Heidegger S Social Ontology
Heidegger S Social Ontology
NICOLAI K. KNUDSEN
Aarhus University
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge , United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, th Floor, New York, , USA
Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, , Australia
–, rd Floor, Plot , Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre, New Delhi – , India
Penang Road, #–/, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/
: ./
© Nicolai K. Knudsen
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions
of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take
place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.
First published
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
: Knudsen, Nicolai, - author.
: Heidegger’s social ontology : the phenomenology of self, world and others / Nicolai Knudsen.
: Cambridge ; New York, NY : Cambridge University Press, . | Includes biblio-
graphical references and index.
: (print) | (ebook) |
(hardback) | (paperback) | (epub)
: : Heidegger, Martin, -. | Interpersonal relations–Philosophy. | Ontology. |
Social systems. | Philosophy, German–th century.
: . (print) | . (ebook) | –dc/
eng/
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/
LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/
---- Hardback
Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence
or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this
publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will
remain, accurate or appropriate.
My suggestion is merely that the problem of the relationship of
human being to human being does not concern a question of
epistemology or the question of how one human being
comprehends another. It concerns rather a problem of being itself,
that is, a problem of metaphysics.
Heidegger, Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics
Heaven and earth and gods and men are held together by
communion and friendship, by orderliness, temperance, and
justice; and that is the reason, my friend, why they call the whole
of this world by the name of order, not of disorder
or dissoluteness.
Plato, Gorgias
Contents
Acknowledgements page xi
List of Abbreviations of Works by Heidegger xiii
Introduction
ix
x Contents
Shared Action
. An Outline of Shared Action
. Pre-Reflective and Reflective Action
. Joint Goals and Joint Commitments
. A Taxonomy of Individual and Shared Actions
. Discourse
. Variations of the We
Conclusion
Bibliography
Index
Acknowledgements
Many people have been helpful to me in the process of writing this book.
I am particularly thankful to Thomas Schwarz Wentzer for his guidance
and mentorship over the years. I would also like to thank Mark Wrathall
for his support and for our walks in the meadow. I am generally grateful to
the friends and colleagues with whom I have discussed ideas and material
related to the book. These include Lars Albinus, Anders Moe Rasmussen,
Katherine Withy, Hans Ruin, Dan Zahavi, Rasmus Dyring, and several
generations of the research group on philosophical hermeneutics at Aarhus
University. I am also in debt to audiences, both real and virtual, in Aarhus,
Ljubljana, Ontario, Oxford, Roskilde, San Diego, and Staffordshire for
discussing Heidegger’s social ontology with me.
My work has been facilitated by generous funding from the Carlsberg
Foundation, by a Junior Research Fellowship at Oxford’s Linacre College,
and, prior to that, by a research stipend at Aarhus University. At
Cambridge University Press, I thank my editor, Hilary Gaskin, for making
what I imagined would be a gruelling process (more or less) enjoyable, as
well as the anonymous peer reviewers, whose comments have improved
the book considerably.
Finally, I would like to acknowledge with gratitude the support (espe-
cially all the help with the kids!) and love of my family – my mom and her
partner, Annette and Gert; my wife’s parents, Søren and Birgitte; and my
brothers, Steffen and Joachim. I owe, however, the greatest gratitude to my
wife, Anne Sofie, for being my best friend and for loving me even when
I am stressed out about work and parenting, and to my sons, Bille and
Aske, for helping me find the balance between work and play. I dedicate
this book to the three of you.
xi
xii Acknowledgements
Section . provides a heavily condensed version of an argument that
first appeared as ‘Heidegger and the Genesis of Social Ontology: Mitwelt,
Mitsein, and the Problem of Other People’ in European Journal of
Philosophy : (), pp. –, published by Wiley.
A shortened and adjusted version of Chapter appears as ‘Shared
Action: An Existential Phenomenological Account’ in Phenomenology and
the Cognitive Sciences (), advance online publication. published
by Springer.
Abbreviations of Works by Heidegger
xiii
xiv List of Abbreviations
GA Grundbegriffe der aristotelischen Philosophie. . Frankfurt
am Main: Klostermann. Translated as Basic Concepts of
Aristotelian Philosophy by R. D. Metcalf and M. B.
Tanzer. . Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs. . Frankfurt am
Main: Klostermann. Translated as History of the Concept of
Time: Prolegomena by T. Kisiel. . Bloomington: Indiana
University Press
GA Die Grundbegriffe der Phänomenologie. . Frankfurt am
Main: Klostermann. Translated as The Basic Problems of
Phenomenology by A. Hofstadter. . Bloomington: Indiana
University Press
GA Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Logik im Ausgang von
Leibniz. . Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. Translated
as The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic by M. Helm. .
Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Einleitung in die Philosophie. . Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann
GA/ Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik. Welt – Endlichkeit –
Einsamkeit. . Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Translated as The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics:
World, Finitude, Solitude by W. McNeil and
N. Walker. . Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press
GA/ Sein und Wahrheit. . Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Translated as Being and Truth by G. Fried and R. Polt. .
Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Logik als die Frage nach dem Wesen der Sprache. .
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. Translated as Logic as the
Question Concerning the Essence of Language by W. T. Gregory
and Y. Unna. . Albany, NY: SUNY Press
GAA Logik als die Frage nach dem Wesen der Sprache. .
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann
GA Hölderlins Hymnen ‘Germanien’ und ‘Der Rhein’. .
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann. Translated as Hölderlin’s
Hymns ‘Germania’ and ‘The Rhine’ by W. McNeill and
J. Ireland. . Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Einführung in die Metaphysik. . Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann. Translated as Introduction to Metaphysics by
G. Fried and R. Polt. . New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press
List of Abbreviations xv
GA Hölderlin’s Hymne ‘Andenken’. . Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann
GA Hölderlins Hymne ‘Der Ister’. . Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann. Translated as Hölderlin’s Hymn ‘The Ister’ by
W. McNeill and J. Davis. . Bloomington: Indiana
University Press
GA Parmenides. . Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Translated as Parmenides by A. Schuwer and
R. Rojcewicz. . Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press
GA/ Zur Bestimmung der Philosophie. . Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann. Translated as Towards the Definition of
Philosophy by T. Sadler. . London and New York:
Continuum
GA Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie. . Frankfurt am
Main: Klostermann
GA Phänomenologie des religiösen Lebens. . Frankfurt am
Main: Klostermann. Translated as The Phenomenology of
Religious Life by M. Fritsch and J. A. Gosetti-Ferencei. .
Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Ontologie. Hermeneutik der Faktizität. . Frankfurt am
Main: Klostermann. Translated as Ontology – The
Hermeneutics of Facticity by J. van Buren. . Bloomington:
Indiana University Press
GA Der Begriff der Zeit. . Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Translated as The Concept of Time by I. Farin and
A. Skinner. . New York and London: Continuum
GA Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis). . Frankfurt am
Main: Klostermann. Translated as Contributions to Philosophy
(From Enowning) by P. Emad and K. Maly. .
Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Seminare: Hegel – Schelling. Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann. Partly translated as On Hegel’s Philosophy of
Right: The – Seminar and Interpretive Essays by
A. Mitchell. . New York: Bloomsbury
GA Zollikoner Seminare. . Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Translated as Zollikon Seminars: Protocols – Conversations –
Letters by F. Mayr and R. Askay. . Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press
xvi List of Abbreviations
GA Überlegungen II–VI. . Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Translated as Ponderings II–VI by R. Rojcewicz. .
Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Überlegungen VII–XI. . Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann. Translated as Ponderings VII–XI by
R. Rojcewicz. . Bloomington: Indiana University Press
GA Überlegungen XII–XV. . Frankfurt am Main:
Klostermann. Translated as Ponderings XII–XV by
R. Rojcewicz. . Bloomington: Indiana University Press
NHS Nature, History, State: –. Translated by G. Fried and
R. Polt. . New York: Bloomsbury
SZ Sein und Zeit. . Tübingen: Niemeyer. Translated as
Being and Time by J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. .
Oxford: Blackwell
Introduction
Chapter discusses why Heidegger would be suspicious of the concept of the mind and of the
internalist/externalist-distinction as well as why and in which sense we might nevertheless use these
concepts to understand his position.
Introduction
introspection, this type of self-awareness is not seen as something radically
private, as the mind’s relation to itself. The mind – or Dasein as we should
call it to avoid some unfortunate internalist associations – is defined by its
relation to the world. Dasein is, as Heidegger says, being-in-the-world.
The term Dasein refers to ‘the entities that, in their being, comport
themselves towards their being’ (SZ, /). Heidegger expands upon this
characteristic by noting that Dasein ‘is in each case essentially its own
possibility’ (SZ, /). This means that Dasein always faces a field of
possibilities towards which it can never be totally indifferent. It has to
navigate these possibilities (should I do this or that?) and the way in which
it navigates these possibilities will come to define what or who it is
(am I this or that?). Our conception of who we are is always at stake in
and gives purpose to our way of responding to the possibilities offered to us
by our social and physical environment. As a first approximation, we might
think of Dasein as the entity that purposefully responds to solicitations.
Importantly, solicitations are not independent of worldly affairs, nor are
they, we might conjecture, independent of social affairs. A solicitation
depends, as we will see, on a complex network or whole of relations
between human and nonhuman entities, between ourselves, the environ-
ment, and other people. If this is correct, Heidegger’s externalism does not
simply say that a subject is inconceivable without an object, but states,
more radically, that Dasein is inconceivable without a system of relations
The concept of Dasein is notoriously difficult to pin down, and scholars disagree whether the term
Dasein refers to individual human beings or to some kind of collective. The majority argues that
Dasein is a term for ‘concrete human particulars, that is, individual persons’ (Carman , ) and
that ‘sociality is treated of only as a feature of individual life’ (Schatzki , ). In contrast, John
Haugeland has argued that ‘[D]asein is a way of living that embodies an understanding of being’
(Haugeland , f ). A way of living is, he argues, irreducible to individual human beings,
although it only exists by virtue of the individuals that embody it. For this reason, Haugeland uses
the expression ‘case of dasein’ as a term for individual people (Haugeland , ).
Haugeland’s collectivist interpretation of Dasein is, however, textually implausible. Heidegger
says, for instance, that one must always use a personal pronoun when addressing Dasein (SZ, /,
cf. Carman , ). Pace Haugeland, we do not do this when we talk about a general way of living.
Carman rightly points out that the passage in SZ mentions singular personal pronouns (I and you)
and takes this to support his individualist reading. Yet, Carman does not discuss similar passages
where Heidegger suggests that it is equally appropriate to address Dasein by saying we (e.g., GA,
; GA, /; GA, /, /, /). This hints that we cannot simply identify
Dasein with concrete human individuals. I propose, instead, that Dasein ‘is’ a human particular in
the sense that it depends on ontically identifiable individual human beings, although it is ontologically
distinct from these. This is so because the term Dasein does not refer to individual minded bodies as
such but to the disclosedness or the open realm of manifestation that lets entities show up as entities
(which is, however, enabled by the individual minded bodies) (cf. Malpas ; Sheehan ). As
I will argue in the following, this realm of manifestation can not only refer to the I or the ego of the
individual but also the you of someone else and the we of a group.
Introduction
which includes relations to oneself, the environment, and other people.
Heidegger’s externalism becomes, then, a form of holism.
To see the social ontological consequences of these different conceptions
of the mind, let us consider what would happen if we were to place two
Cartesian subjects in a room with each other. They would of course have
observational access to each other’s bodies. But since the Cartesian mind is
defined as that which is revealed only by introspection, each Cartesian
subject would only have access to its own mind. Each would hence need
some kind of substitute – a special, as of yet unaccounted for, mental
operation – to access the other as a mind rather than as a mere body.
We would get a very different picture if we were to substitute two Dasein
for the two Cartesian subjects. Now, Dasein is what it is by virtue of
responding to solicitations in the world. These solicitations can take many
forms. An entity solicits one thing if I take it to be inert, and it solicits quite
another thing if I take it to be responsive to solicitations like me. Moreover,
inert entities solicit very different things from me if I am alone compared to
if I am together with someone else. What is crucial is that, in this picture,
the two Dasein need no substitute, no special mental operation, to make
sense of each other. Dasein is what it is by virtue of its being-in-the-world;
similarly, the other ‘is appresented in his fellow Dasein [Mitdasein] by his
world or by our common environment’ (GA, /). Although the
details are missing (e.g., what exactly does it mean to respond to an entity as
a fellow Dasein rather than something inert?), the general suggestion is clear:
The very same ingredients that explain our basic relation to ourselves can in
principle also explain our basic relation to others. In Heidegger’s words:
It also becomes clear, already from the way in which everyone encounters
himself by way of the world, that the experience of alien ‘psychic life’
[fremden ‘Seelenlebens’] as well as my own does not first need a reflection
on lived experience, taken in the traditional sense, in order to apprehend
my own Dasein. Likewise, I do not understand the other in this artificial
way, such that I would have to feel my way into another subject.
I understand him from the world in which he is with me, a world which
is discovered and understandable through the regard in being-with-one-
another. (GA, /)
On this point, my gloss on the concept of Dasein echoes Joanna Hodge’s characterisation of Dasein
as ‘a form of self-relation which is systematically connected to others of the same kind, others of
different kinds, and to the ground of possibility of there being such differences and otherness at all:
to being’ (Hodge , ).
My interpretation is indebted to Jeff Malpas (, , ) who argues that a distinct form of
holism characterises the hermeneutic tradition. See also Chapter below.
Introduction
The Cartesian tradition construes mindedness on the basis of introspection
(‘the reflection on lived experience’), and this makes other minds an
inherently mysterious phenomenon. By arguing that Dasein constitutively
depends on relations to the environment and to other people, Heidegger
believes that he can provide a much stronger foundation for social ontol-
ogy. The problem with the problem of other minds is, in other words, that
it presupposes a flawed conception of the mind – a conception of the mind
that makes the idea of other minds inherently problematic. In contrast,
Heidegger intends to show that a refined conception of the ‘mind’ ulti-
mately dissolves the problem of ‘other minds’.
Margaret Gilbert’s (, ) plural subject theory claims to differ from Bratman’s account by
being non-reductive. Although she argues that collective intentionality presupposes a plural subject
in which individuals are jointly committed to espouse a goal as a single body, she also admits that a
joint commitment only obtains when two or more individuals express their readiness to undertake a
joint commitment. It seems then that also Gilbert’s plural subject theory relies on ontologically
separate individuals. I discuss Bratman’s and Gilbert’s accounts in detail in Chapter .
Introduction
I discuss some of the differences that separate the analytical and the
phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity in Chapters and , but
here I want to emphasise a point of agreement between these three pro-
posals: they all take the dyadic relation – the thematic or intentional
relation between two subjects – to be foundational for social life.
But does the dyadic relation really establish intersubjectivity? If so, what
makes a self capable of intending another self, what provides the ‘onto-
logical bridge from one’s own subject, which is initially given by itself, to
the other subject, which is initially quite inaccessible’ (SZ, /)? Or is
it rather the case that the dyadic relation uncovers or modifies an explan-
atorily prior form of intersubjectivity? Heidegger defends the latter option
by arguing that the shared world is a presupposition for our intentional
directedness towards others. More specifically, he argues that I can only
make sense of the other as a minded agent if I understand him as
responding to the same world of publicly available things that I respond
to. Rather than conceiving coexistence as a dyad, Heidegger proposes that
there is a fundamental interdependence between self, world, and others so
that each of these three elements is inconceivable without, although
irreducible to, the two others.
Borrowing a term from Donald Davidson, we might say that Heidegger
juxtaposes the dyadic relation prominent in analytical social ontology and
recent phenomenology with a form of triangulation. Dasein understands
itself by virtue of its relation to the world, and since the world is shared,
this includes both environmental objects and other people, e.g., those who
are physically there, those with whom Dasein shares a personal history, and
the anonymous others who are ‘present’ in social norms. Dasein under-
stands others by correlating their behaviour to the environmental objects
and to the interpretative models that it inherits from its history, culture,
and society. Finally, Dasein typically understands environmental objects in
terms of socially inflected standards so that a given tool is understood in
terms of its proper use. Indeed, Heidegger even argues that when such
socially inflected interpretative standards fail, we still understand environ-
mental objects as inherently shared with others:
Every being along something present – also that which is solitary – includes
in itself a being-with-one-another. All uncoveredness of something present
must by its essence be something in which Dasein shares itself with others;
the uncoveredness is therefore such that Dasein never keeps it locked up for
itself as if it were its enclosed possession. All uncoveredness of something
present must essentially already be as shared with. . . (GA, )
Introduction
Rather than confining being-with to our intentional relations to others, the
model of triangulation suggests that all intentional relations take place
against a holistic background of relations between ourselves, the world,
and others. In my opinion, the first task of social ontology is to account for
this a priori interdependence. The second task is to use this ontological
framework to examine the nature of various social phenomena such as
social cognition, shared action, and group formation.
Many interpretations of Heidegger’s politics are directly motivated by his affiliation with Nazism,
for example, de Beistegui (), Derrida (), Duff (), Elden (), Fried (),
Lacoue-Labarthe (), and Young (). On Heidegger’s ethics, see Hatab (), Hodge
(), Lewis (), Nancy (), and Webb ().
Hans Bernhard Schmid (, ) is a notable exception. He argues, on the one hand, that the
conventionalist emphasis of the Anyone is insufficient to account for the constitution of the shared
world and, on the other hand, that our manifold non-thematic relations to each other means that
we cannot rely on an analysis of the dyadic relation alone. Schmid thus takes Heidegger to develop a
notion of ‘common disclosure and common concern’ that must be understood as an irreducible,
relational, and often non-thematic structure (Schmid , ). I am sympathetic to Schmid’s
approach but discuss some limitations and problems in Section . and footnote in
Chapter below.
Introduction
In short, we understand others in terms of the social roles, norms, and
practices that constitute our shared world.
Conversely, those who focus on solicitude agree with Sartre (,
ff ) that if there is nothing more to say about being-with than that
which is contained in the analysis of the Anyone, Dasein is unable to
encounter concrete others (McMullin ; O’Brien ; Olafson ).
As Irene McMullin puts it, the overemphasis on the Anyone suggests that
one can only ever encounter other persons as representative types able to
trigger particular preexisting categories – be they ontic social categories or
the overarching ontological category Mitsein. Individual persons do not play
a role in constituting or developing these categories, but are interchangeable
instances whose uniqueness is subsumed to the category by which one
knows them. (McMullin , )
Her alternative is to develop a more nuanced and distinctly Heideggerian
account of the dyadic relation. In her view, the otherness of the other ‘is
rooted in the finitude and uniqueness of its originary temporality’ in such a
way that the other ‘makes itself known in a past that I can never fully
access and a future that I can never entirely predict’ (McMullin
, ).
Compared to these, my approach is quite untraditional. I believe that
Heidegger’s main contribution to social ontology lies neither in his
remarks on solicitude nor analysis of the Anyone, at least not directly. It
lies, rather, in his analysis of the phenomenon of the world. Seen from this
perspective, the respective analyses of interpersonal understanding and
anonymous social normativity are two (however important) pieces of a
larger social ontological puzzle. The crucial and overarching question is:
What does it mean to share the world?
I answer this question by reconstructing, expanding upon, and at times
criticising the social ontology found in Heidegger’s published text, lecture
courses, and private notes. My main focus will be the period from to
in which Heidegger worked most extensively on the transcendental
issue of the world, although I will on occasion use texts from beyond this
period either as a foil or as a supplement to this line of inquiry.
In contrast to many other interpreters, I argue that Heidegger’s point is
not simply the quasi-Wittgensteinian point that typified social practices
underlie our ways of acting and judging. Rather, I show that the notion of
the shared world extends far beyond the background familiarity afforded to
an individual by its community, society, tradition, or language game.
Rather, its non-thematic and triangular relatedness to others render
Introduction
Dasein constitutively responsive to the behaviour of others – whether or
not they share beliefs, intentions, conventions, or languages. In short,
I share the world with you if and only if we are capable of intending the
same entities or range of entities, and if my way of intending entities is
responsive to your behaviour. Or, less technically, I share the world with
you if your behaviour has a stake, however small, in how I understand the
world that occupies us both.
This is a very minimal type of intersubjectivity. Indeed, as I will argue,
our constitutive openness or responsiveness to others is a transcendental
condition of possibility of Dasein’s intentionality. As such, it characterises
human mindedness and agency whether or not anyone is actually present:
‘Being-with is an existential characteristic of Dasein even when factically
no other is occurrent or perceived. Even Dasein’s being-alone is being-with
in the world’ (SZ, /f ). Being-in-the-shared-world or being-with is a
minimal and necessary form of intersubjectivity. This is not to say, of
course, that nothing more can be said about sociality. Rather, being-with
makes other social phenomena like solicitude and anonymous social
normativity possible. A systematic social ontology must show what unites
these various forms of intersubjectivity and what distinguishes them from
each other.
. Outline
Part I of the book examines the relation between Heidegger’s general
conception of ontology, his philosophy of mind, and his conception of
social life. Chapter outlines and situates Heidegger’s transcendental
phenomenological approach to social ontology in the contemporary land-
scape by discussing what he takes to be the scope and the appropriate
method of social ontology. Chapter compares Heidegger’s transcenden-
tal social ontology to Husserl’s and argues that although both take ‘the
world’ or ‘transcendence’ to constitute the most basic form of intersubjec-
tivity, Heidegger ultimately understands this in affective and practical
rather than theoretical terms. Chapter then argues that Heidegger’s
transcendental social ontology entails a commitment to the holist thesis
that intentional states depend on relations to both environmental objects
and other people and discusses whether this amounts to a
vicious relativism.
Part II analyses a range of concrete social phenomena central to both
classical and contemporary social ontology. Chapter focuses on
Heidegger’s ambiguous and polemical discussion of social cognition.
I first identify six different and seemingly incoherent objections raised by
Heidegger against theories of social cognition, before I set out to recon-
struct a positive, Heideggerian account of interpersonal understanding.
Chapter turns from the you of face-to-face interaction to the we of shared
action. I argue, first, that we should approach shared action in pre-
reflective terms, namely, as responses to environmental solicitations, and,
second, that Heidegger’s reflections on plural selfhood can help us under-
stand pre-reflective shared action by showing how responses to solicitations
can be joint. Chapter considers the large-scale and temporally prolonged
interaction of social normativity. Drawing on Heidegger’s analysis of the
Introduction
Anyone and of historicity, I argue that there are two distinct types of social
normativity: anonymous social normativity, which comes with only a min-
imal awareness of its own nature, extent, and origin, and historical social
normativity, which implies a historical awareness in which social norms are
disclosed as historical and hence as fragile and contestable.
Part III discusses the controversial issues of Heidegger’s politics and his
account of authenticity. Chapter outlines Heidegger’s political philoso-
phy paying special attention to how he conceives of community, state, and
education. I then go on to show that Heidegger in the Black Notebooks
attempts to justify his political engagement philosophically in a way that
rests on assumptions and inferences – philosophical mistakes, if you will –
that contradict his earlier and much more convincing social ontology.
Chapter discusses Heidegger’s notion of authenticity and his conception
of the self. I argue that authenticity requires us to ontically understand our
own nature by adopting a set of ontologically transparent second-order
attitudes on our own lives. I then show how these second-order attitudes
solve two problems inherent to Heidegger’s conception of the self, namely,
that it lacks constancy (in the sense of the capacity of the self to remain
itself through changing situations) and that it lacks autonomy (in the sense
of the capacity to commit to some possibilities rather than others). Finally,
I consider () what the demand for authenticity entails for Heidegger’s
conception of face-to-face relations and his conception of historical com-
munities and () how it differs from moral obligations.
Being-In-the-World and Being-With
Social ontology is often said to study and account for the nature of the
social world. But what exactly is ‘the social world’ and what does it
contain? What does it even mean to ‘give an account’ of it?
Although they are not always discussed explicitly, these questions are
fundamental to social ontology. In this chapter, I will sketch some
common answers to them in order to provide an overview of the field of
social ontology (Section .) before I reconstruct Heidegger’s answers
(Sections .–.).
Psychologism, the ontological claim that the mental world constitutes the social world, is distinct
from what Gilbert calls singuralism, namely, the claim that social entities and events are explainable
only with reference to singular agents pursuing their own individual goals (Gilbert , ). It is
entirely possible to reject singuralism but not psychologism by claiming that individual human
beings have the capacity to act and think from the perspective of a group.
What Is Social Ontology?
world. Let us call this naturalism. There are, of course, many forms of
naturalism. Different theories offer different demarcations of the natural
world, and they also disagree on whether the appeal to the natural world
complements or substitutes the appeal to the mental world. Behaviourism,
for instance, claims that we need not refer to the psychological states of
agents in order to explain social phenomena and takes agents’ behaviour,
which is in principle available to third-personal observation, to explanato-
rily exhaust the social. Others, such as John Searle, are committed to both
psychologism and naturalism. For Searle, social ontology studies the
‘portions of the real world’ that exists only by virtue of ‘human agreement’
(, ) – that is, the psychology of individuals – but he also insists that
social ontology ‘must respect the basic facts of the structure of the universe’
that are recorded by ‘physics and chemistry, by evolutionary biology and
the other natural sciences’ (, ). For him, the central question of social
ontology concerns the relation of dependency between the social world,
the mental world, and the natural world:
How can there be an objective world of money, property, marriage,
governments, elections, football games, cocktail parties and law courts in
a world that consists entirely of physical particles in fields of force, and in
which some of these particles are organized into systems that are conscious
biological beasts, such as ourselves? (Searle , xi)
Few contemporary authors are as explicit as Searle, but it is not uncom-
mon to combine psychologism and naturalism in this way.
This assumption about the restricted scope of social ontology is, how-
ever, not logically tied to the assumption that social ontology must explain
the social in terms of the non-social. It is possible to insist that the social,
the mental, and the natural are ontologically distinct, but that the order of
dependence or, at least, the order of explanation goes in the other direction
so that, say, the mental must be explained as a function of the social (as is
the case in, for instance, structuralism and functionalism). Alternatively,
one might agree that social and non-social entities are ontologically distinct
but that we cannot explain one in terms of the other. Then we arrive at a
form of social ontological dualism (or – if we hold that the social, the
mental, and the natural are all irreducible to each other – a form of
trialism).
To take two other examples, Tuomela’s theory is ‘based on a science-friendly philosophical
naturalism’ (, ), and Lawson accepts ‘the doctrine of ontological naturalism, the thesis that
everything can be explained in terms of natural causes’ (, ).
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
These different methodological approaches agree that social ontology is
limited in scope. Some, however, doubt that we can make a sharp
distinction between the social and the non-social. For instance, Sally
Haslanger thinks that it is ‘unlikely that there is a non-circular definition’
of what makes something ‘social’ (, ); Epstein writes that ‘it . . . may
be pointless to engage in a lengthy exercise to pin [that which circum-
scribes social facts] down’ (, f ); and Gilbert notes that ‘the
phenomena aptly thought of as “social” are a motley crew’ (, ).
This might be a simple conceptual difficulty (which definition of ‘social’
will accommodate all of our intuitions?), but it could also be a symptom
that there is no substantial difference between the social and the non-
social. The latter is an ontological claim, but from it derives a methodo-
logical one, namely that we get off on the wrong foot if we attempt to
explain the social in terms of the non-social.
If we reject that the social world is a distinct domain of reality, we have
an unrestricted view of the scope of social ontology. The unrestricted view
poses the following methodological questions: What then does social
ontology do? Which kind of knowledge or explanation does it provide?
The unrestricted view does not necessarily claim that it is nonsensical to
distinguish between, for instance, artefacts that are causally created by
human beings and natural kinds but argues, instead, that allegedly non-
social entities, properties, or facts exist (or are conceived to exist in this or
that way) because of a latent social process. This broadens the scope of
social ontology to include entities that are otherwise categorised as mental
or natural. The aim of social ontology is, accordingly, not to explain the
social in terms of the non-social but to describe the way in which a given
(latently or manifestly social) entity depends upon a particular social
process. There are two versions of this approach.
The first version claims that a given entity depends upon an empirical
social structure. In its most radical form, this approach claims not just that
a specific entity or category (e.g., gender or race) depends for its subsis-
tence or its properties upon a particular empirical social formation but that
our conception of reality as such somehow depends on empirical social
factors. Consider, for instance, Peter Winch, who, inspired by the later
Wittgenstein, postulates that ‘[r]eality is not what gives language sense.
What is real and what is unreal shows itself in the sense that language has’
(, ). Given that language is a product of a contingent and
empirical social formation, Winch claims that the very distinction between
the real and the unreal is somehow socially constituted. Another argument
to the same effect can be found in practice theory, which claims that
What Is Social Ontology?
entities depend for their intelligibility upon the social practices of which
they are part. The term ‘social practice’ refers, in this context, to a mesh of
organised bundles of human activity and material arrangements of organ-
isms, artefacts, and things (cf. Bourdieu ; Giddens ; Schatzki
a, b). In short, entities are only intelligible within a particular
social practice or context.
The second version claims that entities, properties, and facts are intel-
ligible only due to a transcendental social structure. On this account, there
is no clear-cut distinction between the social and the non-social because
entities exist or appear to us in the way that they do because subjectivity
itself (or, to be precise, the correlation between subject and object) implies
a set of necessary and a priori social relations. On this view, the aim of
social ontology is to account for these necessary and a priori social
relations. Phenomenologists such as Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, and
Heidegger have pursued this type of social ontology in the greatest amount
of detail.
This is why Heidegger, rather casually, can claim both that ‘only as long as Dasein is . . . “is there”
being’ (SZ, /) and that ‘entities are independent of the experience, the acquaintance, and the
grasping through which they are disclosed, discovered and ascertained’ by us (SZ, /). He
concedes to the common-sense realist that (most or some) entities are causally independent of us,
because he, as a phenomenologist, has no interest in this type of dependency. Instead, he aims to
describe the intentional structure that allows entities to appear in a particular way. This intentional
structure exists only as long as there are intentional agents such as human beings, ‘only as long as
Dasein is’. For a further discussion of idealism and realism in Heidegger, see Blattner (),
Carman (), and Han-Pile ().
What Is Social Ontology?
because phenomenology describes what subjectivity must be in order to
encounter different kinds of objects (SZ, /). Heidegger’s ontology
describes the being of entities by accounting for the implicit intentional
structure that makes entities appear to us in the way that they do. This,
however, is not simply a description of what subjectivity is. The point is,
rather, that when describing what something is, we necessarily take our
point of departure in our understanding of what it is. These two elements –
being and understanding of being – are inseparable. As Schear puts it,
‘Heidegger holds that part of what you understand when you understand
what it is to be something is what it is to access it’ (, , my italics). For
instance, to say that something is a rook is also to say something about the
conditions under which this entity is accessible as a rook (rather than, say,
a small piece of wood). Phenomenology is ontology because it describes
not just subjectivity but the basic correlation between human being and
world by way of which entities are meaningful to us.
Phrased differently, rather than studying the entity as something that
causally depends on some other thing or as a higher-order object that
constitutively depends on a set of lower-order constituents, Heidegger’s
ontology explicates how the appearance of a given entity phenomenally
depends on an unthematic and taken-for-granted intentional structure
(cf. SZ, /f ). This ontological project is transcendental like Kant’s
insofar as it aims to make explicit those correlative structures (for Kant,
these are the categories and the forms of intuition) that acts as conditions
of possibility for our experience of entities, although Heidegger’s account
ultimately differs from Kant’s by claiming that the transcendental structure
that binds human and world together must be described in conative,
affective, and indeed social terms.
There is a stark contrast between this phenomenological conception of
ontology and the naturalistic view advocated by someone like Searle.
When arguing that it must respect the ‘basic facts’ of the natural sciences,
Searle stipulates a naturalistic constraint on social ontology, thereby sug-
gesting that the ‘basic facts’ of the natural sciences are the ultimate
explanans. Yet, for Searle, the basic facts have simply fallen from the sky
and are beyond philosophical dispute. Heidegger, by contrast, holds that
all forms of cognition must be subjected to a phenomenological analysis.
He would hence point out that the explanation pursued by someone like
Searle is only possible because of an unquestioned and overlooked tran-
scendental intentional structure. Indeed, natural entities and scientific facts
Cf. McManus (, chapters and ).
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
are only intelligible as natural entities and scientific facts on the basis of
what Heidegger calls a ‘projection’. The projection is the way in which
certain features of entities are dimmed down (e.g., utility, beauty, sacred-
ness, sentimental value), while others are brought to the fore (e.g., motion,
force, location, time, universal accessibility).
Only ‘in the light’ of a nature which has been projected in this fashion can
anything like a ‘fact’ be found and set up for an experiment regulated and
delimited in terms of this projection. The ‘grounding’ of ‘factual science’
was possible only because the researchers understood that in principle there
are no ‘basic facts’ [‘blossen Tatsachen’]. (SZ, /)
For Heidegger, the ‘basic facts’ of natural science are intelligible only on
the basis of a specific engagement between human being and world. This
means that the naturalist outlook is itself a ‘distinctive way of making
entities present’ [ausgezeichneten Gegenwärtigung] (SZ, /) rather
than the ultimate explanans of all of reality. Heidegger thus finds the very
notion of ‘basic facts’ problematic, because these facts depend on a set of
scientific practices that are themselves in need of phenomenological
clarification.
Turning to the question of scope, it seems, at first, that we might be able
to adopt a phenomenological method and still insist – with, for instance,
Searle – that reality is divided into three different domains, and that social
ontology studies the subset of distinctively social entities. It appears that
we can reject the naturalistic constraint on our methodology and still hold
that social ontology is a subdiscipline of ontology because it studies only a
distinct subset of what there is.
But Heidegger also rejects this idea. He argues, as I will show briefly,
that the intentional structure that allows entities to appear to us by itself
implies a form of intersubjectivity, that is, that being is always a ‘being-
with others’ (SZ, /). If this is correct, sociality cannot simply be a
subset of what there is. Rather, sociality is itself a transcendental condition
of entities appearing in the first place. In Merleau-Ponty’s memorable
phrase, phenomenological analysis ‘slackens the intentional threads which
attach us to the world and thus brings them to our notice’ (, xv).
Sociality is one of these threads.
Since they are part of our intentional make-up, Heidegger believes that
social relations characterise human mindedness as such. If this is correct,
the psychology of individuals, the mental world, cannot be the explanans
of the social world, since the psychology of individuals itself presupposes a
form of intersubjectivity. For this reason, psychologism fails. Similarly, the
What Is Social Ontology?
naturalistic impulse to explain the social world with reference to a set of
basic facts, the natural world, fails because the basic facts can only appear
as meaningful on the basis of a set of necessary and a priori social relations.
It follows that social ontology should not restrict itself to the study of a
domain of existence but must analyse what I’ll call a dimension of existence.
Borrowing another formulation from Merleau-Ponty, we should conceive
of ‘the social world, not as an object or sum of objects, but as a permanent
field or dimension of existence: I may well turn away from it, but not cease
to be situated relatively to it’ (, ).
We can summarise Heidegger’s approach to social ontology in two
theses. The first concerns the scope of social ontology, and the second
concerns the method of social ontology.
() Sociality is a dimension of the world rather than a domain within
the world.
() Sociality must be accounted for by reference to the de jure or
transcendental social structure of the correlation between human
and world rather than some non-social level of reality or some de
facto or empirical social formation.
Taken together, these theses support the stronger claim that human
mindedness and agency is what it is only by virtue of being embedded in
and engaged with a shared world. This is the central claim of Heidegger’s
social ontology. Although it will take the entire book to defend these
claims, the rest of this chapter provides a preliminary clarification of these
two theses, thereby setting the scene for the chapters to come.
In the next section, I provide an overview of Heidegger’s early attempts
to integrate sociality into his phenomenological ontology. I focus on the
period from to the publication of SZ in , because Heidegger at
first, like Searle, distinguished between three domains of entities: the
surrounding world [Umwelt], the self-world [Selbstwelt], and the with-
world [Mitwelt]. I then outline how Heidegger comes to his mature view
that sociality, conceived phenomenologically, cannot be restricted to such
a domain of entities but is, instead, a constitutive dimension of the world
as such, which is therefore necessarily a shared world.
This implies that we cannot and should not explain the social dimen-
sion of existence by reducing it to an allegedly non-social level of reality.
The shared world is the holistic cloth from which our understanding of
specific entities is cut. Yet, this idea has been misunderstood in the
contemporary literature, and I will therefore, in the last section, provide
a preliminary clarification of what Heidegger means by ‘world’ and by
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
‘shared’. In anticipation of the arguments in Chapters and , I argue that
pragmatic conventionalists like Dreyfus and Okrent fail to recognise the
transcendental gist of Heidegger’s social ontology, although they correctly
understand the scope of it. In short, Dreyfus and Okrent believe that we
share the world if and only if we share certain de facto social formations,
namely, conventions or social practices, but I argue that Heidegger is
committed to the de jure claim that we share the world if and only if we
comport ourselves in accordance with wholes of significance that are
responsive to each other’s behaviour and we are capable of intending the
same entities. This claim is considerably stronger, methodologically speak-
ing, since it does not take world sharing to be a function of empirical social
formations but a transcendental condition of human existence as such.
For a chronological overview of Heidegger’s conceptions of intersubjectivity from SZ onwards, see
Grosser (a, b).
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
‘public’ institutions (the ‘public’ – the ‘market’ of life), certain accessible
networks of goals: school, parliament, etc. (GA, )
Each human being lives within a horizon of intelligibility and familiarity.
This familiarity, however, is not confined to the individual alone but is
carried by a ‘group of people’, who have thus made a part of the world
accessible to themselves. They have a shared understanding of the tools of
everyday life, for instance, and of various public institutions. This already
contradicts the separation between the with-world and the surrounding
world, between the natural and the social, since both of these domains are
required to describe how an environment (as a collection of tools, build-
ings, institutions, and places) is intelligible for a group of people. The
distinction seems to disappear right after it is made.
Similarly, he explains in / that the world has three distinct
aspects:
‘World’ is that in which one can live (one cannot live in an object). The
world can be formally articulated as surrounding world (milieu), as that
which we encounter, and to which belong not only material things but also
ideal objectivities, the sciences, art, etc. Within this surrounding world is
also the with-world, that is, other human beings in a very specific, factical
characterisation: as a student, a lecturer, as a relative, superior, etc., . . ..
Finally, the ‘I’-self, the self-world, is also found within factical life experi-
ence. (GA, /)
While denying that the world is an object, Heidegger nonetheless illus-
trates the three aspects of the world by listing various objects. The
surrounding world is the domain of material things that we can encounter;
that is, it is the totality of non-human objects that can become intentional
content for us. The with-world is the totality of other people in their
factical roles. The self-world is no longer defined as private, but now as a
form of locus that anchors the lifeworld in the individual (cf. GA, /).
To be sure, Heidegger emphasises that there is no hierarchy between these
three worlds (GA, /) and that they cannot be sharply distinguished
from each other (GA, /). In fact, he explicitly states that the meth-
odological utility of these concepts is to characterise the ‘manner, the how,
of the experiencing of those worlds’ (GA, /) rather than what is
inside them.
This points to a fundamental tension in Heidegger’s thought. On the
one hand, the three worlds refer to a what, and, on the other hand, they
refer to a how. In Heidegger’s terms, there is a tension between content
sense and relational sense (GA, /, /) that characterises the entire
What Is Social Ontology?
period from to . He constantly illustrates the three worlds by
referring to a list or domain of entities that makes up the potential content
of experience, but at the same time he maintains that he is, in fact, not
interested in the content, but how it is given. This points to the conceptual
and methodological shortcoming of the early approach: Heidegger simply
lacks the resources to distinguish between sociality as a domain (e.g., the
list of other people, social roles, and so on) and sociality as a dimension
that constantly overflows any such domain thus also affecting how we
experience ourselves in a ‘self-world’ or how we experience material things
in the ‘surrounding world’.
John van Buren also notes how the three ‘worldly spheres’ constantly
overlap. He explains this by saying that ‘[i]n the flow of experience we are
always oriented primarily to one of these “worlds of caring”, while the
other two are there in the background’ (van Buren , ). While this
certainly makes clear why Heidegger’s examples always complicate his
distinctions, van Buren’s distinction between a foreground and a back-
ground is by itself insufficient to solve the ambiguity in Heidegger’s
account. The problem is that van Buren’s formulation suggests that an
entity of the with-world appears in the foreground, while the entities of the
surrounding world and the self-world are in the background. On this
account, however, we cannot explain what makes a foregrounded entity
a social entity, since the foregrounded or thematic entity is only social by
virtue of backgrounded or non-thematic references to other people.
It is, therefore, necessary to say that the with-world is simultaneously in
the (thematic) foreground and the (non-thematic) background – along
with the backgrounded surrounding world and self-world, of course. Van
Buren’s distinction between an experiential foreground and an experiential
background does not, therefore, solve the ambiguity of Heidegger’s con-
cept of the with-world. It is, in short, not radical enough in its distinction
between the thematic and the non-thematic structures of human com-
portment, between domains within the world and dimensions of
the world.
Heidegger draws this conclusion in . Influenced by his simulta-
neous lectures on Aristotle’s practical philosophy, he gives a talk called
‘The Concept of Time’ for the Department of Theology at the University
of Marburg. Here he abandons the terminology of the with-world in
favour of the concept of being-with-each-other [Miteinandersein]. This
new terminology indicates a change in the social ontological architecture
of his thought. He now claims that being-with-each-other characterise
Dasein regardless of whether other people are actually present or whether
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
they are actually intended. In other words, our being-with-each-other is
in principle independent of the entities previously used to illustrate the
with-world:
As ‘being-in-the-world,’ Dasein is at the same time being-with-each-other
[miteinandersein, sic]. The aim here is not to assert that mostly we do not
exist as single persons, that others are also present. Rather, ‘being-with-
each-other’ implies an ontological characteristic of Dasein that is equipri-
mordial with ‘being-in-the-world.’ This aspect of Dasein persists even if no
one else is actually spoken to or perceived. (GA, /)
This reformulation finally solves the tension by insisting that sociality, as a
dimension of experience, goes beyond any domain of objects. Sociality is
posited as being equiprimordial with being-in-the-world and thus given a
transcendental status: When there is Da, there is also a Mit.
A little later, in a lecture course from , Heidegger even comments
on his earlier terminology and explains that he now realises that his focus
on entities (as opposed to the world as such) was confused. The concepts
of being-with [Mitsein], being-with-each-other [Miteinandersein], and
fellow Dasein [Mitdasein] remedies this fault:
the worldhood of the world appresents not only world-things [Weltdinge] –
the surrounding world in the narrower sense – but also, although not as
worldly being [weltliches Sein], the fellow Dasein of others and my own
self. . . . Not to be denied phenomenally is the finding that fellow Dasein –
the Dasein of others – and my own Dasein are encountered by way of the
world. On the strength of this worldly encountering of others, they can be
distinguished from the world-things in their being occurrent or available in
the surrounding world and demarcate them as a ‘with-world,’ while my
own Dasein, insofar as it is encountered in the surroundings, can be grasped
as the ‘self-world.’ This is the way I saw things in my earlier courses and
coined the terms accordingly. But the matter is completely wrong. The
terminology shows that the phenomena are not adequately grasped in this
way, that the others, though they are encountered in the world, really do
not have and never have the world’s kind of being. The others, therefore,
cannot be designated as a ‘with-world.’ (GA, /f )
In this passage, Heidegger offers one formulation of his central thesis,
namely, the idea that we encounter ourselves, others, and things (‘world-
things’, as he calls them) on the basis of the phenomenon of the world. As
he explains, he earlier tried to formulate this thesis by calling the domain of
other people for ‘the with-world’. Now, however, he realises that this
terminology confuses different ontological levels. The entities, with which
Heidegger illustrated the surrounding world and the with-world, are given
What Is Social Ontology?
within a world. That is to say, these domains of entities are innerworldly
and do not, therefore, have the ontological structure of the world. They do
not have ‘worldly being’ [weltliches Sein].
Innerworldly entities are meaningful due to the place they occupy
within the world. The world is the realm of intelligibility in which other
Dasein or tools appear to me. Therefore, the world must necessarily be of a
different ontological order than these innerworldly entities. The terminol-
ogy of the with-world blurs this distinction and leads us to mistakenly
believe that others, who are strictly speaking within the world, can be
conceptualised as a form of world.
To avoid this confusion, Heidegger coins the term ‘being-with’
[Mitsein]. The benefit is that being-with cannot be separated from other
aspects of the world. Furthermore, the concept of being-with makes clear
that sociality is equiprimordial with being-in-the-world and thus not
something that occurs occasionally when we encounter another Dasein.
Most importantly, being-with finalises the separation between sociality as a
transcendental condition that cuts across all domains and sociality as a
term designating a certain type of innerworldly entities. This is, of course,
not to say that Heidegger completely disregards that there is a domain of
objects that is ontologically similar to ourselves. This is what he calls
‘fellow Dasein [Mitdasein]’. As he states programmatically in SZ:
By reason of the with-like [mithaften] being-in-the-world, the world is
always the one that I share with others. The world of Dasein is a with-
world. Being-in is being-with others. Their innerworldly being-in-them-
selves [innerweltliche Ansichsein] is fellow Dasein. (SZ, /)
Thus, his attempts to integrate sociality into phenomenological ontology
lead Heidegger to claim that sociality is a dimension, not a domain, of
the world.
Michael Theunissen, for instance, writes: ‘For the world, in the ontological meaning in which it is
taken here, is organised by the self in the total structure of Dasein as the for-the-sake-of-which
(Worumwillen) of a referential totality. The self is, however, the existential place in which the I is
preserved. So, with Heidegger, even the Other, in the transcendental sense, has to be aligned with
“me”: he is the projected of my project and is not to be distinguished, in this respect, from the
[available, NK]’ (Theunissen , ). Varieties of this criticism can also be found in Buber
(), Löwith (), Levinas (), Habermas (), and, most recently, Darwall ().
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
For Dreyfus (, ), ‘[w]hat we share’, when we share the world, ‘is
simply our average comportment’. Thus, two people share the world if
they comport themselves to entities according to the same typified pattern,
that is, when they have a pragmatic convention in common. Drawing on
Wittgenstein, he then argues that ‘once a practice has been explained by
appealing to what one does, no more basic explanation is possible’
(Dreyfus , ).
Similarly, Okrent argues that
[a] world is shared insofar as there are typical and proper uses for tools,
typical and proper equipmental and functional contextures, and interlock-
ing social patterns of purposive activity in which means and ends are
purposively integrated across a group of individuals. . . . I am with others
insofar as my behavior is proper within my community. (Okrent , , my
italics)
The suggestion is, hence, that the behaviour of the social groups in which
we live crystallises into a world without us being aware of it. In this way,
pragmatic conventions are the ‘source of intelligibility’ (Dreyfus ,
ff ). We should, therefore, take it quite literally, when Okrent writes
that ‘I am with others insofar as my behaviour is proper within my
community’ (Okrent , ) and that ‘[t]he others with whom I share
a world are those who are like me’ (Okrent , ). This does not mean
that I share the world with those who are ontologically like me (and, hence,
that I share the world with all Dasein) but simply that I share the world
with those who are sociologically like me, that is, those who belong to the
same community (Okrent) or society (Dreyfus) as I do.
Although Heidegger’s analysis of the Anyone certainly plays an impor-
tant role in his social ontology, this line of interpretation has several
shortcomings. First, the attempt to explain the world as a function of
social groups begs the question of social ontology. After all, a – if not the –
central aim of social ontology is to explain how groups, communities, and
societies are possible. This being the case, we cannot simply presuppose a
specific social formation to be the source of intelligibility. If social ontology
is a meaningful endeavour, it must be possible to somehow get behind such
social formations, to conceptualise their necessary structure, and to explain
how this dimension fits with the other dimensions of human life.
Dreyfus might still insist that the appeal to certain typified modes of
comportment is the best form of explanation that we can hope for. This,
however, is not Heidegger’s view. His central social ontological claim is not
that some factical social formation – like the pragmatic convention
What Is Social Ontology?
regarding right and wrong ways of comporting oneself – constitutes the
ultimate source of intelligibility. Rather, he claims that being-with is a
transcendental condition – a necessary structure of all human understand-
ing – and that this transcendental condition, in turn, makes concrete social
formation such as a typified comportmental pattern possible. The fact
that being-in-the-world and being-with-one-another are equiprimordial
enables ‘the various possibilities of community as well as of society’
(GA, /).
In short, we need to explain particular social formations in terms of the
world rather than the other way around. Although still unfulfilled, the task
is clear: Social ontology must account for the de jure relations between
human beings that make various de facto social formations possible.
Second, PCI’s claim that we share the world with those that comport
themselves to entities according to the same typified pattern as us leaves us
wondering: What, then, do we have in common with those who are
socialised into different societies? What sort of common ground or shared
understanding can be reached between people that do not share the same
pragmatic convention? One might worry that Heidegger’s holism – his
insistence that all acts of understanding rely on a holistic and socially
constituted background – leads to an untenable relativism that renders
intercommunal understanding impossible. I discuss this issue in
Chapter .
A third problem is that the conventionalist reading threatens to make a
caricature of not just intercommunal understanding but all forms of social
cognition. If we accept that the Anyone is the source of intelligibility, we
might be unable to understand others as anything but instances of their
social roles. McMullin formulates the point well: ‘The problem . . . is that
Heidegger’s account seems to fall into the danger of viewing other Dasein
merely as interchangeable representatives of the public norms and mean-
ings through which we all pursue our particular abilities to be’ (McMullin
, ). Although anonymous social norms certainly permeate social
life, we also need an account of how we experience others as concrete and
unique fellow Dasein rather than just embodiments of a public norm.
I turn to this issue of interpersonal understanding in Chapter .
In what follows, I will argue that we need a more complex account of
the world and a more sophisticated understanding of what it is to share it if
we are to solve these problems. To put it briefly, PCI claims that
See Chapter .
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
Two individuals, A and B, share a world if and only if A and B
comport themselves towards entities in accordance with the same
whole of significance that is afforded to them by a specific (set of )
social practice(s).
I, on the other hand, argue that
An individual, A, shares the world with another individual, B, if and
only if
() A comports himself in accordance with a whole of significance that is
responsive to the behaviour of B,
() A tacitly assumes B to be capable of intending the same entities as A.
Similarly,
Two individuals, A and B, share the world with each other symmet-
rically if and only if
()(a) A comports himself in accordance with a whole of significance
that is responsive to the behaviour of B and (b) B comports himself in
accordance with a whole of significance that is responsive to the
behaviour of A,
()(a) A tacitly assumes B to be capable of comporting himself
towards the same entities as A and (b) B tacitly assumes A to be
capable of comporting himself towards the same entities as B.
Chapter argues in more detail for this account of world sharing and
shows why our capacity to intend the same entities is crucial. Here it
should be noted that I deliberately emphasise our capacity to intend the
same entities, since we should not confuse world sharing – a very basic
form of sociality – with something like joint attention in which this
capacity is enacted. It is also on purpose that the reliance on other people
in () is vaguely described in terms of being ‘responsive’. I intend this to
include both those kinds of dependency of which we are explicitly or
thematically aware, for example, the thematic other-awareness of a face-to-
face encounter, and non-thematic relations like those between strangers
sitting next to each other on a bus. In Section ., I discuss the possibility
of asymmetric world sharing by considering human–animal interaction in
which the animal, at least if we follow Heidegger, is structurally incapable
of intending the same entities as us.
There is a very minimal sense of the word to share at stake here. Indeed,
what we share is not something empirical that can be measured and
formulated in terms of an average or a shared norm. Rather, what we
What Is Social Ontology?
share is a transcendental structure – a common condition of being a
human agent or self. For Heidegger, this condition renders us fundamen-
tally responsive to each other, always already related to each other. As a
minimal kind of sharing, this allows a great degree of differentiation. We,
of course, share the world with those with whom we share a personal
history, a convention, a language, or a common project. But we also share
the world with those with whom we do not have a personal history, who
are raised according to different conventions and in different languages,
and who partake in different – perhaps even opposing – projects. This
differentiated notion of sharing resonates well with the German word for
sharing, teilen, which means both to have something in common but also
to divide.
Although somewhat overlooked by Heidegger scholars, it is not unprec-
edented to extrapolate such a minimal and differentiated notion of world
sharing from Heidegger. In fact, it is central to both Hannah Arendt’s and
Jean-Luc Nancy’s work on being-with. Nancy claims, with an ambiguity
reminiscent of Heidegger’s German, that ‘we share what divides us [nous
partageons ce qui nous partage]’ (Nancy , ). Similarly, Arendt
describes her notion of the world by using the image of a table:
To live together in the world means essentially that a world of things is
between those who have it in common, as a table is located between those
who sit around it; the world, like every in-between, relates and separates
men at the same time. (Arendt , ).
Rather than designating a specific social formation, the world is the
common condition that relates and separates us at the same time. Only if
we keep this in mind can we account for the common ground of the many
different and more robust forms of interaction that make up
human coexistence.
It is controversial whether Husserl’s phenomenology amounts to an occurrent ontology. Overgaard
argues against this by pointing out that ‘“thing”, “substance”, “nature”, and the like, as well as such
concepts as “property”, and “attribute”,’ cannot be used to describe transcendental subjectivity, since
transcendental subjectivity is the ‘source (Quellpunkt) of all that these concepts apply to; it is the
place that allows for things of nature, for substances with properties, to manifest themselves’
(Overgaard , ). Transcendental subjectivity is not an entity, and for this reason it
admittedly makes little sense to claim that it is occurrent. Heidegger’s point is, however, more
subtle than this. In fact, Overgaard’s objection underlines the problem. The fact that transcendental
subjectivity is the ‘the place that allows for things of nature, for substances with properties, to
manifest themselves’ reveals that transcendental subjectivity, despite not being an occurrent entity
Transcendental Social Ontology in Husserl and Heidegger
valuable within social practices. In Heidegger’s view we are, hence, forced
to either give up the (naturalistic or Cartesian) priority given to the
‘naturally real’ or the phenomenological ambition of staying true to ‘the
things themselves’. Husserl, in Heidegger’s interpretation, gives up
the latter.
() ‘The mode of access to the person is nothing other than the already
defined immanent reflection (inspectio sui) upon lived experiences,
from which all the theses of absolute givenness and the like
are derived’.
Heidegger then shifts his focus from the constituted reality to the consti-
tuting subject. He argues that instead of considering the ‘being of the
person’ in a phenomenologically sound way – that is, as it is experienced in
everyday life – Husserl’s reliance on the concepts of the pure consciousness
and the pure ego immediately leads him astray.
A remark from Husserl’s lecture ‘Phenomenology and
Anthropology’ serves as a case in point. ‘Becoming aware of myself as this
[transcendental] ego through the transcendental reduction, I have achieved
a standpoint above all worldly being [weltlichen Sein], above my own
being-human and human life’ (Husserl , ). The reduction, he
says, requires that we abstract from all personal matters and all social
engagement and achieve ‘transcendental solitude’ (Husserl , ).
Heidegger takes issue with this emphasis on purity and solitude and
claims that it prevents Husserl from grasping the being of the human
being. The abstraction implied by the pure ego requires that we bracket all
the aspects that serve to make human existence what it is. Reflections on
the pure ego are essential to the question of how nature is constituted, but
they cannot help us clarify ‘consciousness’ as individuated or individual
(GA, /), that is, as a concrete human being defined by what and
who it cares for.
In Heidegger’s reading, Husserl offers two different solutions to the
problem of personal individuation, an extrinsic and an intrinsic solution,
that both fail.
The extrinsic solution is described in the following way: ‘[N]ow the
theme is not pure consciousness and pure ego but instead the individuated
[verenzelt] and individual [individuelle]. But the individuation is always
itself, leads to an occurrent ontology. The transcendental ego is implicitly positioned over and
against a world of occurrents objects by the attempt to describe entities as ‘objective,’ that is, as
correlates of disinterested, theoretical acts.
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
conditioned by the body [Leib]’ (GA, /). In this reading, Husserl
might try to account for the individuation of the transcendental ego by
reference to how the lived body acts as a locus of experience, both as a
constituted object of experience but also as itself constituting various
experiences, like kinaesthetics. The problem is that this appeal to embodi-
ment remains a layered account of the human being, where the body is
assumed to be the foundational layer, like the naturally real (spatiotempo-
ral extension) was assumed to be the foundational layer of constituted
reality. Thereby individuation is assumed to be independent of personal
and social features. These features only enter at a later and less fundamen-
tal level. Husserl thus conceives of the human being as a unity of three
different layers in an internal hierarchy of foundation: the physical, the
psychic, and the spiritual (GA, /). Heidegger’s challenge, on the
contrary, is to grasp the being and unity of the human being. This requires
that we take into account practical engagement and affective involvement
with the environment and others from the get-go; that is, that we conceive
embodiment as a part of (rather than the basis of ) existential selfhood.
Heidegger then looks at the second option, namely, the intrinsic
solution:
Of course, it is explicitly stated that the connection of experiences
[Erlebniszusammenhang] has its intrinsic individuation [Individuation], that
it is always had by a particular I-subject, but the type of being of the acts
remains undetermined. Acts are performed; the I is the pole of the acts, the
self-persisting subject. (GA, /)
A form of individuation is intrinsic to the immanent reflection on lived
experiences since all of these experiences are had by the same I. From this
perspective, the subject is grasped as the formal unity of the mind afforded
by the transcendental subject as the synthesising activity that unites
distinct intentional states in a single series. In the contemporary debate,
this solution to the problem of individuation is defended by Zahavi, who
calls it the ‘minimal’ or ‘experiential self’. Within the very structure of
intentionality, we find ‘a distinct but formal kind of experiential individ-
uation’ that is, pace Heidegger, ‘not concerned with issues like personality,
character, preferences, and history’ (Zahavi , ).
In Heidegger’s view, this is not the right level of description. All minded
creatures are minimal selves, on Husserl’s and Zahavi’s account, and
although this can indeed explain the asymmetry in how we can access
our own intentional states in the first-person but not that of others, we are
still unable to explain what makes me me and you you. Sara Heinämaa
explains it thus:
Transcendental Social Ontology in Husserl and Heidegger
Essentially, Heidegger’s critical remarks here suggest that the immanent
principle of individuation that Husserl presents can merely distinguish the
reflecting ego from everything else but cannot differentiate between sepa-
rate individuals in the experienced plurality of human life. On purely
immanent grounds, we can only keep ourselves distinct from everything
alien or from a general anonymous other without ever coming to You, He,
She, etc. (Heinämaa , )
As a formal unity of mind, the minimal self abstracts from all our worldly
engagements and will not help us individuate human beings as full and
concrete persons. It can only pick out the I independently of its worldly
engagement and contrast this I to all others, who are conceived indiscrim-
inately as non-I’s.
Underlying this critique is, of course, Heidegger’s alternative account of
existential selfhood. On this account, the self is not the ‘self-persisting
subject’ but an agent engaged in worldly projects, constantly drawn in by
the possibilities of the world. Dasein is ‘primarily being-possible
[Möglichsein]’; it ‘is in every case what it can be, and the way in which it
is its possibility’ (SZ, /). For Heidegger, to be a self is to be self-
referentially committed to a project that can be furthered through certain
affordances. As Wrathall puts it with reference to Merleau-Ponty, the self
is a ‘particular polarization of affordances into solicitations’ (Wrathall
, ). The minimal self is not itself at stake in the factical situations
that appear to it, whereas the existential self is the very feature – the for-
the-sake-of – that polarises such situations into wholes of significance. This
means that Heidegger’s notion of selfhood is ultimately individuated by its
pre-reflective, conative, and affective engagement in the world; by its
existential projections. Traditional notions of embodiment and minimal
selfhood wrongfully abstract from this kind of practical involvement.
() ‘The predetermination of the unity of the connection of experiences
as spirit and person adheres to the traditional definition of man –
homo animal rationale – as its guide’.
Heidegger now goes on to argue that Husserl’s layered account of reality
and subjectivity not only prevents him from answering ‘the question about
the being of the full and concrete human being’ (GA, /) but also
reveal that Husserl proceeds in an unphenomenological way by borrowing
categories and premises from traditional metaphysics:
See Rousse () for a further discussion of minimal selfhood and existential selfhood.
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
Can this being [of the full, concrete human being] be, so to speak,
assembled from the being of the material substrate, of the body, and from
the soul and the spirit? Is the being of the person the product of the kinds of
being of these layers of being? Or is it just here where it becomes evident
that this way of a prior division and a subsequent composition does not get
at the phenomena? (GA, /)
[I]s this definition drawn from experiences which aim at a primary experi-
ence of the being of man? Or does it not come from the experience of man
as an occurrent thing of the world – animal – which has reason – rationale –
as an intrinsic property? (GA, /)
The charge is that Husserl is unable to provide a phenomenology of the
human being because his interest in the constitution of objectivity forces
him to conceptualise the human being as a ‘multilayered thing of the
world’ (GA, /). He is thereby incapable of dealing with the
problems inherent to the traditional definition of the human being as
animal rationale and as body, soul, and spirit because he simply cannot
account for how these layers fit together and form an ontological unity.
The problem of the personalistic attitude thus echoes the problem of
naturalism, even though they were supposed to be opposite extremes
(GA, /f ): How does soul and spirit, mental world and the social
world, relate to the objectivity of the natural world?
In this way, Heidegger’s critique of Husserl echoes the problem outlined
in Chapter . While Husserl does indeed provide rich analyses of social
life, he fails to realise that social ontology is a dimension of phenomeno-
logical ontology as such and not just a single layer or a single region
of existence.
Husserl’s transcendental social ontology is right to emphasise that
sociality has an essential relation to transcendence, and his ambition of
accounting for this relation through an analysis of experience is correct
despite the fact that he never, in Heidegger’s opinion, manages to carry out
such an analysis. The main problem, on the other hand, is that Husserl’s
‘idea of absolute and rigorous science [Wissenschaftlichkeit]’ (GA, /
) prevents him from adequately grasping the correlation between
(inter)subjectivity and transcendence. He sees the human being primarily
as the pure impersonal ego and transcendence as objective reality: Husserl’s
position ‘certainly does not take the human as a reality of nature
[Naturrealität], but it is still a reality of the world [Weltrealität] that
constitutes itself as transcendence in absolute consciousness’ (GA, /).
The question of the human being is not only a regional problem, not
simply a question of how we understand the ontological domain of
Transcendental Social Ontology in Husserl and Heidegger
humans. On the contrary, the issue goes to the very heart of the phenom-
enological project insofar as Heidegger’s critique puts into question
Husserl’s concept of transcendental subjectivity.
As we saw above, the general idea underlying Heidegger’s charges is that
the phenomenological subject, as the one to whom the world is given, must
also simultaneously be an entity in the world. In his terms, the phenome-
nological subject must be both ontological and ontic.
How is it at all possible that this sphere of absolute position, pure con-
sciousness, which is supposed to be separated from every transcendence by
an absolute gulf, is at the same time united with reality in the unity of a real
human being, who himself occurs as a real object in the world? How is it
possible that lived experiences constitute an absolute and pure region
of being and at the same time occur in the transcendence of the world?
(GA, /)
Husserl himself recognised the significance of the challenge posed by
Heidegger. Responding to the popularity of SZ, he explicitly argued
against Heidegger’s position, as he understood it, in the lecture
mentioned above. He never mentions Heidegger by name but he does
comment on the new type of phenomenology according to which ‘the true
foundation of philosophy must lie . . . solely in the human being, namely,
in an essential doctrine [Wesenslehre] concerning its concrete, worldly
being-there [konkret-weltlichen Daseins]’ (Husserl , ). Husserl
believes that this turn to anthropologism or psychologism, as he deroga-
torily calls it, exhibits a ‘subjectivistic tendency’ in direct opposition to his
own transcendental and scientific ambition (Husserl , ).
Husserl argues that if we presuppose the validity of the world, we fall
back into a kind of metaphysical naïveté because we cannot live up to the
truly philosophical task of grounding the sciences. The problem with
Heidegger’s insistence on the ontic–ontological status of Dasein is, hence,
that any positive doctrine of the human being ‘whether empirical or a
priori presupposes the existing or possible existing world’ (Husserl ,
). If the phenomenologising subject does not achieve transcendental
solitude, it is unable to describe the necessary structures of its experiential
field as it remains steeped in contingency. A phenomenology conducted by
an innerworldly entity rather than the transcendental subject remains,
therefore, a mere regional ontology of limited philosophical interest
(Husserl , ).
In assessing Husserl’s critique, it is important to remember that
Heidegger’s primary interest is not to ground the sciences and not to
account for the objectivity of the world. In Heidegger’s view, the sciences
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
do just fine without such a Cartesian quest for certainty. Instead, he aims
to pose the question of being, and this question can only be worked out
from the perspective of an entity that always already moves within a
(however vague) understanding of being (SZ, /).
We can outline Heidegger’s approach in two steps:
() To grasp being, we must clarify how entities appear.
() To clarify how entities appear, we must analyse the kind of entity to
which (or rather to whom) entities appear.
The second step is important since the kind of entity to whom appearances
are given determine how these appearances are given. Chad Engelland puts
this point nicely when he says that ‘[t]o be given, being needs a dative, and
to be a dative, one needs to be an entity’ (Engelland , ). This makes
clear why it is crucial for Heidegger that we abandon Husserl’s distinction
between human being (as a constituted entity) and the transcendental ego
(as the constituting subject). This distinction denies () by splitting the
appearances of entities from the concrete being of the entity to whom
entities appear. It follows from Heidegger’s premises that
() To grasp being, we must analyse the kind of entity to which (or
rather to whom) entities appear, namely, Dasein.
As he puts it in SZ, phenomenology is transcendental but also
hermeneutical:
[T]o the extent that by uncovering the meaning of being and the basic
structures of Dasein in general we may exhibit the horizon for any further
ontological study of those entities which do not have the character of
Dasein, this hermeneutic also becomes a ‘hermeneutic’ in the sense of
working out the conditions on which the possibility of any ontological
investigation depends. (SZ, /)
Had Husserl taken Heidegger’s ‘anthropological’ approach to phenome-
nology seriously, he would have realised that the dative of manifestation
cannot be understood as a series of disinterested acts of constitution (with
or without an internal hierarchy of foundation), that the transcendental
subject cannot be clearly distinguished from the concrete human being.
Heidegger’s hermeneutic point is that the dative of manifestation is an
entity with a particular mode of being and that this, in turn, gives
manifestation itself a particular shape. In SZ, this thesis is famously
substantiated with the further claim that the being of the entity to whom
entities appear is care in the form of ecstatic temporality. In contrast to
Husserl’s disinterested observer, Heidegger grounds phenomenology in the
Transcendental Social Ontology in Husserl and Heidegger
temporal unity of Dasein as an existential self, that is, a self that is
practically engaged in and affectively attuned by the world that it shares
with others.
In Chapters and , I show that this structure not only individuates the I as a particular person
opposed to all others but also makes our understanding of others and their existential projections
possible. Along these lines, to experience the tennis court as a field of possibilities not only provides
me with a pre-reflective self-awareness but also a pre-reflective other-awareness, because I also
encounter the other – my opponent – as immersed in and responding to the same field of forces
in his own way.
There are, of course, other problems inherent to this account of individuation. I deal with two of
them in Chapter .
Transcendental Social Ontology in Husserl and Heidegger
necessary to explain its type of experience, the entity in question is not D.
Specifically, Heidegger claims that transcendence in the form of a tempo-
rally structured experiential field is indispensable if we are to explain
intentionality, that is, the factical experience of a as b. Borrowing a
topographical analogy from Malpas, we can say that Heidegger’s transcen-
dental attempt to uncover the fundamental structure of experience is akin
to trying to map a region (Malpas , ). Why indeed should this
endeavour be impossible from within this region itself? Given that what is
at stake is the necessary structure of D’s experiential life, it seems to me that
this type of inquiry is radically incompatible with a sideways-on perspec-
tive. We have no choice but to proceed from within.
This problem relates to what Wayne Martin () has called the
‘semantics’ of Dasein. Martin argues that our view on what fixes the
meaning of the term Dasein has wide-ranging implications for our con-
ception of what it is to do phenomenological ontology. If, for instance, we
define Dasein intensionally, for example, as the entity that comports itself
towards its own being, it is difficult to see how concrete phenomenological
descriptions might justify necessary and transcendental claims, since only
the truths that follow analytically from this intensional definition of
Dasein are by necessity true for Dasein. It seems that phenomenological
descriptions can only uncover contingent features of (a particular) Dasein,
while all necessary features must be analytically derived from the definition
of Dasein as the entity that comports itself towards its own being.
Alternatively, if we define Dasein extensionally, for example, as another
name for human beings, phenomenological description of the experiential
life of a human being might justify claims about the necessary truths about
human beings but only if we, from the outset, have assumed that all
human beings are ontologically similar (Martin , ).
Martin rightly points out that these approaches are dead ends. Instead,
Heidegger’s phenomenology seems to rest on what Martin calls an ‘exem-
plar semantics’ in which the meaning of Dasein is fixed by Heidegger’s
literary ostension of himself and the reader, by his suggestion that ‘we are
ourselves the entities to be analysed’ (SZ, /). This means that the
transcendental claims issued by Heidegger are, strictly speaking, neither
necessary truths about all human beings nor analytical truths about the
concept of an understanding of being. Rather, they are necessary truths
about the exemplars subjected to the phenomenological description as well
as any entities that are ontologically similar to these exemplars. As Martin
points out, this means that I, as a phenomenologist, can issue necessary
claims about the ontological structure of myself as well as entities that are
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
ontologically like me, although these claims are necessarily provisional
in the sense that their extension has not been fixed in advance
(Martin , , ). This is another way in which Heidegger’
transcendental phenomenological method is tied to ‘the most radical
individuation’ (SZ, /).
Second, we should note that the apparent tension between the factical
and the transcendental appears all the way through Heidegger’s ontology.
As discussed in Chapter , the distinction between the ontic-existential
sense of world, denoting specific realms of familiarity, and the ontological-
existential sense of world, as the manner of being of all these particular
realms of familiarity, runs parallel to it. It is built into the very core of
Heidegger’s project that we must find an ontological-existential structure
that is common to all worlds in the ontic-existential sense. We might
follow Martin and reply to Guignon that this is the (provisional) result of
our attempt to fix the extension of the ostensive definition of Dasein and
being-in-the-world or we might, in an even more deflationary reading,
argue that the move from the ontic-existential to the ontological-existential
only involves a comparative procedure rather than an actual transcendental
deduction. In both these readings, the universalist ambition is built into
the philosophical project from the outset. Without this, there would
indeed, as Husserl feared and Heidegger denied, be no difference between
phenomenology as a form of philosophy and phenomenology as a method
occasionally used by regional sciences like anthropology. Some hermeneu-
ticists, of course, simply accept this fate (e.g., Caputo ; Rorty ,
; Vattimo , ), but Heidegger certainly did not.
Third, it seems to me that Guignon’s suspicion against universal claims
pulls the rug from under his own feet. From which standpoint does the
hermeneuticist claim that all interpretations are relative to a specific culture
and historical period? Although I cannot argue this point here, I believe
that a consistent hermeneutic itself rests on a, however minimal, transcen-
dental foundation since the proposition ‘All truths are relative to their
historical periods’ must itself be of a different nature than the relative and
historical truths that it describes at pain of being self-refuting. Within his
phenomenological transcendental framework, Heidegger can easily claim
that ‘world-entry has the characteristic of happening [Geschehen], of
history [Geschichte]’, and that ‘world-entry happens when transcendence
happens, i.e., when historical Dasein exists’ (GA, /) since the
This is how I read Dreyfus’ claim that ‘[i]f we can show a structure to be common to the world and
each of its modes, we shall have found the structure of the world as such’ (Dreyfus , ).
Transcendental Social Ontology in Husserl and Heidegger
peculiarly universal structure of transcendence is that it always opens up
factical fields of possibilities. The hermeneuticist who claims that all truths
are relative to their historical periods, on the other hand, struggles to
explain why exactly this proposition should be exempted from his or her
proposed relativism.
Like Husserl, Heidegger aims to describe the necessary structures of
Dasein’s lived experience by way of an a priori analysis. Yet, in contrast to
Husserl, transcendence is not distinct from factical life but designates the
process that opens a horizon of intelligibility in which a holistically
constituted self finds itself locally situated and practically engaged with
things and other people. Heidegger puts the point well in a passage from a
-lecture course:
Dasein is thrown, factical, thoroughly amidst nature through its bodiliness
[Leiblichkeit], and transcendence lies in the fact that these entities, among
which Dasein is and to which Dasein belongs, are surpassed by Dasein. In
other words, as transcending, Dasein is beyond nature, although, as factical,
it remains surrounded by nature. As transcending, i.e., as free, Dasein is
something alien to nature. (GA, /)
As ontological, Dasein is ‘beyond nature’; it transcends entities by
disclosing them within a world. As ontic, however, Dasein remains
‘surrounded by nature’. That is to say, it is itself an entity, and it cannot
separate itself from its factical situatedness in a specific location amongst
other entities that it cares about and with which it is involved in the
pursuit of specific projects. Finally, Dasein is ‘alien to nature’, which
simply means that Dasein is ontologically distinct from the other entities
within the world.
For my present purpose, it is interesting that Heidegger, in his discus-
sion of individuation, not only denies that individuation isolates the I from
the shared world (GA, /) but explicitly claims that the individ-
uation entailed by transcendence serves to make a multiplicity of interre-
lated existential projections possible. As he puts it, this conception of
individuation provides ‘the clarification of the intrinsic possibility of
multiplication [Vermannigfaltigung] which . . . is present in every Dasein
and for which embodiment presents an organising factor’ (GA, /
). As I read these difficult passages, Heidegger’s point is that Dasein, as
a holistically constituted self, is always in relation to other entities (both
objects and other people). This implies that Dasein’s individuation is
always at stake in its existence. Dasein is what it is by virtue of its concrete
field of possibilities, and since these fields of possibilities are always at the
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
brink of changing, so is Dasein’s sense of self. This is one way in which
Dasein harbours within itself the ‘intrinsic possibility of multiplication’.
More importantly, however, Heidegger also argues that ‘multiplicity
[Mannigfaltigkeit] belongs to being itself’ (GA, /). This suggests
that Dasein is not only itself capable of a multiplication (in the sense that
its individuation is constantly at stake for it) but also that our facticity
disperses us into a multiplicity of holistically constituted and, hence,
intrinsically related selves.
To repeat the key points: First, transcendence is always factically con-
figured into the concrete field of possibilities of Dasein’s care, and, second,
this is what individuates Dasein. To be sure, embodiment is, as noted
above, ‘an organising factor’ in this structure but it is not the determining
factor. As ultimately individuated by the care structure, Dasein is neither
necessarily confined to the immanence of its mind (revealed by the
inspectio sui) nor its embodiment (although bodily abilities and location
are bound to affect what we care about) for the simple reason that the
existential self, reflected back by what it cares about, need not refer to the
distinctly minded or embodied individual. As I will argue later, we might
care for something together. Following the argument just sketched, the self
thus individuated is a we that covers several distinctly minded and embod-
ied individuals. Heidegger’s transcendental phenomenology shows that
this form of multiplication is a constitutive or inherent possibility for
Dasein because the existential self is holistically constituted; its under-
standing of itself and the world around it is necessarily responsive to the
behaviour of others. Transcendence involves, as I will detail in the next
chapter, a form of pre-reflective triangulation.
See Crowell (, ), Dahlstrom (), Malpas (), Crowell & Malpas (ed.) (),
Engelland () and, most recently, Westerlund ().
Transcendental Social Ontology in Husserl and Heidegger
world entails a form of subjectivism (see also Engelland , ). If this
interpretation is correct, however, there is no reason to believe that the
transcendental project, as I understand it, is radically incompatible with
the later Heidegger. It seems to me that Heidegger merely rejects his earlier
terminology to avoid a certain misinterpretation of his thought. Important
as this may be, it fails to raise any substantial objections. As a result, the
switch from the activistic metaphors of ‘transcendence’ and ‘projection’ to
the passivistic metaphors of ‘event [Ereignis]’ and ‘releasement
[Gelassenheit]’ amounts to a shift of emphasis insofar as both terminologies
try to spell out the basic structure that enables entities to appear
as meaningful.
There are of course more substantial points of divergence between the
early and the late Heidegger – especially concerning the ontological role of
historicity. In Chapter , I argue that Heidegger in the ‘s and ‘s
develops a being-historical or metapolitical manner of thought that under-
lies his political engagement. I show, however, that this philosophical
underpinning is partly motivated by a rejection of the transcendental
framework outlined here and that certain elements of his politics, there-
fore, contradict his social ontology.
His self-criticism notwithstanding, it is fair to say that Heidegger’s
account of being-with is transcendental insofar as he believes that the
world is necessarily bound up with social life and that intentionality itself
comes with an irreducible social dimension. In line with traditional
transcendental philosophy, Heidegger arrives at these indispensability
claims by way of an a priori analysis of experience. In contrast to the
classical approaches, however, Heidegger’s transcendentalism does not
purport to secure knowledge, science, or objectivity nor does it locate
the conditions of possibility squarely in the subject. Heidegger contends
that phenomenology must shed light on the necessary structure of exis-
tential projections, and his analysis shows that existential projections are
made possible not by internal conceptual schemes or the acts of an
absolute ego but the holistic relations to things, others, and ourselves that
constitute the basic correlation between human and world.
Holism and Relativism
As this passage shows, the concept of being-in-the-world radically expands
both the realm of the ‘internal’ and the realm of the ‘external’ to such an
extent that they become indistinguishable. In this way, Heidegger’s con-
cept of being-in-the-world complicates the internalist/externalist distinc-
tion by showing that his methodological ‘internalism’ (i.e., his study of the
ontological make-up of the ‘mind’) is equally committed to the ‘externalist’
view that intentionality depends in crucial ways on elements ‘out’ in ‘the
world’. When Putnam famously states: ‘Cut the pie anyway you like,
“meanings” just ain’t in the head’ (Putnam , ), Heidegger would
reply the same thing as McDowell (), namely, ‘neither is the mind’.
In consequence, I use the terms object externalism and social externalism to
refer to relations of dependence between mind and world that can only be
studied from within the first-person perspective of phenomenology.
Heidegger is an object externalist and a social externalist insofar as he
holds that entities are meaningful by virtue of appearing within a whole
consisting of both relations between objects and relations between people.
For this reason, Heidegger’s position can also be characterised as a form of
holism. Roughly, this is the thesis that the meaning of the parts (entities)
depends on the whole (the world). A common objection to holism is that it
leads to a form of relativism. In traditional terms, holism states that an
attitude depends on an entire system of attitudes. If this is true, two people
can only have the same attitude if they share the exact same system of
attitudes. Yet, so the objection goes, this is very unlikely. We are, after all,
raised in different ways, engaged in different personal projects, and we,
therefore, cannot be assumed to possess the exact same information about
the world. The same objection can easily be translated into Heideggerian
terms: If our understanding depends on a relational whole, and if two
people, qua their facticity, necessarily find themselves embedded within
different relational wholes, then these two people are bound to understand
entities in different ways.
Using the term ‘understanding of being’ to refer to this relational
structure that guides or shapes our comportment towards entities (cf.
SZ, /, /; GA, /; GA, /f ), it seems that different
people have different understandings of being. But if this is the case, it
seems that interpretative differences cannot be reconciled, since it would
be impossible to do so by reference to the common ground of a realm of
brute facts, and since it would be impossible to translate two divergent
interpretations into each other, assuming that such translation could only
be done piecemeal in which case my interpretation of some entity would
necessarily be informed by my understanding of being, while your
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
interpretation of the same entity would necessarily be informed by your
understanding of being. It seems, then, that Heidegger’s holism entails a
form of relativism.
This chapter aims to clarify the nature of Heidegger’s holism and its two
directions of context-sensitivity. I argue that Heidegger’s externalist con-
ception of intentionality puts us into relation with others – including those
with whom we do not share an understanding of being – in a way that does
not lead to a vicious relativism.
In Section ., I outline two prominent interpretations of Heidegger’s
holism. The first interpretation is found in Lafont’s work on what she calls
Heidegger’s linguistic idealism. According to this interpretation,
Heidegger is a social externalist since he believes that meaning depends
on one’s linguistic community and an object internalist since he takes
linguistic meaning to fully determine what a subject can intend and refer
to. The other interpretation, the pragmatic conventionalist interpretation
(PCI), argues, first, that Heidegger is an object externalist since he takes
pragmatic engagement with tools to be the paradigmatic form of inten-
tionality and, second, that he is a social externalist since proper tool use is
determined by collective social practices. Despite their differences, I argue
that both interpretations give rise to charges of relativism like the one just
outlined because they both take Heidegger to be committed to the claim
that meaning depends on some kind of social convention. Section . calls
this assumption into question and proposes an alternative reading of
Heidegger’s holism. Drawing on his account of object-awareness – that is,
his account of what it is to thematically intend inert entities – I argue that
the pragmatic interpretation is right in holding that Heidegger is an object
externalist and a social externalist since he believes that our engagements
with objects like tools constitutively depend on backgrounded relations to
other people or what I’ll call non-thematic other-awareness. Against the two
lines of interpretation, however, I argue that Heidegger does not restrict
such non-thematic other-awareness to those with whom we share conven-
tions. In Section ., I thus go on to argue that Heidegger’s social
externalism is much more dynamic than usually believed and that he holds
that we share the world with whomever is there because we, to borrow a
phrase from Davidson, constantly triangulate our understanding of objects
with the behaviour of others. Finally, in Section ., I show that this
reading of Heidegger’s holism enables us to dispel the relativistic worries
often associated with holism and that his account of object and social
externalism allows us to intend the same entity even with people that do
not share our understanding of being.
Holism and Relativism
Lafont speaks of semantic externalism and social externalism rather than object externalism and social
externalism (Lafont ). I largely agree with her characterisation of the two positions. In her
words, the former is the ‘thesis that concepts are not individuated by the understanding of the
speakers who use them, but are partly individuated by their referents’, whereas the latter is the ‘thesis
that concepts are not individuated by the understanding of the individual speakers who use them,
but are partly individuated by other speakers’ (Lafont , ). Nonetheless, I find her use of the
term ‘semantic externalism’ misleading for two reasons. As we will see briefly, it is questionable that
Heidegger’s primary concern is to develop a semantic theory in the traditional sense of a theory that
assigns semantic contents to linguistic expressions. Second, the term semantic externalism usually
just means that the meanings of words depend on our relations to either the physical or social
environment and, hence, covers both object externalism and social externalism.
Holism and Relativism
externalist, that is, a proponent of the idea that intentional content is
individuated by the (linguistic) community rather than the individual, and
an object internalist, who holds that the meaning of intentional states is a
function of elements internally accessible to the (linguistically extended)
subject rather than external factors. To share a world is, accordingly, to
belong to the same linguistic community. ‘[T]he world in which Dasein
lives must be an expressible system of relations in order to be sharable with
others as the same world’ (Lafont b, ).
Dreyfus and Spinosa do, in fact, suggest that ‘it makes sense to talk of some internally consistent
unity like a kind that is outside any world’ (Dreyfus & Spinosa , ), but as Wrathall has argued
‘to insist that the universe itself works in incompatible ways would threaten that unity, since if we
find that something can be truly described as both p and not-p, we must either deny the principle of
non-contradiction or conclude that there is more than one object involved’ (Wrathall , ).
This means that Dreyfus and Spinosa, threatened by inconsistency, are forced to give up their claim
to an ontic unity outside any world and thereby embrace a form of pragmatic relativism.
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
object externalism, for example, natural kind externalism, according to
which at least some of our references are determined by the object’s
physical microstructure or by the object’s causal history. Presumably,
natural kind externalism would enable intercommunal references, but this
option is not available to Heidegger or his pragmatist interpreters.
It seems, then, that Heidegger’s holism leads to an ontological relativism
where the understandings of being handed over to us by our culture or
society fully determine how we discover entities. This social externalism
determines whom we share the world with to the extent that those raised
according to different pragmatic or linguistic conventions can be said to
live in worlds entirely different from our own.
Heidegger never offers an account of when we are epistemically justified in believing that we intend
an entity with someone. He is in general quite dismissive of epistemological issues due to his focus
on the b-side of the a as b-formula. As Golob rightly notes, ‘Heidegger has focused intensely on the
question of how we can intend any entity; indeed, his whole theory is intended as an account of the
transcendental conditions on such. But he has said little about the question of how we intend this
entity as opposed to that’ (Golob , ).
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
ourselves in unconcealment, we have something in common that is not a
piece of the chalk and likewise not something that can be the possession of
an individual. (GA, )
This dense passage continuously uses the formulation ‘wir teilen uns in’.
This requires a bit of unfolding. The German phrase ‘wir teilen uns’ means
that we share something equally. For instance, ‘wir teilen uns die
Aufgaben’ means that we share the tasks. Relatedly, ‘wir teilen in etwas’
means that we share in something, as when you share in the success of
something. The expression ‘wir teilen uns auf’, on the other hand, means
that we are (or should be) splitting up. As already pointed out, the word
teilen means both to share and to divide, and Heidegger constantly alludes
to this ambiguity. The problem is that ‘wir teilen uns in’ is not a common
German idiom, but a phrase coined by Heidegger. It means, literally, that
we ourselves are divided in some element. As I read it, Heidegger uses the
phrase to combine the jointness condition, that is, that we are related or
united in sharing something equally, and the differentiation condition,
according to which we each intend the entity in our own way and have
thus somehow split up. My (inelegant) solution is to translate the phrase
‘wir teilen uns in. . .’ to ‘we share and divide ourselves in. . .’
The central claim of the passage is, then, that we share and divide
ourselves in the unconcealment or truth of entities. Whenever Dasein
intends an entity, it does so by disclosing it within a field of possibilities
shaped by its upbringing in certain social practices and its own personal
preferences, but in intending the entity Dasein is also non-thematically
aware that the entity is also (potentially) given to others in such a way that
the entity – as a pole of our joint object-awareness – can be disclosed
differently. The entity relates and separates us at the same time.
This leaves ample room for both the jointness condition and the
differentiation condition. Two Dasein can intend the same object in
roughly similar ways if they share an understanding of being by being
raised in the same social practices. In this case, they would share the
experience of, say, a single lectern even though they would comport
themselves to it in slightly different ways due to their different spatial
and social positions. But two Dasein can also intend the same object even
if they do not share an understanding of being. In this case, they would
still share the experience of a single entity even though one could conceive
of it as a lectern while the other conceives of it as a shield against arrows.
Despite their differences, they still intend the same object. The reason for
this is not that one Dasein (say, the German Professor) suddenly has access
to the ‘mind’ of the other Dasein (the Senegalese) and can compare their
Holism and Relativism
respective ‘mental states’ from a point of nowhere. Rather, the jointness is
satisfied by the transcendental condition according to which it is a neces-
sary constraint on each of their respective interpretations that they take the
object to be a potential object of use for the other as well. For each the
saliences of the object are correlated with the other’s behaviour and
vice versa.
In the next section, I will unfold in more detail exactly which type of
relation holds between two Dasein that intends the same object while not
sharing an understanding of being. Before doing so, let us recap how this
discussion of what it is to share unconcealment relates to the issue
of externalism.
First, Heidegger does not take object-awareness to be settled solely by
factors available to the individual subject. Rather, when we intend an
object, we are put into relation with an environmental thing, which we
always understand in terms of its potential use. Intentionality depends in
this sense on our physical environment even if Heidegger rejects that
references are, in the end, settled by physicalist descriptions. This makes
Heidegger an object externalist in the pragmatic sense.
Second, whenever we intend entities, we are aware that they are
entrusted to mutual use. By mutual use, Heidegger means that the same
entity can figure in different types of comportment, that is, that the same a
can be intended as several b’s. It follows that understandings of being do
not exhaust our relations or references to entities even if we cannot intend
an entity without an understanding of being. It is intrinsic to unconceal-
ment that an entity can figure in several distinct understandings of being.
In Heidegger’s words, ‘we do not disjoint [zerteilen] and distribute [vertei-
len] the entity, rather we leave it undivided [ungeteilt]’ (GA, ). This
contradicts Lafont’s claim that Heidegger takes meaning to determine
reference and the idea that an understanding of being comes with its
own body of entities.
Third, Heidegger’s discussion of object-awareness shows that he does
indeed believe that intentionality is fundamentally social. But in contrast
to the strong social externalism of Lafont and PCI, Heidegger endorses a
weak or open-ended social externalism according to which meaning depends
on ongoing social interaction rather than stable social conventions or
practices. In object-awareness, we are non-thematically aware that the
This is why I agree with Carman that Heidegger is committed to the idea that nature is ‘minimally
accessible to us’ as extending beyond our respective interpretations of it (Carman , ). See
also note above.
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
same a can led to b. . .n even if our tacit conventions dispose us to see a as b.
Unconcealment makes entities available to a plurality of different usages.
Schmid has a very different reading of these passages in GA. On his view, Heidegger effectively
‘rejects the idea that inter-intentional givenness of this thing lies in its use within some joint activity’
(Schmid , ). When Heidegger says that the commonality of an intentional object is prior to
our usage – that it is founded in a ‘lettings things be’ (GA, ) – Schmid takes him to claim that
sociality is ultimately only to be found in our awareness of things as occurrent, which, he argues, is a
derivative form of intentionality compared to our disclosure as things as available. This leads him to
the conclusion that ‘Heidegger seems to keep the innermost of intentionality clear of sociality’
(Schmid , ). I do not think that the textual evidence supports this conclusion. In fact,
Schmid seems to turn Heidegger’s argument on its head. Not only does Heidegger endorse the idea
that a ‘mutual use’ [gemeinsame Gebrauch] is possible and, hence, that practical comportment can be
joint, he even shows that the most basic form of object-awareness – a form prior to the distinction
between practical and theoretical comportments – is constitutively open to others. Consider, for
instance, the following paragraph, which Schmid wrongly takes to support his conclusion:
‘This dividing in something first appeared to us in the form of a mutual entrusting of something
in use. But it turned out that already without making use of something, we jointly have entities,
present things, available things [Seiendes, Vorhandenes, Vorliegendes] lying in front of us in a certain way,
so that this sharing in something in being-with-each-other by something present [Vorhandenen]
cannot lie in the fulfillment of usage itself, but rather in a way of being of Dasein that already lies
before all usage and which makes the mutual usage of something possible in the first place’. (GA,
, my italics)
On Schmid’s reading, the central part of the passage is the claim that joint comportment only
discloses entities as Vorhandenes. He takes this as evidence that jointness is only possible in the
derivative form of intentionality that discloses entities as occurrent rather than available. The
problem is, however, that Heidegger a few pages later notes that he does not use the term
Vorhandenes in the technical sense known from SZ. He only uses it in the broad sense of ‘things
in contrast to Dasein’ (GA, ). For this reason, the passage claims that a form of jointness or
shared availability is prior to any idiosyncratic usage of an object. Heidegger does not, pace Schmid,
keep the innermost of intentionality clear of sociality.
Holism and Relativism
A little later, he elaborates:
Yet, if Dasein and Dasein never exist next to each other, then this means:
Each has, as essentially stepping-outside, already stepped into the manifes-
tation of the other. They necessarily carry themselves in the same sphere of
manifestation, even if they do not concern themselves with each as Da-sein
[sic]. To imply this, as Dasein, means: They communicate [mitteilen] with
entities of their own kind. In the nature of Da-sein lies being-with, even if
no other entity in fact exists. Dasein already brings with it the sphere of
possible neighbourship; it is from the outset already neighbour to . . .;
whereas two stones, for example, cannot be neighbouring. In being-with,
however, already lies the giving-free and giving-away of the Da – as
manifest broken-open-ness [offenbarer Aufgebrochenheit], in which entities
can appear, in turn, in accordance with their kind. (GA, )
The point put forward in these passages is that two Dasein, whether they
share conventions or not, share a world whenever they are phenomeno-
logically present to each other. This follows a priorily from the holistic
nature of human understanding: Whoever is ‘there’ is incorporated into
the relational whole that forms the interpretative background of our
understanding. Others have a say, however small, in how we understand
the world. In contrast to the stones, two Dasein cannot be completely
indifferent to each other. Even if they are not thematically concerned or
aware of each other but look at something else – Heidegger uses the term
‘being at . . .’ to refer to this intentional rather than spatial relation – they
have already stepped into each other’s realm of manifestation. They already
affect how the other intends the object.
The second passage describes this non-thematic other-awareness as a
form of communication. This requires a bit of unpacking because we tend
to think of communication as the exchange of fully formed linguistic
utterances. Yet, the communication described here is not linguistic in this
narrow sense. It is, after all, something that the two Dasein necessarily
partake in whenever they exist next to each other. Instead, Heidegger’s
point is that whenever another Dasein shows up in my realm of manifes-
tation, his behaviour (linguistic or otherwise) will affect how I comport
myself towards the surrounding entities. By the mere presence of the other,
I come to share the world with him – even if only in the minimal sense
that I come to see things as potential objects of use for him and not just for
me.
Merleau-Ponty makes a similar point when he writes:
The communication or comprehension of gestures comes about through
the reciprocity of my intentions and the gestures of the others, of my
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
gestures and intentions discernible in the conduct of other people. . . . The
gesture which I witness outlines an intentional object. This object is
genuinely present and fully comprehended when the powers of my body
adjust themselves to it and overlap it. The gesture presents itself to me as a
question, bringing certain perceptible bits of the world to my notice, and
inviting my concurrence in them. Communication is achieved when my
conduct identifies this path with its own. (Merleau-Ponty , )
In Merleau-Ponty’s description, communication is gestural rather than
strictly linguistic. The other’s gestures ‘outline an intentional object’ in
the sense that I join him in his awareness of the object. This affects not
only what I see but also how I see it. The communication succeeds when
‘the powers of my body’ adjust themselves to both the intended object and
the fact that the other also intends it. In this case, the object becomes an
object for us and our powers rather than just for me and my powers. This is
why Merleau-Ponty in the same paragraph suggests that everything hap-
pens ‘as if the other person’s intention inhabited my body and mine his’
(Merleau-Ponty , ). A non-thematic awareness of the other guides
my awareness of the world.
Merleau-Ponty tends to stress how the two co-intenders act as a unity
effectively forming a single body in the form of what we might call an
‘intercorporeal self’, but Heidegger’s account of socially responsive fields of
possibilities also covers more agonistic relations. As Heidegger occasionally
puts it, being-with enables both our being-with-each-other [Miteinandersein]
and our being-against-each-other [Gegen- or Widereinandersein] (e.g., GA,
/; SZ, /, /; GA, f/). Consider, for instance, a
football player who, after a pass unexpected by the defence, can dribble
freely towards the goal. Now, suddenly and without him thinking about it, a
shadow appears at the perimeter of his perceptual field. The defender is by
no means a thematic object of the striker, yet his behaviour communicates
to the striker that he should move in the other direction from where he can
take a shot at the goal without fear of being tackled. The defender trans-
forms how the striker understands the playing field so that the striker is pre-
reflectively drawn to a different path.
When Heidegger, in the second quote above, speaks of the ‘the giving-
free and giving-away of the Da’ and the ‘manifest broken-open-ness’
(GA, ), he has this kind of responsiveness in mind. Being-with
means that we experience entities in relation to the behaviour of others,
as available for mutual use. This is a ‘broken-open-ness’ [Ausgebrochenheit],
because we are constitutively open towards others in this way, because they
step into and alter our realm of manifestation whether we like it or not.
Holism and Relativism
Returning to the initial formulation of joint attention, I remarked above
that it was not obvious how Heidegger’s claim that ‘one comports oneself
in the same way as the other’ complies with the differentiation condition
(GA, ). We can now see more clearly what he meant. The suggestion
is not that we have the exact same attitude (i.e., that both striker and
defender intend to shoot at the same goal to score for the same team and so
on) but that we comport ourselves in ontologically similar ways, that is, that
two people must both be constitutively open or responsive to the behav-
iour of others qua the holistic and temporal structure of their
understanding if they are to intend objects together. This complies with
the differentiation condition since the same transcendental structure, as
Heidegger understands it, is configured differently in accordance with the
thrownness or facticity of the individuals.
So, on the one hand, intentionality depends on social relations insofar as
we constantly adjust our understanding of objects in light of the behaviour
of other people. On the other hand, intentionality depends on objective
relations insofar as we constantly adjust our understanding of other people
in light of our shared environment. This way of putting things reveals just
how close Heidegger’s point is to Davidson’s idea of triangulation.
Triangulation, as Davidson uses the term, involves two creatures and an
object. Taken together, these three elements constitute a shared physical
environment. The idea is, then, that the two creatures ‘triangulate’ or
correlate each other’s behaviour with the physical environment in order to
make sense of each other. Through triangulation, they understand which
stimuli trigger which response. This process enables each of them to
understand the responses of the other. However, it also enables each
creature to discern the objective stimuli that cause its own responses, since
the triangulation with the other creature enables it to locate the stimulus in
a shared environment where it exists independently of its own mind.
Given that we cannot tell what is subjective without any notion of what
is objective, triangulation makes it possible for us to ‘know our own mind’,
as Davidson puts it (, Chapter ). The central idea behind triangu-
lation, which is shared by both Davidson and Heidegger, is that the two
directions of context-sensitivity belong together and that such context-
sensitivity is a necessary condition for having intentional states.
Davidson conjoins these two directions of externalism by invoking the
principle of charity. To understand the other, we must, first, ‘take the
speaker to be responding to the same feature of the world’ that we, as
interpreters, would respond to under similar circumstances (Davidson
, ). In addition, we must ‘discover a degree of logical consistency
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
in the thought of the speaker’ (Davidson , ). That is, we must
assume that the other’s attitude largely coheres with both the other
attitudes reasonably attributed to the other and with our own attitudes,
and we must assume that the other’s attitude depends causally on objects
in the world.
Davidson stresses that his argument
does not require (though of course it allows) a shared routine, but it does
depend on the interaction of at least two speaker-interpreters, for if I am
right, there would be no saying what a speaker was talking or thinking
about, no basis for claiming he could locate objects in an objective space
and time, without interaction with a second person. (Davidson , )
Heidegger agrees with this. We do not need shared conventions, rules, or
routines in order to become intelligible to one another but only this basic
responsiveness in and to a shared environment. Thus, in he contrasts
the agreement of linguistic conventions (and, by extension, all types of
conventions) with what he calls an ‘originary, essential agreement’:
Words emerge from that essential agreement [wesenhaften Übereinkunft] of
human beings with one another, in accordance with which they are open in
their being with one another for the entities around them, which they can
then individually agree about – and this also means fail to agree about. Only
on the grounds of this originary, essential agreement is discourse possible in
its essential function: semainein, giving that which is understandable to
be understood. (GA/, f/)
For both Davidson and Heidegger, conventions are made possible by a basic
form of communication in which two people are jointly oriented towards a
shared environment in such a way that the behaviour of one person can make
certain features of the environment salient to the other person. ‘Essential
agreement’ is Heidegger’s version of Davidson’s principle of charity. It states
that each Dasein – to make sense of the world, of the other, and ultimately of
itself – must assume that the entities that it encounters are available to a
plurality of different usages and that other people comport themselves to the
same entities or range of entities that it does. Two Dasein involved in such
triangulation need not agree on which usage is correct. They can, as
Heidegger writes, fail to agree about this, but only if the essential agreement –
that is, the transcendental condition that they comport themselves in a
roughly similar way to the same entities – is already in place.
It is debated whether Davidson’s principle of charity is an epistemological or ontological principle.
Dreyfus and Charles Taylor have suggested that Davidson’s version of the principle of charity is an
Holism and Relativism
The preceding discussion, however, also shows that Heidegger and
Davidson, despite agreeing that self, other, and world are interdependent,
disagrees about the fundamental nature of intentionality. More specifi-
cally, they disagree about the role of language in triangulation.
For Davidson, triangulation provides the condition of possibility of the
propositional attitudes that are operative in linguistic utterances. It does so
in two ways. First, it enables people to know their own minds, to know
their own propositional attitudes, since ‘only communication with another
can supply an objective check’ and thus enable the person to distinguish
between ‘what is thought to be the case and what is the case’ (Davidson
, f ). Second, triangulation enables a person to attribute proposi-
tional attitudes to another person, because it is only when the observing
person ‘consciously correlates’ the responses of the other person with
objects in the world that it is possible to say that the other person responds
to this rather than that, for example, to the sound of a whistle rather than
an itch (Davidson , ).
Heidegger, on the contrary, rejects the traditional emphasis on propo-
sitional attitudes as is clear from his early (and rather confusing) discussion
of language. SZ suggests that traditional philosophy has taken the assertion
to have a privileged role in our access to the world and that this focus leads
to an occurrent ontology. In his terms, ‘occurrent determination
[Vorhandenheitsbestimmung] is . . . the speciality of assertion’ (SZ, /
). Some commentators take this to imply that the primary mode of
intentionality described by Heidegger is wholly independent of, if not
outright at odds with, a linguistic mode of intentionality. In other places,
however, Heidegger loosens the tight connection between assertion and
epistemological idea, according to which ‘the condition of my understanding you as you think and
act in your terms is that I construe you as making sense in my terms most of the time’ (Dreyfus &
Taylor , ; cf. Taylor ). In comparison, they argue that Gadamer’s equivalent, the fusion
of horizons, is ontological because it suggests that all human beings are always in contact with the
same reality even though they tend to see things differently. Different replies to the charge of
relativism follow from this contrast. The epistemological version of the principle of charity suggests
that an interpreter should simply and to the best of his ability translate the language of the other into
his own pre-existing idiom, while the more radical ontological version holds that understanding is
achieved only when a proper fusion of horizon has taken place thus effectively developing a new and
richer language (Dreyfus & Taylor , ). Others oppose such a reading and hold that
Davidson’s principle is both an ontological presupposition (i.e., the presupposition that two people
share a common world) and a methodological principle (that serves to constrain the possible
interpretations of a given behavioural pattern) (e.g. Malpas , Chapter , ). Heidegger,
on his part, clearly holds that triangulation and his version of the principle of charity is a constitutive,
ontological feature of Dasein qua being-with.
Dreyfus, for instance, writes that our primary level of understanding is ‘non-conceptual, non-
propositional, non-rational and non-linguistic’ (Dreyfus , ).
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
occurrentness by saying, for instance, that there are many ‘intermediate
gradations’ between circumspective understanding and theoretical asser-
tions (SZ, /) and by suggesting that assertions uncover entities as
‘either available or occurrent’ (SZ, /). What is the exact relation
between intentionality and language in (early) Heidegger? Which form of
communication is inherent to this form of triangulation? I cannot discuss
these far-reaching questions in detail here, but I will outline an answer that
enables us to, first, survey the difference between Heidegger and Davidson,
and, second, shed further light on the disagreement between Lafont
and PCI.
The object in Davidson’s analysis of radical interpretation is explicit
linguistic utterances, and when inquiring into the conditions that would
render foreign utterances meaningful to us, he argues that we must assume
these utterances to express a truth. Heidegger’s main interest lies, however,
not in truth-apt assertions but our practical and affective engagement with
the world. As Wrathall has noted, Heidegger would argue that Davidson,
due to his argumentative set-up, errs by ‘reading language’s propositional
structure back into all forms of human comportment’ (Wrathall ,
f ). Heidegger instead aims to account for a much wider range of
phenomena than Davidson. The communication he has in mind is, as
he puts it, ‘existential’ and ‘ontologically broad’ (SZ, /). This means
that rather than focusing directly on linguistic utterances – the totality of
which SZ calls simply language (SZ, /) – Heidegger is interested in
the broader issue of how significance ‘maintains itself in some definite way
of concernful being-with-one-another’ (SZ, /) or, in other words,
how significance is ‘“emphatically” shared’ with others (SZ, /).
Existential communication refers, hence, to the many ways in which our
behaviour not only responds to matrices of salience but also expresses these.
In other words, existential communication makes the matrices of salience,
which guide our comportment, manifest to others. Section . examines
this kind of communication or expression in more detail by analysing
Heidegger’s concept of discourse [Rede], but for now, it suffices to note
that the ontologically broad form of communication that provides the
foundation of Heidegger’s triangulation covers both non-linguistic behav-
iour (such as the gestures and the body-language described by Merleau-
Ponty) and explicit linguistic behaviour (including both performatives and
For helpful discussions of the role of assertions in SZ and its relation to the distinction between
availableness and occurrentness, see the critical discussions in Schear (), McManus (), and
Golob ().
Holism and Relativism
constantives) as well as everything in between (such as laughter and
disconcerted grunts) insofar as these expressions spring from and feed back
into matrices of salience.
As we saw above, the disagreement between Lafont and PCI concerns
the role of language in early Heidegger. To which extent does linguistic
meaning determine reference? Lafont reads the claim that ‘language is the
house of being’ back into the early Heidegger and takes this to mean that
his hermeneutic phenomenology is a form of linguistic constitutionalism
or idealism. The pragmatic conventionalist interpretation, on the other
hand, follows the early Heidegger in reserving the term ‘language’ for
explicit linguistic utterances. At first glance it might seem as if we face
an exclusive disjunction – either intentionality is pervaded by language all
the way down or it is wholly independent of it. Yet, in spelling out
Heidegger’s position we have to be very careful in distinguishing between
the different ways in which he uses the term ‘language’. As already noted,
SZ denies that language in the sense of the totality of linguistic utterances
used by a specific community constitutes intentionality. This alone con-
tradicts Lafont’s claim to linguistic idealism since her argument hinges on
the assumption that the difference between various ontic or natural lan-
guages (such as German or English) amounts to a difference between
understandings of being. Nevertheless, Heidegger’s argument implies that
the primary mode of intentionality is in some sense ‘expressive’ and that it
inherently ‘communicates’ with others. So, if we, on the other hand, use
the term ‘language’ to refer to any meaning articulating structure that is
inherently communicative or expressive, being-in-the-world is always
already a being-in-language (cf. Wrathall , Chapter ).
Heidegger’s holism implies that we constantly triangulate the shared
world with others. Although this form of triangulation often involves the
exchange of linguistic utterances, it does not necessarily do so. It is not
conditioned by shared linguistic conventions. Triangulation does, how-
ever, involve ‘communication’ in the ontologically broad sense: Dasein
constantly responds to and thereby expresses to others the particular
matrices of salience that it comports itself towards, and it constantly
responds to the matrices of salience expressed by the behaviour of others.
In the following, I will avoid the ambiguous term ‘language’ whenever
possible. Instead, I will use the terms ‘expression’ and ‘communication’ to
See also Guignon’s claim that for Heidegger ‘the articulation of intelligibility embedded in our
public languages extends across all dimensions of Dasein’s being’ so that ‘there is no exit from the
maze of language’ (, ).
Being-In-the-World And Being-With
refer to the (ontologically broad) way in which all purposeful behaviour has
the potential of making certain possibilities salient for other people.
Henceforth, the term ‘linguistic utterances’ refers to overt speech acts,
and ‘natural language’ refers to the totality of words and linguistic utter-
ances that are used by a specific and ontically identifiable community of
speakers. In this sense, linguistic utterances are (somewhat pace
Heidegger’s worry about assertions) for the most part expressive, but
expression and communication go beyond the exchange of linguistic
utterances. Seen in this light, the problem with Davidson’s account – as
well as Lafont’s critique of Heidegger – is that it takes linguistic utterances
to be the paradigm of meaningful communication, whereas Heidegger
broadens the scope of the argument to include all forms of expression.
Interpersonal Understanding
Forms of Being-With
understanding appropriate to non-Dasein-like entities like hammers and
stones?
In posing these questions, we enter the domain of social cognition.
Heidegger was highly critical of the theories of social cognition of his time,
and he would be equally critical of the theories of social cognition currently
in vogue. I thus start by outlining the historical and contemporary debates
on social cognition, so that we can more easily map the positions that
Heidegger opposes (Section .). I then reconstruct the arguments that he
did (or could have) formulated against these positions (Section .).
Drawing on these arguments, I spell out four conditions for a successful
theory of social cognition that I argue are all satisfied by the concept of
‘transpositioning’ developed in Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics
(Section .). I, then, consider (and reject) the claim that our ability to
recognise others as Dasein constitutes something like a Heideggerian ethics
(Section .) before I finally discuss how our understanding of nonhuman
animals compares to interpersonal understanding (Section .).
Husserl often uses the term empathy, but he also finds it problematic for the reasons identified below
(cf. Husserl a, ff ). Scheler completely rejected the term empathy in order to avoid confusing
his own approach with Lipps’. Instead, he talks of Nachfühlen, which is sometimes translated into
Forms of Being-With
from the details of his account. Specifically, they take issue with the idea
that empathy requires a form of imitation on several grounds. First, the
model of imitation presupposes that I am already familiar with the con-
nection between bodily process and emotion before I can recognise it in
someone else. Yet, as Scheler points out, ‘we can understand the experience
of animals, though even in “tendency” we cannot imitate their manner of
expression; for instance when a dog expresses its joy by barking and
wagging its tail, or a bird by twittering’ (Scheler , ). It seems, then,
that we can understand other creatures even when we do not recognise
their expressions from ourselves and when we cannot imitate the gesture.
Second, Stein argues that empathy does not require that I undergo the
same experience as the other. Instead, empathy is characterised by a
fundamental difference between the experience of the empathiser and
the experience of the object of empathy. Empathy requires a distinction
between self and other that Lipps, on Stein’s reading, glosses over.
Arguably, Lipps describes the wrong phenomenon by mistaking empathy
(Einfühlung) for a feeling-of-oneness (Einsfühlung) (Stein , f ).
Third, the phenomenologists criticise Lipps for presupposing what he is
supposed to prove, namely, our basic recognition of other creatures as
minded. The problem is that Lipps’ theory presupposes that we can
successfully distinguish between those bodily movements that are expres-
sive of mental states (e.g., the clinching of a fist) and those bodily
movements that are not expressive of mental states (e.g., a rock tumbling
down a mountain side). For Lipps, this is the initial stimulus that triggers
our instinct for imitation. Yet, this basic capacity for recognising other
creatures as minded is what needs clarification. As Scheler notes, ‘imitation,
even as a mere “tendency”, already presupposes some kind of acquaintance
with the other’s experience, and therefore cannot explain what it is here
supposed to do’ (Scheler , )
“vicarious feeling” or “reproduced feeling.” These translations are, however, misleading since
Scheler’s point is exactly, pace Lipps, that we do not replicate the experience undergone by the
other. “In Nachfühlen we sense the quality of the other’s feeling, without it being transmitted to us,
or evoking a similar emotion in us” (Scheler , ). Despite these terminological hesitations,
I follow Zahavi () in classifying both Husserl’s, Stein‘s, and Scheler’s respective positions as
empathy theories.
Karsten Stueber argues that Stein‘s reading of Lipps is uncharitable and that Lipps does indeed take
self-other distinction to be a necessary part of empathy (Stueber , ), but even if we grant this
point, Lipps’ theory still seems to conflate empathy with what is today called emotional sharing, that
is, a case where several subjects share isomorphic emotional states while maintaining self/other
distinction. For a taxonomy of social emotions, see Scheler (, ff ); for a contemporary
discussion of the distinction between emotional sharing and empathy, see Zahavi and Rochat
().
Interpersonal Understanding
Phenomenological theories of empathy claim that our knowledge of
others requires neither inference nor simulation. Instead, empathy is a sui
generis type of intentional act that provides us with direct access to others’
mental states in a perception-like way (e.g., Stein , ). We ‘believe
ourselves to be directly acquainted with another person’s joy in his laughter,
with his sorrow and pain in his tears’ (Scheler , , my italics). There
is some disagreement in the phenomenological tradition about how exactly
to describe the relation between the empathiser and the object of empathy.
Scheler argues that ‘everyone can apprehend the experience of his fellow-
men just as directly (or indirectly) as he can his own’ (Scheler , ),
while Stein and Husserl believe that the relation is essentially asymmetrical
because the empathiser has a ‘primordial [originär]’ access to her own
mental states that she lacks when it comes to the mental life of the other.
As an experience of a foreign consciousness, empathy is defined by Stein as
‘the non-primordial experience which announces a primordial one’ (Stein
, ). Nevertheless, what is common to phenomenological empathy
theories is that they conceive of empathy neither as inference nor reso-
nance but as a form of direct perception.
() Theories of social cognition tend to reduce the other to the self.
Heidegger claims that empathy conceives of interpersonal understanding in
such a way that the relation one has towards others ‘becomes a projection
[Projektion] of one’s own being toward oneself “into an other”’ (SZ, /
, my italics). This suggests that in empathy we primarily understand
ourselves only to transfer this understanding into the other. But then the
other becomes a mere ‘duplicate of the self’ (SZ, /), because we, as
empathisers, only find in the other what we have put there ourselves. On
this model, the empathiser E simulates a set of mental states M that are then
projected into the object of empathy O. In this case, however, E only ever
reaches his own mental states, ME, rather than the mental states of O, MO.
Heidegger here construes empathy as an emotional simulation, where
the self understands the other mind by constructing a model of what the
object feels or thinks in a situation out of its own psychological mecha-
nisms. Understood historically, the target is clearly Lipps, as Heidegger
also indicates by referring to the term projection. Today, Goldman’s
description of social cognition as ‘simulation-plus-projection’ (Goldman
, ) also seems to fit the bill.
() Theories of social cognition tend to reduce the self to the other.
Elsewhere, Heidegger argues the reverse point by saying that some theories
reduce the self to the other by requiring that we substitute ourselves for the
Interpersonal Understanding
object of empathy, that we ‘take its place’ and imagine that we are in the
others’ shoes (e.g., GA/, /). This shift in perspective requires,
however, that ‘we could somehow vacate our own position and directly fill
out and occupy the place of that [other] entity’ (GA/, /).
While formulated rather polemically, Heidegger’s point is that some
theories of social cognition require that the empathiser has identical mental
states to the object of empathy, that the empathiser reproduces the mental
states of the other as if they were his or her own. E would then substitute
his own mental states, ME, for the mental states of O, MO. In contrast,
Heidegger says that there can be no understanding of the other if the one
who wishes to understand ‘relinquishes himself in advance’ (GA/,
/). He firmly believes that social cognition implies self/other-
distinction.
Heidegger’s use of references is, as always, sparing. He might have in
mind Kant’s second paralogism, which holds that ‘[i]t is obvious that if one
wants to represent a thinking being, one must put oneself in its place, and
thus substitute one’s own subject for the object one wants to consider’
(Kant , A–A). Alternatively, Heidegger might simply be mak-
ing the same point as the one we saw Stein make against Lipps, when she
charged him for confusing Einfühlung with Einsfühlung, empathy with a
feeling-of-oneness. In the contemporary debate, some simulation theorists
do insist that social cognition requires the substitution of the self for the
other. Gordon, for instance, believes that empathy requires not a transfer-
ring of a mental state from one person to another but a personal transfor-
mation (Gordon , ) in which the empathiser, as a distinct
individual, ‘cease[s] to be the referent of the first person pronoun’ in such
a way that his or her personal characteristics are ‘out of the picture
altogether’ (Gordon , ). In contrast to (), the aim of simulation
is that I imagine that I am you rather than you are me.
() Theories of social cognition tend to presuppose the phenomenon that they
are supposed to explain.
In a lecture course from , Heidegger claims that
[t]he idea of empathy and projection already presuppose being-with the
other and the being of the other with me. Both already presuppose that one
has already understood the other as another human being; otherwise,
I would be projecting something into the void. (GA, /)
The point is that we can only empathically project something into the
other if we are already aware that the entity in front of us possesses
intentional states. If we lacked this basic understanding, we might as well
project mental states into coffee cups and tables. From this point of view, it
seems that empathy presupposes the phenomenon that it is supposed to
explain, namely, our basic recognition of other people as minded creatures.
This line of argument seems to target Lipps and, in a contemporary
context, simulation theory, but not Heidegger’s fellow phenomenologists.
Above we saw Scheler make the same argument against Lipps.
One might object that Heidegger misses an obvious third commitment that might also support the
idea that the dyadic relation is foundational: Empirical evidence shows that the infant-caretaker
relation is developmentally crucial. This suggests that reciprocal relations between child and parent is
developmentally prior to various group formations. In reply, we should recall two things. First, the
issue being discussed here is not which phenomena is developmentally prior but whether the dyadic
relation is logically or explanatorily prior to the relation to the shared world. Second, Heidegger does
not endorse the collectivist thesis that a sense of us (e.g., a unity or fusion between child and caretaker)
is prior to the self/other distinction. These points help us formulate Heidegger’s retort: The point is
that the self/other distinction logically presupposes that self and other share a world, that is, that there
is a common medium in which self and other can understand each other. In Chapter , I argue that
once we have the basic structure of a fundamentally shared world in which agents act pre-reflectively
and purposefully, we also have the possibility of the agents acting pre-reflectively and purposefully
together. This is the case, I believe, even if robust forms of collectivism (i.e., the sense of us of group
biases) are developmental latecomers compared to reciprocal recognition.
Forms of Being-With
approach to the issue as supported by such quasi-Cartesian commitments.
According to him, Husserl’s conception of empathy fails () because it
remains bound to an idealist and egological sphere, and () because it
remains oriented towards ‘pure thing- and data-experience rather than
concrete relations of existence’ (GA, ).
If we abandon these commitments, we must, according to Heidegger,
also abandon the idea that the dyadic relation is foundational. As we saw,
Heidegger does indeed oppose both of them. He endorses a holistic
conception of the mind and takes practical comportment to be the
paradigmatic form of intentionality. Instead of grasping sociality by adding
a special mental operation to a preconceived self, Heidegger argues that our
understanding of others is cut from the same holistic cloth as our under-
standing of ourselves. ‘Since in understanding world the relations of the in-
order-to, of involvement and for-the-sake-of are understood, it is essen-
tially self-understanding . . .. Contained in this, again, there is the under-
standing of being-with-others’ (GA, f/). As a holistically
constituted world-enmeshed agent, the self is already radically out there
among others in a way that is presupposed by rather than derived from the
face-to-face relation.
. Transpositioning
Taking stock, points ()–() are most likely formulated with Lipps’
empathy theory and Mill’s argument from analogy in mind, but
Heidegger’s critique also applies to the contemporary debate between
theory theory and simulation theory. Somewhat surprisingly, Heidegger
rejects inference and simulation on the same ground as Husserl, Scheler,
and Stein. It would, however, be wrong to count Heidegger among the
phenomenological empathy theorists. He believes that his fellow phenom-
enologists fail to completely deconstruct the Cartesian conception of the
subject because they take the face-to-face relationship between two
embodied subjects to be intelligible apart from its practical engagement
in a physical and social environment. In this sense, Heidegger is closer to
modern-day enactivism. Finally, Heidegger opposes the claim, widespread
Despite the similarities between him and Heidegger (see note above), Schütz remains loyal to
Husserl’s second path in claiming that the face-to-face relation is foundational for social life (e.g.,
Schütz , ). This causes him to claim that other social formations, like that of anonymous
social norms, are secondary to and derived from face-to-face relations, while Heidegger maintains
that a truly phenomenological approach sees the face-to-face relations as unintelligible apart from a
shared context and as already imbued with social norms.
Interpersonal Understanding
also among contemporary phenomenologists, that empathy is foundational
for social life on the ground that this leads to a problematic social
ontological layer theory (cf. Section .).
From this discussion, we can distil four conditions that a successful
theory of social cognition must satisfy according to Heidegger:
() The immediacy condition: Social cognition must be so construed as to
account for the fact that we ordinarily understand other minds in an
immediate or quasi-perceptual way.
() The minded/non-minded discrimination condition: Social cognition
must be so construed as to account for our basic distinction between
minded and non-minded entities.
() The world dependency condition: Social cognition must be so con-
strued as to account for the fact that we understand other minds as
constitutively dependent on and in interaction with their physical
and social environment.
() The alterity condition: Social cognition must be so construed as to
account for the fact that we must neither adapt the perspective of
others on the world nor reduce it to our own perspective.
Before turning to each of these four conditions in detail, I’ll describe
Heidegger’s approach in broad strokes, drawing partly on the above
interpretation of existential projection and selfhood and partly on sections
from GA/.
In my account, Dasein is not simply a name for the individual human
being. The self of Dasein does not necessarily refer to the I ‘as this factical
individual’, to ‘the individual I-ness, of my self’ (GA, /).
Selfhood, in Heidegger’s existential sense, does not take selves to be
individual discrete entities. Instead, existential selfhood is a specific type
of reference – the for-the-sake-of – that structures a relational whole of
significance. These self-references ensure that a field of possibilities is
always significant to someone, that they are anchored in a self that cares
about what and how it is in the world, in an entity ‘that in its being has
this very being as an issue’ (SZ, /).
Often the disclosed possibilities are simply significant to me as an
individual. They appear as possibilities that I can choose to realise.
Interestingly, however, Heidegger occasionally suggests that possibilities
can also be disclosed as significant to someone else, to another individual
human agent or group of human agents. SZ thus tells us that ‘[i]n being-
with, as the existential “for-the-sake-of” of others, these have already been
disclosed in their Dasein’ (SZ, /). Elsewhere, he emphasises that
Forms of Being-With
Dasein is not a term for the individual but a term for existential selfhood
and that ‘self can be said equally of the I and the you: “I-myself”, “you-
yourself”’ (GA, /). For instance, I might understand a hammer as
salient to a carpenter building a fence. While significance requires both in-
order-to’s and for-the-sake-of’s, the for-the-sake-of’s need not point in my
direction, so to speak. Sartre might have something like this in mind when
he describes the appearance of another person in a park as a ‘decentraliza-
tion of the world which undermines the centralization which I am simul-
taneously effecting’, because everything is now also conceived as significant
to the other (Sartre , ).
For Heidegger, personal pronouns like I, you, and he do not mainly refer
to discrete entities. Instead, they are ‘adverbs of Dasein [Daseinsadverbien]’
(GA, /). By this, he means to say that we understand ourselves
and others as different modifications of the same whole of significance, as
different constellations of in-order-to relations and for-the-sake-of rela-
tions. So, when I understand an entity as a he, I do so because I understand
this entity as relating to its environment as significant, that is, as soliciting
responses from the entity in a way that matters to the entity in question. In
this way, interpersonal understanding cannot be a relation between two
distinct entities. It can only take place by virtue of the transcendence of the
shared world in which I and you coexist as different polarisations of a field
of possibilities (cf. Wrathall , ). It is in and through transcendence
that ‘it first becomes possible to distinguish among entities and to decide
who and in what way a “self” is, and what is not a “self”’ (GA, /f ).
In GA/, Heidegger uses the term transposedness or, more dynami-
cally, transpositioning [Versetztheit] for the process in which we come to
understand other minded agents. The term Versetztheit comes from the
verb versetzen, which means to put, transfer, or displace something. It
resonates with the term übersetzen, the German word for translate.
Transpositioning is, for Heidegger, the process through which the world
as a field of possibilities is reconfigured in interpersonal encounters. As
such, transpositioning is not an ontological latecomer compared to a prior
solitary being-in-the-world (as being-for-others is for Sartre according to
whom the ‘other’s existence has the nature of a contingent and irreducible
fact’ [Sartre , ]). Rather, transpositioning enacts or fulfils the
transcendental condition of being-with.
Heidegger describes transpositioning by saying that in it
the other entity is precisely supposed to remain what it is and how it is.
Transposing oneself into this entity means going along with what it is and
with how it is. Such going-along-with [Mitgehen] means immediately
Interpersonal Understanding
experiencing how it is with this entity, discovering what it is like to be this
entity with which we are going along in this way. Perhaps in doing so we
may even comprehend the other entity more essentially and more incisively
than that entity manages to do on its own. (GA/, f/)
And a little later:
[I]t consists precisely in we ourselves being precisely ourselves, and only in
this way first bringing about the possibility of ourselves being able to go
along with the other entity while remaining other with respect to it. (GA/
, /f )
Taking these two passages as guidelines, we can now see how Heidegger’s
account satisfies the four conditions.
In terms of the immediacy condition, Heidegger explicitly writes that we
immediately experience how it is with this other entity. This underlines that
phenomenologically speaking inference and simulation or indeed quite
rare. Like the phenomenological sense of empathy, transpositioning is
quasi-perceptual in being as direct and immediate as our perception of
tools. We know from the analysis of tools that it requires no cognitive
operations to go from the perception of the hammer to the perception of
the hammer as something to hammer with. In everyday life, our practical
coping with a hammer is prior to a pure, disinterested perception.
Heidegger claims that the same thing holds for our approach to other
people: We do not start with a flurry of unintelligible bodily movements
and then interpret it as purposeful behaviour. In everyday life, we perceive
the other as a minded creature doing things in the world. Any deliberate
reflection on the other’s behaviour only enters if our immediate under-
standing fails for some reason.
Concerning the minded/non-minded discrimination condition, Heidegger
writes that the other is supposed to remain ‘what it is and how it is’. The
what in this formulation concerns our basic ability to distinguish between
minded and non-minded creatures as is clear from the further discussion in
GA/. Here Heidegger discusses whether and how we can transpose
ourselves into human beings, animals, and non-minded objects like stones.
I will return to the issue of nonhuman animals later and for now, focus on
the basic ability to distinguish between Dasein and inert objects
like stones.
Keeping in mind that Dasein is an entity ‘that in its being has this very
being as an issue’ (SZ, /), it is clear that an entity is disclosed as
Dasein if it is disclosed as relating to its physical and social environment as
something significant to it. Significance is, as we have seen, constituted by
Forms of Being-With
in-order-to relations and for-the-sake-of relations. I understand an entity as
Dasein if I understand it as relating to its environment as something that
can be used in order to pursue specific ends that are determined by its care
for its own being. The stone, on the other hand, lack this type of self-
reference; it does not polarise its environment into a matrix of salience.
Dasein can integrate the stone into its specific activities by using it as
means to some end, but we do not ordinarily understand entities like the
stone as having the same type of self-reference as us and therefore we do
not understand entities like the stone as relating to its environment in the
same significant way as us. For entities like the stone ‘their being is “a
matter of indifference”; or more precisely, they “are” such that their being
can be neither a matter of indifference to them, nor the opposite’ (SZ, /
). Minded entities are distinct from non-minded entities because we
only disclose the former based on a for-the-sake-of reference (cf. SZ, /
; GA, /f; GA, /, /). Lacking this type of
self-reference, stones offer no sphere of transposability (GA/, f/
). Human beings, in contrast, ‘already find themselves transposed in
their existence into others’ (GA/, /).
Let us turn to the world dependency condition. In transposing ourselves
into an entity, we do not grasp it independently of our shared surround-
ings. Rather, we ‘go along with’ it. ‘Going-along-with’ indicates that
interpersonal understanding discloses the other within a teleologically
and normatively structured context. I do not merely see the other as being
sad, but as being sad because of something. Similarly, I do not merely see
the other who is standing around doing nothing as an inanimate object
but as someone who has zoned out or as someone who is taking a break
(cf. SZ, /). The other is constitutively related to our shared sur-
roundings, which means that I only understand the other if I can pre-
reflectively correlate his behaviour to the world; if I can interpret his
behaviour as responding to a matrix of salience.
In some places, Heidegger qualifies this point by taking various forms of animism into consideration.
In “myth” and “art” certain objects, which are considered non-minded from a “scientific” point of
view, are experienced as animated [beseelt] (GA/, f/). Yet, this merely underlines the
thesis that our experience of what is minded depends on how we ascribe for-the-sake-of references
rather than, say, the physical microstructure of the entities in question (cf. GA, –).
An objection to this claim is that certain expressions are indeed meaningful without this form of
context. One might argue that when I see lowered eyebrows, squeezed eyes, wrinkled nose, raised
upper lip and so on, I simply see pain without correlating this expression with a cause. I agree that it
is important (qua the immediacy condition) to maintain that any correlation or triangulation must
be pre-reflective in nature. However, I am not sure that we would understand pain if we separated it
from the background understanding granted to us by triangulation. In the case of pain, I think it is
particularly important that we triangulate the other’s expression diachronically. Would we recognise
Interpersonal Understanding
That such going-along-with is a necessary constituent in interpersonal
understanding resonates with the idea of pre-reflective triangulation. In
interpersonal understanding, I triangulate the behaviour of the other with
the environment and myself. In joint attention, two people comport
themselves thematically towards the same object, while being non-
thematically aware that the other person also comports himself towards
the object in a similar manner. In going-along-with, in contrast, one
person comports himself thematically towards another person, while being
non-thematically aware that this other person comports himself themati-
cally towards some object. So, where joint attention is a triangulating
object-awareness, the going-along-with of interpersonal understanding is
a triangulating other-awareness.
The alterity condition states that transpositioning must maintain a dis-
tinction between self and other. It is clear from the passages cited above
that Heidegger certainly does not intend transposition to reduce the other
to the self or the self to the other: ‘[T]he other entity is precisely supposed
to remain what it is and how it is, while we ourselves “[remain] other with
respect to it” (GA/, f/f ). Yet, Levinas, to take just one example,
has famously objected that the alterity of the other must be conceived as an
“opening up which is not being-in-the-world”’ (Levinas , , my
italics). How do we satisfy the alterity condition if our understanding of
ourselves and our understanding of the other are both drawn from the
same medium?
The solution to this problem draws, once again, on the idea of inter-
personal understanding as a pre-reflective triangulation. When one person
transposes himself into another person, he does not adopt the perspective
of the other. Rather, he correlates the other’s behaviour with the world
seen from his own perspective, thereby also slightly altering his own
perspective on the world. Remembering that perspective, in this context,
means practical involvement, we can say that transpositioning succeeds if
the person gets a good interpretative fit between the other’s behaviour and
the world understood as a matrix of salience. The other remains what and
how the other is – a Dasein engaged in existential projections – once we see
a facial expression as pain if we did not tacitly assume it to be preceded by a specific stimulus (the
cause of the pain) and be followed by another type of reaction (expressions of relief )? Would we
recognise said facial expressions as pain if it occurred entirely at random and if it was not followed
by relief but a random emotion ranging from hysterical laughter to complete indifference? Of
course, we might see it as something akin to pain (let us call it pain*), but it seems to me that the
intelligibility of pain* is parasitic on our usual triangulating understanding of pain.
For a discussion of Heidegger’s conception of alterity, see McMullin (, Chapter ).
Forms of Being-With
the other not as, say, an occurrent entity or a self-enclosed transcendental
subject but as a polarisation of the field of possibilities that we ourselves
also polarise.
In this account, the distinction between self and other is neither the
absolute difference between two transcendental subjects nor the absolute
distance between the worldly self and an other-worldly other. The difference
between self and other is the difference between two involved perspectives in a field
of possibilities, two polarisations of the same matrix of salience. Accordingly,
interpersonal understanding does not require that we abandon our perspec-
tive nor that two perspectives merge. Transpositioning opens a single struc-
ture of possibilities in which these perspectives are related but separate. In
understanding another person, certain possibilities light up as salient (for me,
for the other, or for us), while others are dimmed down. World understanding
is ‘eo ipso an understanding of one another’ (GA, /).
Of course, we do not always get a good fit between the matrix of salience
and the other’s behaviour. These cases call for ‘the special hermeneutics of
empathy’. Here ‘empathy’ refers to a kind of cognitively demanding social
cognition in which we through conscious and deliberate mental operations try
to make sense of and predict the behaviour of the other. As Heidegger points
out, it is a ‘substitute’ of the fluid and dynamic social cognition of transpo-
sitioning (SZ, /). If we, for example, continuously expect the other to
respond to certain solicitations in our shared environment that he or she
completely ignores, then we might utilise folk-psychological theories or
deliberate simulations to improve our understanding of the other. But this
only shows us that the special hermeneutics of empathy presupposes the basic
understanding of the other as a minded world-enmeshed agent provided in
transpositioning. Empathy in this sense enters the scene when the fluid
transpositioning breaks down. What is more, it seems that transpositioning
is not only the presupposition but also the aim of theorising and simulation
insofar as theorising and simulation arguably must feed back into transposi-
tioning to count as a way of understanding other people. After all, we would
not normally say that we ‘understood someone’ if we constantly needed a
series of explicit cognitive operations to interact with them with just a
modicum of success. In this sense, other people are more like tools than
mathematical puzzles. We usually understand them without further ado.
See Sherover (), Vogel (), Young (), and, more recently, O’Brien (), Sikka
(), and Reid ().
Forms of Being-With
). ‘[T]he acknowledgement of the other Dasein’s status as fundamen-
tally distinct from a thing’, she writes, ‘lie[s] deeper than authentic/
inauthentic ways of being in the world’ (McMullin , ).
Since transpositioning is not itself an ethical phenomenon, I think there
is good reason to doubt that the distinction between leaping-in and
leaping-ahead is an ethical distinction. Rather, I take it to be an attempt
to show that very different forms of intersubjectivity can be accommodated
within Heidegger’s framework. In my reading, leaping-in and leaping-
ahead are two extreme ways of caring for the others’ for-the-sake-of
references as these are disclosed in transpositioning.
We can see that the distinction is not an ethical distinction by the fact
that it does not align with what we with Nagel might call ‘the possibility of
altruism’ (Nagel ). Someone can, for instance, leap in for someone else
with the very best of intentions. For example, imagine a father to a nearly
grown child. This father correctly recognises the needs, wants, and interests
of his child. Altruistically, he then takes it upon himself to satisfy these needs
and wants and to stimulate all the child’s interests. In this case, the father
transposes himself into the child: he recognises the child as an existential self
and – let us assume – has a good grasp of what matters to the child. As
Heidegger noted above, he might even understand the child better than the
child understands itself (GA/, f/). Yet, by taking over the child’s
concerns and thus micromanaging the life of the child, the father leaps in for
the child. Expressed in everyday language, the nearly grown child may,
rightfully, accuse the parent of being patronising even if he is altruistic.
Regarding leaping-ahead, let’s adopt an example from the animated sci-fi
TV-show Rick and Morty. In the show, there is an invention called a Meeseeks
Box. Whenever you press a button on the Meeseeks Box, it spawns a blue
humanoid called a Mr. Meeseeks that will live until it has completed the first
order given to it. In one of the episodes, Beth, a mother and wife, presses the
button and asks Mr. Meeseeks to help her become ‘a more complete woman’.
Mr. Meeseeks takes Beth on a date and encourages her to focus more on
herself and, in effect, to liberate herself from the expectations of her family.
Beth realises that she should leave her husband and leans in to kiss Mr.
Meeseeks, which disappears after having completed its task.
For the sake of the argument, we will assume that Mr. Meeseeks is
sufficiently similar to human beings to qualify as Dasein; we see that
Mr. Meeseeks could only help Beth become a more complete woman by
This is not quite the case in Rick and Morty since Mr. Meeseeks has no choice but to complete his
order, whereas Dasein understands possibilities as possibilities.
Interpersonal Understanding
transposing itself into her. Mr. Meeseeks arguably tries to give Beth back
her potentiality-for-being by encouraging her to assume responsibility for
her life. In this sense, Mr. Meeseeks leaps ahead of Beth and, yet, it seems
that no element in this example qualifies as altruistic. Beth, on her part,
decides to focus on herself, probably to the dismay of her family. And, as
the TV-show explains, Mr. Meeseeks does not help Beth for her own sake
but only because existence is painful for Mr. Meeseeks.
This shows that transpositioning and solicitude are by themselves
ethically neutral even if they are presupposed by altruistic concerns for
others. This is not to say that no normative lessons can be learned from
Heidegger. In Chapter , I argue that his account of authenticity involves a
kind of normativity that, although it is distinct from moral normativity,
does indeed affect our relations to other people.
For an attempt to develop an ethical theory by combining a Heidegger-inspired account of social
cognition with a philosophical anthropology based on altruism, see Løgstrup ().
Forms of Being-With
being-in-the-world of human beings. Being-in-the-world is a distinctive
ontological holism that relates human beings to the objective and social
environment in a particular way. Assuming that animals are also holisti-
cally constituted, the difference must lie in the way the animal, vis-à-vis the
human, relates to its objective and social environment. In transposing
oneself into an entity one relates this entity to its environment in accor-
dance with the type of being of the entity in question. Given that the
animal relates to its environment differently than humans do, it must also
be different to transpose oneself into an animal than into a human being.
Before turning to the details of his analysis, we should note that
Heidegger’s argument is ambiguous. He clearly juxtaposes the human
being and the animal in a way that resonates with Western humanism
and anthropocentrism, but what exactly does animality mean in this
context? On the one hand, Heidegger defines animality in a commonsen-
sical extensional way. The thesis that animals are world-poor ‘does not tell
us something merely about insects or merely about mammals, since it also
includes, for example, non-articulated creatures, unicellular animals like
amoebae, infusoria, sea urchins and the like – all animals, every animal’
(GA/, /). The discussion of world-poverty concerns all ani-
mals – except the human being. Heidegger has rightly been criticised for
operating with such an unconvincingly crude conception of animality.
As Derrida says, it suggests
that there is one thing, one domain, one homogeneous type of entity,
which is called animality in general, for which any example would do the
job. This is a thesis which . . . remains fundamentally teleological
and traditional. (Derrida , )
But in more careful passages, Heidegger says that his analysis is speculative,
that his thesis ‘goes too far’ (GA/, /), and that his characteri-
sation of animality is not ‘drawn from animality itself’ but conceived in
‘comparison with the human being’ (GA/, /). At one point
Heidegger even seems to admit that we are right to be suspicious of the
idea that animals can be taken as one uniform group since some animals
display a type of intentionality that corresponds closely with our own while
others are indeed very distant (GA/, /). If this is indeed the
case, Heidegger’s analysis of animality hardly holds for all animals. As
Carman notes, Heidegger’s use of the term ‘animal’ is ‘deliberately vague,
since the point is to specify an ontological distinction between the world-
For an overview, see Cykowski ().
Interpersonal Understanding
[building] and the world-poor, not to speculate about where the division
occurs biologically among species’ (Carman , n). In this reading,
we should first and foremost understand the concept of animality inten-
sionally. The concept refers, by definition, to those entities that are ‘world-
poor,’ while the exact extension of the term is debatable.
To be sure, Heidegger assumes ‘animality’ to be fixed both extensionally
and intensionally but when pressed I believe he would argue that the
intensional definition is primary. Since Heidegger’s explicit aim is not
ethological but to clarify human being-in-the-world through a conceptual
contrast, we should, following the principle of charity, take the concept of
animality to be defined intensionally. Animality refers primarily to those
entities that are world-poor; any specification of the term’s extension must
be provisional. Following this advice, I will first clarify how Heidegger
understands the ontological holism of world-poverty, and then I will
compare this to the holism of human beings and clarify what it entails
for our possibility of transposing ourselves into world-poor entities, which
I, for stylistic reasons, call simply animals. In this reading, Heidegger’s
frequent examples are mere illustrations of world-poverty rather than actual
empirical evidence. This is not to say, however, that we should completely
disregard the question of extension, and I will return to it towards the end
of the section.
Following the biologist Jakob von Uexküll, Heidegger emphasises that
the animal, whatever its differences to the human being, has a surrounding
world [Umwelt]. A lizard, he says, does not exist like an occurrent thing,
simply lying indifferently next to things like a rock lying indifferently next
to a tree. It ‘has its own relation to the rock, to the sun, and to a host of
other things’ (GA/, /). Yet, according to Heidegger, the lizard
does not relate to the rock as a rock.
One is tempted to suggest that what we identify as the rock and the sun are
just lizard-things for the lizard, so to speak. When we say that the lizard is
lying on the rock, we ought to cross out the word ‘rock’ in order to indicate
that whatever the lizard is lying on is certainly given in some way for the
lizard, and yet is not known to the lizard as a rock. If we cross out the word
we do not simply mean to imply that something else is in question here or is
taken as something else. Rather we imply that whatever it is not accessible
This, at least, is how I read his claim that the thesis on world-poverty is a statement of essence
[Wesensaussage] but not “simply because it holds true for all animals and not merely for some of
them. Rather, it is the other way around: it holds true for all animals because it is a statement of
essence. Universal validity can only result from our knowledge insofar as it is essential in each case,
and not the other way around” (GA/, /).
Forms of Being-With
to it as an entity. . . . Every animal as animal has determinate set of relations
to its sources of nourishment, its prey, its enemies, its sexual mates, and
so on. (GA/, f/)
Here Heidegger grants that animals certainly have a form of intentionality.
Things are ‘given in some way for the lizard’. Furthermore, like human
beings, animals operate within a relational whole that determines how they
experience things. For the animal, this whole consists of relations to
nourishment, prey, enemies, and so on.
Heidegger calls the relational whole surrounding the animal a ‘disinhibi-
tion ring’ suggesting that the drives and capabilities of the animal entirely
determine which and how entities appear within this sphere (GA/, /
). ‘Since capability for . . . thoroughly governs the animal’s type of being,
an entity such as the animal, when it comes into relation with something else,
can only encounter something that “affects” [angeht] or initiates [an-lässt] the
capability. Nothing else can ever penetrate the ring around the animal’ (GA/
, /). Animals are also individuated holistically. They are not simply
biological specimens. Rather, they are essentially bound to or captivated by
their disinhibition ring in such a way that the animal body itself is only
meaningful as long as we conceive of it as grounded in – as an organ within –
‘the unity of captivation’ [Einheit der Benommenheit] that allows an environ-
ment to display itself for the animal (GA/, /). Yet, how animals
relate to their environment is fully determined by their instincts and capac-
ities. ‘Throughout its life, the animal is confined to its environmental world,
immured as it were within a barrel that is incapable of further expansion or
contraction’ (GA/, /). The world of the animal thus appears to be
a fixed sphere that in advance determines how things appear to it.
Let us compare this with the holism of human being-in-the-world.
Above we saw that human beings also encounter entities based on a
relational whole. I argued that this holism constitutively depends on
environmental objects in such a way that real-world entities constrain
our existential projections and that it constitutively depends on social
relations since our manner of encountering entities is necessarily respon-
sive to the behaviour of others. The juncture of object externalism and
social externalism is that even though we always encounter a as b depend-
ing on our specific existential projections, we are also aware that the entity
a can be disclosed differently. Entities are free for ‘mutual use’; they are
what relates and separates us at the same time.
The crux of Heidegger’s analysis is that animals are world-poor because
they do not have access to entities as entities. This claim follows from the
idea that the animal is fixed or captivated within its disinhibition ring in
Interpersonal Understanding
the following way: If the animal is captivated within its disinhibition ring,
it can only experience entities as correlates of its drives and capabilities, as
pure affects. If this is the case, animals do not take entities to exist
independently of themselves, and, therefore, they lack the possibility of
properly revising or modifying their understanding of entities in light of
the behavioural evidence afforded to them in encounters with other
creatures. Animals are object internalists in the sense that they cannot
successfully refer to or intend an object as anything but an affect
interior to its own realm of manifestation, its own disinhibition ring.
Correspondingly, in terms of social externalism, this means that the animal
cannot intend an object with someone who does not share its disinhibition
ring to some degree. ‘[T]he encircling rings are not comparable amongst
themselves at all, and in each case the totality of the manifest, dovetailing
encircling rings are not simply part of the entities that are otherwise
manifest to us, rather they hold us captive in quite specific ways’
(GA/, /).
This means, further, that animals lack the a as b-structure characteristic
of Dasein. As we saw above, the a as b-structure requires that we possess an
awareness that our intended objects are independent of and therefore not
exhausted by our particular understanding of them. This enables us to
successfully intend or refer to objects even with someone who does not
share our understanding of being. We, hence, understand entities as
enmeshed in a dynamic structure of possibility that is responsive to the
behaviour of those we encounter. Now, in the case of human–human
interaction, this responsiveness is mutual. However, given that animals do
not perceive entities as entities but simply as affects, they cannot modify
their understanding of entities in response to the behaviour of other
creatures like ourselves to the extent that we can. The relational whole
that guides the intentionality of animals is fixed or static, meaning that
they only have a determinate set of relations through which they can make
sense of their surroundings. If an entity does not seem to fit one sort of
relation (e.g., being-mate), the animal must try another relation
(e.g., being-prey or being-predator) within its fixed set of relations to
secure a good interpretative fit between its environmental matrix of
salience and the other’s behaviour. If it fails to achieve a good fit, it cannot
make sense of the entity.
In contrast, ‘the world of man is rich’, Heidegger says,
greater in range [Umfang], far more penetrating [Eindringlichkeit], con-
stantly extendable not only in range (we can always bring more and more
entities into consideration) but also in respect to the manner in which we
Forms of Being-With
can penetrate [durchdringen] ever more deeply into this penetrability
[Eindringlichkeit]. Consequently, we can characterise the relation man
possesses to the world by referring to the multiplication [Vermehrbarkeit]
of that which the human relates to. Therefore, we speak of [the human as]
world-building. (GA/, /)
Whereas the animal is captivated or bound by its way of seeing, human
beings can expand their field of appearing and penetrate deeper into it by
getting a better and more nuanced understanding of the entities that they
encounter. This does not mean, of course, that the human being is
suddenly a limitless, other-worldly reason, but simply that the horizon of
being-in-the-world is open-ended. The relational whole of Dasein is
dynamic insofar as the whole of relations that constitute it can be made
to accommodate various types of behaviour in a way that is not reducible
to a set of presupposed interpretative types. We can express this open-
endedness that characterise human understanding by borrowing an image
from ‘Letter on Humanism’ – human understanding ‘walks the boundary
of the boundless’ (GA, /). It is finite and open-ended at the
same time.
The fact that we comport ourselves to entities as entities, that we intend
real-world objects in a way that is responsive to the behaviour of others,
marks the ontological difference between human being and animal.
According to Heidegger, humans can, in contrast to animals, extend and
nuance their understanding of being by virtue of transpositioning or
triangulation.
What does this entail for the possibility of interspecies understanding?
Heidegger insists that we can indeed transpose ourselves into animals in
much, although not exactly, the same way as we do with other human
beings. ‘Human Dasein is intrinsically a peculiar transposedness into the
encompassing contextual ring of living entities’ (GA/, /). We
can ‘[go] along with the animal in the way in which it sees and hears, how
it seizes its prey or evades its predators, how it builds its nest and so forth’
(GA/, /). Human beings triangulate the world with animals. In
a sense, this point is quite obvious, for if we did not, we would not have
pets, and we would certainly have fared poorly in evolutionary history.
There is little reason to believe that this type of transpositioning is
radically different from our transpositioning into humans. It seems to me
that Dasein-animal social cognition must satisfy the same four conditions
mentioned above: () To some extent, we presumably understand animals
immediately without conscious inferences or deliberate simulations; () we
have a basic awareness of the animal as minded rather than non-minded;
Interpersonal Understanding
() we understand animals by relating them to their environment; and ()
we do so without abandoning the self/other-distinction.
While we can, in principle, understand the animal by transposing
ourselves into its disinhibition ring, the crucial difference to Dasein–
Dasein interaction is that when we transpose ourselves into animals we
do not expect animals to transpose themselves into us. Due to their
captivation by disinhibition rings, animals cannot triangulate the world
with us – or they can only do so in a fixed, static, and deficient way – even
if we can triangulate the world with them. For social cognition amongst
human beings, we must then add a fifth requirement, namely,
() The mutuality condition: Social cognition among human beings must
be so construed as to account for the fact that others can understand
us in the same way that we understand them.
Lacking the capacity to intend entities as entities, the animal cannot
triangulate the world in response to our behaviour; they cannot engage
in such a fusion of horizons, to borrow a phrase from Gadamer. Therefore,
the animal ‘grants the possibility of transposedness’, and yet ‘necessarily
refuses any going along with’ (GA/, /) in the proper sense of
intending an entity with someone who has a different understanding of
being. More specifically, we might share the world with the animal in the
sense that () we comport ourselves in accordance with a whole of
significance that is responsive to the behaviour of the animal, that is, that
adjusts to the lens through which we take the animal to see the world, and
() we tacitly assume the animal to respond to the same entities that we do.
The world sharing is asymmetrical, however, since () the animal’s disin-
hibition ring is fixed and unresponsive to our behaviour and () the
animal, which might tacitly assume us to respond to the same drive-
triggers as it does, does not assume us to intend the same entities, since
to intend something as an entity is to understand the entity as something
that can be disclosed in multiple ways.
Now, is this account of interspecies understanding plausible? One might
object that our relations to real animals – like real-life dogs and chimpan-
zees – are far richer and more complicated than Heidegger would have us
believe. People train their dogs, so the objection goes, and thereby enrich
their world. It is undeniable that dogs can ‘read’ their owners or trainers in
the sense that they take their expressions and actions to be correlated with
the environment. Imagine, for instance, a dog that senses the fear of its
owner and starts barking at an intruder. This obviously involves a kind
of triangulation.
Forms of Being-With
At this point, Heidegger would insist that his point is not that there is
no triangulation between humans and animals whatsoever, but, rather,
that this triangulation is marred by a fundamental asymmetry. On
Heidegger’s analysis, the asymmetry consists in the fact that human beings
have the possibility of transposing themselves into the animals – that is, the
possibility of understanding the environment with reference to the set of
relations that constitute the drives and capacities of that particular animal –
while the animal is completely locked up within its own horizon. This does
not by itself render something like training unintelligible since it might
still be possible to modify when the different drives are triggered as well as
the sequence in which they are triggered. To train a dog to fetch would, on
this account, be to develop a game that involved hunting as well as the
sharing of prey with the pack. Or, more precisely, this would be a game for
the human trainer, while it is unclear to which extent it could be a game
for the dog since animals, on Heidegger’s reductive account, lack the
capacity to pretend. For them, objects simply are drive-triggering affects
such as ‘prey’ or ‘enemy’.
The critic might try to counter this by saying that the ability to
‘transpose’ oneself into other species must come in degrees and that
Heidegger fails to accommodate this. Is the difference between human
Dasein and animal really ‘abysmal’, as Heidegger says? However, if I am
right that Heidegger’s conception of animality is defined intensionally, he
is self-evidently right that the difference cannot be one of degrees, because
the term ‘animal’ is defined in such a way that it necessarily contrasts with
the concept of human Dasein. As I argued above, we should not read the
analysis as a reflection on real animals, but a reflection on what it is (or
what it might be) to be world-poor, that is, to be conscious but to lack the
a as b-structure. Defined this way, there is an essential and insurmountable
difference between human Dasein and animal.
This clearly lets Heidegger off the hook too easily. We cannot disregard
the question of extension completely, and despite moments of hesitation,
Heidegger does claim that his concept of animality extends to all (nonhu-
man) animals. Does the continuum established through natural selection
allow an abysmal difference between human and nonhuman? The question
of extension is an empirical question, and Heidegger could very well be
wrong in claiming that certain real species are world-poor. We can thus
easily imagine that some yet-to-be-discovered breed of alien or higher
primate would satisfy the mutuality condition. We would then – perhaps
after a transitional period where we grew accustomed to seeing them as co-
intenders and co-actors rather than nonhuman puzzles – see these aliens or
Interpersonal Understanding
primates as fellow Dasein with whom we could triangulate our environ-
ment symmetrically.
Michael Tomasello’s empirically informed comparison between human
thinking and the cognitive abilities of other animals and other great apes in
particular is, however, more or less congruent with Heidegger’s analysis.
Difference species have different ways of life, of course, which means that
they perceive or attend to different situations (and components of situa-
tions). Thus, for a leopard, the situation of bananas in a tree would not
represent an opportunity to eat, but the presence of a chimpanzee would.
For the chimpanzee, in contrast, the leopard’s presence now presents an
obstacle to its value of avoiding predators, and so it should look for a
situation providing opportunities for escape, such as a tree to climb without
low-hanging limbs – given its knowledge that leopards cannot climb such
trees and its familiarity with its own tree-climbing prowess. If we now
throw into the mix a worm resting on the banana’s surface, the relevant
situations for the three different species – the obstacles and opportunities
for their respective goals – would overlap even less, if at all. Relevant
situations are thus determined jointly by the organism’s goals and values,
its perceptual abilities and knowledge, and its behavioural capacities, that is
to say, by its overall functioning as a self-regulating system. (Tomasello
, f )
For Tomasello, nonhuman animals are ‘self-regulating systems’, and these
systems are pigeonholed, as it were, within specific interpretations of their
environment in a way that is completely determined by the goals and
values of the organism in question. In contrast, ‘only humans can concep-
tualize one and the same situation or entity under differing, even conflict-
ing, social perspectives (leading ultimately to a sense of “objectivity”)’,
which also means that only humans can participate in complex forms of
shared intentionality through which joint goals are formed and joint
actions initiated (Tomasello , ).
Whether the leopard, the chimpanzee, and the worm are aptly described
by the intensionally fixed concept of animality is an empirical question. As
such, it lies beyond the scope of Heidegger’s project. As we recall, his
ambition in GA/ is to clarify what it is for Dasein to have a world
through an admittedly speculative comparison.
Perhaps some of us already see our animal companions in this way. Once the question of extension
is bracketed, there is nothing in Heidegger’s account to rule out this possibility. Indeed, as we saw
in footnote , he believes that his conception of existential selfhood can explain the phenomenon of
anthropomorphism (or, better, Daseinmorphism). This might be another reason that his remarks
on real animals such as dogs are so ambiguous.
Shared Action
Human beings often act together. They dance, paint houses, and go for
walks together. It is widely recognised that shared actions such as these are
not simply aggregates of individual actions. Rather, if two or more people
are to act together, their actions and intentions must interrelate, so that
each person’s actions constitutively depend on the other people’s actions.
This interdependence must be immediately obvious to the co-agents so
that they are each aware that they act together rather than individually.
The general capacity for individuals to ‘team up’ is discussed under the
term collective intentionality. In this chapter, I will develop a Heideggerian
account of one type of collective intentionality, namely, our capacity to act
together. I will thus use the term ‘shared action’ to refer to any intentional
activity that constitutively depends on several people being co-actors in a
way that is immediately obvious to them.
It is widely acknowledged that our capacity for shared action is a key
element in understanding the human condition. As we have just seen,
Tomasello suggests that it is the central feature that separates human
beings from the rest of the animal kingdom. Yet, it is conceptually unclear
what exactly shared action is and how it differs from individual action.
One of the reasons for this incertitude is, or so I shall argue, that the
dominant approaches to shared action and intentions (Bratman ,
; Gilbert , ; Searle , ) presuppose an overly
intellectualist model of action that is largely at odds with the phenome-
nology of action, i.e., with how minded agents typically understand
themselves and what they do in everyday activities. Given that shared
action requires that we are aware that we act together, we must get the
As I use the term, ‘shared action’ refers to any intentional activity in which we are immediately aware
that it constitutively depends on other people. Construed this way, ‘shared action’ is an umbrella
term that covers several distinct forms of action with different degrees and types of intersubjective
cooperation. ‘Joint action’ is the subtype of shared action with the highest degree of cooperation,
namely, jointly coordinated and jointly committed action (cf. Section .).
Shared Action
phenomenology right. Recently, some work has been put forth that aims
to correct the intellectualism of the dominant approaches (e.g., Schmid
a, b, ; Zahavi a, b, , ), but I will argue
that these approaches do not go far enough in their phenomenological
reinterpretations of shared agency. Instead, I will draw upon the model of
agency found in Heidegger and other phenomenologists like Merleau-
Ponty and Dreyfus to spell out the phenomenological structure of shared
action. I argue that a specific form of agency – what I call pre-reflective
agency – is best explained as the way in which an environment solicits us
to act. Recall, as I use the terms, solicitations differ from affordances
insofar as affordances can be inert. Solicitations, in contrast, are affor-
dances that prompt actions because the relevant agent is committed to
some underlying project that is furthered through these affordances.
Extending this line of thought, I will argue that some solicitations prompt
shared action. They do so because they solicit several agents to cooperate
(i.e., to act on shared affordances) or because they solicit an agent or several
agents to act to further a joint project (i.e., to act due to a joint
commitment).
In line with the contemporary debate on collective intentionality, this
chapter focuses on small-scale, egalitarian, and temporary group forma-
tions. In contrast, most (but not all) of Heidegger’s explicit reflections on
the we appear in the ‘s in the politically charged context of his discussion
of the national identity of the Germans and, hence, target a very different
we, namely, a large-scale, hierarchical, and prolonged group formation.
I discuss large-scale we’s in Chapters and .
I proceed in the following way: First, I outline some of the problems
characteristic of contemporary approaches to shared action (Section .).
I then suggest that these problems can be avoided if we construct our
model of shared action on the account of pre-reflective action found in
existential phenomenology rather than the standard account of reflective
action. Since, however, the phenomenology of action is typically formu-
lated in individualistic terms, I combine it with the idea of plural pre-
reflective self-awareness to show how solicitations can be given to a group
rather than an individual (Section .). I proceed to analyse solicitations in
terms of (a) affordances inflected by someone’s abilities and dispositions
and (b) someone’s self-referential commitment to a project furthered by
these affordances (or, in short, in terms of (a) goals and (b) commitments)
(Section .). Drawing on this analysis, I construct a phenomenologically
plausible taxonomy of individual and shared actions that incorporate both
teleological and normative elements of shared actions (Section .). In
Forms of Being-With
response to the question of which process enables individuals to share
solicitations, I show that what Heidegger calls discourse [Rede] is the
expressive process in which saliences are shared between people (Section
.). I conclude by offering a few reflections on how this interpretation of
the small-scale we compares to the large-scale we’s of social norms and of
nations, which will occupy us in the following two chapters.
In a reply to Petersson, Bratman argues that his account avoids the threat of circularity since (),
which is supposed to explain what shared intentionality is, does not have an instance of shared
intentionality as its object. Instead, Bratman argues that ‘we J’ in () refers to a joint activity that is
‘neutral with respect to shared intentionality’ (, ). If I understand it correctly, the suggestion
is that conditions ()–() explain what it is for us to reflectively endorse and undertake some joint
activity. For Bratman, to have an intention to do something is to plan to do it in the sense of settling
on a goal and deliberating on the means to achieve it (, ). In other words, there is no
circularity in saying that we intend J only if you and I each intend that we J, since the instance of ‘we
intend J’ that appears in the analysandum refers to us having reflectively endorsed and undertaken
(i.e., us having planned to) J, while the ‘we J’ that appears in the analysans refers to a joint activity
without this reflective endorsement. Formulated in this way, Bratman clearly presupposes that we are
already aware of possible joint activities prior to forming a full-blown shared plan. In emphasising
pre-reflective rather than reflective action (see Section .), I want to pose the question: How are we
aware of what we can do prior to our reflection or deliberation?
Shared Action
The second problem, which I call the taxonomy problem, concerns the
question of whether Bratman and Gilbert target the same phenomena. The
disagreement is often described as a contradiction between theoretically
incompatible positions, but perhaps Gilbert and Bratman simply describe
different phenomena – for example, normative versus teleological types of
coordination. If this is the case, the problem is no longer to provide one
simple formula for all types of shared actions and intentions but rather to
come up with a suitably nuanced taxonomy capable of integrating their
respective target phenomena.
The third problem – the intellectualist problem – concerns how Bratman
and Gilbert account for the awareness condition. They disagree on
whether shared action requires that we normatively rely on or non-
normatively predict the behaviour of others but both argue that the
awareness condition only obtains under conditions of common knowledge
(e.g., Bratman , –; Gilbert , –, , ). In
addition, they both subscribe to fairly standard models of agency according
to which a piece of behaviour counts as action only if it is guided by certain
occurrent mental states. For Gilbert, for instance, when joint commit-
ments come into conflict with other desires on our part, we must actively
remind ourselves of our obligation(s) to the other members of the plural
subject. Some have questioned the adequacy of this model by distinguish-
ing different kinds of self- and other-awareness. Phenomenologists in
particular argue that an adequate understanding of shared actions and
we-experiences in general require that we cash out the awareness condition
in pre-reflective terms (e.g., Schmid a, ; Walsh ; Zahavi
a, ). Similarly, it can be argued from an action-theoretic point of
view that the relation between actions and mental states such as intentions,
beliefs, and desires are far more elusive than Gilbert and Bratman assumes.
In this vein, phenomenologists like Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty, and
Dreyfus claim that actions do not involve an awareness of identifiable
mental states and that the dominant approaches to the philosophy of
action commit an intellectualist error that flies in the face of
everyday experiences.
Schmid admits that there are important differences between singular and plural self-awareness; for
example, ‘the singular “sense of self” . . . establishes an authoritative point of view for which there is
no equivalent in the plural case’ (a, ), but these are not pertinent for our discussion.
Shared Action
Husserl’s conception of the transcendental subject and the other underlies
Heidegger’s existential analysis of Dasein. As it turns out, it matters a
great deal which type of singular self-awareness we take as our point of
departure, when developing our model of plural self-awareness.
Let me briefly recap the difference between these two concepts of
selfhood:
Atomistic singular self-awareness is Husserlian in spirit. It names the
formal unity of the mind afforded by a transcendental subject that unites
distinct experiences in a single stream of consciousness. In this view, self-
awareness is not something added to the experience but is, rather, an
intrinsic feature of the experience itself; it is what makes an experience
an experience for me. Zahavi calls it the minimal or experiential self by
which he means to suggest that this type of self-awareness is formal as it
says nothing about the personal characteristics of an individual. This type
of self-awareness is atomistic since it is not ‘constitutively dependent upon
social interaction’ (, ). Indeed, atomistic singular self-awareness is
formal in the sense that it is entirely independent of whatever the subject
directs itself towards. It is, rather, a permanent feature of the subject’s
experiential life.
Holistic singular self-awareness is the alternative type of self-awareness
advocated by existential philosophers like Heidegger. For this reason,
I have called call it ‘the existential self’. In contrast to the minimal self,
the existential self targets the pre-reflective sense of self that is intrinsic to
our practical engagement with the world and with other people. Like its
atomistic counterpart, this self-awareness is given non-inferentially and
non-observationally. Yet, holistic singular self-awareness is not formal.
Rather, it is the sense of self that is intrinsically bound to how concrete
situations appear to us in light of our everyday projects and engagement
with other people. It is the pre-reflective self-awareness ‘reflected back to
me’ based on how the world solicits me to act. Formally put,
Holistic singular self-awareness is the sense of self inherent to how a
social and physical environment solicits actions based on (a) the
affordances inflected by the individual’s abilities and dispositions
and (b) the individual’s self-referential commitment to a project that
is furthered through these affordances.
It is somewhat curious that Schmid does not discuss these two types of self-awareness in any detail as
his earlier work, in contrast to his more recent work, endorses an existential conception of
intentionality (, ).
Forms of Being-With
In this definition, (a) designates that environments afford different things
from different agents based on the agent’s know how. Affordances are,
hence, neither objective nor subjective but a correlation between the
objective relations available in the environment and the abilities and
dispositions of the agent. (b) refers to the fact that not all affordances are
salient. According to Heidegger, what accounts for this fact is how the
agent’s self-understanding ties in with his or her activities. For instance,
teacher-affordances are salient to me if I am committed to the project of
teaching. Heidegger calls this the ‘for-the-sake-of’ thereby suggesting that
for something to be significant or salient an agent must be doing it for the
sake of some particular self-understanding. For-the-sake-of relations tie
agents to the affordances of their environment, because the agent’s prac-
tical self-awareness as this or that determines which set of in-order-to’s,
which practical possibilities, show up as salient rather than as inert affor-
dances. The agent must be self-referentially committed to some project for
an environment to solicit actions.
This is not necessarily a deeply personal type of commitment.
Sometimes the commitment underlies trivial cases like an agent being
drawn to the chips in the buffet rather than the salad. Yet, this trivial
solicitation can only get a grip on the agent if he or she is committed to a
project, say, the project of wanting to taste deliciously deep-fried food. As
we recall, to be an agent is to be ‘a particular style of polarizing the
affordances of a situation into particular solicitations to act’ (Wrathall
, ). This kind of polarisation necessarily requires commitments
because the agent cares about the activity in a way that can succeed or fail,
for example, if the chips turn out to be soggy and under-seasoned.
Affordances only become solicitations once someone cares about or com-
mits to them. Borrowing a few terms from Crowell, we might say that
goals and affordances are ‘telic’, while commitments are the ‘atelic’ under-
pinnings that render these goals and affordances worthwhile to someone
(, ).
Such polarising commitments are self-referential because they resist
further explanation. I am drawn to the chips because I simply care about
tasting them. ‘Self-referential’ does not mean, however, that the agent
deliberately chooses his or her commitments. On the contrary, our
To be clear, self-referential commitments are not necessarily the result of a deliberative process but
usually an expression of our pre-reflective dispositions. As I argue below, some commitments are
deficient in the sense that they are default commitments that result from an agent’s pre-reflective
social dispositions (see Chapter ) while other commitments are disclosive of who the particular
Shared Action
commitments are part and parcel of the solicitations. Indeed, in most
cases, we barely take notice of our commitment as we are too busy
pursuing the teleological steps of our project (getting to the buffet, picking
up a plate, scoping over handfuls of chips. . .). Nonetheless, it makes sense
to say that we are non-thematically aware of our commitments since they
are a constituent feature of the teleological steps that thematically occupy
our attention and since they can be brought to the forefront of our
attention if, for instance, our project fails.
This type of self-awareness is holistic because it names a non-thematic
awareness of oneself as normatively engaged with an environment consist-
ing of worldly objects and other people. A non-thematic sense of self, as
committed to this or that project or self-understanding, is reflected back to
us by the solicitations that draw us in.
The distinction between atomistic and holistic self-awareness reveals
two problems for the attempt to use Schmid’s account of plural self-
awareness to understand pre-reflective shared action. First, since atomistic
self-awareness is a permanent feature of our experiential life, it cannot help
us identify the self-awareness necessary to distinguish pre-reflective action
from bodily happenings. We cannot experience the failure of atomistic
self-awareness, since atomistic self-awareness is a necessary condition for
having an experience in the first place. Pre-reflective action implies an
immanent measure of success, but since we cannot experience the success
or failure of atomistic self-awareness, it cannot help us distinguish pre-
reflective action from bodily happenings. If I see my arm soar into the air
because it is triggered by the implanted microchip, this is still an experience
for me. My atomistic self-awareness remains the same. From the perspec-
tive of holistic self-awareness, however, things look very different. On this
account, I would not recognise the activity as mine if, for instance, I am
unaware of any affordances in response to which it would make sense for
me to raise my arm. Here, the activity would fail to satisfy one of the
immanent measures of success characteristic of pre-reflective action,
namely, condition (a) above. We can also imagine another case, akin to
alien hand-syndrome, where my left hand, when triggered by the micro-
chip, gets a ‘mind of its own’ in the sense that it responds purposefully to
affordances in my immediate environment (such as unbuttoning my shirt),
agent is (see Chapter ). While there is no liberum arbitrium and no otherworldly position from
which the agent can pick and choose his commitments in a detached way, Heidegger still accounts
for the specific type of normativity that makes certain projects (and, hence, solicitations) crucial to
the life of an agent while others are tangential and insignificant. In Chapter , I discuss this as the
attributability problem.
Forms of Being-With
but in this case, my activity does not count as pre-reflective action, because
the activity does not satisfy the other immanent measure of success,
namely, condition (b) according to which I must be self-referentially
committed to a project that is furthered through the affordances to which
my activity responds. In this example, I simply do not recognise the
purposes and responses of the alien hand as part of one of my projects
and, thus, I am not aware of myself as successfully performing the activity
in question.
Second, Schmid fails to recognise that only one form of pre-reflective
self-awareness can be pluralised in shared action. As noted above, atomistic
self-awareness is a permanent feature of the subject’s experiential life; yet,
in accounting for pre-reflective shared action, we need to show how an
environment occasionally prompts us while it, in other circumstances,
prompts me to act in a certain way. The self-awareness intrinsic to shared
action cannot, in other words, be formal in the sense described above, but
must rather be ‘reflected back to us’ from a specific engagement with the
world. Schmid does, at times, acknowledge that social relations and plural
self-awareness are transitory (a, ), yet he seems to consider plural
self-awareness to be analogous to atomistic singular self-awareness, when
he claims that singular self-awareness ‘establishes something like the formal
unity of mind’ and ‘plays the role of Kant’s “transcendental apperception”’
(a, ). Like Zahavi’s minimal self, Schmid’s singular self-awareness is
the unity of a stream of consciousness or the immanence of consciousness
to itself. According to this analogy, Schmid’s plural self-awareness ‘formally
unifies our social mind’ (a, ), that is, it is independent of whatever
is experienced. I contend, on the other hand, that ‘our social mind’ must
be unified by the solicitations that prompt us to respond.
In short, my suggestion is, first, that holistic self-awareness helps us
explain the nature of pre-reflective action and, second, that a plural version
of holistic self-awareness will help us explain the nature of pre-reflective
shared action. Extrapolating from the previous definition, we get the
following (preliminary) definition of this type of plural self-awareness:
Plural self-awareness is the sense of self inherent to how a social and physical
environment solicits actions based on (a) the affordances inflected by a
As a third variation of this example, we can imagine that the person controlling my hand through the
microchip knows me so well that they make my hand respond only to the environmental affordances
that aligns with my self-referential commitments. This activity would be distinguishable from
reflective action, since my hand would then move without me consciously representing the mental
states that in normal deliberative circumstances make it do so, but indistinguishable from pre-
reflective action. Yet, it seems to me that this is still very different from a mere bodily happening.
Shared Action
group’s abilities and dispositions and (b) the group’s self-referential com-
mitment to a project that is furthered by these affordances.
The upshot of this redefinition is that it retains the main pro of Schmid’s
original proposal by not assuming shared action to involve the intellectu-
ally demanding representation of mental states and that it, in addition,
allows us to account for the transience of plural self-awareness by way of
our relations to other people and our environment while remaining true to
the phenomenology of pre-reflective action.
Haugeland claims that existential commitments are ‘crucially not social’ (, ), and Crowell
maintains that only the ‘I-myself’ – the first-person singular – can be authentically committed to the
norms that governs its behaviour (e.g., , ). Sánchez Guerrero‘s () Heideggerian
approach to collective emotions (what he calls ‘affective intentional community’) is a notable
exception. He agrees that Heidegger’s for-the-sake-of should be understood as a tacit self-reference
intrinsic to our intentional acts, but that it is also possible that ‘others are referentially included in the
intentional structure of the emotions at issue by way of a tacit self-reference, and not by way of a
second- or third-personal indication’ (Sánchez Guerrero , ).
Shared Action
intentional background that guides their actions. If we imagine that one
camper had a cold and cancelled, but the other camper went on the trip
anyway, he could still unreflectively engage in chopping wood and thus his
state of mind, understood internalistically, would remain the same. Yet,
Heidegger would insist that without the tacit reference to his friend, the
activity would no longer make sense in the same way since the non-thematic
goal would no longer be a joint goal but now only an individual goal.
However, we must also account for the for-the-sake-of that, ex hypothesi,
affects how the environment of wood and potatoes solicits actions from the
campers. Suppose that the campers are a father and his teenage son. Father and
son have planned their camping trip a few weeks in advance but in the days before
their departure, the teenage son becomes inexplicably moody. The son is
conscientious and does not try to bail on the camping trip, although he complains
a lot. During the trip, he constantly listens to angry music with his headphones,
and he keeps a gloomy look on his face while peeling the potatoes. Do father and
son correctly coalesce in shared action? They did, of course, coordinate their
actions in pursuit of the joint goal of camping. However, another sense of the we
seems missing. Despite their coordination and their joint goal, father and son
perform, to some extent, their tasks next to rather than with each other.
Neither Bratman nor Gilbert sees any substantial difference between
these two examples. Bratman would say that each intends that they go
camping, that they have correctly meshing subplans, and that they operate
under conditions of common knowledge. For Gilbert, the decisive part is
that father and son constituted a plural subject when they expressed their
initial readiness to go on the camping trip and that they emulated a single
body in doing so. On this account, the attitude of the sulky teenager is
beyond rebuke, and, tellingly, Gilbert maintains that joint commitments
hold even under coercive circumstances (). In contrast, I believe that
there is a significant difference between the two cases and that the latter
case misses a crucial feature of genuine joint action even though a joint
goal is intended and achieved.
In brief, the difference consists in how the father and son relate to their
joint goal. What is similar between the two cases is the set of in-order-to’s
and what differs are the for-the-sake-of’s. The happy campers have a joint
goal and a joint commitment. Father and son go camping as an end-in-
itself, as we might say with reference to Kant. They go camping for the
Heidegger sometimes compares the for-the-sake-of with Kant’s end-in-itself in order to underline
that this type of commitment cannot be grounded in any further commitment. In , he for
example writes: ‘[Dasein] is for the sake of its own capacity-to-be-in-the-world’ and this constitutes
Forms of Being-With
sake of doing something together, and the affordances of the situation prompt
them to act in a specific way due to this joint commitment.
Like the happy campers, the father to the sulky teenager intends to go
camping for the sake of doing something with his son. Yet, the teenager
does not share this commitment. He is motivated by a different for-the-
sake-of than his father. Perhaps the son simply goes camping because he
does not want to get blamed for cancelling the trip. In any case, the son
pursues the joint goal in light of an individual rather than joint commit-
ment. Consequently, the father’s for-the-sake-of breaks down as it consti-
tutively depends on being shared by the son. This alters what the
environment solicits from him. The possibility of lighting a fire is now
less salient than, say, the possibility of going to bed early. The trip is a
failure for the father, not because father and son did not carry out the joint
goal that they had agreed upon, but because he tried to do something for
the sake of doing something together with his son and, alas, his son did not
share this commitment.
This shows that the existential joint commitment is not tantamount to a
reflective endorsement. It is pre-reflective in the sense that it is an integral
feature of how a shared environment solicits people to response. It is the
condition in light of which environmental affordances prompts us to act.
As a commitment, it retains a normative element, however, since our
project can succeed or fail in a way that is independent of the mere
teleology of the action. The sulky teenager shows that the success or failure
of shared action is not only measured by whether we achieve the goals that
we aim for but also by whether others on which our commitment depends
turn out to be similarly committed. In contrast to Schmid, who under-
stands joint commitment as the ‘constant normative pressure for coherence
between the attitudes of interacting individuals’ (a, ), the existential
the ‘structural element that motivated Kant to define the person ontologically as an end, without
inquiring into the specific structure of purposiveness and the question of its ontological possibility’
(GA, /).
Sánchez Guerrero makes a comparable point, when he argues that it is possible for a number of
individuals to pursue not only the actualisation of a certain possibility but also to do so as a group,
that is, by understanding themselves as group-members who act for the sake of the ‘wellbeing’ or
‘flourishing’ of the group that they constitute (e.g., , ). I agree with Sánchez Guerrero that
it is important to distinguish between the joint possibility or goal that the individuals try to
actualise, on the one hand, and whether they do so as a group or as individuals, on the other
hand. I think, however, that it is misleading to say that the individuals must act for the sake of the
group’s wellbeing or flourishing, since this seems to require a prolonged concern for the group and
that we entertain certain beliefs about the desires and goals of the group that lie beyond the concrete
goal currently being pursued. Instead, I propose that the joint for-the-sake-of requires that the
individuals are committed to the project only if the others are similarly committed.
Shared Action
account of joint commitments does not concern coherence between atti-
tudes as such but the fact that we sometimes care about things because we
simply assume this care to be shared by others. As the disappointed
father might complain: ‘I just wanted us to do something together
for once!’
It is central to Gilbert’s reflective concept of joint commitments that they
provide us with obligations and entitlements. For her, joint commitments are
the battle ground on which we coerce others to do their parts by invoking the
rights and duties that we conferred upon each other when we expressed our
readiness to undertake a joint commitment. Gilbertian joint commitments
are thus in no way opposed to reflection. In fact, they come most fully into
view when we explicitly remind each other and ourselves that we are jointly
committed to do something as a single body. Existential joint commitments
are very different for the father only feels the need to explicitly remind the son
of their agreement to go camping because their existential joint commitment
has already gone awry. When pre-reflective shared action succeeds, things go
smoothly and we don’t feel the need for overt normative exchanges. This need
only arises because the campsite no longer solicits father and son to spend
quality time with each other. Thus, when the father explicitly reminds his
son – and perhaps himself – that they agreed to go camping and have a good
time, their pre-reflective action has already been replaced by a reflective
substitute in which we recall and represent our intentions, beliefs, common
knowledge, obligations, and so on.
At this point of the camping trip, I imagine that things can go one of
two ways. Either the reproach is successful and the son tells what has been
bothering him after which father and son can finally enjoy their trip. In
this case, the shared action becomes, once again, pre-reflective. Or father
and son sit in awkward silence for the rest of the night deliberately forcing
themselves to remain seated although the fire no longer solicits them to sit
there, although the fire has lost its magic. In this case, the shared action
remains reflective.
To put the point differently, existential joint commitments do not concern the coherence or
consistency of our attitudes due to the fact that when we act pre-reflectively, we do not question
whether or not the attitudes of our co-agents cohere with our own. We simply act on the tacit
assumption that they do. The question whether our attitudes do in fact cohere only arises, when
pre-reflective shared action breaks down and we enter a reflective mode. This means that each of us
might experience something as a shared action to which we are jointly committed even if it later
turns out that we were wrong to tacitly assume others to be thus committed. Joint commitments are
intrinsic to the first-person perspective but fallible. As Heidegger once noted, in a passage where he
uses ‘decision’ [Entscheidung] to refer to the for-the-sake-of: ‘no individual among you can in any
manner ascertain about how any other individual has decided’ (GA, /; GAA, ).
Forms of Being-With
. Discourse
Let us turn to the genetic problem. We have seen that both Gilbert and
Bratman accounts for the transition from individual intentions and actions
to shared intentions and actions by arguing that there must be a thematic
interrelation between the individuals (either deliberate planning or a
mutually expressed readiness to form a joint commitment). Schmid, in
contrast, argues that the we is primary and explanatorily basic. For him, it
appears that the we is a fundamental explanans that cannot be explained
further (cf. Zahavi , ). The problem with Schmid’s alleged solution
to the genetic problem is, however, that it merely reverses the individual-
istic accounts so that the issue is no longer how to get from individual
intentionality to collective intentionality but how to get from collective
intentionality to individual intentionality. If the we is explanatorily and
developmentally prior to the I (a, f ), how are individual I’s carved
out from this primordial we?
Heidegger proposes less a solution than a dissolution of the genetic
problem. He rejects the methodological assumption that our interpretation
must proceed by reducing a given phenomenon to its building blocks, for
example, that we must explain the we in terms of individual I’s (or, in
Schmid’s case, individual I’s in terms of the we). Instead, he hopes to
identify a single structure or mechanism that makes both I, you, and we
possible without postulating that one of these phenomena is more funda-
mental than the others. As we have already seen, he claims that I, you, and
we are equiprimordial, not in the strong sense that we constantly live as an
I, a you, and a we, but in the weak sense that they are different modes of
the same basic process. I, you, and we are all explananda, and the shared
world is the fundamental explanans.
Following this approach, we should not ask how individual intentions
make shared intentions possible but rather which process transforms one
kind of solicitations (e.g., those of individual action) into another kind of
solicitation (e.g., those of shared action). I believe that this is the role
discourse [Rede] plays in SZ. Discourse is the expressive process in which
We find a similar problem in the later Merleau-Ponty’s conception of intercorporeality as the
‘primordial we’ that precedes and makes possible the differentiation into distinctly embodied I’s and
you’s (, ).
This is the stronger sense in which understanding, affectivity, and discourse are equiprimordial.
Shared Action
saliences are shared between people. To see how the account works, we
must, however, clarify a few textual issues that mar it.
As I mentioned in Section ., Heidegger distinguishes discourse from
‘language’ in the sense of the totality of words and linguistic utterances.
Discourse is, he claims, ‘[t]he existential-ontological foundation of lan-
guage’ (SZ, /). It is the ‘“significant” articulation of the intelligi-
bility of being-in-the-world, which belongs to being-with, and which in
every case maintains itself in some definite way of concernful being-with-
one-another’ (SZ, /). We have seen that significance and intelligi-
bility are constituted by the interrelation of in-order-to’s and for-the-sake-
of’s in a relational whole, so when Heidegger claims that discourse is what
articulates this structure and thus maintains a definite way of concernful
being-with-one-another, it seems he has in mind the process through which
a relational whole is shared between several Dasein, that is, the way in
which certain possibilities become salient to several people. Discourse
includes linguistic utterances insofar as these serve to communicate or
express saliences, but, as we have seen, Heidegger has a much wider range
of phenomena in mind than just speech acts.
This distinction between discourse and language has caused commentators
like Dreyfus and Haugeland to translate Rede with telling in the sense of
‘being able to tell the time, or tell the difference between kinds of nails’
(, ). On this reading, Rede simply refers to our ability to tell things
apart, to respond to them in a differentiated manner in our everyday practices
(e.g., Haugeland , ). Blattner (, f ) argues that whenever we
tell things apart and respond to them according to their respective purposes,
our behaviour will by itself express something along the lines of: This thing
is typically used for this purpose. Carman (, ) and McMullin (,
), however, object that Dreyfus, Haugeland, and Blattner fail to do justice
to the communicative or expressive aspect essential to discourse. Not only
is it somewhat perverse to use the term Rede to refer to a process that does
not necessarily include other people, on this account it is also rather difficult
to see what the existential of discourse adds to the structure of affectivity
and understanding outlined previously in SZ.
The problem is that Heidegger’s formulations are ambiguous. On the
one hand, he writes that ‘the very sense of discourse is discourse to others
and with others’ (GA, /, his italics), thereby indicating that
discourse only takes place when saliences are in fact shared between people.
Similarly, Heidegger claims that discourse is a ‘matter of being-with-one-
another becoming manifest in the world’ (GA, /). This seems to
Cf. Carman (, ).
Forms of Being-With
warrant Carman’s and McMullin’s claim that it is essential to discourse
that others are actually attuned to the world in the same way that we are,
that discourse succeeds in bringing about ‘co-understanding’ (SZ, /
, /) and ‘co-affectivity’ (SZ, /). On the other hand,
however, discourse can hardly depend on the ontic presence of others
insofar as it is an existential or ontological feature of Dasein’s being-in-the-
world in much the same way that being-with does not depend on others
actually being there (SZ, /). This means that although discourse is
indeed ‘discourse to others and with others’, it still makes ‘no difference for
the essential structure of discourse whether there is a fixed address directed
to a specific other or not’ (GA, /). Or, as he formulates the point
in , ‘[w]e are always speaking [sprechen], even when we do not utter a
single word aloud, but merely listen or read, and even when we are not
particularly listening or speaking but are attending to some work or taking
a rest’ (GA, /, see also Withy ).
Heidegger ultimately uses the term ‘discourse’ in two related but
ultimately distinct ways. In some places, ‘discourse’ refers to the existential
feature according to which our behaviour always already expresses the
whole of significance that guides our comportment. In other places,
‘discourse’ refers to the way in which this expression is received by others,
i.e., the process in which a whole of significance is made manifest to
others. The former is a general and constitutive capacity or feature of
Dasein, which is, hence, operative even when we do not talk and no one is
around. In this sense, I still express or communicate something when
I attend to some work all by myself. The latter is a process, which is
enabled by this general and constitutive capacity or feature, the actualisa-
tion of which obviously requires that someone is present to understand
what I express through my behaviour. In short, Heidegger’s concept of
discourse refers both to the process in which saliences are shared between
people and the condition of possibility of this process.
The reason for this ambiguity is that Heidegger attempts to avoid the
model according to which communication is ‘a matter of transporting
information and experiences from the interior of one subject to the interior
The fact that discourse is both an ontological feature and an interactive process is important if we
are to determine just what it adds to the structure of affectivity and understanding. In short, as an
ontological feature, discourse formally ensures that the whole of significance that guides my
comportment is indeed responsive to that of others, and as an interactive process with a concrete
set of peers, discourse gives content to this responsiveness. In the words of Haugeland, it is ‘one of
the basic cultural mechanisms by which the practical and cognitive achievements of the past are
preserved and propagated’ (, ).
Shared Action
of the other one’ (GA, /), that is, in order to avoid a model
according to which social phenomena – such as communication – are
explained in terms of pre-existing individual phenomena. As an ontological
feature, discourse refers to the ontological fact that we always already
‘participate in what is manifest’ (GA, /); that we both necessarily
express matrices of saliences and are constitutively responsive to the
matrices of salience that are expressed in the behaviour of others. This is
what makes interpersonal understanding (where we understand the exis-
tential projections of the other) and shared action (where our existential
projections are synchronised) possible.
As we have seen, discourse does not necessarily require linguistic utter-
ances but should be understood in the ontologically broad sense of
communication according to which all purposeful behaviour has the
potential of making certain possibilities salient for other people. Through
our words, our actions, or our gestures, we make the sharedness of the
world phenomenally transparent to each other. In this way, a nod or a
simple exchange of glances might transform an awkward situation so that it
is no longer an awkward situation for each of us but now a slightly less
awkward situation for us together. So, although discourse does not struc-
turally depend on the actual presence of others, it does ensure that we have
a potential for collective intentionality that is only fulfilled once several
agents have a sense that they are similarly attuned to the world.
Discourse has four structural elements: () That which is talked about
[das Beredete], () that which is said [das Geredete], () the communication
[die Mitteilung], and () the intimation [Bekundung] (SZ, /; GA,
f/f ). To cut a long story short, () what is talked about refers to an
entity or a relation in the world, while () that said calls attention to
something particular about this entity or relation; that is, it highlights
certain affordances, for example, by saying that ‘the chair is upholstered’
(GA, /). () Communication underlines that discourse is inher-
ently expressive, because discourse also lays these affordances out in the
open. It makes them manifest in a way that others can and sometimes
must respond to. When communication is successful, the said and talked
about affordances are raised into salience for multiple interacting agents.
Finally, () intimation refers to how the speaker necessarily ‘expresses itself’
in communication (SZ, /; GA, /) in the sense that the
speaker necessarily reveals something intimate about itself by way of
informal expressions like ‘intonation, modulation, the tempo of talk’
(SZ, /). Intimation refers to how the speaker herself stands in
relation to the manifested saliences. For instance, her tone of voice or
Forms of Being-With
the look in her face might reveal that she desires or is disgusted by
whatever is raised to joint attention.
In contrast to Gilbert’s account, according to which communication is
paradigmatically explicit and linguistic, Heidegger’s concept of discourse
targets all expressive behaviour, linguistic and non-linguistic. Pre-reflective
agency is always discursive in the sense that it expresses a certain concern
with the world. Occasionally, this discursive feature of agency causes
others to respond to the world in a way that converges with our own
way of responding. Once, we are aware of this convergence, we have pre-
reflective shared action. Sometimes the convergence is, of course, estab-
lished through linguistic utterances, but, in line with my discussion of the
camping trip, the measure of success of such communication is often
located at the pre-reflective level. As Heidegger writes regarding linguistic
utterances, the point is rarely to transfer ‘a store of heaped up propositions’
(or a set of occurrent mental states) between two independent individuals
(GA, /). Instead, ‘communication . . . should be seen as possi-
bilities by which one Dasein enters with the other into the same funda-
mental comportment toward the entity asserted about’ (GA, /).
In this vein, the point of discourse is not to ensure that our attitudes are
consistent, that we have the same pieces of knowledge and the same desires
and beliefs, but to orient agents towards the same saliences or possibilities
in a way that is immediately obvious to them.
That Dasein’s existence is necessarily discursive means that shared
action is not something that is somehow added on top of individual action.
Rather, in both individual action and shared action, our environment is
inherently shared with others, our behaviour is inherently expressive for
others, and our way of comporting ourselves is inherently responsive
to others.
The four elements of discourse also reveal the ways in which discourse might malfunction. In fact,
these ways of malfunctioning are essential to discourse in the sense that we cannot have discourse
without at least the possibility of these kinds of malfunctioning. The first form of malfunctioning
occurs when we lose sight of that which is talked about [das Beredete] in favour of that which is said
[das Geredete]. We exchange the appropriate glances and glosses with others (or ourselves) although
we do not really understand what we are talking about; that is, without having the appropriate
affective or practical grasp of the saliences that our discourse is supposed to make manifest. This
malfunctioning is what Heidegger calls idle talk [Gerede]. We can also imagine another form of
malfunctioning (unnamed by Heidegger) in which one speaker balances that which is talked about
[das Beredete] and that which is said [das Geredete] but where the communication [Mitteilung] fails
to convey this to others so that although they understand the concepts that the first speaker uses and
the inferences that he makes, this never sinks into the matrices of salience that guides their
comportment. This we might call idle communication.
Shared Action
Forms of Being-With
In this regard, Heidegger’s conception of anonymous social normativity is comparable to Ruth
Millikan’s () interpretation of ‘natural conventions.’ Yet, Millikan argues that natural
conventions, like all conventions, require knowledge of ‘genuine alternatives’ (, ). Heidegger
rejects this claim as phenomenologically incorrect.
Two Types of Social Normativity
that an agent acts deliberately by choosing A over B because A aligns with
the agent’s interests. As we saw above, conformity to Anyone-norms does
not require this kind of deliberation. In fact, the normative force of
Anyone-norms lies precisely in that we cohere to them without delibera-
tion and reflection. ‘The more openly the Anyone behaves, the harder it is
to grasp, and the slier it is, but the less is it nothing at all’ (SZ, /).
We tap into a set of norms fluidly and unthinkingly. Another way of
putting this point is that we conform to these norms neither for the sake of
us as in the case of jointly committed action nor for the sake of me as in
individually committed action but ‘for the sake of the Anyone’ (SZ, /
). In contrast to when I do something ‘for the sake of me’ or ‘for the
sake of us’, doing something ‘for the sake of the Anyone’ is not significant
to anyone in particular. When conforming to Anyone-norms we are thus
‘committed’ to something by default. This means that the Anyone provides
the standard possibilities that guide Dasein in the absence of overriding
concerns. As Heidegger puts the point, the Anyone causes Dasein to be
‘indifferent’ to its own being (SZ, /, /).
Who enforces anonymous social normativity? For Lewis, conventions
require that almost everyone in a population conform to a regularity. For
Searle, an institutional fact comes with deontic power that must be
recognised both by those concrete people who have the power and by
those concrete people who are subjected to the power. The who of
Background/Network power, on the other hand, refers to anybody within
a specific community. Heidegger, however, writes: ‘The “who” is not this
one, not that one, not oneself [man selbst], not some people [einige], and
not the sum of them all. The “who” is the neuter, the Anyone’ (SZ, /
). This means that the Anyone does not refer to a specifiable fraction of
a given population, nor even to everyone or even an objective average within
a specific community. Rather, when we are under the guise of the Anyone,
we are completely unaware of the extent of the social norms that we follow.
When Heidegger says ‘anyone’, he does not mean anyone within a distinct
community, as Searle does, since this still implies an awareness that the
social norms that we follow have a limited extension. Instead, the norm in
question is assumed to apply to anyone in general. It is assumed to be a
universal default. As Mulhall has pointed out, Dasein’s indifference to itself
‘is realized in an essentially undifferentiated existence’ (, ). It is, of
course, almost never correct to assume that a social norm is a universal
In Chapter , I contrast the idea that the Anyone commits us to something by default with a
particular kind of normativity – attributability – which is closely linked to authenticity.
Forms of Being-With
default. We easily realise this when we reflect on the social norms in
question. But this is exactly the point: Someone under the guise of the
Anyone does not reflect on the social norms that they conform to and are,
hence, not aware of their limited extension.
Finally, we ask: Whence does anonymous social normativity come?
What grounds it? Lewisian conventions are grounded in the joint rational
pursuit of interests. Searlian institutional facts are grounded in collective
intentionality. Admittedly, Heidegger does not provide an explicit answer
to the whence-question, but in light of the analysis of being-with presented
above, I’ll attempt to construct an argument, which I take to be largely
consistent with the textual evidence and to have the added advantage of
clarifying some of the more difficult concepts and notions in Heidegger’s
analysis.
Fredrik Westerlund has recently argued that the main motive that
underlies Dasein’s sensitivity to social pressure and conformity is ‘our
desire for social affirmation’. He writes,
We want to be affirmed and accepted by our group and we dread the
prospect of incurring its hostility and contempt. This motive goes deep in
us and tends to fuel both our self-perception and our identity. . . . Whereas
seeing ourselves as likeable and affirmable incurs feelings of pride and self-
confidence, seeing ourselves as unlikeable and despicable makes us feel
embarrassment and shame. (Westerlund , )
There is something to be said for Westerlund’s reconstruction. It seems
quite plausible that Heidegger’s concept of the Anyone is indeed supposed
to show how our ‘desire for social affirmation’ propels us to measure
ourselves and others in light of social norms. But, as Westerlund (,
) notes, Heidegger’s own account does not invoke the moral psycho-
logical terminology of ‘motives’ and emotions like ‘pride’ and ‘shame’. The
reason for this is, I believe, that although our desire for social affirmation
might be one of the surface phenomena that Heidegger wish to under-
stand, his aim is to uncover the ontological foundation of our responsive-
ness to social norms. Westerlund’s moral psychological reconstruction
presupposes rather than illuminates this foundation. To put it bluntly,
our capacity for feeling, for instance, shame and for seeing ourselves as
unlikeable because we fail to conform to some social norm clearly pre-
supposes that we have a basic understanding of what a social norm is.
Although our basic desire for social affirmation might be a ‘deep’ or ‘basic’
motive for us, it is, as a mere motive, unsatisfactory as an answer to the
whence-question of social normativity.
Two Types of Social Normativity
Instead, I think Heidegger’s notion of distantiality is supposed to answer
the whence-question. This is clear once we see that it involves triangulation.
Distantiality, I suggested, refers to how we constantly care about others, what
they do, and the way in which we and our actions differ from them. In short,
we measure ourselves against others. In SZ, Heidegger formulates this idea in
dismissive terms, but we have already encountered the systematic foundation
of this point. In triangulation, we use three elements – the shared environ-
ment, the other, and ourselves – as measuring points, and we achieve an
understanding of all three by correlating environmental stimuli and purposive
responses. The other’s behaviour will cause us to refine the field of possibilities
through which we navigate the world; that is to say, whatever the other does
affects how we understand our environment and ourselves. In this sense, we
are, qua triangulation, constitutively responsive to the behaviour of others. If,
as I have argued, triangulation is a transcendental feature of Dasein, it follows
that we measure ourselves against the other, that ‘there is a constant care as to
the way one differs from [others]’ (SZ, /).
Triangulation alone does not entail conformity, and thus we have yet
to account for Dasein’s basic understanding of what a social norm is. If,
however, the triangulating creatures are also temporal creatures with habits
and memories, certain patterns of purposive responses will sooner or later
reproduce themselves by the weight of precedent. Only at this point, do
we get anonymous social norms of the type described by Heidegger.
In discussing different types of rule-following, Haugeland arrives at a
similar story:
[C]ommunity members effectively promote similarities in how they and
their fellows are disposed to behave relative to circumstances. This pre-
supposes that they can tell who behaved how in what circumstances, and
how that compares with what others would have done; it also presupposes
that they can modify their own and each other’s dispositions in the
direction of conformity. . . . Assuming the dynamic parameters are com-
patible with stability, this institutes a community with a common set of
social customs and mores. (Haugeland , )
Haugeland takes a process of stabilisation, incurred by our ability to track
how the behaviour of others correlates with our shared environment, to be
Carman’s interprets distantiality as a form of ‘standoffishness’ that instils a ‘departure from everyday
understanding in its mundane form’ in which ‘normality and abnormality as such become the focus
of our concern’ (, ). But this cannot be right, since it makes distantiality a rare
phenomenon. Rather, I contend with Dreyfus, that distantiality ‘denotes an essential structure of
all Dasein’s activity that inconspicuously reduces difference and so performs the ontological function
of establishing norms and thus opening up a shared human world’ (, ).
Forms of Being-With
the genesis of group formations. Community members respond to how
others behave, they track this behaviour over time, and thereby they come to
modify their own behaviour in the direction of conformity. Heidegger’s
account uses two interrelated and partly overlapping terms, averageness and
levelling down, to describe a similar process of stabilisation. He says that
distantiality ‘is grounded in the fact that being-with-one-another concerns
itself as such with averageness [Durchscnittlichkeit]’ (SZ, /). The
Anyone concerns itself with averageness in the sense that it orients itself
towards what is assumed to be the standard, that is, the universal default:
‘The Anyone maintains itself factically in the averageness of that which
belongs to it, of that which it regards as valid and that which it does not,
and of that to which it grants success and that to which it denies it’ (SZ, /
). The concern for averageness is the drift towards a default that occurs
once we are continuously exposed to each other in distantiality.
At the level of lived experience, the result is a ‘levelling down of all
possibilities of being’ (SZ, /). Once we are continuously exposed to
a precedent – a certain way of doing things – we unconsciously accept it as
the standard way of doing things. It thereby becomes the salient way of
doing things. So, unless something exceptional happens – unless the tool
breaks down, we face a new unprecedented situation, or we consciously
decide to try something new – our possibilities of acting and being will
simply be the possibilities prescribed by the Anyone.
In conclusion, the Anyone provides social norms in the form of com-
portmental patterns reproduced through the weight of precedent that we
conform to by default under the tacit assumption that it is a universal
default. Furthermore, the Anyone is an existential feature of Dasein
because it follows from our continued (qua averageness) exposure to or
triangulation with others (qua distantiality).
See also Carman‘s suggestion that discourse ‘constitutes the bridge between the anonymous social
normativity of das Man and the concrete interpretive practices of individual human agents’, because
there is a ‘generic drift of discourse towards anonymity and banality’ (, ).
Two Types of Social Normativity
norms – a measure of what is appropriate in a given situation – the validity
of which is taken for granted. Heidegger then goes on to characterise the
public in clearly contemptuous terms: The public ‘is insensitive to every
difference of level and of genuineness and thus never gets to the “heart of
the matter” [“auf die Sachen”]’; it ‘obscures everything and presents that
which has been covered over as what is familiar and accessible to everyone’
(SZ, /).
Olafson argues that what is thus covered over is the possibility of an
authentic life beyond the confines of the Anyone. But this contradicts
Heidegger’s claim that authenticity is not ‘an exceptional condition of the
subject that has been detached from the Anyone’ (SZ, /). So, which
phenomenon is covered over by the public? My suggestion is that the
public covers over the fact that any given set of social norms is ultimately
arbitrary by presenting it as a universal default. Thus, the public brings a
‘tranquillised self-assurance – “being-at-home”, with all its obviousness –
into the average everydayness of Dasein’ (SZ, /). As members of
‘the public’, we take for granted a standard of intelligibility, an average; we
take it to be the standard of intelligibility. What is thereby suppressed or
covered over is ‘everything unfamiliar’ (SZ, /) and ‘exceptional’
(SZ, /), which is to say, all the possibilities of doing and being
something that do not fit this socially inflected comportmental pattern.
For this reason, Heidegger associates the Anyone with the inflexibility of
what he calls ‘stubbornness’ [Versteifung] (SZ, /, cf. Blattner
, ).
Olafson is right that Dasein can indeed overcome any given set of social
norms that happen to shape its way of interpreting the world. But it
cannot (pace Olafson) overcome the normative pressure towards coherence
and relatively stable models of prediction. What is essential – indeed, what
is a transcendental feature of Dasein – is not its conformity to any specific
set of social norms but its generic drift towards social norms.
After noting that Dasein discloses its possibilities in terms of heritage, Heidegger writes that ‘[i]n
one’s coming back resolutely to one’s thrownness, there is hidden a handing down to oneself of the
possibilities that have come down to one, but not necessarily as having thus come down [Das
entschlossene Zurückkommen auf die Geworfenheit birgt ein Sichüberliefern überkommener
Möglichkeiten in such, obzwar nicht notwendig als überkommener]’ (SZ, /). These claims are,
admittedly, difficult to reconcile, and in their translation of SZ, Macquarrie and Robinson notes that
the sentence is grammatically ambiguous. What does it mean that the possibilities handed down are
‘not necessarily [disclosed] as having thus come down’? As Katherine Ward (, ) explains, this
can mean one of two things: Either the factical possibilities are, in contrast to what I have just said,
not necessarily handed down as heritage or the process through which the possibilities are handed
down is not necessarily disclosed along with the possibilities that are disclosed as heritage. I agree
with Ward that the latter interpretation must be correct for both textual and systematic reasons.
Read in this light, the claim is that resolute Dasein is necessarily aware of what I below call the
modality of its social norms but not necessarily explicitly (or philosophically) aware of the process or
structure that enables this modal change.
Two Types of Social Normativity
through what Heidegger calls ‘historiology [Historie]’, that is, scientific or
quasi-scientific inquiry into the past. ‘It is not necessary that in resolute-
ness one should explicitly know the origin of the possibilities upon which
that resoluteness projects itself’ (SZ, /). Instead of being aware of
the genealogy of our social norms, Heidegger believes that we should
become aware of their modality. This happens in ‘repetition’
[Wiederholung]:
The resoluteness which comes back to itself and hands itself down, then
becomes the repetition of a possibility of existence that has come down to
us. Repeating is handing down explicitly – that is to say, going back into the
possibilities of the Dasein that has-been-there. (SZ, /)
Repetition does not mean that we somehow go back in history and ‘bring
back something that is “past”’ (SZ, /). After all, existential pro-
jections are holistically constituted and rely upon a vast network of in-
order-to’s. For example, it no longer makes sense to bring back the
possibility of being a knight or a samurai, because the social and instru-
mental networks that made these social roles possible are long gone. The
possibilities repeated and emphatically handed down must remain within
their historical or cultural milieu.
Heidegger’s point is that in repeating a historical possibility, it is no
longer a default but something that we actively choose and commit
ourselves to. Dasein ‘may choose its hero’ and thus ‘choose the choice
which makes one free for the struggle of loyally following in the footsteps
of that which can be repeated’ (SZ, /). So, instead of just following
in the footsteps of the Anyone, Dasein now chooses to follow a precedent as
a precedent or as heritage. What is repeated is a factical possibility rather
than a new possibility but in repeating it we become aware of it in a new
way, namely, as an ultimately contingent product of our historical situa-
tion. ‘By repetition, Dasein first has its own history made manifest’
(SZ, /).
Heidegger argues that this modal change provides Dasein with a more
flexible and phronetically fine-grained understanding of its world, because
Dasein, no longer committed by default to a set of socially typified
possibilities, is now free to pursue possibilities that deviate from this
taken-for-granted default. He expresses this by saying that the Anyone
only knows ‘the general situation’ [Lage], where this means that Dasein
simply assumes that it already understands the available and relevant
possibilities of a situation. In his formulation, Dasein ‘represents the
situation to itself’ prior to entering it (SZ, /), whereas the resolute
Forms of Being-With
Dasein is ‘called forth into the situation [Situation]’ in order for it to ‘take
action’ (SZ, /). In contrast to the inflexible and highly typified
possibilities of anonymous social normativity, Dasein develops a ‘gradual
refinement of responses’ (Dreyfus , ). Although, as I have argued,
we cannot leave the Anyone behind, this lessens the ‘dictotorial hold’ that
anonymous social normativity has on us (Knowles , ).
A further consequence of this type of historical awareness is that we
become aware that our social norms are the norms of a particular commu-
nity. Heidegger formulates this point by drawing a parallel between the fate
[Schicksal] of the individual and the destiny [Geschick] of the community.
Fate is the ‘simplicity [Einfachheit]’ achieved once Dasein tears itself away
from ‘the endless multiplicity of possibilities which offer themselves as
closest to one’ by seizing a single possibility that is ‘inherited and chosen at
the same time’ (SZ, /). David Carr formulates this point well:
[W]hat the individual is is thus a function of his or her place in a historical
setting. This is not a ‘straightforward’ affirmation of the sort that might be
made by a historical determinist, who calls the individual a ‘product’ of
history or the inevitable result of historical forces. Instead it is a phenom-
enological assertion about what the individual is ‘for himself.’ It means
that the individual’s self-understanding of himself passes through history.
(Carr , )
While this sounds like a heroic individualism, Heidegger goes on to argue
that since Dasein is constitutively being-with, ‘its happening [Geschehen] is
a co-happening [Mitgeschen] and is determined as destiny [Geschick]. This is
how we designate the happening of community, of the people’ (SZ, /
). The point is that in being fatefully committed to a factical possibil-
ity, say, my role as a teacher, I am not only committed to this possibility as
an atomistic possibility. Since existential projections are holistically con-
stituted, I also become co-responsible for the social and historical condi-
tions that make this possibility possible. Thus, in resoluteness, I become
aware that the possibility I choose to commit myself to depends on
contingent social and historical factors, and I commit myself to sustain
these background relations to the best of my ability. I commit myself to
the individual activity of teaching and the community or, rather, the
institution of teaching.
Some find the invocation of people and community highly suspect and
see it as a direct precursor to Heidegger’s fatal politics. Crowell, for
This suspicion is supported by Karl Löwith‘s description of his last meeting with Heidegger in which
Löwith suggested that Heidegger’s support of National Socialism stemmed from his philosophy.
Two Types of Social Normativity
instance, argues that Heidegger moves on ‘very shaky ground’, when he
juxtaposes fate and destiny, individual and community. Resoluteness, as
Crowell understands it, amounts to a form of self-responsibility. And
communities, he argues, lack the ontological structure required for self-
responsibility because they have ‘no first person’ (, ). This yields two
illusions: ‘first, that in choosing I am choosing for my whole community;
and second, that what I can choose must somehow be a function of that
very community’ (, ).
However, Crowell is wrong on both counts. First, Heidegger’s point is
not I can somehow choose for my whole community, as this implies that
I am in a position where I can choose for everyone else. Instead, he
suggests that I, in making my choice, am also choosing the community
itself. I commit myself to sustain the social and historical conditions for a
factical possibility. Thus, in choosing to be a good teacher, I also commit
myself to not sabotaging faculty meetings and to not selling drugs to my
students even when I am off work, as these activities would eventually
undermine the very institution that is a prerequisite for being a good
teacher. Second, Crowell believes that there is no way in which what
I choose is a function of the community, but this is equally wrong.
Although my choice depends on an irreducible form of self-responsibility,
self-responsibility is insufficient to account for the choice. Not only are the
different factical possibilities among which I choose holistically and socially
individuated qua the in-order-to relations, but, as I have argued, my
commitments themselves occasionally depend on others being similarly
committed. Being a teacher, I will eventually lose my sense of purpose if
I get the sense that my students could not care less about what
I teach them.
Furthermore, the claim that community has no first-person reveals that
Crowell understands community in a strangely reified way. In contrast, the
very point of Heidegger’s two accounts of social normativity is that
community is an integral part of the first-person perspective. As I have
argued, we see this in the way that other’s behaviour sets a precedent for
me so that I unconsciously adopt it as the standard for how anyone should
act in a similar situation. Expanding upon this basic insight, Heidegger
believes that individuals are members of groups and communities once
Heidegger reportedly confirmed this without any reservations and specified that his conception of
historicity [Geschicklichkeit] provided the foundation of his political commitment (, ).
However, it is important to note that this remark was made in at which point, as I argue
below, Heidegger’s conception of history has changed dramatically. For this reason, Löwith’s
testimony does not by itself provide evidence against the SZ-account.
Forms of Being-With
they understand themselves, others, and their shared environment in light
of the field of possibilities characteristic of these groups and communities.
Once conceived on the basis of pre-reflective triangulation, it becomes
clear the communities are irreducibly first personal, although first personal
plural. In Heidegger’s own words:
Destiny is not something that puts itself together out of individual fates,
any more than being-with-one-another can be conceived as the occurring
together of several subjects. Our fates have already been guided in advance,
in our being-with-one-another in the same world and in our resoluteness
for definite possibilities. (SZ, /)
So, in contrast to Crowell’s individualism, Heidegger understands I and we
as emerging from the same holistically constituted world.
As I argue in detail below, there is no necessary connection between
Heidegger’s conception of history and his political engagement.
Nevertheless, historical social normativity does modify social life in a
way that underpins and makes politics possible. Historical social norma-
tivity implies an awareness of social norms as the social norms of a
particular community. It thereby also enables us to understand our com-
munity in contrast to other communities. Historical social normativity
involves in-group/out-group discrimination. Through historical awareness,
we realise that the social norms taken for granted in everydayness are not
only contingent but ontologically fragile, that our way of making sense of
things can fail or breakdown. Therefore, the communal space of possibil-
ities requires commitment and sometimes even a kind of protection if we
are to sustain our sense-making practices. Heidegger alludes to this proto-
political aspect of historical social normativity by saying that ‘the power of
destiny becomes free in communication [Mitteilung] and struggle [Kampf]’
(SZ, /).
In a similar vein, Samuel Scheffler‘s Death and the Afterlife describes what we might characterise as a
breakdown of a global communal commitments. He argues that in a world where – due to, say,
general infertility – the currently living human beings would be the last, ‘people would lose
confidence in the value of many sorts of activities, would cease to see reason to engage in many
Forms of Being-With
Returning to the eerie example from Section ., we now see that when
he connects the we of the lecture hall to the we of the people by appealing
to the patriotism of his students, Heidegger tries to instil a communal
commitment in them. I will show this in more detail in the next chapter,
where I examine Heidegger’s political philosophy by asking which com-
munal commitments he considers worthwhile, why he does so, and how he
hopes to sustain these.
familiar sorts of pursuits, and would become emotionally detached from many of those activities
and pursuits’ (, ).
Two Types of Social Normativity
Heidegger’s discussion of social normativity is complicated by the fact
that he fails to distinguish between community understood as an existen-
tial condition and community understood as an existentiell ideal. My
discussion makes clear that authentic historicity is an existentiell possibility
(SZ, /) that derives its content from anonymous social normativity.
Anonymous social normativity is thereby existential because the Anyone in
the form of a generic drift towards stabilised social norms is an unavoidable
feature of social life. As these norms spring from the unconscious processes
of distantiality, averageness, and levelling down, they are initially ontolog-
ically obscure to the individual. Historical social normativity is an ideal in
which we are aware of this dimension of our own being. This is required if
we are to assume responsibility for our communities. However, as
Heidegger realised during his brief appearance on the political scene, such
awareness is a difficult seed to plant in the minds of others.
Politics and Authenticity
Heidegger’s Politics
I will not attempt to reconstruct why Heidegger thought that there was a special connection between
the Germans and the Greeks but this assumption is not uncommon in German intellectual history.
See Schmidt () and Heller ().
See also Bambach (), Kisiel (), and Knudsen (). See Sikka ().
Politics and Authenticity
conception of the history of being, and I will return to this in the next
section. First, however, we must see how Heidegger in the ‘s imagines
that his fellow Germans will come to share his commitment to a philo-
sophically infused nationalism.
If Heidegger’s commitment to nationalism seems rather trivial, so will
his ideas of how to sustain this communal commitment. He appeals, first
and foremost, to two institutions – the state and the educational system.
As he sees it, these are instrumental in establishing the prolonged and
large-scale we of the German people. This is particularly evident in the
politically charged speeches that he held as rector of Freiburg University in
the period from April to April and in his lecture courses from
to that centres around the themes of history, people, and state
(NHS, GA, GAA, GA, GA). In these texts, Heidegger not only
tries to instil nationalism in his students but also offers a philosophical,
although fragmentary, analysis of the National Socialist state.
For Heidegger, the state is not simply a governing body that sovereignly
posits laws (as in the rule of power) nor is at a governing body that
exercises power while being constrained by the law or constitution (as in
the rule of law). In his characteristic way, Heidegger dismisses these
conceptions of the state as ontic quarrels that must be bracketed in favour
of an ontological interpretation. He formulates the point in a variety of
ways but the general direction of the argument is clear: The state is
not simply an ontic institution but ‘the historical being of the people’
(GA, /; cf. GAA, ; GA, /, /; NHS, ).
The similarity to the analytic of Dasein is obvious; we must examine not
entities but their being. But what exactly does Heidegger mean when
suggesting that the state is the historical being of the people? Drawing
on Hegel’s understanding of the state as spirit, Heidegger contends that
the state is the ‘self-becoming’ or the ‘self-consciousness’ of the historical
Dasein of a people (e.g., GA, /, /). Hegel understands this
in terms of the objectification of freedom, while Heidegger, in contrast,
cashes out this idea in terms of finite existence: The state becomes a name
for the ‘care of the people (not ‘for’ the people)’ (GA, /). The care
is not ‘for’ the people because the state is not an external governing body
that takes care of the interests of the people. Rather, it is a care of the
people in the dual sense that the people is both subject and object of care.
The state is not something distinct from the people, not something that
governs on its behalf. It is, rather, the people’s care for itself. It is a form of
‘self-willing’ (GA, /). Heidegger’s notion of ‘the state’ thus aligns
with his conception of communal commitments; the state is the way in
Heidegger’s Politics
which a community gives shape to its own existence and cares about
its own endurance. In his terms, the state is that ‘by virtue of whose decree
the people first secures for itself historical duration, that is, the preservation
of their mission and the struggle over its mandate’ (GA, /;
GAA, ). The state is, it seems, the people’s way of being at issue
for itself.
Which exact ontic shape this communal care takes depends on the
community in question: ‘[C]onstitution and law are the actualisation of
our decision for the state – they are factical attestations of what we take to
be our historical task as a people, the task that we are trying to live out’
(NHS, ). In other words, the state is the community’s attempt to give
itself an enduring form, to provide itself with a temporally prolonged
equilibrium. As the exact form of this equilibrium depends on the partic-
ular community, Heidegger emphasises that his analysis of the state in no
way amounts to a general legal theory: ‘[O]ne cannot establish a theory of
the state that is not already built upon particular ties to the being of a
people’ (NHS, ).
Heidegger believes that the historical task of the Germans is incompat-
ible with the idea of civil liberties and constitutional democracy. In line
with his times, he explicitly endorses the authoritarian Führerprinzip
according to which the Führer or leader has the sole authority over all
governmental structures. In Heidegger’s words, the leader ‘thinks much
and wills knowingly – what the people want, who indeed do not know
what they want, but precisely in the leader come to themselves’
(GA, /). Paradoxically, the state is the care of the people for
itself, and yet, it is the state, embodied by the leader, that first unifies the
people: ‘The will of the leader first transforms the others into a following,
and from the following arises a community’ (NHS, ).
Heidegger never offers any argument for this authoritarianism, but it is
an intrinsic part of his politics. He simply assumes that the leader has an
extraordinary insight into the historical task of the people. Accordingly, the
leader assigns everyone else a specific role that they must fulfil in pursuit of
this task. ‘“State” . . . should consist in the “fact” that one commands and
the others obey!’ (GA, /). The state provides the people with ‘an
order in the sense of mastery, rank, leadership, and following’ (NHS, ).
In other words, the leader provides the institutional hierarchy necessary to
sustain and enforce the cultural particularity of the German people. In
contrast, people without state and without homeland – like ‘the Semitic
nomads’ – ‘are in constant danger of losing their peoplehood and perish-
ing’ (NHS, f ).
Politics and Authenticity
In line with my analysis of shared action and social normativity,
Heidegger’s account of communal commitments involves both a teleolog-
ical and a normative element. It involves ‘both an understanding of [] the
goal and engagement – that is, a leap into the accomplishment of the
goal – along with [] persistence, which makes the engaged person
develop’ (NHS, , numbers added). Mere authoritarianism is more or
less sufficient to ensure [] the teleology, that is, that all citizens obey and
do their part. But for Heidegger, the citizens must also be [] committed to
the task: ‘The true implementation of the will is not based on coercion,
but on awakening the same will in another’ (NHS, ). The citizens must
align their wills with the will of the leader; they must share his commit-
ment to the order of the state.
The important task of ensuring this commitment befalls the educational
system. Indeed, as the notebook entries, speeches, and manuscripts pro-
duced during and slightly after he was rector shows, Heidegger sees
education as a way of tying students to the state. He writes, for instance:
‘Education [Erziehung] – [is] the effective and binding realisation of the
power of the state as the will of the people to itself’ (GA, /).
Similarly, in the semester after having stepped down as rector, he notes in a
lecture manuscript:
‘Political education’! All education is ‘political’ – i.e. co-grounding and
developing and retaining the Dasein of the state. The people is brought
up into the state and only through this does it become the people. Whereby
the state is not something ‘outside’ of the ‘people’. (GA, /)
This idea is also the background for Heidegger’s infamous Rectorship
Address. Here, Heidegger points out that his acceptance of the rectorship
reveals a ‘commitment to the spiritual leadership of the university’
(GA, /). In accordance with the Führerprinzip, such leadership
must direct and awaken the will of the followers – the faculty and the
students (GA, /). This requires a ‘clarity, rank, and power’ that is
only attained when the leaders are ‘themselves led by the inexorability of
that spiritual mission which impresses onto the fate of the German people
the stamp of their history’ (GA, /).
In assuming the Rectorship, Heidegger anticipated a ‘revolution within
the university’ (GA, /) similar to the authoritarian revolution that
had just taken place within the state. However, in Heidegger’s self-
understanding, this revolution is not simply a grasp for power, and his
assumption of the rectorship is not, as has been suggested, an instance of
personal opportunism (e.g., Bourdieu , ). Rather, in line with his
Heidegger’s Politics
understanding of the cultural and philosophical particularity of the
German people, his professed aim is to elevate the German people to
the philosophical height of ‘the questionableness of being in general’
(GA, /). In James Phillips’ () excellent phrase, Heidegger is
driven by an ‘ontological opportunism’. He believes that the rectorship
provides an opportunity for his metaphysical revolution to gain traction.
Before showing how he attempts to justify his politics with reference to
the history of being, let me briefly summarise the understanding of
communal commitments operative in Heidegger’s politics by contrasting
it to the types of we analysed in the previous chapter. The Anyone
designates a community-wide social normativity that coordinates comport-
ments by offering a pattern of interlinked in-order-to’s and for-the-sake-
of’s. There is, however, no joint commitment in this type of social
normativity, and the community members are not aware of the norms
that they follow as norms. There is a we, a communal practice, that guides
the comportment of each individual, but this we is not phenomenally
transparent.
In historical social normativity, the individuals are aware of the com-
munal and fragile nature of their social norms and that these are, poten-
tially, threatened by other social norms. This makes the individuals capable
of communally committing to their social norms in such a way that they
not only follow the trajectories outline by anonymous in-order-to’s but
also commit to these in a way that depends on other community-members
(past, present, and future) being similarly committed.
Communal commitments occasionally require that we assume respon-
sibility for the social norms that structure our communal life. This is what
Heidegger, variously, calls a ‘self-affirmation’, a ‘self-willing’, or ‘the care of
the people’. In Heidegger’s ontological analysis, the state simply is the
community’s care for itself. Depending on the specific normative content
of the communal commitment, the state can take many forms (e.g., liberal
or socialist, constitutional or authoritarian) but the general idea is that the
community’s care for itself causes it to establish certain ontic institutions
whose aim is to ensure, enforce, and maintain its own unification over
time and against the external forces threatening to disrupt its unity.
On this point, I agree with Rorty‘s (, –) conjecture that it would not have affected
Heidegger’s philosophy if he had lived a politically innocent life. See also Hans Ruin’s ()
argument that Heidegger’s idea of destiny is progressive and conservative at the same time.
Rorty emphasises this aspect of the history of being when claiming that ‘the only thing which links
[Heidegger] with the tradition is his claim that the tradition, though persistently sidetracked onto
beings, was really concerned with Being all the time – and, indeed, constituted the history of being’
(, ).
See Okrent‘s reply to Rorty: ‘The actual content that Heidegger gives to his history of Being is both
discovered through and different from the actual content of the history of philosophy. It is
discovered through the tradition in that it traces what is forgotten by but necessary for each
specific moment in the history of philosophy’ (, ).
Heidegger’s Politics
which entities make sense and that it is impossible to arrive at an
ahistorical and foundational description of being [Seyn].
HoB The history of being is a narrative about a decline in Western
culture that culminates in the nihilism of the modern techno-
logical age.
HoB The history of being is the claim that an awareness of the human
being’s situatedness within this historical structure will remedy
(part of ) this nihilism.
For Heidegger, these ideas are woven together in roughly the following
way: (HoB ) The historical account of what philosophers mean when they
say ‘being’ enables us to elucidate (HoB ) the transcendental correlation
between human and world that they have systematically overlooked.
Assuming that philosophers have ‘played a privileged role in opening up
for their culture the possibilities given by the prevailing understanding of
being’ (Wrathall , ), this history of metaphysics reveals (HoB )
the understanding of being characteristic of different historical epochs.
This leads to (HoB ) a narrative of steady decline starting with the ancient
Greeks and culminating in modern technology. If, however, (HoB ) we
were to realise HoB -, we would be able to remedy this decline and
inaugurate a new beginning for Western philosophy and (hence) Western
civilisation at large.
This cursory overview shows the insufficiency of claiming that
Heidegger’s politics and antisemitism are ‘being-historical’, as Trawny
This is what Wrathall calls ‘the universal and total grounds thesis’: ‘Within each historical
(metaphysical) age, there is a particular understanding of being in terms of which entities show
up and make sense. This understanding of being is universal, meaning it determines every entity as
such. It is also total, meaning it also governs every way that entities can relate to and interact with
each other’ (, ).
In Iain Thomson‘s summary: ‘Before Nietzsche, the metaphysical tradition had refused to give up
the foundationalist project of securely “grounding” beings in an ontotheological Being of beings,
despite the fact that its own history, as an unbroken succession of epochal overturnings (in which
each metaphysically grounded epoch rose from the ashes of the metaphysics which preceded it),
shows that time and again metaphysics has proven incapable of providing itself with the
unimpeachable ontotheological foundation it sought. Ironically, the epoch of the metaphysical
tradition which Nietzsche himself inaugurates now effectively deprives itself, and thus us, of any
ground whatsoever. The groundless Nietzschean metaphysics of eternally recurring will-to-power
pre-conceptualizes “the totality of beings as such” as concatenations of energy in the service of
human will’ (, ).
Guignon expresses the idea in the following way: ‘[W]e have reached a moment in which the
history of the West is up for decision: either the future will bring nothing but an endless dark night
of minor variations on this “metaphysics to end all metaphysics”, as the ever-greater presence of
machination and giganticism dominating the world seems to foretell, or it may happen that the
“future ones”, the ones who might yet respond in the appropriate way to the call of be-ing, will
open up a site in which entities can show up in their question-worthiness’ (, ).
Politics and Authenticity
() and Di Cesare () have recently suggested. How exactly does
Heidegger use these elements to justify his politics? And which, if any, can
be salvaged?
Let me lay my cards on the table. Although they might offer a novel
approach to the history of philosophy, I doubt that HoB and HoB are
fine-grained enough to yield convincing phenomenological analyses.
I accept a moderate version of HoB , the claim that historical and social
conditions shape how we disclose entities, but not the stronger claim that
historical epochs fully determine how things are meaningful for the same
reasons that I reject the strong version of social externalism in favour of
weak or open-ended externalism. Further, I have yet to hear a convincing
argument in support of the assumption that philosophers play a ‘privileged
role’ in opening an understanding of being. These issues aside, however,
the real problem – the smoking gun, if you will – is how Heidegger in the
‘s and early ‘s ties together HoB and HoB in a geopolitical knot
according to which some people embody modern nihilism while other
people represent the only hope for a new metaphysics.
To be sure, Heidegger does not outline a political philosophy in any
traditional sense. He is not interested in questions about liberty, justice,
rights, authority, etc. This kind of philosophy ‘avoids the essential ques-
tion’ (GA, /). In a passage alluding to Lenin’s famous question
‘What is to be done?’ (‘Что делать?’ or in German ‘Was tun?’), he
describes the central motif of his ‘political philosophy’ in a way that is
bound to leave any political theorist dumbfounded:
Then what is to be done? That which you already had to do all along:
exercise relentlessly the simple craft of interpreting the great thinkers, of
getting used to long thinking, and think for yourself – in concealment –
that which is most necessary for you to think. (GA, /)
This shows the close relation between Heidegger’s politics and the history
of philosophy (i.e., HoB ): It is politically imperative that we study the
history of being by relentlessly reading the great thinkers!
The underlying point is that Heidegger’s support for the regime and his
projected reformation of the university is motivated by his hope for a
metaphysical revolution. Hence, he argues that the individual must both
‘restrain’ and ‘empower’ itself by binding itself to the people. He then asks:
‘What does this restraining empowerment presuppose existentielly
Löwith recalls that the students, who witnessed the rectoral address, were unsure whether they
should go home and read the pre-Socratics or go marching with the SA (, ). Well, here is
the answer.
Heidegger’s Politics
[existenziell]?’ His answer hinges on the assumption (HoB ) that an
understanding of being characterises a historical epoch and the idea
(HoB ) that philosophy – and in this case, Heidegger’s own philosophy –
can bring about a new such historical epoch: ‘First and last: a change in the
understanding of being! Time!’ (GA, /).
In the Black Notebooks, Heidegger aptly calls this mixture of politics and
metaphysics for ‘metapolitics’ (e.g., GA, f/). Metapolitics is not a
meta-study of the various political discourses, but rather the belief that
current political practices are supported by a specific ontological frame-
work that can be radically transformed. As Marion Heinz puts it, it is an
‘ontologisation of the political’ and a ‘politicisation of ontology’ that
supposedly leads to ‘an epochal caesura’ (, ). More precisely,
metapolitics is the nexus between (i) a communal commitment to the
people that is (ii) enforced by political institutions like the state and the
educational system, and (iii) which is philosophically ‘justified’ by refer-
ence to the history of being and its call for a cultural cum metaphysical
transformation. For Heidegger, the political revolution of state and uni-
versity is the means to this metaphysical end.
Heidegger allegedly described his political engagement in these terms to Karl Jaspers (cf.
Hochkeppel ; Pöggeler ).
We have already seen Heidegger make this analogy explicit in the quote from GA that introduced
Section . above. Elsewhere, he claims that the historical task of the German people requires ‘a
readiness for sacrifice’ like that of the frontier soldiers (GA, /, /, cf. NHS, ).
See Arendt’s () comparison of Heidegger’s politics with Thales, who fell down a well while
star gazing.
Politics and Authenticity
consists in coming to blows with one another; it is often far more difficult and
wearisome to catch sight of the enemy as such, to bring the enemy into the
open, to harbor no illusions about the enemy, to keep oneself ready for attack,
to cultivate and intensify a constant readiness and to prepare the attack looking
far ahead with the goal of total annihilation. (GA/, /)
At this time, Heidegger could not have known how literally the regime
was to carry out such an annihilation, but the very fact that he buys in to
the discourse of total annihilation is disturbing.
The external enemies are, as we have seen, America and Russia, and the
internal enemies are, among others, the Jews. In the Black Notebooks,
Heidegger frequently refers to Judaism in the years – in a way
that clearly aligns with (HoB ) the narrative of decline. In one place, he
describes his contemporary historical situation as ‘the ending of the history
of the great beginning of Western humanity’ (GA, /). The possi-
bility of a second beginning requires an interpretative struggle [Kampf]
with what he calls machination [Machenschaft] and gigantism [die Riesige].
These terms prefigure the understanding of being later known as en-
framing. Interestingly, Heidegger formulates this as a struggle between
those who have history – the Germans with their historical task – and
those who are ‘historyless’ [geschichtslos] and ‘alienated from being’ (GA,
/). This historyless enemy is ‘the greater uprootedness that, not being
bound to anything, avails itself of everything (Judaism)’ (GA, /).
He then notes that ‘the genuine [eigentliche] victory, the one of history
over what is historyless, is achieved only where what is groundless excludes
itself because it does not venture beyng but always only reckons with
entities and posits their calculations as what is real’ (GA, /f ).
Drawing upon antisemitic stereotypes (greed, a flair for calculation,
nomadic existence), Heidegger associates Judaism with the culmination
of metaphysics, with the ‘hopeless frenzy of unchained technology’
(GA, f/f ). This amounts to a form of historylessness not because
the Jewish people lack a history in the sense that they have no body of
historical facts that describe their development (this is what SZ dismisses as
‘historiology [Historie]’ [SZ, /]) but because Judaism plays an
agonistic part in the metapolitical revolution. Recalling that for
Heidegger historical communities have both past, present, and future,
both fate and mission (cf. Section . above), Judaism is deemed history-
less because it is continuous with the traditional, backwards-looking
metaphysical framework that Heidegger’s Germans rebels against.
Paradoxically, Judaism is rendered historyless by virtue of the ‘history
[Geschicklichkeit] of calculating, manipulating and interfering’
Heidegger’s Politics
(GA, /). In other words, the Jews are historyless because they are
embedded within the historical epoch of modernity, while the Germans
are historical in the proper sense that they make history, that is, in the sense
that they will inaugurate a new understanding of being (cf. GA, /;
GAA, ).
The Jews’ history or capacity for calculation, manipulation and inter-
fering also grounds ‘the worldlessness of Judaism’ (GA, /, my italics).
Understandably, this remark has gained some attention by commentators
(e.g., Bergo ; Mendieta ). Does Heidegger really suggest that
Jews lack being-in-the-world, that they are ontologically like nonhuman
animals or even stones?
The claim is surprising as Heidegger’s earlier work never suggests a
distinction between those human beings that have being-in-the-world and
those that do not. As Georgios Petropoulos has argued, the early concep-
tion of being-in-the-world is ‘inclusionary and arguably pluralistic’
(, ). Indeed, as we saw in Chapter , he readily admits that ‘primitive
peoples’ have being-in-the-world (SZ, ff/f; GA, /; GA/,
f/).
Heidegger would involve himself in a blatant contradiction if he claimed
both (i) that Jews are worldless in the sense of the occurrent and (ii) that
Jews have a history of or capacity for calculation, manipulation, and
interfering since the latter is an understanding of being, and any under-
standing of being requires being-in-the-world. The only systematically
viable option is to dismiss (i). Thus, I agree with Trawny that Heidegger
considers the Jews to be worldless because they allegedly embody a
particular understanding of being. More specifically, machination is the
origin of the worldlessness of Judaism (). The difference between the
Germans and the Jews is, hence, a difference between world disclosures.
Their positions within the history of being make Jews incapable of
grasping history as history and world as world. The Jews – along with
the Americans and Russians – embody the decline of the West.
Geschicklichkeit means literally skilfulness, but given Heidegger’s attentiveness to the link between
Geschichte and Geschick, it is unlikely that he would use this word without also thinking of
historicity [Geschichtlichkeit].
Heidegger’s remarks about Husserl in the Black Notebooks follow the same line of reasoning. He
acknowledges his indebtedness to Husserl and the phenomenological reduction but adds that
Husserl’s method ‘never reaches into the domains of the essential decisions [wesentlicher
Entscheidungen]; instead, it entirely presupposes the historiological tradition of philosophy’
(GA, f/). Husserl’s chief error is, hence, that he worked in continuity with the tradition.
This renders him historyless and unable to grasp the second beginning.
Politics and Authenticity
When mapping different peoples onto the history of being, Heidegger
uses crude and frankly unconvincing social categories. Why should we
assume that these social groups have distinct understandings of being?
Heidegger never questions the plausibility or fairness of speaking about
‘Americans’, ‘Russians’, or ‘Jews’ in this way, but he does, somewhat
despite himself, realise that the Germans are not a unified people with a
single fate. In particular, ‘Ponderings III’, which was written mostly when
Heidegger was rector, shows not only his initial enthusiasm for the
National Socialist revolution but also his subsequent disappointment in
the movement.
Heidegger thus doubts that the students at the university are up for the
task of revolutionising Western metaphysics:
According to everything the students offer now at the start of this summer
semester, it must be concluded that they are disappointing all along the
line – not primarily with regard to the reconstruction, but already with
regard to the revolution within the university.
Ever so much courage and enthusiasm cannot compensate for the complete
spiritual immaturity. . . . Nevertheless, the will to vague yet certain claims
on the part of the students must be kept alive and shown the way. (GA,
/f )
But even this vague hope that the revolutionary movement will at some
point grow spiritually mature comes to nothing, and Heidegger’s disap-
pointment only grows. In a notebook entry that boldly states that he did
indeed express something essential in the rectoral address, Heidegger now
also airs his disappointment with the faculty:
The great error of the address surely consisted in its assuming that in the
purlieu of the German university there would still be a concealed group of
questioners and in still hoping that these could bring themselves to the
work of inner transformation. But neither the previous personnel, nor the
subsequent one, belong to this group. (GA, /f )
Heidegger even distinguishes between what he calls ‘vulgar Nationalism
Socialism’ (GA, /) and his own ‘spiritual National Socialism’
(e.g., GA, /, /). The difference between the two is that
vulgar National Socialism – which Heidegger increasingly identifies with
the actual political movement – remains tied to a traditional metaphysical
framework by understanding human beings through occurrent categories
like race (GA, /, /, /, /) and in accordance
with ontic domains like biology (GA, /, /, /, /
) and economy (GA, /, /). Heidegger’s spiritual
Heidegger’s Politics
National Socialism, on the other hand, understands human beings as the
temporal unfolding of Dasein and the Germans as the protagonists of the
metapolitical revolution.
Heidegger’s faith in the German people is a communal commitment,
and a communal commitment succeeds only if it is shared by a historical or
intergenerational community. Heidegger’s growing disillusionment with
the National Socialist movement indicates that his communal commit-
ment did, in the end, fail. After resigning from the rectorship, Heidegger
thus speaks of the ‘impotence for a genuine self-assertion’ and laments the
fact that the Nazi functionaries controlling the educational system are
entirely caught up in the old ways of thinking (GA, /). He
‘misjudged’ the greatness of the movement, when he ‘saw in National
Socialism the possibility of a transition into the other beginning’, when it
was in fact ‘the consummation of modernity’ and ‘the complete “mobilisa-
tion” of all the capacities of self-reliant humanity’ (GA, /).
Heidegger thereby finds himself caught in a strange limbo: He hopes for
a metaphysical revolution but knows the revolutionary subject to
be missing.
From this tension emerges another conception of the history of being.
In texts such as GA, the history of being is no longer conceived in terms
of geopolitics and communal commitments but in terms of an eschatology
according to which the epochal transformation is carried out by ‘the last
god’ rather than the chosen people. He explains this in the Spiegel-
interview by saying that ‘philosophy will not be able to effect an immediate
transformation of the present condition of the world. This is not only true
of philosophy, but of all merely human thought and endeavor’ (Heidegger
in Wolin , ). Realising that neither the present community nor
future generations can carry out his revolution, Heidegger’s commitment
is transformed so that it no longer depends on other people – on merely
human thought and endeavours. From his social and political disillusion-
ment springs a form of (absurd) faith in an absent god:
Dostoyevsky says at the end of the first chapter of Demons: ‘But whoever
has no people also has no God’. – But who does have a people, his people,
and how so? Only he who has a God – and only in that way? But who has a
God, and how so? . . . Only the relation to beyng can bestow the possibility
of a plight of the encounter with God. (GA, /)
For a more detailed analysis of Heidegger’s antisemitism, his growing disappointment in the
German people, and how this prepares the ground for his later eschatology of being, see
Knudsen ().
Politics and Authenticity
. Heidegger’s Mistakes
I have interpreted Heidegger’s politics as a communal commitment to
what he considers to be the metaphysical destiny of the Germans. This
does not mean, however, that I consider Heidegger’s politics to follow
naturally from his social ontology. In fact, I will now argue that
Heidegger’s attempt to philosophically justify his politics contradicts his
social ontology on three counts: the disclosive function assigned to the
Führer (Section ..), the conception of community and world sharing
inherent to his geopolitics (Section ..), and the general methodological
priority that he grants to historicism over and above transcendentalism in
the history of being (Section ..).
It is difficult to pinpoint exactly when Heidegger changes his mind on this issue, but his changing
attitudes towards the metaphysics of the will serves as a good indicator since the idea of the creative
individual is bound up with the idea that an act of the will can transform our understanding of
being. And for Heidegger the question of the will is inevitably bound up with the question of
Nietzsche. Thus, in , Heidegger takes Nietzsche and Hölderlin to be telling the same story
about the Greeks and the Germans, the Dionysian and the Apollonian (GA, /), while he,
in declares that the difference in how they determine the ‘future of the Germans and of the
West’ is ‘abysmal’ (GA, ). By , the metaphysics of the will co-constitutes modern nihilism
and the disclosure of entities as ‘standing reserve’ [Bestand] (e.g., GA, /).
Heidegger’s Politics
own creative violence, they must be able to somehow separate themselves
from the fundamental condition of being-with. If they could not separate
themselves in this way, their projections would remain intrinsically respon-
sive to the behaviour of others in a way that would undermine their
radically creative power. As in the case of the leader, the creative individual
develops an understanding of being by himself and then makes this the
communal standard. As Heidegger puts it in :
use violence as violence-doers and become those who rise high in historical
being as creators, as doers. Rising high in the site of history, they also
become apolis, without city and site, lonesome, un-canny, with no way out
amidst entities as a whole, and at the same time without ordinance and
limit, without structure and historical order [Fug], because they as creators
must first ground all this in each case. (GA, /)
In this view, certain human beings can disclose the world anew and do so
from a position that is separate from the historical order of the communal
space of intelligibility. For this reason, Heidegger writes in that a true
leader ‘understands, considers, and brings about what people and state are,
in the living development of his own essence’ (NHS, ). The leader is,
hence, conceived of as an ontological sovereign who has the unconstrained
power to posit laws for his community.
This account of the disclosive power of the Führer clearly contradicts the
fundamental tenet of Heidegger’s social ontology, namely, the idea that
intentionality is fundamentally responsive to the behaviour of others. This
idea implies that meaning is an indeterminate product of social interaction,
whereas Heidegger now takes meaning to be the product of the creative
acts of certain individuals. Furthermore, the idea that the creative individ-
ual is ‘without structure and historical order’ contradicts the account of
social normativity elaborated above. We saw that although it is possible for
us to modify our relation to social norms, it is impossible to fully separate
ourselves from them or, to be precise, from the generic drift towards social
norms. In his political enthusiasm, Heidegger seems to have forgotten that
no self – neither the authentic self nor the self of the leader – can ‘rest upon
an exceptional condition of the subject, a condition that has been detached
from the Anyone’ (SZ, /).
Clare Pearson Geiman puts the point well: The human being is ‘the creator of order and governance
for human beings, and as such unable to be bound by his own created order’ (, ). Non-
coincidentally, a similar topology is central to Carl Schmitt’s conception of sovereignty: ‘For the
legal order to make sense, a normal situation must exist, and he is sovereign who definitely decides
whether this normal situation actually exists’ (, ).
Politics and Authenticity
Richard Polt has recently argued that Heidegger’s turn to politics picks up a thought laid out but
not carried through in SZ, namely, that ‘existential insights are ultimately existentiell’ and that
‘philosophical insights . . . necessarily form part of one’s way of existing at a certain historical
juncture’ (, ). According to Polt, Heidegger’s turn to the ‘collective selfhood’ of the people
follows from his very conception of philosophy insofar as philosophy requires us to decide on who
we are in a fundamentally shared world (, ). This implies, he argues, ‘a politics that would
have to be nationalist in some sense – grounded in the living, shared world of a particular group and
inciting that group to ask who it is’ (, ).
But this reading conflates the ontological–existential sense of living in a world that is inherently
and open-endedly shared with others and the ontic–existential sense of living in a particular world
that can be demarcated along the lines of nationality (or language or whatever). Polt argues that
these levels of analyses cannot be neatly separated, because authenticity requires us to take a
standpoint on who we are ‘within a concrete place, time, and community’ (, ). In the
next chapter, however, I argue that it is wrong to see the demand for authenticity as a demand that
we perform some first-order action or decision, for example, that we live in a specific community.
Rather, authenticity demands that we adopt a set of second-order attitudes on our own existence
that reflects the nature of Dasein.
Politics and Authenticity
Nancy puts it, being-with is only a ‘banal being-alongside’ and a later
collectivism according to which the ‘ownmost structure’ of Dasein is
suddenly cashed out in terms of ‘the common’ (Nancy , ).
Although they are right in criticising the collectivism of the ‘s, this
framework is clearly inadequate for understanding Heidegger’s thought,
for, as I have argued, Heidegger was never an individualist. He always
conceived the capacities distinctive of Dasein to depend on social relations.
The error of the ‘s is, hence, how he confuses being-with, as an
ontological condition, with something that can be neatly demarcated along
ontic lines.
If he had opted for (b) the phenomenological sense of the historical,
Heidegger could have avoided these problems. On this view, being-with is
a transcendental condition for Dasein that makes specific social formations
possible without being exhausted by them. Different peoples or different
communities instantiate this condition in different ways depending on
their facticity but they never inhabit distinct worlds. According to this
sense of the historical, our historical tradition does not separate us from all
other historical traditions. Rather, historical awareness reveals that com-
munities are necessarily exposed to other communities, to different ways of
doing and seeing things, and that we, whether we like it or not, are
constantly engaged in interpretative struggles that must be negotiated
through pre-reflective triangulation and communication rather than
geopolitical warfare.
See Gadamer (), Guignon (), Kisiel (), van Buren (), and Wrathall ().
For an overview of such left-Heideggerianism, see Oliver Marchart (). Marchart argues that a
range of post-Heideggerian thinkers transpose the ontological difference between being and entities
into the realm of politics by claiming that there is a fundamental difference between the particular
ways in which we happen to organise our lives with each other (what he calls politics) and the
ultimate ground of society, the space of possibility, on which this organisation rests (what he calls
the political). Marchart further argues that theorists like Badiou and Agamben analyses the latter in
terms of its ontological categories (e.g., history, contingency, event, freedom) in a way that will lead
to an ‘increasing acceptance of the contingency and historicity of being, which potentially has a
liberating effect’ (, ), that is, they analyse ontological categories and structures in order to
transform the historical situation.
Politics and Authenticity
Seen in this light, Heidegger’s metapolitics is not merely a quest for an
understanding of being long forgotten but an attempt to transform the
basic structures of human existence.
The first question we should ask is, of course, which kind of support
Heidegger offers for the radical historicist thesis. Recalling the various
elements of the history of being, it seems that Heidegger identifies (HoB
) a form of metaphysical trajectory that will hopefully collapse and make
room for (HoB ) a new understanding of being. Yet, he qualifies this set of
claims with reference to (HoB ) what various philosophers have meant
with the word ‘being’. But why should we accept that what philosophers
have said about the word ‘being’ have a privileged position in opening up
an understanding of being? After all, an understanding of being is multi-
faceted and underlies not only philosophical discourse but also everyday
activities like shopping, cooking, and raising a child. If we reject this claim,
the connection between politics and metaphysics falls apart. Indeed,
without this claim, Heidegger’s history of metaphysics is just that: a history
of metaphysics.
Furthermore, appeals to (HoB ) what philosophers have said about
being do not themselves prove the much stronger claim (HoB ) that the
fundamental structure of being-in-the-world cannot be described in tran-
scendental and ahistorical terms. It is entirely possible that philosophers
have simply overlooked the fundamental structure that made their philo-
sophising possible in the same way that both Descartes and Hume accord-
ing to Kant overlooked the possibility of synthetic a priori judgements,
which nonetheless made them capable of thinking in the first place.
Drawing on Richardson’s () influential Heidegger: Through
Phenomenology to Thought, commentators often present Heidegger’s turn
to the history of being as an attempt to amend the flaws in his earlier
transcendental analytic of Dasein. More specifically, it is argued that
transcendentalism, first, entails a form of subjectivism and, second, is
incapable of accounting for the historicity of truth.
First, in Olafson’s reconstruction, the problem of subjectivism is that
being, in the period of SZ, depends on Dasein and that Dasein is seen as
actively projecting its understanding of being. Hence, in the later works
[Dasein’s] active character, which was of such fundamental importance in
the account given of presence and being, is effectively eclipsed. . . . [T]he
To be clear, I suggest neither that Heidegger’s thought in toto implies radical historicism nor even
that all of Heidegger’s later thought implies radical historicism. I only claim that he tries to justify
his politics with reference to a form of radical historicism.
Heidegger’s Politics
active aspect of Dasein is now associated not with the uncovering of entities
as entities – that is, with being – but with the obscuration of being. This
obscuration is declared to be the hallmark of the subjectivism that has made
impossible any genuine understanding of being in modern philosophy.
(Olafson , )
However, as Heidegger says in the ‘Letter on Humanism’, even the
‘execution and completion of this other thinking that abandons
subjectivity . . . is not a change of standpoint from SZ’ even if it is a kind
of ‘turning [Kehre]’ (GA, /f ). Heidegger thus recognises that the
terminology of projection in SZ might lead to a subjectivist misinterpre-
tation (à la Sartre) where ‘projection’ is understood as a ‘human perfor-
mance’ [menschliche Leistung] (GA, /f, cf. GA, /). But it is
crucial to note that Heidegger does not say that SZ is itself subjectivist; only
that it is possible to (mis)interpret it in this way. It is possible, then, to
both grant commentators like Richardson and Olafson that Heidegger
introduces the history of being – and the related concepts of the event
[Ereignis] and the fourfold [das Geviert] – to counter this subjectivist
misinterpretation of his work, while also maintaining that this does not
require us to abandon insights won from his earlier transcendentalist
inquiry into the conditions of possibility of meaningful engagement with
the shared world. In fact, the holist thesis that intentionality depends on a
whole of both objective and social relations provides a comparable anti-
subjectivist account of world disclosure.
Second, Heidegger worries that transcendentalism is incapable of
describing our experience of truth (aletheia) as this varies between histor-
ical epochs. He writes, for instance,
The task of the grounding of Da-sein by way of thinking and poetry
overcomes the question of possibility. That question – How is such and
such possible? – is the last implementation of mathematical thinking, which
is the result of the dominance of the proposition as such, which in turn is
the result of the collapse of aletheia. (GA, /)
The argument is that the transcendental method – the inquiry into
conditions of possibility – is itself a form of mathematical thinking, and,
hence, a distinctly modern way of doing philosophy, and that this will, in
the end, prevent us from understanding truth as aletheia.
Yet, on the same page, Heidegger suggests that ‘the question of possi-
bility’ need not necessarily lead to an obfuscation of aletheia: ‘The limits
and rights of possibility and of the question of possibility are to be
established anew on the basis of a grounding of the partitioning in the
Politics and Authenticity
(event) [Begründung der Zerklüftung im (Ereignis)]’ (GA, /). This
suggests that it might be possible to account for the condition of possibility
not of a single world disclosure or a single understanding of being but of
that which grounds a plurality of such world disclosures. We should note
that the radical historicist thesis is not necessary to account for there being
a plurality of world-disclosures. In fact, the transcendental reading makes
the same point by distinguishing between the shared world in the
ontological–existential sense, that is, the a priori structure characteristic
of any particular world, and a shared world in the ontic–existential sense,
namely, a concrete, historical realm of familiarity. In this way, both
approaches entail holistic conceptions of truth and meaning, and they
both take Dasein’s pre-reflective engagement with the world to be histor-
ical. The main difference is that the transcendentalist approach believes
that it can deduce the a priori structure of intelligibility from this historical
mode of experience.
To some this is unpalatable. How do we deduce ahistorical claims from
historical experiences? But, as I argued in Chapter , Heidegger’s tran-
scendentalism does not commit him to what we might call radical tran-
scendentalism that deduces transcendental claims from finite experience
with apodictic certainty. Instead, his transcendentalism is modest in the
sense that it takes the transcendental conditions deduced from experience
to be tentative, or, as he would put it, to be formally indicative. On this
reading, transcendental phenomenology aims to be right about the funda-
mental correlation between human and world – including the way in
which this correlation is subject to historical variation – although the
concrete analysis of this structure must be provisional. The right descrip-
tion of the correlation or, to use Heidegger’s term, of transcendence is a
philosophical ideal that we aim for.
As it turns out, we cannot seriously dispense with the transcendentalist
ideal of getting transcendence right. For what exactly is the alternative?
Heidegger’s radical historicism argues that transcendence itself is subjected
to radical transformations and that it is foolish to even attempt to describe
the structure that underlies and constraints such transformations. As such,
Heidegger can only describe the second beginning in negative terms. For
example, he writes in ‘Ponderings IV’ that the second beginning provides a
new measure for Dasein and explains that this must be a ‘measuring out as
a tearing away of the forgottenness of being, a tearing away that leaps in
and thus is an outline [Aufriß] of the essence of truth’ (GA, /).
What is the new essence of truth that comes forth in the metapolitical
revolution? It is methodologically impossible for Heidegger to say since
Heidegger’s Politics
any description of this new essence of truth would necessarily presuppose
that we, in our present historical situation, can indeed say something
meaningful about a fundamentally different historical situation.
Heidegger acknowledges this impasse in the next notebook entry:
The ‘history’ of philosophy – only the creative thinker knows of it, but
never does the ‘historiologist’. So that the thinking of beyng may smoothly
take its course for a long time to come, there must be impulses toward a
displacement onto the other, at once higher and deeper, course. But how
could a person endure both together: undergo this impulse and transmit it
for the others and simultaneously be content to proceed along the already
opened and common course itself? (GA, /)
The great creative thinker – who, as we recall, plays a privileged role in
opening a new understanding of being – receives an ‘impulse’ that inau-
gurates a new trajectory for Western metaphysics. But how is it possible for
this creative thinker to also become a leader, to gather a community
around him, to communicate this impulse to those lesser thinkers who
are still stuck in the old ways of thinking? Heidegger offers no solution to
this metapolitical aporia:
A simple either-or is at issue here:
either the sacrifice of the suffering of the impulses and the sacrifice of the
reticent configuration of that suffering, in that apparently it is always only
what was earlier that is spoken of, although the complete otherness of the
second beginning is thought –
or the gift of immediately proceeding on the indicated course (GA, /
f )
The radical historicist thus faces the following dilemma: Either he sacrifices
his hard-won metapolitical insight and continues to speak in the tongue of
the past even though he constantly thinks of the second beginning. Or he
accepts the gift of his new insight and stays on that trajectory even though
this causes him to remain completely silent and to remain utterly unin-
telligible to his contemporaries. According to the radical historicist, his-
torical transformations remain uncommunicable and unintelligible to
others. They remain, with Nietzsche, untimely. If we hold, as I think we
must, that philosophy is essentially discursive, radical historicism appears
rather unphilosophical.
I have argued that Heidegger’s politics amounts to an authoritarian
nationalism in which state and education serve to align the will of the
citizens with the will of the leader and his specific conception of the
national community. I have further shown that Heidegger attempts to
Politics and Authenticity
philosophically justify his politics with reference to a form of being-
historical geopolitics. Drawing on his systematic social ontology, I have
criticised this justification on three counts: it inconsistently attributes an
exceptional type of world disclosure to the leader; it confuses ontic and
ontological senses of community and world sharing when it assumes that
each people have a distinct understanding of being thereby contradicting
Heidegger’s own open-ended social externalism; and, finally, it gives
methodological priority to historicism over and above transcendentalism,
which ultimately threatens to undermine its status as a philosophical
discourse.
It is not the task of social ontology to choose which type of government,
state, or community is best. In this sense, Heidegger’s social ontology
cannot ‘correct’ his political choices. What it can do is illuminate where
Heidegger’s justification of his choices relies on mistaken conceptions of
intersubjectivity, community, and human being-in-the-world.
Politics and Authenticity
individuated by its possibilities, each change in its field of possibilities (e.g.,
no longer facing the possibility of eating dinner but now facing the
possibility of doing the dishes) seems to cause a new self to emerge.
Heidegger faces the volatility problem because he explicitly refuses to grasp
the selfhood of Dasein as a self-identity or as the immanence of conscious-
ness to itself.
In some places, he seems to bite the bullet:
But if the self is conceived ‘only’ as a way of being of this entity, this seems
tantamount to volatilizing the real ‘core’ of Dasein. Any apprehensiveness
however which one may have about this gets its nourishment from the
perverse assumption that the entity in question has at bottom the kind of
being which belongs to something occurrent, even if one is far from
attributing to it the solidity of an occurrent corporeal thing. (SZ, /)
On the other hand, it is clearly a problem for Heidegger if his intended
analysis of ‘the full and concrete human being’ cannot account for personal
identity. Heidegger’s must explain the unity or stability of the self in terms
of its existential projections, but how is that possible?
The second problem is the attributability problem. Questioning
Heidegger’s conception of selfhood from a normative rather than meta-
physical perspective, this problem focuses on the fact that we do not
identify with all the senses of self that are reflected back to us from things.
Imagine, for instance, that although I am generally known to be a nice and
gentle guy, it occasionally happens that I lose my temper in traffic and yell
obscene things at other motorists. In such situations, a sense of myself as a
road raged driver is reflected back to me, even if I feel that this is somehow
misattributed to me, that it is not really me who acts in those situations.
Now, even if we admit that the solicitations that prompt my road rage does
indeed reveal something about me, we must still explain how and why
I can find this sense of self misattributed to me. Some might be inclined to
see this as a conflict between a superficial self (the impulsive road rage-self )
and a deeper self (e.g., a narrative self, a rational self, or a self embodying
certain core values), but it is not obvious that this option is available to
Heidegger. Given that experiences of misattribution and attribution are
common, we need to reconcile them with Heidegger’s idea that the self of
Dasein is individuated by its possibilities.
These problems concern what Heidegger calls the ‘constancy’
[Ständigkeit] of the self (e.g., SZ, /) and they question the image
of the self as something at the whims of the world. Heidegger hopes to
solve both problems, to kill two birds with one stone, with his account of
authenticity [Eigentlichkeit]. Roughly put, authenticity is the idea that
The Demand for Authenticity
because Dasein’s self is not merely given but at stake in its existence, it can
somehow ‘choose itself’ and ‘determine its existence’ (GA, /)
thereby granting itself the constancy required to solve the volatility prob-
lem and the attributability problem.
If this is correct, authenticity has an important systematic role to play in
Heidegger’s social ontology. Yet, many commentators fear that the
account of authenticity points in a direction wholly other than that of
Heidegger’s social ontology. They take anxiety, death, and conscience to
be ‘centrifugal tendencies’, to borrow a term from Carr (, ), that
threatens to tear the individual from the fabric of the shared world. In
short, many believe that authenticity amounts to a form of individualism
that is, at best, irrelevant to his social ontology and, at worst, outright
incompatible with it.
The aim of this chapter is, first, to present a reading of authenticity that
dispels this individualistic worry and, second, to answer the volatility
problem and the attributability problem. In Section ., I outline the
formal structure of Heidegger’s notion of authenticity by arguing that
authenticity refers to those instances in which Dasein has a high degree
of continuity between its own ontological structure and its ontic
self-understanding. On this reading, authenticity does not lead to an
individualism in which Dasein engages only with individually inflected
possibilities but amounts to a form of emphatic individuation in which
Dasein adopts an ontologically transparent second-order attitude on its
own existence. In Section ., I show that Heidegger’s conception of
being-towards-death solves the volatility problem by identifying an inalien-
able possibility for each Dasein that runs through all its factical and
volatile existential projections. The authentic relation to death makes us
aware that we can endure the loss of all possibilities except the possibility of
dying and that death, therefore, is a constitutive possibility for our existence.
In Section ., I discuss Heidegger’s analysis of conscience as a solution to
the attributability problem. More specifically, I argue that conscience
demands that we assume responsibility for the factical possibilities
lying ahead of us in the sense that we come to see them as attributable
to us as agents and, hence, as disclosive of who we are. Finally, in Section
., I discuss what Heidegger’s notion of authenticity entails for his
conception of being-with by addressing, first, the way in which attribut-
ability figures in both face-to-face relations and in larger communities
and, second, how authenticity, despite being fundamentally different
from moral obligations, demands that we relate to others in a
particular way.
Politics and Authenticity
Ontic understanding can be practical or theoretical. Practical understanding is a tacit and pre-
reflective way of comporting oneself towards a as b or, to put the same point differently, of projecting
an entity onto a field of possibilities. The paradigm of practical understanding is Dreyfusian skilful
The Demand for Authenticity
Instances of ontic understanding can exhibit a high or a low degree of
continuity with their underlying ontological understanding. For example,
Heidegger introduces the project of SZ by saying that the analysis is
authentic [eigentlich] when the entities with which it concerns itself ‘show
themselves with the kind of access that genuinely belongs to them’
(SZ, /). Later, he argues that the available is grasped ‘authentically’
when we cease to examine it theoretically and allow it to withdraw and
become transparent in our usage (SZ, /). Most importantly, Dasein is
‘inauthentic’ when it understands itself by way of innerworldly entities
(GA, /) or when it understands itself ‘in terms of the world’
(SZ, /; /). Conversely, it is authentic when its self-
understanding arises ‘out of its own self as such’ (SZ, /). The main
idea here is that our ontic understanding can recognise or misrecognise its
own condition of possibility, namely, our ontological understanding.
I suggest that Heidegger’s concept of authenticity refers to a mode of
existence that exhibits a high degree of continuity between its ontological
understanding of itself and its ontic understanding of itself. I thus agree
with Golob that
[t]he defining feature of authenticity . . . is that Dasein accurately under-
stands its own nature: i.e. it makes sense of itself . . . in a way that reflects
the facts about Dasein that texts such as SZ have supposedly identified.
(Golob , )
This does not necessarily mean that Dasein must entertain a set of
theoretical propositions about its own being. To be authentic means,
rather, that we must adopt certain second-order attitudes towards our
own actions and beliefs, and these second-order attitudes must reflect
Dasein’s own nature.
To summarise, Dasein has an ontological understanding of its own type
of being and the type of being of certain other entities. We would not be
Dasein if we lacked this ontological understanding. However, we might
coping. In contrast, theoretical understanding is an explicit and reflective way of comporting oneself
towards a as b. To use Heidegger’s example, an assertion is a form of theoretical understanding
insofar as the assertion projects an entity (e.g., a proposition or a concept) onto a field of possibilities
(as constituted by, for instance, the rules that determines what counts as a valid inference within a
specific discourse) in a way that largely abstracts from our embodied practices (SZ, /).
Ontology – or other philosophical disciplines – would be another example of a theoretical
understanding. In Heidegger’s view, traditional metaphysics constitute a particularly problematic
form of theoretical understanding because it not only abstracts from the embodied practice of
practical understanding but also obscures ontological understanding by characterising what entities
are in fundamentally inadequate terms (e.g., Dasein as animal rationale or available entities as
brute facts).
Politics and Authenticity
misconstrue our ontological understanding of entities in our ontic under-
standing of them. Heidegger often points out that I can comport myself
towards myself in such a way that I ontically understand myself solely in
terms of innerworldly entities or activities. In doing so, I obscure certain
crucial features of my own being. This makes me inauthentic. It remains to
be seen which exact second-order attitudes must be adopted to correct this
flawed self-understanding.
This formal framework is clearly compatible with the idea that authen-
ticity is a methodological concept as a continuity between ontological
understanding and ontic understanding is paramount to the project of
fundamental ontology. The ambition of SZ is ‘never to allow . . . fancies
and popular convictions’ to obscure our ontological understanding but
rather ‘to make [it] the scientific theme’ of our investigation (SZ, /
). Furthermore, one might also see this framework as a way of account-
ing for a particular normative dimension of human existence because it
enables us to draw a distinction between a life lived in light of our own
being rather than merely in structural conformity to it. Regarding the idea
that authenticity is an existentiell ideal, one could, for instance, try to make
the case that once we understand ourselves in light of our own being a
wholly different way of life becomes possible or one could argue, more
modestly, that the existentiell ideal consists in the fact that some people
who possess an ontologically adequate self-understanding can help others
understand themselves in the right way. (I argue something along these
lines in Section ..)
See, for instance, Robert Pippin’s claim that Heidegger’s attempt to account for a ‘non-individualist,
non-mentalist account of our sensible, norm-governed dealings with the world’ is undermined by his
analysis of authenticity (Pippin , ). See also Tugendhat ().
Politics and Authenticity
let this weighing determine whether or not I should φ. But as Heidegger
objects, ‘the idea of guilt must . . . be raised above the domain of concern
of bookkeeping [den Bezirk des verrechnenden Besorgens]’ (SZ, /).
The type of guilt that Heidegger has in mind is entirely independent of our
ability to list pros and cons. Moreover, accountability implies that I am in
control of my commitment so that I can simply change my attitude if the
justification turns out to be insufficient. Yet, Dasein is a null reason, and
this means, as we have seen, that Dasein never has power over its own
being ‘from the ground up’ (SZ, /). Dasein’s reasoning is, in other
words, never sufficient to determine the contingent project (the nullity)
that it is engaged in. No matter how long I weigh for and against φ-ing, my
choice can never be fully justified as it relies on a disposition that I do
not control.
What is the normative stance of conscience, if not one of accountability?
I believe that Heidegger’s point is better described as a form of attribut-
ability. Rather than describing the normative relation between an agent’s
commitments and the discursive space of reasons, attributability describes
the normative relation between the character of an agent and his or her
commitments as these are expressed in his or her behaviour or attitudes.
More formally, φ-ing is attributable to me if and only if φ-ing expresses a
commitment that is significant to who I take myself to be, where φ-ing is a
piece of behaviour. In this sense, attributability concerns self-referential
commitments, namely, the way in which an agent’s self-understanding (as
engaged in this or that project) prompts her to respond to certain envi-
ronmental affordances. Importantly, attributability flouts the control con-
dition inherent to accountability, since we might not be fully in control of
what we respond to in this way, and severs responsibility from the
intersubjective process of giving and asking for reasons, since we might
not be able to explain why we respond in the way that we do, but it
Crowell takes the fact that anxiety reveals ‘the normative force’ of innerworldly activities to depend
on us to be enough to satisfy this control condition: In anxiety, everyday activities confronts me as
‘something without normative force’, and this, in turn, means ‘that factic grounds become subject to
a choice for which I am accountable’, that is, a choice in which I gain ‘responsibility for the
normative force’ (, f, ). But this cannot be right for two reasons. First, when anxiety
ceases, and the world becomes normatively significant once again, it seems to me that this happens
globally in the same way that the onset of anxiety caused a global breakdown of meaning. If this is
indeed the case, anxiety does not allow us to pick and choose which activities are most important to
us. Second, being a mood, anxiety is independent of human cognition and volition. As such, it
remains beyond our control. Accordingly, anxiety reveals normative force to depend on us but not to
be controlled by us.
The Demand for Authenticity
remains an important normative arena since our self-understanding is at
stake in a way that can succeed or fail.
The distinction between accountability and attributability is important
because there is a normatively significant ground between the extremes of
Crowell’s ‘quasi-mechanical conformism’ and full-blown accountability
(, ). Thus, I might care for φ-ing without being able to explain
why, without being able to ground my commitment to φ in any evaluative
reasons. Yet, by virtue of my caring, my relation to φ-ing is fundamentally
different than my relation to quasi-mechanic responses like that of scratch-
ing my nose. To borrow an example from David Shoemaker (),
I might care for a person even if everything speaks against it and everyone –
including me – agrees that the person is a jerk. We might say I have an
inexplicable soft spot for the person in question. In such cases, I am
responsible for my attitude in the sense that it is attributable to me but
I am not accountable for it.
The idea of thrownness entails that some of my commitments are
grounded in a way that remains beyond the space of reason. In the end,
my ability to give an account of myself will always fall short of this basic
fact. For this reason, Heidegger insists that ‘conscience discourses solely
and constantly in the mode of keeping silent’ (SZ, /), that it
summons Dasein ‘into the reticence of itself’ (SZ, /). But this does
not render my commitments normatively insignificant. The fact that there
are no ultimate justifying grounds for my commitments means, as
Wrathall () argues, that I must assume or attribute to myself that
grounding function. When the actions of someone cannot be accounted
for by reference to universally valid and, therefore, impersonal reasons, we
must either attribute it to no one in particular (which leaves us with the
lack of responsibility characteristic of Anyone-norms [SZ, /]) or we
must attribute it the agent. In the latter case, the agent becomes the
reason for the action, because any successful attempt to make sense of
the action must refer to the agent and who they take themselves to be.
Wrathall writes:
Let me clarify a possible misunderstanding. I do not suggest that authenticity is a prerequisite for
self-referential commitments. As we have seen, some self-referential commitments are commitments
by default. In these cases, the corresponding action is not attributable to the particular agent as such
but only attributable to the Anyone or, technically speaking, to the Anyone-self (SZ, /; cf.
Boedeker ). I also do not suggest that individual or joint commitments as discussed in
Chapter presuppose that the agents in question are authentic. I take this to be too demanding.
My suggestion is simply that our capacity for authenticity, as evidenced in the phenomenon of
conscience, goes hand in hand with the phenomenon of attributability.
Politics and Authenticity
If in deciding my existence, there were always fully adequate reasons for my
having the dispositions that I do, or pursuing the possibilities of existence
that I do, then we could eliminate me as a reason for what I do by invoking
the reasons that moved me. But if my being who I am is a necessary
background to making sense of what I do, then my actions are necessarily
constituted by the fact that they are my actions. (Wrathall , )
So, rather than rendering Dasein accountable for its choices, conscience
demands that our choices become attributable to us. We now see that
φ-ing is attributable to me if and only if I am self-referentially committed
to φ-ing so that it is necessary to refer to who I am in order to make sense
of my φ-ing. I hence agree with Gary Watson () that attributability is
a ‘self-disclosure view’ of responsibility.
When Heidegger in ‘On the Essence of Ground’ argues that human
finitude makes the why-question possible, he does not mean that authen-
ticity requires full accountability. Rather, in order to understand his
account of justification [Begründung] as a form of displaying
[Ausweisung], we must bear in mind that the term Ausweisung, when used
as a reflexive verb [sich ausweisen], means to reveal oneself or to prove one’s
identity. Similarly, when he describes such ‘displaying’ as the way in which
an entity makes itself known ‘as “cause” or as the “motivational grounds”
(motive) for an already manifest nexus of entities’ (GA, f/), it is
crucial that we remember that any ‘manifest nexus of entities’ is anchored
in a for-the-sake-of. Accordingly, to answer the why-question is not for an
agent to offer sufficient, explicit, impersonal, and evaluative reasons but to
point to the holistic network of relations that makes the agent who she is.
In line with the interpretation of discourse, this ‘displaying’ of who the
agent is can be both linguistic and gestural. What matters is that the agent
discloses who she is by displaying the project to which she is committed.
We are now able to discern Heidegger’s solution to the attributability
problem and how it connects with his solution to the volatility problem.
Being-towards-death solves the volatility problem because it is a constitu-
tive possibility that runs through all our factical projections as a structural
feature. It thereby provides a being-possible that affords each Dasein with a
form of constancy in an otherwise volatile world. This sense of self does
not, however, come with any norms, and it is therefore too minimal to live
by. Rather, what happens when Dasein grasps its own being-towards-death
Watson mainly discusses attributability as an ethical category, but as Wrathall () has argued the
attributability inherent to authenticity extends to the domain of existence as such. I discuss the
relation between authenticity and moral responsibility further in Section ..
The Demand for Authenticity
is that it ontically realises what it already understands ontologically,
namely, that it is existence is bound to its being-in-the-world. This means
that it must live its life with reference to the possibilities afforded to it by
its being along things and with others. It now understands both that there
is no security from the fragility and volatility that follows from its two-
directional ontological dependency and that it – as emphatically individ-
uated through being-towards-death – is nonetheless capable of enduring
this ontological insecurity. In anticipation, Dasein achieves the constancy,
steadiness, and stability [Ständigkeit] lacking in the ‘non-self-constancy’
[Unselbst-ständigkeit] characteristic of fallenness (SZ, /).
Turning to the normative dimension of authenticity, conscience appeals
to our existential guilt – the fact that we must live one life at the expense of
all others – and demands that we assume responsibility for this contin-
gency. I have argued that this type of responsibility requires that we come
to acknowledge that who we are depend on the things that we care about.
Conscience thereby establishes a normative relation between my ownmost,
inalienable, and unsurpassable possibility and the factical possibilities in
which I am thrown. It requires me to assume responsibility for – to
attribute to myself – these fragile, factical possibilities. This is what
Heidegger calls resoluteness. Resoluteness does not require me to commit
to a particular set of first-order beliefs and actions; rather, it requires me to
commit to my first-order beliefs and actions whatever they are. Formulated
differently, resoluteness is the second-order attitude according to which the
first-order possibilities of being that I may not control nonetheless disclose
who I am.
Through attributability as resoluteness, we get a normatively rich sense
of ourselves because we now ‘choose’ certain of our factical possibilities;
we ‘choose’ that these are the possibilities that matter to us the most and
therefore define who we are. The mismatch between the possibilities
that I attribute to myself and the sense of self reflected back to me from
the possibilities that I happen to respond to (like that of yelling at
other motorists) explains our fairly common experiences that we do
something that is out of character, that does not integrate with who we
take ourselves to be.
In Heidegger’s parlance, ‘the constancy of the self’ involves not only
the ‘steadiness’ of living through different existential projections but
also the ‘steadfastness’ [Standfestigkeit] of ‘having taken a stand’
Resoluteness is ‘the choosing to choose a kind of being-one’s-self’ (SZ, /) and the ‘reticent self-
projection upon one’s ownmost being-guilty, in which one is ready for anxiety’ (SZ, /).
Politics and Authenticity
[Standgewonnenhabens] on what matters to us (SZ, /). Thus,
authenticity amounts to what in Heidegger’s German is called Selbst-
ständigkeit. This term usually means independence or self-sufficiency,
but the hyphenation suggests that we should hear this term both as the
constancy [Ständigkeit] of the self that endures the volatility of the world
and the autonomy [Selbstständigkeit] of the self that commits itself to or
attributes to itself a factical way of existing (SZ, /).
To summarise, anticipation is the proper or transparent way of com-
porting oneself to the ontological feature of being-towards-death. In
anticipation, we ontically understand that we are ontologically individu-
ated by a possibility that runs through volatile world configurations.
Likewise, resoluteness is the proper or transparent way of comporting
oneself to the ontological fact of conscience. In resoluteness, we ontically
understand that we ontologically must be our factical possibilities, that is,
that our individuation always takes place in relation to things and other
people. Therefore, anticipatory resoluteness – Heidegger’s final formula for
authenticity – amounts to an emphatic individuation in which we ontically
understand who or what we already are, ontologically speaking.
I thus agree with Golob according to whom authenticity ‘requires that one lives through, by, and for,
a certain self-understanding’ because it demands that an agent ‘make[s] sense of her life and world in
light of’ a full understanding of Dasein’s nature (, ).
Politics and Authenticity
of the entity thus made manifest’ (GA, /). The demand is not
that we act in light of the moral law but that we become emphatically
individuated.
Since authenticity does not offer a competing ‘practical identity’,
Crowell believes that there is ‘no unconditional obligation to be authentic’
(Crowell , ). And the methodological significance of authenticity
does indeed seem to suggest that we should care about authenticity only if
we want to become philosophers. This would make the demand for
authenticity a conditional demand.
Yet, Golob (, ) rightly points out that Heidegger thinks that we
have no choice but to do philosophy. Therefore, philosophising is not a
‘practical identity’ among others but something that Dasein must engage
in by its very being:
Even if we explicitly know nothing about philosophy, we are already in
philosophy, because philosophy is in us and belongs to us, in the sense that
we are always already philosophising. . . . To exist as a human being means:
to philosophise. (GA, )
One way of reconstructing Heidegger’s reasoning is this: Existence always
involves self-understanding. Some self-understandings are better than
others, not in a moral sense, but in the sense that some self-understandings
simply provide us with a better understanding of the self. Most of the time,
we understand ourselves in terms of innerworldly entities and activities but
this is an inadequate way of understanding the self. Instead, Heidegger
argues that there is but one self-understanding that is wholly correct or
adequate. Unlike the first-order self-understandings of practical identities,
this is a second-order self-understanding that reflects the ontology of
Dasein. Dasein is, hence, always doing philosophy because Dasein neces-
sarily understands its own being, and philosophy is nothing but the on-
going process of making sense of ourselves, each other, and our world. As
he says, ‘philosophising is emphatic transcendence [ausdrückliches
Transzendieren]’ (GA, ), the coming to terms with our being-in-
the-world.
If Dasein by its very existence embodies a self-understanding, and if
Dasein’s mode of existence provides the measure for what constitutes a
good or a bad self-understanding, there is, pace Crowell, an unconditional
demand to be authentic because this demand for understanding oneself in
the right way is inherent to existence: ‘the obligation is planted in our
Dasein’ (GA, ); authenticity is something that Dasein ‘demands of
itself’ (SZ, /).
The Demand for Authenticity
As the demand to understand Dasein as Dasein, authenticity is at the
very heart of Heidegger’s phenomenology. In a sense, we can see it as his
particular interpretation of the Husserlian injunction that we go ‘back to
the things themselves!’ For Heidegger, this means that we must comport
ourselves to the ‘being of entities’ (SZ, /) – paradigmatically, to the
being of the entity that each of us is. But as our own being is by itself a
being-with, there also seems to be a, although slightly indirect, injunction
that we comport ourselves to the being of our fellow Dasein, that is, that
we also disclose them as Dasein. In other words, his commitment to the
project of phenomenology commits Heidegger to understand others in
light of their being. This means, among other things, to understand others
as having the possibility for authenticity, for becoming ontologically
transparent.
I take it that this is what Heidegger means when he says that Dasein
‘can become the “conscience” of others’ (SZ, /). Of course, we
cannot force others to become authentic as this requires them to adopt the
right self-understanding. As the conscience of others, we can only appeal to
what they already understand ontologically, not answer the appeal on their
behalf. The suggestion is, in short, that Dasein must comport itself
towards other Dasein as Dasein, and that this might inspire them to
cultivate their own inherent capacity for becoming authentic. This is a
non-political way in which the philosopher might become the leader or
guide [Führer] of others:
Guidance [Führerschaft] is the obligation to an existence that in some sense
understands the possibilities of human Dasein more fully and, in the end,
more originally and that becomes an exemplar by virtue of
this understanding. (GA, )
This is another point on which Heidegger’s politics failed in light of his own philosophy. He
assumed that the Jews (and the Americans and the Russians) were incapable of becoming
ontologically transparent.
Conclusion
Bibliography
Bourdieu, P. (). The Logic of Practice, Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
(). Back to History: An Interview. In R. Wolin, ed., The Heidegger
Controversy: A Critical Reader, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. –.
Bratman, M. (). Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(). Shared Agency: A Planning Theory of Acting Together, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Buber, M. (). Between Man and Man (R. G. Smith, trans.), Abingdon:
Routledge.
Caputo, J. D. (). Radical Hermeneutics: Repetition, Deconstruction, and the
Hermeneutic Project, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Carman, T. (). On Being Social: A Reply to Olafson. Inquiry, (), pp.
–.
(). Must We Be Inauthentic? In M. Wrathall & J. Malpas, eds, Heidegger,
Authenticity, and Modernity, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. –.
(). Was Heidegger a Linguistic Idealist? Inquiry, , pp. –.
(). Authenticity. In H. Dreyfus & M. Wrathall, eds, A Companion to
Heidegger, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. –.
(). Heidegger’s Analytic: Interpretation, Discourse and Authenticity in Being
and Time, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(). Things Fall Apart: Heidegger on the Constancy and Finality of Death.
In D. McManus, ed., Heidegger, Authenticity and the Self: Themes from
Division Two of Being and Time, Abingdon: Routledge, pp. –.
Carr, D. (). Time, Narrative, and History, Bloomington: Indiana University
Press.
Carruthers, P. (). Mindreading in Infancy. Mind & Language, (),
pp. –.
Crowell, S. G. (). Husserl, Heidegger, and the Space of Meaning: Paths toward
Transcendental Phenomenology, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
(). Facticity and Transcendental Philosophy. In J. Malpas, ed., From Kant
to Davidson: Philosophy and the Idea of the Transcendental, Abingdon:
Routledge, pp. –.
(). Authentic Historicality. In D. Carr & C.-F. Cheung, eds, Space, Time
and Culture, Dordrecht: Springer Science and Business Media, pp. –.
(). Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Crowell, S. G., & Malpas, J. (). Transcendental Heidegger, Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Cykowski, E. (). Heidegger’s Metaphysical Abyss: Between the Human and the
Animal, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dahlstrom, D. (). Heidegger’s Transcendentalism. Research in
Phenomenology, (), pp. –.
Darwall, S. (). Being With. Southern Journal of Philosophy, , pp. –.
Bibliography
Davidson, D. (). Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective: Philosophical Essays,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (). Participatory Sense-Making: An Enactive
Approach to Social Cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, ,
pp. –.
De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E., & Gallagher, S. (). Can Social Interaction
Constitute Social Cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, (), pp. –.
De Jaegher, H., & Froese, T. (). On the Role of Social Interaction in
Individual Agency. Adaptive Behavior, (), pp. –.
Derrida, J. (). Of Spirit: Heidegger and the Question, Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press.
Di Cesare, D. (). Heidegger e gli ebrei: i ‘Quaderni neri’, Milan: Bollati
Boringhieri.
Dreyfus, H. (). Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and
Time, Division I, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(). Interpreting Heidegger on Das Man. Inquiry, (), pp. –.
(). Comments on Cristina Lafont’s Interpretation of Being and Time.
Inquiry, (), –.
(). The Return of the Myth of the Mental. Inquiry, (), pp. –.
(). Being-with-Others. In M. Wrathall, ed., The Cambridge Companion to
Heidegger’s Being and Time, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
pp. –.
(). Skillful Coping: Essays on the Phenomenology of Everyday Perception and
Action, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
(). Background Practices: Essays on the Understanding of Being. (M.
Wrathall, Ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dreyfus, H., & Dreyfus, S. (). Mind Over Machine: The Power of Human
Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer, New York: Free Press.
Dreyfus, H., & Spinosa, C. (). Coping with Things-in-themselves:
A Practice-Based Phenomenological Argument for Realism. Inquiry, (),
pp. –.
Dreyfus, H., & Taylor, C. (). Retrieving Realism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Duff, A. S. (). Heidegger and Politics: The Ontology of Radical Discontent,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Elden, S. (). Speaking Against Number: Heidegger, Language and the Politics of
Calculation, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Engelland, C. (). Heidegger’s Shadow: Kant, Husserl, and the Transcendental
Turn, Abingdon: Routledge.
Epstein, B. (). A Framework for Social Ontology. Philosophy of the Social
Sciences, (), pp. –.
Faye, E. (). Heidegger: The Introduction of Nazism Into Philosophy, New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Ferencz-Flatz, C. (). The Element of Intersubjectivity. Heidegger’s Early
Conception of Empathy. Continental Philosophy Review, , pp. –.
Bibliography
Fried, G. (). Heidegger’s Polemos: From Being to Politics, New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (). Enactive Intersubjectivity: Participatory
Sense-making and Mutual Incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive
Sciences, , pp. –.
Gadamer, H.-G. (). Truth and Method (J. Weinsheimer, trans.), London;
New York: Continuum.
Gadamer, H.-G., & Dottori, R. (). A Century of Philosophy: A Conversation with
Riccardo Dottori (R. Coltman & S. Koepke, trans.), New York: Continuum.
Gallagher, S. (a). Direct Perception in the Intersubjective Context.
Consciousness and Cognition, (), pp. –.
(b). Intersubjectivity in Perception. Continental Philosophy Review, ,
pp. –.
Gallagher, S., & Hutto, D. D. (). Understanding Others through Primary
Interaction and Narrative Practice. In J. Zlatev, T. P. Racine, C. Sinha, & E.
Itkonen, eds, The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity, Amsterdam,
Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company, pp. –.
Geiman, C. P. (). Heidegger’s Antigones. In R. Polt & G. Fried, eds,
A Companion to Heidegger’s Introduction to Metaphysics, New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Giddens, A. (). The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of
Structuration, Berkeley: University of California Press.
Gilbert, M. (). Walking Together: A Paradigmatic Social Phenomenon.
Midwest Studies in Philosophy, (), pp. –.
(). On Social Facts, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
(). Agreements, Coercion, and Obligation. Ethics, (), pp. –.
(). Joint Commitment: How We Make the Social World, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Goldman, A. (). Simulating Minds: The Philosophy, Psychology, and
Neuroscience of Mindreading, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Golob, S. (). Heidegger on Concepts, Freedom and Normativity, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (). Words, Thoughts, and Theories. (J. S.
Rosenschein, Ed.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (). Why the Child’s Theory of Mind Really
Is a Theory. Mind & Language, (–), pp. –.
(). Reconstructing Constructivism: Causal Models, Bayesian Learning
Mechanisms, and the Theory Theory. Psychological Bulletin, (),
pp. –.
Gordon, R. M. (). Simulation without Introspection or Inference from Me
to You. In M. Davies & T. Stone, eds, Mental Simulation, Oxford:
Blackwell, pp. –.
Grosser, F. (a). Mitsein: Variationen auf das Thema Gemeinschaft. In D.
Thomä, F. Grosser, K. Meyer, & H. B. Schmid, eds, Heidegger-Handbuch:
Leben – Werk – Wirkung, Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler, pp. –.
Bibliography
(b). Zwischen Gleichschaltung und robustem Pluralismus: Volten des
“Mitseins”. In P. Sörensen & N. Münch, eds, Politische Theorie und das
Denken Heideggers, Bielefeld, transcript, pp. –.
Guala, F. (). The Philosophy of Social Science: Metaphysical and Empirical.
Philosophy Compass, (), pp. –.
Guignon, C. (). Heidegger and the Problem of Knowledge, Indianapolis, IN:
Hackett Publishing Company.
(). The History of Being. In H. Dreyfus & M. Wrathall, eds,
A Companion to Heidegger, Oxford: Blackwell., pp. –.
(). Authenticity and the Question of Being. In D. McManus, ed.,
Heidegger, Authenticity and the Self: Themes From Division Two of Being
and Time, Abingdon: Routledge, pp. –.
Habermas, J. (). The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures,
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(). Work and Weltanschauung: The Heidegger Controversy from a
German Perspective. Critical Inquiry, (), pp. –.
Han-Pile, B. (). Early Heidegger’s Appropriation of Kant. In H. Dreyfus &
M. Wrathall, eds, A Companion to Heidegger, Oxford: Blackwell.,
pp. –.
Haslanger, S. (). What Is a (Social) Structural Explanation? Philosophical
Studies, (), pp. –.
Hatab, L. (). Heidegger and the Question of Empathy. In F. Raffoul and D.
Pettigrew, eds, Heidegger and Practical Philosophy, Albany: State University
of New York Press, pp. –.
Hatab, L. J. (). Ethics and Finitude: Heideggerian Contributions to Moral
Philosophy, Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Haugeland, J. (). Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
(). Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland’s Heidegger. (J. Rouse, Ed.),
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Heinämaa, S. (). On the Complexity and Wholeness of Human Beings:
Husserlian Perspectives. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, (),
pp. –.
Heinz, M. (). Seinsgeschichte und Metapolitik. In M. Heinz & S. Kellerer,
eds, Martin Heideggers “Schwarze Hefte”: eine philosophisch-politische Debatte,
Berlin: Surhkamp, pp. –.
Heller, A. (). The Gods of Greece: Germans and the Greeks. Thesis Eleven,
(), pp. –.
Hochkeppel, W. (, May ). Heidegger, die Nazis und kein Ende. Die Zeit.
Hodge, J. (). Heidegger and Ethics, Abingdon: Routledge.
Høffding, S. (). A Phenomenology of Musical Absorption, London: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Hoffman, P. (). Death, Time, History: Division II of Being and Time. In C.
Guignon, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. –.
Bibliography
Husserl, E. (). Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology (D.
Cairns, trans.), Dordrecht: Springer Science & Business Media.
(). The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An
Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy (D. Carr, trans.), Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press.
(a). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität I. Erster Teil: -, The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
(b). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität II. Zweiter Teil: -,
The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
(c). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität III. Dritter Teil: -,
The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
(). Aufsätze und Vorträge (–) (T. Nenon & H. R. Sepp, Eds),
Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.
Kant, I. (). Critique of Pure Reason (P. Guyer & A. W. Wood, Eds),
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kisiel, T. (). The Genesis of Heidegger’s “Being and Time,” Berkeley:
University of California Press.
(). Heidegger’s Philosophical Geopolitics in the Third Reich. In R. Polt &
G. Fried, eds, A Companion to Heidegger’s Introduction to Metaphysics, New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, pp. –.
Kjosavik, F., Beyer, C., & Fricke, C. (). Husserl’s Phenomenology of
Intersubjectivity: Historical Interpretations and Contemporary Applications,
Abingdon: Routledge.
Knowles, C. (). Das Man and Everydayness: A New Interpretation. In H. B.
Schmid & G. Thonhauser, eds, From Conventionalism to Social Authenticity:
Heidegger’s Anyone and Contemporary Social Theory, Cham: Springer
International Publishing, pp. –.
Knudsen, N. K. (). Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk.
Research in Phenomenology, (), pp. –.
(). Heidegger and the Genesis of Social Ontology: Mitwelt, Mitsein, and
the Problem of Other People. European Journal of Philosophy, (),
pp. –.
Koo, J.-J. (). Concrete Interpersonal Encounters or Sharing a Common
World: Which Is More Fundamental in Phenomenological Approaches to
Sociality? In T. Szanto & D. Moran, eds, The Phenomenology of Sociality:
Discovering the ‘We,’ Abingdon: Routledge, pp. –.
(). Early Heidegger on Social Reality. In A. Salice & H. B. Schmid, eds,
The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality: History, Concepts, Problems,
New York: Springer.
Krueger, J., & Overgaard, S. (). Seeing Subjectivity: Defending a Perceptual
Account of Other Minds. ProtoSociology, , pp. –.
Kukla, R. (). The Ontology and Temporality of Conscience. Continental
Philosophy Review Continental Philosophy Review, (), pp. –.
Lacoue-Labarthe, P. (). Heidegger, Art, and Politics: The Fiction of the
Political, Oxford: Blackwell.
Bibliography
Lafont, C. (). Heidegger, Language, and World-Disclosure, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
(a). Précis of Heidegger, Language, and World-Disclosure. Inquiry, (),
pp. –.
(b). Replies. Inquiry, (), pp. –.
(). Was Heidegger an Externalist? Inquiry, (), pp. –.
Lawson, T. (). The Nature of Social Reality: Issues in Social Ontology,
Abingdon: Routledge.
Levinas, E. (). Reflections on the Philosophy of Hitlerism. Critical Inquiry,
(), pp. –.
(). Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority (A. Lingis, trans.),
Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.
(). Otherwise than Being, or, Beyond Essence (A. Lingis, trans.), Pittsburgh,
PA: Duquesne University Press.
Lewis, D. (). Convention: A Philosophical Study, Oxford: Blackwell.
Lewis, M. (). Heidegger and the Place of Ethics: Being-With in the Crossing of
Heidegger’s Thought, London: Bloomsbury.
Lipps, T. (). The Knowledge of Other Egos. The New Yearbook for
Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, , pp. –.
Løgstrup, K. E. (). The Ethical Demand (R. Stern & B. Rabjerg, trans.),
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Löwith, K. (). Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen, Darmstadt:
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
(). Mein Leben in Deutschland vor und nach : Ein Bericht (F.-R.
Hausmann, Ed.), Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.
Ludwig, K. (). From Individual to Plural Agency: Collective Action: Volume ,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Malpas, J. (). Donald Davidson and the Mirror of Meaning: Holism, Truth,
Interpretation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(). Gadamer, Davidson, and the Ground of Understanding. In J. Malpas,
U. Arnswald, & J. Kertscher, eds, Gadamer’s Century: Essays in Honor of
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. –.
(). Heidegger’s Topology: Being, Place, World, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(). Heidegger and the Thinking of Place: Explorations in the Topology of
Being, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(). Place and Situation. In J. Malpas & H.-H. Gander, eds, The Routledge
Companion to Hermeneutics, Abingdon: Routledge, pp. –.
Marchart, O. (). Post-foundational Political Thought: Political Difference in
Nancy, Lefort, Badiou and Laclau, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Martin, W. (). The Semantics of “Dasein” and the Modality of Being and
Time. In M. Wrathall, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger’s Being
and Time, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. –.
Mathieson, K. (). Collective Consciousness. In D. W. Smith & A. L.
Thomasson, eds, Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind, Oxford:
Clarendon Press, pp. –.
Bibliography
McDowell, J. (). Putnam on Mind and Meaning. Philosophical Topics, (),
pp. –.
(). Mind and World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
McManus, D. (). Heidegger and the Measure of Truth: Themes from His Early
Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
(). Constitution (Konstitution). In M. Wrathall, ed., The Cambridge
Heidegger Lexicon, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. –.
McMullin, I. (). Time and the Shared World: Heidegger on Social Relations,
Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
McNeill, W. (). The Glance of the Eye: Heidegger, Aristotle, and the Ends of
Theory, Albany: State University of New York Press.
Meijers, A. (). Speech Acts, Communication and Collective Intentionality:
Beyond Searle’s Individualism, Utrecht: A.W.M. Meijers.
Mendieta, E. (). Metaphysical Anti-Semitism and Worldlessness: On World
Poorness, World Forming, and World Destroying. In A. Mitchell and P.
Trawny, eds, Heidegger’s Black Notebooks: Responses to Anti-Semitism, New
York: Columbia University Press, pp. –.
Merleau-Ponty, M. (). Signs, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
(). Phenomenology of Perception, Abingdon: Routledge.
Miettinen, T. (). Transcendental Social Ontology. In Sara Heinämaa, Mirja
Hartimo, & Timo Miettinen, eds, Phenomenology and the Transcendental,
Abingdon: Routledge, pp. –.
Mill, J. S. (). An Examination of Sir William Hamilton’s Philosophy (J. Robson
& A. Ryan, Eds), Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Millikan, R. G. (). Language: A Biological Model, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Moran, D. (). Dasein as Transcendence in Heidegger and the Critique of
Husserl. In T. Georgakis & P. Ennis, eds, Heidegger in the Twenty-First
Century, New York: Springer, pp. –.
Mulhall, S. (). Inheritance and Originality: Wittgenstein, Heidegger,
Kierkegaard, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
(). Human Mortality: Heidegger on How to Portray the Impossible
Possibility of Dasein. In H. Dreyfus & M. Wrathall, eds, A Companion to
Heidegger, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. –.
Nagel, T. (). The Possibility of Altruism, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Nancy, J.-L. (). The Inoperative Community, Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
(). The Experience of Freedom, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
(). Heidegger’s “Originary Ethics.” In F. Raffoul & D. Pettigrew, eds,
Heidegger and Practical Philosophy, Albany, NY: State University of New
York Press.
(). The Being-with of Being-there. Continental Philosophy Review, ,
pp. –.
Bibliography
(). The Banality of Heidegger (J. Fort, trans.), New York: Fordham
University Press.
Nenon, T. (). Husserl and Heidegger on the Social Dimensions of the Life-
World. In Ľ. Učník, I. Chvatík, & A. Williams, eds, The Phenomenological
Critique of Mathematisation and the Question of Responsibility: Formalisation
and the Life-World, New York: Springer International Publishing,
pp. –.
O’Brien, M. (). Leaping Ahead of Heidegger: Subjectivity and
Intersubjectivity in Being and Time. International Journal of Philosophical
Studies, (), pp. –.
Okrent, M. (). Heidegger’s Pragmatism : Understanding, Being and the
Critique of Metaphysics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
(). Equipment, World, and Language. Inquiry, , pp. –.
(). The Truth of Being and the History of Philosophy. In A. Malachowski,
ed., A Companion to Rorty, Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd,
pp. –.
Olafson, F. A. (). Heidegger and the Philosophy of Mind, New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
(). Heidegger à la Wittgenstein or Coping with Professor Dreyfus. Inquiry,
(), pp. –.
(). Heidegger and the Ground of Ethics: A Study of Mitsein, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
O’Murchadha, F. (). Reduction, Externalism and Immanence in Husserl and
Heidegger. Synthese, (), pp. –.
Overgaard, S. (). Husserl and Heidegger on Being in the World, Dordrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Petersson, B. (). Collectivity and Circularity. The Journal of Philosophy,
(), pp. –.
Petropoulos, G. (). Actuality Without Existence: The Jewish Figure in
Heidegger’s Notebooks. Critical Horizons – A Journal of Philosophy and
Social Theory, (), pp. –.
Phillips, J. (). Heidegger’s Volk: Between National Socialism and Poetry,
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Pippin, R. B. (). Idealism as Modernism: Hegelian Variations, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Pöggeler, O. (). Den Führer führen? Heidegger und kein Ende. Philosophische
Rundschau, (/), pp. –.
Polt, R. (). Time and Trauma, London ; New York: Rowman & Littlefield
International.
Putnam, H. (). The Meaning of “Meaning.” Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, , pp. –.
Raffoul, F. (). Rethinking Selfhood: From Enowning. Research in
Phenomenology, (), pp. –.
Reid, J. D. (). Heidegger’s Moral Ontology, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Bibliography
Richardson, W. J. (). Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought, New
York: Fordham University Press.
Rorty, R. (). Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey. The Review
of Metaphysics, (), pp. –.
(). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
(). Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
(). Philosophy and Social Hope, New York: Penguin.
Rousse, B. S. (). Self-awareness and Self-understanding. European Journal of
Philosoph, (), pp. –.
Ruin, H. (). Historicity and the Hermeneutic Predicament. In The Oxford
Handbook of the History of Phenomenology, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
pp. –.
Sánchez Guerrero, H. A. (). Feeling Together and Caring with One Another:
A Contribution to the Debate on Collective Affective Intentionality, New York:
Springer International Publishing.
Sartre, J.-P. (). Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology
(H. E. Barnes, trans.), Abingdon: Routledge.
Schatzki, T. R. (a). A New Societist Social Ontology. Philosophy of the Social
Sciences, (), pp. –.
(b). The Site of the Social, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University
Press.
(). Early Heidegger on Sociality. In H. Dreyfus & M. Wrathall, eds,
A Companion to Heidegger, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. –.
Schear, J. (). Historical Finitude. In M. Wrathall, ed., The Cambridge
Companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, pp. –.
Schear, J. K. (). Judgment and Ontology in Heidegger’s Phenomenology.
New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, ,
pp. –.
(). Being (Sein): In Being and Time. In M. Wrathall, ed., The Cambridge
Heidegger Lexicon, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. –.
Scheffler, S. (). Death and the Afterlife (N. Kolodny, Ed.), Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Scheler, M. (). Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New
Attempt Toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism (M. S. Frings & R.
L. Funk, trans.), Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
(). The Nature of Sympathy (P. Heath, trans.), Piscataway, NJ: Transaction
Publishers.
Schmid, H. B. (). Can Brains in Vats Think as a Team? Philosophical
Explorations, (), pp. –.
(). Wir-Intentionalitat. Kritik des ontologischen Individualismus und
Rekonstruktion der Gemeinschaft, Freiburg im Breisgau: Verlag Karl Alber.
Bibliography
(). Plural Action: Essays in Philosophy and Social Science, Dordrecht:
Springer Science & Business Media.
(a). Plural Self-awareness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, (),
pp. –.
(b). The Feeling of Being a Group: Corporate Emotions and Collective
Consciousness. In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela, eds, Collective Emotions:
Perspectives from Psychology, Philosophy, and Sociology, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. –.
(). Authentic Role Play: A Political Solution to an Existential Paradox. In
H. B. Schmid & G. Thonhauser, eds, From Conventionalism to Social
Authenticity: Heidegger’s Anyone and Contemporary Social Theory, New
York: Springer, pp. –.
(). The Subject of “We Intend.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences,
(), pp. –.
Schmidt, D. J. (). On Germans & Other Greeks: Tragedy and Ethical Life,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Schmitt, C. (). Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (T.
B. Strong, trans., G. Schwab, Ed.), Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Scholl, B. J., & Leslie, A. M. (). Modularity, Development and “Theory of
Mind.” Mind and Language, (), pp. –.
Schütz, A. (). The Phenomenology of the Social World (G. Walsh & F.
Lehnert, trans.), Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Schweikard, D. P., & Schmid, H. B. (). Collective Intentionality. In E.
Zalta, ed., Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/
entries/collective-intentionality/, accessed on //
Searle, J. (). Collective Intentions and Actions. In P. R. C. Jerry Morgan &
M. Pollack, eds, Intentions in Communication, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
pp. –.
(). The Construction of Social Reality, New York: The Free Press.
(). Neither Phenomenological Description Nor Rational Reconstruction.
Revue Internationale de Philosophie, (), pp. –.
(). Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Sheehan, T. (). A Paradigm Shift in Heidegger Research. Continental
Philosophy Review, (), pp. –.
(). No One Can Jump Over His Own Shadow: Richard Polt and Gregory
Fried in Conversation with Thomas Sheehan. Retrieved September ,
, from www.ammagazine.com/am/no-one-can-jump-over-his-own-
shadow/
(). Making Sense of Heidegger: A Paradigm Shift, Lanham, MD: Rowman
& Littlefield.
Sherover, C. M. (). Founding an Existential Ethic. Human Studies, (), pp.
–.
Shoemaker, D. (). Attributability, Answerability, and Accountability: Toward
a Wider Theory of Moral Responsibility. Ethics, (), pp. –.
Bibliography
Sikka, S. (). Heidegger, Morality and Politics: Questioning the Shepherd of
Being, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stein, E. (). On the Problem of Empathy (W. Stein, trans.), The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff.
Steinbock, A. J. (). Home and Beyond: Generative Phenomenology after
Husserl, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Stroh, K. M. (). Intersubjectivity of Dasein in Heideggers Being and Time:
How Authenticity is a Return to Community. Human Studies: A Journal for
Philosophy and the Social Sciences, (), pp. –.
Stueber, K. (). Rediscovering Empathy: Agency, Folk Psychology, and the
Human Sciences, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Taylor, C. (). Understanding the Other: A Gadamerian View on Conceptual
Schemes. In J. Malpas, U. Arnswald, & J. Kertscher, eds, Gadamer’s Century:
Essays in Honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Theunissen, M. (). The Other: Studies in the Social Ontology of Husserl, Heidegger,
Sartre, and Buber (C. Macann, trans.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Thompson, K. (). The Historicality of Das Man: Foucault on Docility and
Optimality. In S. H. Bernhard & T. Gerhard, eds, From Conventionalism to
Social Authenticity: Heidegger’s Anyone and Contemporary Social Theory, New
York: Springer, pp. –.
Thomson, I. (). Ontotheology? Understanding Heidegger’s Destruktion
of Metaphysics. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, (),
pp. –.
(). Death and Demise in Being and Time. In M. Wrathall, ed., The
Cambridge Companion to Heidegger’s Being and Time, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. –.
Thonhauser, G. (). Transforming the World: A Butlerian Reading of
Heidegger on Social Change? In H. B. Schmid & G. Thonhauser, eds,
From Conventionalism to Social Authenticity: Heidegger’s Anyone and
Contemporary Social Theory, New York: Springer.
Tollefsen, D. P. (). Collective Intentionality and Methodology in the Social
Sciences. In M. Jankovic and K. Ludwig, eds, The Routledge Handbook of
Collective Intentionality, Abingdon: Routledge, pp. –.
Tomasello, M. (). A Natural History of Human Thinking, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Tönnies, F. (). Tönnies: Community and Civil Society (M. Hollis, trans., J.
Harris, Ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trawny, P. (). Heidegger und der Mythos der jüdischen Weltverschwörung,
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Tugendhat, E. (). Aufsätze –, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
Tuomela, R. (). Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tuomela, R., Hakli, R., & Mäkelä, P. (). Social Ontology in the Making: An
Introduction. In R. Tuomela, R. Hakli, & P. Mäkelä, eds, Social Ontology in
the Making, Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. –.
Bibliography
van Buren, J. (). The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King,
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Varga, S. (). Toward a Perceptual Account of Mindreading. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, (), pp. –.
Vattimo, G. (). The End of Modernity: Nihilism and Hermeneutics in Post-
modern Culture, Cambridge: Polity.
(). Beyond Interpretation: The Meaning of Hermeneutics for Philosophy,
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Vogel, L. (). The Fragile We: Ethical Implications Of Heidegger’s Being and
Time, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
von Herrmann, F.-W., & Alfieri, F. (). Martin Heidegger: Die Wahrheit über
die Schwarzen Hefte, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Walsh, P. (). Intercorporeity and the First-person Plural in Merleau-Ponty.
Continental Philosophy Review, , pp. –.
Ward, K. (). Responsible for Destiny: Historizing, Historicality, and
Community. Gatherings: The Heidegger Circle Annual, , pp. –.
Watson, G. (). Two Faces of Responsibility. Philosophical Topics, (),
pp. –.
Webb, D. (). Heidegger, Ethics and the Practice of Ontology, London, New
York: Continuum.
Weber, M. (). Economy and Society: A New Translation (K. Tribe, trans.),
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Weichold, M. (). Social Authenticity: Towards a Heideggerian Analysis of
Social Change. In H. B. Schmid & G. Thonhauser, eds, From
Conventionalism to Social Authenticity: Heidegger’s Anyone and
Contemporary Social Theory, New York: Springer.
Westerlund, F. (). Heidegger and the Problem of Phenomena, London:
Bloomsbury.
Winch, P. (). Understanding a Primitive Society. In N. K. Frankenberry &
H. H. Penner, eds, Language, Truth, and Religious Belief: Studies in
Twentieth-Century Theory and Method in Religion, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. –.
Withy, K. (). The Strategic Unity of Heidegger’s The Fundamental
Concepts of Metaphysics. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, (),
pp. –.
(). Heidegger on Being Uncanny, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
(). We Are a Conversation: Heidegger on How Language Uncovers. In C.
Engelland, ed., Language and Phenomenology, Abingdon: Routledge,
pp. –.
Wittgenstein, L. (). Philosophical Investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, trans.),
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Wolin, R. (Ed.). (). The Heidegger Controversy: A Critical Reader, Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Bibliography
(). The Politics of Being: The Political Thought of Martin Heidegger, New
York: Columbia University Press.
Wrathall, M. (). Practical Incommensurability and the Phenomenological
Basis of Robust Realism. Inquiry, (), pp. –.
(). Heidegger, Truth, and Reference. Inquiry, (), pp. –.
(). Heidegger and Unconcealment: Truth, Language, and History,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(). Autonomy, Authenticity, and the Self. In D. McManus, ed., Heidegger,
Authenticity and the Self: Themes from Division Two of Being and Time,
Abingdon: Routledge, pp. –.
(). “Demanding Authenticity of Ourselves”: Heidegger on Authenticity as
an Extra-Moral Ideal. In H. Pedersen & M. Altman, eds, Horizons of
Authenticity in Phenomenology, Existentialism, and Moral Psychology: Essays
in Honor of Charles Guignon, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands,
pp. –.
(). “I” “here” and “you” “there”. Yearbook for Eastern and Western
Philosophy, (), pp. –.
(). The Task of Thinking in a Technological Age. In A. J. Wendland, C.
Merwin, & C. Hadjioannou, eds, Heidegger on Technology, Abingdon:
Routledge, pp. –.
Young. (). Heidegger, Philosophy, Nazism, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Zahavi, D. (). Husserl and Transcendental Intersubjectivity: A Response to the
Linguistic-Pragmatic Critique, Athens: Ohio University Press.
(). Internalism, Externalism, and Transcendental Idealism. Synthese,
(), –.
(). Empathy, Embodiment and Interpersonal Understanding: From Lipps
to Schutz. Inquiry, (), pp. –.
(). Self and Other: Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy, and Shame, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
(a). Self and Other: From Pure Ego to Co-constituted We. Continental
Philosophy Review, (), pp. –.
(b). You, Me, and We: The Sharing of Emotional Experiences. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, (–), pp. –.
(). Collective Intentionality and Plural Pre-Reflective Self-Awareness.
Journal of Social Philosophy, (), pp. –.
(). Second-Person Engagement, Self-Alienation, and Group-
Identification. Topoi, (), pp. –.
Zahavi, D., & Rochat, P. (). Empathy6¼sharing: Perspectives from
Phenomenology and Developmental Psychology. Consciousness and
Cognition, , pp. –.
Index
a as b-structure, –, , , , and the Anyone, –
as responsive to others, , , , –, definition of, –
, autonomy, , –
lacking in animals, –, averageness, , ,
PCI on, –,
absorption, Beauvoir, Simone de,
accountability, –, See also attributability Befindlichkeit. See affectivity
action, , –, being-towards-death, , , –, ,
joint, , –, –
shared, –, –, , , and demise, –
affectivity, , and perishing, –,
affordance, –, , , –, –, being-with, , , , –
, See also goal; in-order-to relation and authenticity, –
joint, –, – and discourse, –
alterity, –, , – as essential agreement, –
America, –, –, –, concept of, –
animal rationale, , –, transcendental status of, , , , –,
animality, , –, , –, ,
animism, Biles, Simone,
anticipation, , – Bird, Larry,
antisemitism. See Judaism Blattner, William, , , –
anxiety, , –, –, – body. See embodiment
Anyone, the, –, –, –, –, Bratman, Michael, , –, –, ,
–, , , , , , See also
pragmatic conventionalist interpretation, Buber, Martin, ,
the; social normativity: anonymous
and externalism, – camping trip, example of the, –,
as drift towards social coherence, –, care, –, , , , , , –,
–, , –, –
Arendt, Hannah, , Carman, Taylor, , , , –, , , ,
argument from analogy, –, , , , , –, , –,
, –
Aristotle, , Carr, David,
atomism, , , –, Cartesianism, –, –, , , ,
attributability, , –, –, –, ,
–, See also accountability collective intentionality, –, –, , ,
authenticity, –, , –, –, , –, , , –,
, , –, , –, collectivism, , –
– commitment, –, , –, –,
and intersubjectivity, – , , See also for-the-sake-of relation
and social change, by default, , , , ,
Index
communal, –, –, , fellow Dasein, , –, , , , , ,
–, , –, , See also interpersonal
Gilbert’s notion of, – understanding
joint, –, , – football,
Schmid’s notion of, , for-the-sake-of relation, –, , –,
conscience, , –, , –, See also commitment
of others, , – fragility, –, ,
constitution, –, – Fried, Gregory,
in Husserl, –, – Fug. See dikē
convention, –, –, , –, , , , Führerprinzip, –, –
–, –, Fürsorge. See solicitude
Crowell, Steven, , , , , –,
, , –, – Gadamer, Hans-Georg, , ,
Gelassenheit,
dancing, , , genetic problem, the, ,
das Man. See Anyone, the geopolitics, , , , –,
Dasein, concept of, , –, Gerede. See idle talk
as individual or collective, Germany, , –, –, –
Davidson, Donald, , , – Gestell. See en-framing
death. See being-towards-death Gilbert, Margaret, –, , , –,
Derrida, Jacques, , , –,
Descartes, Rene. See Cartesianism goal, , , , , –, , –,
destiny, , –, , , , –, , , See also affordance;
in-order-to relation
developmental psychology, , , Golob, Sacha, , , , ,
dikē, –, – Greece, , ,
discourse, –, –, – Guignon, Charles, , –, , ,
distantiality, , –, , guilt, –,
Dreyfus, Hubert, , , –, , , –,
–, –, , , , –, Habermas, Jürgen, , ,
Hatab, Lawrence,
dyadic relation, –, , –, Haugeland, John, , , –, –,
education, –, , –, Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, , , ,
Eigentlichkeit. See authenticity –
embodiment, –, , –, Heinämaa, Sara, –
empathy, , , –, –, See also heritage, –,
interpersonal understanding; hermeneutics, –, –, –, , ,
transpositioning –, , , –
Heidegger’s critique of, – historicism, –, , –
special hermeneutics of, , history, , –, , –, –,
enactivism, , , –, See also social normativity:
en-framing, , , –, historical; historicism
epoché, –, , See also constitution Hölderlin, Friedrich, –,
Ereignis, , –, See also historicism holism, –, –, –, –, ,
existentialism, , , See also externalism; relativism
externalism, , –, –, –, See also and animality,
holism and historicity, –
and natural kinds, and relativism, , –
open-ended (or weak), , , , , and the differentiation condition, , , ,
, ,
strong, , and the jointness condition, , ,
facticity, –, , , Husserl, Edmund, , –, –, , ,
fallenness, , –, , –, , ,
Index
Husserl, Edmund (cont.) McManus, Denis, ,
and the critique of Heidegger, – McMullin, Irene, –, , –, ,
Heidegger’s critique of, , –, –, Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, , –,
– metapolitics, –, , –, –,
See also Nazism
idealism, , , , , , See also realism Mill, John Stuart, –,
idle talk, , See also discourse Millikan, Ruth,
inauthenticity, –, –, , mineness, , , , , See also authenticity;
–, –, , See also Anyone, care
the; authenticity Mitdasein. See fellow Dasein
individualism, , , , –, Mitsein. See being-with
methodological, mood. See affectivity
individuation, –, , , –, mutual use, , , , , ,
as emphatic, –, –, –,
Nancy, Jean-Luc, ,
most radical, – naturalism, –, –, , , , –
of the world, Nazism, –, –, , , , ,
in-order-to relation, –, –, , , –, See also Germany; metapolitics
, See also affordance; goal Nietzsche, Friedrich, , ,
institutional facts, –, – normativity
intellectualism, , , , and acting in light of norms, , ,
intellectualist problem, the, and morality, –
intentionality. See a as b-structure as inert, , –,
intergenerationality, –, as lacking in Heidegger,
internalism, , –, –, , , , See in Dasein’s existence,
also animality; externalism in shared action, –, –
interpersonal understanding, , , , See
also empathy; transpositioning O’Brien, Mahon, ,
Heidegger’s neglect of, object-awareness, –, –, –, ,
problem of, ,
introspection, , , , , , Okrent, Mark, , –, –,
Olafson, Frederick, , –, –
Jemeinigkeit. See mineness open intersubjectivity, –, , ,
joint attention, , –, , order, historical. See dikē
Judaism, , –, – other-awareness (non-thematic), –, –,
See also interpersonal understanding
Kant, Immanuel, , , , , , , Overgaard, Søren, –, –
, –
people, concept of the, –, –, ,
Lafont, Christina, –, , –, –, –, –,
language. See discourse –, See also geopolitics; Germany;
layer ontology, , , , , metapolitics; social normativity: historical
leaping-ahead, –, –, See also polis, –
solicitude Polt, Richard,
leaping-in, –, , See also solicitude power, –
levelling down, , pragmatic conventionalist interpretation, the,
Levinas, Emmanuel, , , , , –, –, , , , –,
Lewis, David, –, – problem of other minds, the, –
Lipps, Theodor, –, – projection, , , –
Löwith, Karl, , , , psychologism, –, , ,
Ludwig, Kirk, public, the, –
Sánchez Guerrero, Héctor Andrés, , taxonomy problem, the, , –
Sartre, Jean-Paul, , , , , , , , , Taylor, Charles,
teleology. See goal
Schatzki, Theodore, , , temporality, –, –
Schear, Joseph, , tennis, –
Scheffler, Samuel, The Gods Must Be Crazy,
Scheler, Max, , –, –, – theory theory of mind, –,
Schmid, Hans Bernhard, –, , –, Theunissen, Michael, ,
–, , Thomson, Iain, , , –
Schmitt, Carl, thrownness, –, , , , ,
Schütz, Alfred, , –
Searle, John, –, –, –, , , , Tomasello, Michael, –
, – Tönnies, Ferdinand, –
Sein-zum-Tode. See being-towards-death transcendence, –,
self-awareness. See selfhood and alterity,
selfhood and intersubjectivity, –,
and constancy, , , – in Husserl, –, –, –
and I, you, and we, , , , , transcendentalism, , –, –,
existential, –, , , , –,
– late Heidegger’s rejection of, –, –
in action, – transpositioning, –, –
minimal, –, , triangulation, –, –, , , –,
plural, – –, , , ,
self-world. See world, the: threefold conception
of understanding, , –, , , , –,
Senegalese, example of the, –, – , ,
shared action. See action of being, , , , –, , –,
significance, –, , –, –, –, , –, , –,
–, –, –,
simulation theory of mind, –, ontic, –
social cognition. See interpersonal understanding ontological, –,
social normativity, , –, , , Uneigentlichkeit. See inauthenticity
anonymous, –, See also Anyone, the
historical, –, , , , van Buren, John,
social ontology Verstehen. See understanding
and fundamental ontology, – volatility, –, –, –,
and politics, –, –
restricted view of, Weber, Max, , –
transcendental, , –, Westerlund, Fredrik, ,
unrestricted view of, – with-world. See world, the: threefold conception
solicitation, –, , , , –, of
–, , , , , Wittgenstein, Ludwig, , , , –
Index
world, the world sharing, , –, –, –, –,
a priori structure of, – –
concept of, – as distribution,
threefold conception of, –, asymmetric, –
Lafont on,
world-building, –, , , See also PCI on, ,
transpositioning; world sharing Wrathall, Mark, , , , –, ,
worldlessness, , –,
world-poverty, –, –, , See also Zahavi, Dan, , , , –, , , ,
animality