
Constantine, 50, 157–58 electio. See choice
contemplation, 263 emotions, as intentional, 162
contingency: of being, 25, 196–98; of the ends: in Aquinas, 192–95; as chosen,
human perspective, 104–5 74n44, 159–62; indetermination of,
conversion: in Sartre, 175–80, 254, 269n46 201–5; possessed in intention or reality,
cosmology, medieval, 197 258–59
creation, 58 enjoyment, 256
culture, 25, 185; and language, 111 Ens causa sui, 251
l’en-soi-pour-soi. See in-itself-for-itself
Dasein 14, 112 epoche, 112
Davison, Ray, 191 equipment, 99n17
De anima (Aristotle), 66, 69 Eschmann, Ignatius, 5–6
death: in Aquinas 262; in Sartre, 247–48 “esse est percipi” (Berkeley), 34
De consolatione (Boethius), 6 essence: in Sartre, 25–26, 29–31, 57; as fol-
De divinis nominibus (Pseudo-Dionysius), 7 lowing existence, 167–68
De ente et essentia (Aquinas), 7 essentialism: in Sartre, 26
Degrees of Knowledge, The (Maritain), 12 ethics: existential, 252n44: in Sartre, 170,
De hebdomadibus (Boethius), 7 249n32; utilitarian, 276
deliberation: and choice, 207–8 L’Étranger (Camus), 168
delight, 256 être-dans-le-monde. See being-in-the-world
De malo (Aquinas): dating, 119; historical l’être-en-soi. See being-in-itself
background, 4 L’être et le néant (Sartre). See Being and No-
dépasser. See surpass thingness
i n d e x = 295
l’être-pour-soi. See being-for-itself good, the: in Aquinas, 74–79; indetermi-
eudaimonia. See happiness nation of particular goods, 196–201;
Eudemian Ethics (Aristotle), 135, 230 perfect, 141–44; as perfection of be-
exercise of act of will, 124–28, 135–39, 218 ing, 76–79; as possessed, 256–57; ratio
exist: as transitive verb, 110 of, 122–23; as something desired, 74–76;
existence: preceding essence, 167–68 viewed as not-good, 139–44, 146–47, 211,
Existentialism and Humanism (L’Existenti- 218–19
alisme est un Humanisme; Sartre), 14–15, grace: in Sartre, 180
163–65 Gregory the Great: in Aquinas, 6
exitus-reditus, 7
experience, 34, 38, 94–95 Haldane, John, 65
happiness: in Aquinas, 256–73; as attracting
facticity (la facticité), 24–25, 31, 110–11, 157, the will, 123; disagreement about where
180–86; in Aquinas, 196–98 found, 202–4, 258; final end, 136–37, 193;
failure: in Sartre, 253–55 as goal of life, 279–80; history of ques-
family, xv tion, 2; impossibility of perfect happiness
fear: as motive, 85–86 in this life, 259–64; perfect and imper-
Fell, Joseph, 114 fect, 2, 7–8, 258; perfect good, 141; per-
Finnis, John, 209, 224 fect happiness in God, 264–67, 270–73;
Flannery, Kevin, 119, 209 in Sartre, 243–55
Flaubert, Gustave, 19, 157 Hartmann, Klaus, 113–14
flesh: and interworld, 108–10 Hause, Jeffrey, 227–29
Flynn, Thomas, 164 Hayman, Ronald, 14
form (forma), 60–62, 70; as universal, heaven, 3
215–17 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 43; influ-
Franciscans: on freedom, 2 ence on Sartre, 14
freedom: in Aquinas, 192–239, 278–79; and Heidegger, Martin: influence on Sartre, 13,
choice, 205–09; as choice about identity, 14–15, 40–41, 112; thought, 107
84–90; condemned to, 31, 182; contin- Heisenberg, Werner, 104
gency of, 182; for excellence, 169; history Hemingway, Ernest, 168
of question, 1–3; of indifference, 169; higher order volitions, 231
limits of, 180–86; not determined by hikers, 172
sensitive appetite, 82–84; persistence hope: in Sartre, 253–55
of existential, 186–91; in Sartre, 155–91, Howells, Christina, 18–19
278–79; Huis Clos (Sartre). See In Camera
free will. See freedom human reality: as substitute for Dasein, 112
Freud, Sigmund: influence on Sartre, 18, 185 Husserl, Edmund: influence on Sartre, 13,
15–16, 33, 35–37; the natural attitude,
Gallagher, David, 120, 128, 204, 212, 229, 238 98n17, 111; reception in France, 11–12
gambler, 27–28, 52, 85–86, 175–77
Garcin (In Camera), 248 Ibn Rushd. See Averroes
Gauthier, R.-A., 5, 119 Ibn Sina. See Avicenna
gestaltism, 96–98 ideal, the, 245–47
Gide, André, 55n132, 179 idealism, 39; Sartre accused of, 113–16; Sar-
Giles of Rome, 229 tre’s critique of, 96–98
Gilson, Étienne, 9, 10, 58 Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology
God: as external principle of will, 230, and to a Phenomenological Philosophy
235–26; as final end, 199–200, 266; as (Ideen; Husserl), 15, 18
highest intellectual principle in Aquinas, identity: in Aquinas, 59–60, 224, 237–39,
134–35; natural desire for, 8n25, 270–73; 277–78; as denied, 40–43; as given,
not a source of ends in Sartre, 161; in 24–26; objectification, 248–49; as open
Sartre, 250–53, 255, 267–70; as universal 69–74; result of choice, 87–89; in Sartre,
good, 266–67 23–57, 277–78
296 = i n d e x
Idiot of the family, The (Sartre), 19 Lacan, Jacques: influence on Sartre, 18,
image: in Sartre, 46 41n79, 185
L’Imaginaire. See Psychology of the Imagi- lack, 48–53, 157
nation language: and freedom 111; in Sartre, 25
imagination: in Sartre, 43–46 Leo XIII, 9
immanence, 47 Le Saulchoir, 9
In Camera (Sartre), 248 Letter on Humanism (Heidegger), 14
Index: of prohibited books, 11 Lévinas, Emmanuel, 15
Inès (In Camera), 248 liberum arbitrium, 1–2, 195–96. See also
in-itself-for-itself, 243–47, 267–70 freedom
instinct: animal and human 81–82; in Aqui- Lisska, Anthony, 86
nas, 196–97; in Sartre, 32 look, the, 248–49
instrumentality: in Sartre, 98–102 Lottin, Odon, 119
intellect: activated by will, 135–39; in Aqui- Louvain: Higher Institute of Philosophy, 9
nas, 63–74; immateriality of, 67–69; in- love, xv; in Sartre, 249
terdependence with will, 121–24; know- Lubac, Henri de, 10
ing itself, 72–74; meaning of, 194–95;
priority of, 132–35; reflexivity, 128–35; le manqué. See lack
taking form of other things, 64–67, Marcuse, Herbert: criticisms of Sartre, 16,
69–74, 79–80 unity of, 3–4 187
intellectualism, xi–xii, 142–43, 224–25 Maréchal, Joseph, 9
intellectualist interpretations of Aquinas, Maritain, Jacques, ix–x, 9, 12, 204
226–33 Marx, Karl: influence on Sartre, 18, 185
intellectus. See intellect Marxism: Sartre against, 189
intellectus possibilis, 66 materia. See matter
intentionality: in Bachelard, 107; in Sartre, matter, 60–62
32–37, 43 Matthieu (L’Age de Raison), 28
intentional structure of human act, 155–58, la mauvaise foi. See bad faith
161 McCabe, Herbert, 68
interworld, 16, 108–10 McCulloch, Gregory, 186
l’ipséité, 53–57 McDermott, Timothy, 65–66
irascible appetite, 81 Me, the, 30, 37, 39, 55, 57
Isidore of Seville: in Aquinas, 6 meaning: in Sartre, 48
measurement: and human values, 104
James, William, 34 memory: as interpretation, 177–78
Jaspers, Karl: influence on Sartre, 13 Mercier, Désiré, 9
Jeanson, Francis, 35, 39 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice: criticisms of Sar-
Jerome: in Aquinas, 6 tre, 16, 108–11
Jesuits: interpretations of Aquinas, 9 metaphysics, 94, 114, 251
John Damascene: in Aquinas, 6 mind-world identity theory (Haldane), 65
John of La Rochelle, 2 le moi. See Me
Jopling, David, 163 moi-profond, 167
judgment: in choice, 207 monism, 39
Moore, G. E., 51n118
Kenny, Anthony, 8 moral sources, 276–77
Kerr, Fergus, 9–10 Morris, Phyllis Sutton, 171, 176, 178, 186
Kierkegaard, Søren: influence on Sartre, motivation. See motive
13; teleological suspension of ethical, motive (motif), 28, 31, 155–59, 162–63,
170 171–74; incommensurability of motives,
knowledge: in Aquinas, 63–74, 117–151; in 163–65
Sartre, 104–5, 111–16
Köhler, Wolfgang, 13, 96–97 Naples, University of, 7
le Néant. See nothingness
i n d e x = 297
negation: and constitution of end, 157–59; Psychology of the Imagination, The (Sar-
in Sartre, 40, 43–46, 52, 94–95 tre), 47
négatités, 44, 157–58 Ptolemy: in Aquinas, 6
neighbor, 110 purpose: in Sartre, 98–102
Neoplatonism: in Aquinas, 7
Nichomachean Ethics (Aristotle), 6, 7–8, 76 Quaestiones disputatae: historical back-
nothingness, 40 ground, 4
questioning: in Sartre, 45
objectivity and subjectivity: in Aquinas,
117–151; in Sartre, 93–116 Raskolnikov (Dostoyevsky), 179
Odo Regaldus, 2 ratio agendi, 125
Olafson, Frederick, 252–53 rational appetite. See will
ontological proof: of the world, 34 rationality of choice: in Sartre,168–74
ontology, phenomenological, 94 realism, 39; in analytic tradition, 65; in Sar-
oppression: and freedom, 187–89 tre, 96–98, 113–17
other, the, 248–49 réalité-humaine. See human reality
reason: in Aquinas, 82–84; indetermina-
Paris: Faculty of Arts, 3, 7; Faculty of The- tion of, 208, 209–17; will’s influence over,
ology, 3, 9 217–26
Pasnau, Robert, 230–33 reflexivity of intellect and will, 128–35, 148
perception: in Sartre, 96–98 le regard. See look
perfection: in Aquinas, 74–79 relationships: in Sartre, 248–49
personhood: in Aquinas, 70n37, 71, 89–90, resistance of the world, 180–82; and objec-
200, 237–39; in Sartre, 17, 35, 53–57, tivity, 107–11
165–68, 249 rest: in possession of the good, 256–57
perspectivism: in Sartre, 103–6 Rhetoric (Aristotle), 5
Peter Lombard. See Sentences riches, and happiness, 203, 260–61
phenomenology: Husserlian, 33; reception Robert Kilwardby, 9
in France, 11–12 Roman law: in Aquinas, 6
Philip the Chancellor, 2 Rome, 50
Philoktetes (Gide), 179 Rousselot, Pierre, 9
Pinckaers, Servais-Théodore, 6, 169–70
place, the human, 101–2 sadism, 249
plants: movement, 58–59 salvation: in Sartre, 254
play, 254 Sartre, Jean-Paul: faith, 11; influences on,
pleasure: and happiness, 203; possession of 13–16; interpretation of, 16–19; later
good, 256 work, 19, 185n106; life, 10–12, 110n66
politics, xv, 25 Scheler, Max: influence on Sartre 13; and
Popper, Karl, 149 objectivity, 107
possibility: in Sartre, 48–53 Scholasticism, nineteenth-century, xiii
postmodernism, 275 science, and human purposes, 102–4
potentia aestimativa, 80 Sein und Zeit (Heidegger). See Being and
preference: in Aquinas, 205–09 Time
presence to self (la présence à soi): in Aqui- Selbstheit, 55n133
nas, 72–74; in Sartre, 39, 42, 166–67 self: in Aquinas, 66, 237–39; deep, 167; in
pride, 248 Sartre, 38, 41–42, 53–57, 163–68; and sin-
prison: and freedom, 187–191 cerity; in Wittgenstein, 36n49
prochain, mon. See neighbour self-coincidence, 41, 245–47
project, the, 162, 168–74; collapse of, 179 self-consciousness: in Aquinas, 72–74,
Pseudo-Dionysius: influence on Aquinas, 128–32; in Sartre, 37–43, 171, 245–47
6, 7 self-deception. See bad faith
psychoanalysis, existential: 186, 254 self-movement, 82–83; of will, 130–31,
psychological determinism: 157 233–39
298 = i n d e x
selfness, 53–57 Time and Freewill (Bergson), 13
sensitive appetite, 80–81, 83, 88, 122, 196–98, Torrell, Jean-Pierre, 5
200–201 Toy Story, 275
sensitive apprehension: in Aquinas, 63–64; Transcendence of the Ego, The (La Trans-
in Sartre, 99–101 cendance de l’ego, Sartre), 17, 18, 35–37,
Sentences (Peter Lombard), 5, 7 38, 54–55
seriousness (sérieux), 53, 186, 254 transcendent object, 33
shame, 248 truth: as object of intellect and will, 128;
sheep: as lacking freedom, 85–86 objectivity of, 150–51; in Sartre, 114–16,
Siger of Brabant, 3 183n99; and subjectivity, 118
sin, 269n46
sincerity (la sincérité), 29–30, 86, 180, 186 understanding, 278; in Aquinas, 63–74,
situation, the, 184 75, 117–52; exercise of, 137–38; in Sartre,
Société Thomiste, 12 93–116
le soi. See self universals, 215–17
Sokolowski, Robert, 112 l’ustensilité. See instrumentality
soul, 62–63, 65, 69–72, 120; powers of,
127–28, 130; subsistence of, 62 values: as ideals, 246, 267; and instrumen-
specification of human act, 124–28, 212 tality, 98–102; and motives, 156–57; in
Spiegelberg, Herbert, 17, 37 Sartre, 48–53
Stalag XII D, 11 vécu, 19, 185
structuralism, 25; Sartre’s opposition to, 111, Venus de Milo, 50
184–85 Verstraeten, Pierre, 191
Stump, Eleonore, 133 vertigo, 24–32
subject, 34, 42; non-substantial, 34–35 Vichy regime, 191
subjectivity, 34; in Aquinas, 117–51; and ob- voluntarism, xi–xii, 142–43, 224–25; in later
jectivity, 93–116 Aquinas, 119; not in Sartre, 168–74
suffering, existential, 252; as motive, 158; in voluntas. See will
Sartre, 50–52
Summa theologiae: historical background waiter, café, 29, 31
and structure, 5–6 Warnock, Mary, 44
surpass, 43 Westberg, Daniel, 119
Suttor, Timothy, 68 will: activating intellect, 135–39; in Aqui-
nas, 79–84; indetermination of particu-
Taylor, Charles, 224–25, 275–77 lar goods, 198–99; influence over reason,
technique: as human activity, 107; language 217–26; interdependence with intellect,
as, 111 121–24; meaning of, 194–95; non-
Tempier, Stephen, 3 necessity of movement, 139–142; reflexiv-
temporality: in Aquinas, 215–17, 260, 263; in ity, 128–35; role in specifying good, 139–
Sartre, 158, 175–80, 246–47 144; self-movement, 233–39
theology: in Sartre, 250–253 William of Auxerre, 2, 3
La Théorie de l’intuition dans la phénomé- William of Ockham, 169
nologie de Husserl (Levinas), 15 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 36n49
Thomism: existential, 9; nineteenth- and wonder, 260
twentieth-century, 9; and phenomenol- world: in Aquinas, 148–51; and objectivity,
ogy, 12; transcendental, 9 107–111; in Sartre, 33, 93–96
Aquinas & Sartre on Freedom, Personal Identity, and the Possibility of
Happiness was designed and typeset in Minion by Kachergis Book Design
of Pittsboro, North Carolina. It was printed on 60-pound House Natural
Smooth and bound by Sheridan Books of Ann Arbor, Michigan.