Exploring Law's Empire - The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin - Scott Hershovitz (Editor) - 2008 - Oxford University Press - 9780191706462 - Anna's Archive
Exploring Law's Empire - The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin - Scott Hershovitz (Editor) - 2008 - Oxford University Press - 9780191706462 - Anna's Archive
THE JURISPRUDENCE OF
RONALD DWORKIN
Exploring Law’s Empire:
The Jurisprudence of Ronald Dworkin
Edited by
SCOT T HERSHOVITZ
3
This book has been printed digitally and produced in a standard specification
in order to ensure its continuing availability
1
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
© the several contributors 2006
Reprinted 2012
The plan for this book was simple: ask leading scholars in jurisprudence and con-
stitutional law who are sympathetic to Ronald Dworkin’s work to write essays
about it. The invitation was open-ended. Authors were asked to contribute to
Dworkin’s project by offering new arguments for old conclusions, by offering new
arguments for new conclusions consistent with Dworkin’s project, by filling gaps,
or by criticizing Dworkin’s work to show how it could be improved. We hoped
that in putting together a collection of such essays, and by asking Dworkin to
respond to them, we would enrich the discourse to which Dworkin has con-
tributed so much.
With such an open-ended invitation, we were bound to get an eclectic mix of
essays, and that was the point. The scope of Dworkin’s contributions to our
understanding of law is vast. He has made seminal contributions to debates over
doctrinal and theoretical issues in American constitutional law, to debates over
topics such as civil disobedience and the obligation to obey the law, and, of course,
to our understanding of the nature of law and its relationship to morality. And this
list leaves unmentioned much of Dworkin’s groundbreaking work in political and
moral philosophy, which has had a significant impact on legal discourse. We
therefore set authors loose with the charge that they should engage with whatever
aspect of Dworkin’s work they saw fit, not simply to honor it, but to increase our
understanding of it and push it forward. In that way, we hoped to produce a book
that would explore the full richness of Dworkin’s contributions to our under-
standing of law’s empire.
While there is no overall theme to the book that resulted, a number of themes
recur throughout. Justice Breyer’s introductory essay recounts a discussion
Dworkin led at a conference of international judges. Justice Breyer goes on to
describe how Dworkin’s work has influenced the way judges on constitutional
courts around the world conceive of their role in democratic societies.
Dworkin’s constitutional theory is further examined in essays by Chris
Eisgruber, Jim Fleming, and Rebecca Brown. Eisgruber and Fleming address the
role of history in Dworkin’s moral reading. Eisgruber argues that history has a
more significant role in Dworkin’s account than many recognize. But he argues
that the moral reading as Dworkin presents it does not provide a fully satisfactory
account of constitutional interpretation because it does not adequately explain
how American-style constitutionalism, which requires a legislative supermajority
to overrule a constitutional decision, facilitates government based on principles of
justice. Fleming’s essay examines the relationship between Dworkin’s moral read-
ing and both process-oriented and originalist approaches to constitutional inter-
pretation. Brown’s essay explores the influence that Dworkin has had on the
vi Preface
development of constitutional law in the United States. She focuses on the ways in
which Dworkin’s constitutional theory helped scholars come to terms with Brown
v. Board of Education, and she traces Dworkin’s influence on contemporary consti-
tutional law.
Essays by Susan Hurley and Scott Hershovitz transition the book from explor-
ations of Dworkin’s constitutional theory to explorations of his legal theory more
generally. Hurley argues for the somewhat counterintuitive view that the content
of the law is not simply a function of actual cases which courts have decided, but is
also a function of hypothetical cases which courts have not and may never be called
upon to decide.¹ She develops a coherence account of legal reasoning similar to
Dworkin’s, and she addresses objections Kenneth Kress has raised to such
accounts. Hershovitz’s essay tackles a different aspect of legal reasoning—stare
decisis. He argues that accounts of stare decisis that justify the practice of follow-
ing precedent by appealing to the values of efficiency and fairness are unsuccessful.
Stare decisis, he urges, is best understood as a practice which promotes integrity in
adjudication.
Integrity is also a subject of investigation in three further essays. Dale Smith
considers problems in Dworkin’s account of checkerboard solutions, policies that
Dworkin claims are defective due to a lack of integrity. Smith aims to clarify the
ways in which checkerboard solutions are defective. Jeremy Waldron considers
objections the Critical Legal Studies movement raised to Dworkin’s theory of law
as integrity and the adequacy of Dworkin’s response. Waldron suggests that there
is a tension between the role of integrity in Dworkin’s account of legal practice and
his constructivist approach to legal interpretation. Finally, Stephen Perry con-
siders integrity as it relates to the problem of political obligation. His essay clarifies
the relationship between Dworkin’s account of political obligation and his
account of the nature of law.
This volume ends where Dworkin’s career began—with questions about the
nature of law. John Gardner’s essay considers whether law has a distinctive pur-
pose, and the role that such a purpose plays in Dworkin’s account of law. Gardner
argues that some of Dworkin’s commitments in this regard push him towards legal
positivism. Mark Greenberg, on the other hand, argues for a broadly Dworkinian
view of the nature of law, on which value facts are among the determinants of the
content of the law. Greenberg’s approach is novel because it focuses on law’s meta-
physics—on, as he puts it, “how facts make law”—rather than on how judges and
lawyers come to know what the law is. Greenberg’s argument extends across two
essays. The first essay was originally published in Legal Theory;² the second essay,
¹ Hurley’s essay was previously published as Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precendent, 10(2)
OXFORD JOURNAL OF LEGAL STUDIES 221 (1990). It is reprinted here by kind permission of Oxford
University Press.
² Greenberg’s essay was previously published as How Facts Make Law, 10 LEGAL THEORY 157
(2004). It is reprinted here with permission.
Preface vii
which is published here for the first time, responds to a family of objections to the
argument of the first essay and further develops that argument in the course of
criticizing positivist theories commonly associated with H. L. A. Hart.
The volume concludes with responses from Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin com-
ments on each essay, but focuses his attention on those that challenge views he has
defended. His responses are in each instance illuminating and they contain valu-
able statements of his views across a range of topics.
Each of the contributors to this book played an important role in its produc-
tion, and I am grateful to all of them for the work they took on. Three deserve spe-
cial thanks: Chris Eisgruber, John Gardner, and Mark Greenberg. Chris hosted a
conference at Princeton University in September 2004, at which many of the
essays in this book were presented. Mark and John have been incredibly generous
with their support and encouragement. This project would not have come to
fruition without their help, and I appreciate all that they did. I also appreciate the
support—and patience—of John Louth and Gwen Booth, our editors at Oxford
University Press.
Collectively, our deepest gratitude is reserved for Ronnie. All of us know that
our work would be less insightful and less exciting had he not taught us so much.
We appreciate his willingness to join our project and engage with our essays. We
didn’t set out to write a conventional festschrift, but we hope that in developing
and criticizing Ronnie’s work, we have honored him nonetheless.
SAH
Washington, D.C.
January 2006
List of Contributors
Stephen Breyer is an Associate Justice of the United States Supreme Court.
Rebecca L. Brown is the Allen Professor of Law at Vanderbilt Law School.
Ronald Dworkin is the Frank Henry Sommer Professor of Law at New York University
School of Law and the Bentham Professor of Jurisprudence at University College London.
Christopher L. Eisgruber is the Provost of Princeton University and the Laurance S.
Rockefeller Professor of Public Affairs in the Woodrow Wilson School and the University
Center for Human Values.
James E. Fleming is the Leonard F. Manning Distinguished Professor of Law at Fordham
University School of Law.
John Gardner is the Professor of Jurisprudence at the University of Oxford.
Mark Greenberg is Acting Professor of Law and Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the
University of California, Los Angeles.
Scott Hershovitz is a faculty-designate at the University of Michigan Law School. He cur-
rently practices law in Washington, D.C.
S. L. Hurley is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Bristol and a Fellow of All Souls
College, Oxford.
Stephen Perry is the John J. O’Brien Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy at the
University of Pennsylvania Law School.
Dale Smith is a lecturer in the Faculty of Law at Monash University, Australia.
Jeremy Waldron is University Professor at New York University Law School.
Introduction: The “International”
Constitutional Judge
Stephen Breyer
In July 2000 a small group of jurists from several western nations, mostly judges,
met for a week in Southern France to discuss the judge’s role in our increasingly
similar, interdependent societies. Our focus was upon constitutional judges,
including judges of international courts. We did not try to reach conclusions. We
hoped to learn through conversation.¹
Professor Dworkin led a discussion about the judge’s moral authority, a matter
we had entitled, with some irony, “the secular papacy.” His paper tied the discus-
sion to a more basic view of constitutional law, which he set forth in three theses.²
First, law, particularly constitutional law, inevitably embodies standards that
require a judge to make moral decisions. Administrative law, for example, sets aside
agency actions that are “unreasonable,” “disproportionate,” or an “abuse of power.”
Constitutional law protects “liberty,” including “freedom of speech,” “freedom of
the press,” and “freedom from unreasonable searches and seizures.” Judges cannot
apply these standards in difficult cases without revealing their own moral views, at
least those that concern proper political structure (itself a matter of political moral-
ity). The thought that judges must rely upon their own “political convictions”³
makes judges uncomfortable. But there is no satisfactory alternative.
Secondly, it is not “undemocratic”⁴ for unelected officials such as judges to pos-
sess the power to enforce these standards. This is not because “the people . . . do
not object to” the judicial practice “and, from time to time in different ways
endorse it.”⁵ Nor is it because “democracy compromised” is a “better form of gov-
ernment” (say, because it produces “a more just community by protecting the
rights of minorities”).⁶ Rather, it is because the best “conception” of “democracy”⁷
is a conception under which “majority rule is fair;” and majority rule is “fair” only
when certain conditions are met. Where these conditions are realized, then
democracy in its best sense is realized. Insofar as the judge helps to assure that
those conditions are met, the judge’s work helps to support democracy itself.
Thirdly, societies increasingly have turned to judges to assure that these con-
ditions are met because they are increasingly uncertain that parliaments or “the
people themselves”⁸ will do so unaided. Before the “short and terrible Twentieth
Century”⁹ many thought that parliaments alone might do so by properly bal-
ancing the “general interest” with “fairness to individuals.”¹⁰ That is to say,
legislatures might “at once” be “the voice and the conscience of the people,”
pursuing “the general interest, but subject to ancient constraints of fairness and
decency to individual citizens.” Some thought this because they held the aristo-
cratic notion that parliament embodied the wisdom of a “political elite”¹¹ with
the best interests of the nation at heart. Others thought this because they held
the romantic notion that parliament embodied the majority’s “decent and hon-
orable general will.”¹² But given a Twentieth Century history that discredited
both notions, societies now seek institutionally to separate the “social acceler-
ator” from the “moral brake.”¹³ And they have given judges ever greater authority
to operate the latter.
What controls the judge when he or she exercises this increased authority? The
control lies not only in the general ends they pursue—assuring the conditions of a
democracy in its best sense, namely, fair majority rule—but also in the specific
means they employ, in particular the process of judicial reasoning. This process
encompasses the judicial “responsibility for articulation,” which constrains judges
to “do nothing that they cannot justify in principle, and to appeal only to prin-
ciples that they thereby undertake to respect in other contexts as well.”¹⁴
These three theses require elaboration, a matter that I leave to Professor
Dworkin and to others to pursue elsewhere. Here, I shall simply note that the
judges at the conference found that the theses, though set forth in summary form,
usefully informed a wide-ranging discussion, touching upon subjects as disparate
as judicial activism, court/media relations, and international human rights tri-
bunals. I shall also point to several aspects of Dworkin’s theses that may help to
explain their broad appeal to practical judges, not themselves legal philosophers,
at work in different national and international settings.
For one thing, Dworkin accurately described the role that reason plays in the
judicial process. He said that judges “owe us . . . an argument that meets two condi-
tions. First they have to believe it; they must offer it in good faith as an argument.
Second, it has to connect what they do in a particular case with something more
general and basic.”¹⁵ He added that “in the end, what argument a judge finds con-
vincing will depend on that judge’s more general attitude and convictions, and no
one can demonstrate to those who do not share these attitudes and convictions that
they are inescapably right. But they must seem right, after open argument and seri-
ous reflection, to those who rely on them.”¹⁶ As a judge, I would say that that is how
it seems to us. And I would add that in a modern era where we must apply old values
I. Introduction
Ronald Dworkin has urged American judges and lawyers to embrace the “moral
reading of the [United States] Constitution.” The moral reading insists that the Bill
of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment “invoke moral principles about political
decency and justice.”¹ Some critics worry that the moral reading emphasizes
morality too much. They believe that it gives short shrift to text and history and
that it calls upon judges to become philosophers instead of lawyers.² Dworkin, in
return, has contended that his theory allows ample room for historical reasoning.
Yet, when Dworkin interprets the Constitution, the principles that he finds in it are
very abstract ones—such as the principle that “government must treat everyone as
of equal status and with equal concern”—and his analysis of them is thoroughly
philosophical. Historical concerns rarely figure in his arguments.
Why is Dworkin’s “moral reading of the Constitution” so moral—that is, why is it
concerned so much with moral issues and so little with other considerations, includ-
ing historical ones? Can Dworkin’s “moral reading” in fact accommodate historical
argument and other traditional forms of legal reasoning, or does it require constitu-
tional judges to become philosophers? If the latter, is that requirement defensible?
This essay examines these questions. It concludes that the abstract, philosophical
character of Dworkin’s constitutional interpretation is partly—but only partly—a
matter of Dworkin’s intellectual style. The general theoretical parameters of his
* For helpful comments on earlier drafts, I would like to thank Ronald Dworkin, Mark
Greenberg, Lewis Kornhauser, Liam Murphy, Larry Sager, the Faculty and Fellows of Princeton’s
University Center for Human Values, and the NYU Colloquia in Constitutional Theory and in Law,
Philosophy, and Social Theory. The Filomen D’Agostino and Max E. Greenberg Faculty Research
Fund at the New York University School of Law and the Woodrow Wilson School at Princeton
University provided financial support for this research.
¹ R. M. Dworkin, Freedom’s Law: The Moral Reading of the Constitution 2 (1996).
² An example of such criticism is M. McConnell, The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review:
A Comment on Dworkin’s Moral Reading of the Constitution, 65 Ford. L. Rev. 1269 (1997).
“moral reading” permit interpreters with different styles to invoke history more
often than Dworkin himself does. This preliminary conclusion is consistent with
Dworkin’s claim that lawyers who want to make historical arguments should do so
within the umbrella of the moral reading rather than in opposition to it.
Dworkin’s emphasis upon abstract moral principle is not, however, wholly
attributable to his intellectual style. This essay’s second conclusion, and its most
important claim, is that Dworkin’s arguments about moral principle and the
Constitution presuppose an unarticulated, controversial theory about the purpose
of written constitutions and super-majoritarian amendment procedures. They pre-
suppose, in particular, a theory that explains why people might adopt a constitu-
tion with super-majoritarian amendment procedures if they aim to accommodate
evolving judgments about abstract standards of justice. Some of Dworkin’s critics
deny that such an explanation is possible. They believe that the Constitution is
hard to amend because its purpose is to entrench past practices against revision on
the basis of subsequent judgments by later generations. Lawyers and judges who
hold this view about the Constitution sometimes assume that they should interpret
ambiguous constitutional provisions in ways that increase the influence of the past
upon the present. They believe that they are thereby faithful to what they take to be
the Constitution’s chief purpose—namely, preventing change. As it turns out,
there exist reasons to reject this past-oriented view of the Constitution’s purpose.
These reasons, however, are not yet part of the case that Dworkin has offered on
behalf of his position, and they depend on considerations different in kind from
those upon which he typically relies (they depend, in particular, upon pragmatic
judgments about political institutions). Unless supplemented by such reasons (or
some comparable theory of the Constitution’s purpose), Dworkin’s theory of
constitutional interpretation is significantly incomplete.
Almost three decades ago, Dworkin called for “a fusion of constitutional law and
moral philosophy.”³ His subsequent work has carried out that project. When
Dworkin offers views about specific constitutional issues, moral philosophy takes
center stage. For example, when Dworkin analyzes the Equal Protection Clause, he
says that there are only two possible interpretations of it. One possibility is that the
Clause merely requires government to honor the terms of its laws, whatever those
laws may say. If the law prohibits theft, then the police must enforce that law against
anybody who steals, without regard to the race of the culprit or victim. This princi-
ple is a very weak one. It does not preclude the government from writing racially dis-
criminatory terms straight into its laws; it merely prohibits the executive and judicial
branches from discriminating when the legislature has not authorized them to do so.
Dworkin says that precedent forecloses this minimialist interpretation of the Equal
Protection Clause. I doubt that anybody would disagree. But, according to
Dworkin, “[o]nce that much is conceded, . . . then the principle must be something
much more robust, because the only alternative, as a translation of what the framers
actually said in the equal protection clause, is that they declared a principle of quite
breathtaking scope and power: the principle that government must treat everyone
as of equal status and with equal concern.”⁴ And just like that we are off to the
philosophical races, free (if not compelled) to consult liberal political theory in order
to determine the meaning of “equal status and concern.”
Indeed, Dworkin says that, on his approach to the Constitution, it “seems
unlikely that anyone who believes that free and equal citizens would be guaran-
teed a particular individual right will not also think that our Constitution already
contains that right, unless constitutional history has decisively rejected it.”⁵
Moreover, “since liberty and equality overlap in large part,” the Equal Protection
Clause and the Due Process Clause will “each be comprehensive in that same
way”—comprehensive enough, that is, to embrace every right appropriate to free
and equal citizens. One clause—or indeed, either of two clauses—will suffice to
answer every civil liberties need! Dworkin’s argument seems to make not only his-
tory, but much of the constitutional text (including the Bill of Rights, which sin-
gles out specific liberties for constitutional protection), superfluous.
It is thus easy to see why critics accuse Dworkin of eliding the distinction between
constitutional law and moral philosophy. Nevertheless, as James E. Fleming has
correctly argued, Dworkin’s approach to constitutional interpretation can accom-
modate a great deal of historical argument.⁶ To begin with, Dworkin does not
claim that every constitutional provision articulates a moral principle. On the
contrary, he points out that some provisions (he mentions the Third Amendment,
which prohibits the government from quartering troops in homes during peace-
time, and the Presidential Qualifications Clause, which requires that the President
be thirty-five or older) do not.⁷ Moreover, even with regard to provisions that do
state moral principles, Dworkin permits interpreters to use history when deciding
which principle is named by the provision. For example, Dworkin says that when
construing the Equal Protection Clause, judges should remember that
“Congressmen of the victorious nation” were “trying to capture the achievements
and lessons of a terrible war” and so likely enacted an expansive moral principle
rather than a limited one.⁸
In addition, Dworkin maintains that judges owe allegiance to precedent as well
as to constitutional principle. The obligation to fit past decisions limits the ability
of judges to honor their moral convictions about, for example, the principle
embodied in the Equal Protection Clause. Thus, as we have seen, Dworkin con-
tends that precedent prevents judges from reading the Clause so narrowly that it
⁴ Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 1, at 10. ⁵ Id. at 73.
⁶ J. E. Fleming, Fidelity to Our Imperfect Constitution, 65 Ford. L. Rev. 1335 (1997).
⁷ Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 1, at 8. ⁸ Id. at 9.
8 Christopher L. Eisgruber
would stipulate “only the relatively weak principle that laws must be enforced in
accordance with their terms, so that legal benefits conferred on everyone . . . must
not be denied, in practice, to anyone.”⁹ He also maintains that precedent prevents
judges from reading the Clause so broadly that it would require equality of wealth.¹⁰
Finally, Dworkin’s theory permits history to play a role internal to moral and
political argument. History might enrich political theory in at least three ways:
with examples that stimulate reflection; with data about institutional perform-
ance and human behavior; and with rhetorical resources that enhance the
persuasive power of moral argument. Dworkin does not discuss connections of
this kind; perhaps he believes that political theorists have little to learn from
history. Yet, that belief, if indeed Dworkin holds it, is not a necessary part of his
view of the Constitution. If we believe that moral principles are best identified and
applied through historical reflection or argument, then Dworkin’s moral reading
of the Constitution will compel us to consult history.
This last possibility bears emphasis. Some influential defenses of historical
argument about the Constitution depend on claims about policy-making in gen-
eral, not about constitutional law in particular.¹¹ These claims, which sometimes
operate under the banner of “pragmatism,” suggest that we should rely on
contextual arguments about institutions and history whenever we make policy
decisions, not just when we are interpreting a written Constitution. Dworkin has
argued vigorously on behalf of abstract moral theory and against pragmatism and
its cousins.¹² Nevertheless, those arguments are distinct from his defense of the
moral reading. If one believes that historical reasoning of some sort is in general
the best way to make practical moral judgments, then one will also believe that
historical reasoning is the key to applying the moral principles identified by
Dworkin’s “moral reading.”
¹⁹ Professor Michael Moore has argued that neither the framers’ intended meaning nor their
expectations should determine what the Constitution means. M. S. Moore, Justifying the Natural
Law Theory of Constitutional Interpretation, 69 Ford. L. Rev. 2087, 2096–2099 (2001). On Moore’s
view, Dworkin is too much concerned with history and framers’ intention. I will put this interesting
view to one side for purposes of this essay, where my project is to assess the charge that Dworkin has
been too little interested in history.
²⁰ A. Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law 17 (A. Guttman,
ed., 1997).
²¹ R. M. Dworkin, The Arduous Virtue of Fidelity: Originalism, Scalia, Tribe, and Nerve, 65 Ford.
L. Rev. 1249, 1253 (1997); see also Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 1, at 8–9, 76.
Should Constitutional Judges be Philosophers? 11
The two propositions of the moral reading are thus relatively modest. They not
only might be endorsed, but in fact have been endorsed, by prominent originalists
such as Scalia and Bork. They more or less echo views articulated almost two cen-
turies ago by John Marshall, who wrote that the drafters and ratifiers of the
Constitution “must be understood to have employed words in their natural sense,
and to have intended what they have said.”²⁸ Yet, despite its relatively uncontro-
versial premises, the moral reading has an important consequence for the status of
practices that existed when the Constitution was written. The moral reading’s first
proposition says that if the framers invoked moral principles, then the
Constitution’s meaning is determined by the meaning of those principles, not by
the framers’ views about how they would apply to contemporary practices. The
moral reading’s second proposition says that the framers did in fact invoke moral
principles. It follows that, in the words of Mark Greenberg and Harry Litman,
“original meaning, properly understood, must [allow for] the possibility that a
traditional practice is unconstitutional.”²⁹
The moral reading thus rules out a popular form of originalist argument which
supposes that “[w]hen a practice not expressly prohibited by the Bill of Rights
bears the endorsement of a long tradition of open, widespread, and unchallenged
use that dates back to the beginning of the Republic, we have no proper basis for
[holding it unconstitutional].”³⁰ Originalists must argue by reference to the prin-
ciples the framers invoked in the Constitution; they are not entitled to assume
that the framers’ practices were consistent with those principles.³¹ If the moral
reading were to succeed in disciplining originalist argument in this way, it would
greatly improve constitutional argument.
The moral reading does not, however, say anything about which principles the
framers invoked. One might (correctly) suppose that history is relevant to answer-
ing that important question. We have therefore not yet identified the features of
Dworkin’s interpretive method that render it so thoroughly moral. To do so, we
must proceed beyond the moral reading and investigate how Dworkin determines
which principles the American framers invoked.
everything else we know.”³² What else we know may include facts about constitu-
tional history; thus, as we have already noticed, Dworkin says that the principles we
attribute to the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment must fit the mindset of a
Congress trying to “capture the achievements and lessons of a terrible war.”³³
Yet, as we have already seen, the principles that Dworkin ultimately identifies are
exceedingly abstract. What leads Dworkin to those principles? He claims that the
constitutional text itself is responsible for his conclusions. According to Dworkin,
the Constitution’s “key clauses are drafted in the most abstract possible terms of
political morality.”³⁴ He supports this claim by pointing out that the Fourteenth
Amendment “commands ‘equal’ protection of the laws, and also commands that
neither life nor liberty nor property be taken without ‘due’ process of law.”³⁵ That is
true, of course. We can easily add other provisions to Dworkin’s list.³⁶
Dworkin’s argument, however, glosses over the complexity of constitutional
language. None of the Constitution’s expansive phrases sound unambiguously in
moral principle. On the contrary, all of them mix justice with positive law in
mysterious proportion. The Constitution demands not “equality” but “the equal
protection of the laws;” it protects not against “deprivations of liberty” but against
“deprivations of liberty without due process of law;” and it guarantees not “the
privileges and immunities of free citizens” but the “privileges [and] immunities”
attendant upon a particular legal status, that of “citizens of the United States.” The
Constitution’s sonorous phrases are hard to interpret because they couple diverse
terms without explaining the relationship among them. What does it mean to
guarantee the “equal protection of the laws”? Does it mean that law must live up
to the standards of equality? Or does it mean that equality must be toned down to
accommodate the practical, political functions of the law?
Dworkin’s construction of the Due Process Clauses is especially vulnerable.
Other interpreters have thought that those Clauses by their terms impose only
procedural restrictions upon the government. John Hart Ely, for example, said
that “there is simply no avoiding the fact that the word that follows ‘due’ is
‘process.’ ” In Ely’s view, “substantive due process” is an oxymoron akin to “green
pastel redness.”³⁷ Ely’s “process-means-process” argument would be stronger if the
Clauses said “without fair process” or “without legal process” or simply “without
due process,” rather than without “due process of law,” a combination that beefs
up “process” in a way that common sense cannot easily decode. Does it matter that
the Constitution adds “of law” to “due process”? Perhaps not to positivist legal
theorists, who believe that the meaning of legal rules depends entirely upon the
processes through which they were enacted. For these theorists, the reference to law
merely compounds the reference to process. But Americans have never understood
the concept of law in purely positivist ways. The American legal tradition has
consistently recognized a connection between law and justice. That connection is
written into the text of the Constitution, which declares itself to be “supreme
Law” and which lists among its purposes “to establish justice.”³⁸
So Dworkin might well be right about the meaning of the Due Process Clauses.
Nevertheless, the Constitution never quite articulates explicitly the grand moral
principles that Dworkin attributes to it. Moreover, his interpretation renders
much of the text redundant. On his view, for example, the Fourteenth
Amendment contains two consecutive clauses—the Due Process Clause and the
Equal Protection Clause—each of which protects all the rights appropriate to a
free government. The Fifth Amendment’s Due Process Clause does likewise, so
that the other eight amendments in the Bill of Rights appear superfluous. Of
course, it is entirely possible that the framers repeated themselves—perhaps they
took several stabs at expressing a difficult idea. Still, the apparent repetition fits
awkwardly with Dworkin’s highly textual form of argument. Unfortunately for
him, the constitutional text says both less and more than his philosophical
approach to the Constitution requires: less, because it never states a pure, compre-
hensive moral principle clearly; more, because it uses many duplicative phrases
where, according to Dworkin, one would suffice.
I do not believe that the constitutional text can, without more, bear the weight
that Dworkin puts upon it. There is, however, a (nontextual) reason why we
might interpret the Equal Protection Clause and the Due Process Clauses in the
expansive way that Dworkin recommends. The reason invokes a kind of interpre-
tive charity: all other things being equal, it will always make sense to attribute the
most noble principles and purposes to the framers.³⁹ We might rephrase our inter-
pretive task in this way: “The framers who drafted the Due Process Clauses and
the Equal Protection Clauses were not content to itemize specific instances of gov-
ernment misbehavior; instead, they drafted general principles to govern the
nation in the future. Which principles did they choose?” Why would we want to
say the framers did less than the best they could have done? Once we agree that the
framers might have put aside their prejudices to endorse justice and equality in
general, it seems insulting to assume they did anything less.
Given an ambiguous and potentially sweeping moral principle, we will face a
strong tug to read the best into that principle. Historical circumstances are
unlikely to provide much of a barrier. Suppose, for example, that we discover that
the framers of the Fourteenth Amendment all shared some ugly prejudice that
would have kept them from respecting equality in full measure.⁴⁰ Perhaps this
prejudice led them to enact unjust statutes in the course of their political careers.
Could we say that, in light of this prejudice, it “makes sense to attribute” to the
³⁸ For further discussion, see C. L. Eisgruber, Justice and the Text: Rethinking the Constitutional
Connection Between Principle and Prudence, 43 Duke L. J. 1, 48–53 (1993).
³⁹ On the inherent optimism of interpretation, see Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 1, at 38.
⁴⁰ It does not matter that the prejudice be very ugly. The argument would go through equally well
if we substituted “second-best view” for “ugly prejudice.”
Should Constitutional Judges be Philosophers? 15
framers some dilute or truncated principle of equality consistent with their preju-
dices? No, for we will then be confronted with the fact that the framers could have
made their prejudices explicit, but chose not to. It is possible that the principle
they enacted embodied their prejudices, but it is also possible that the framers
enacted a broader principle which—while they might have hoped and believed it
to be consistent with their prejudices—transcended their prejudices. All other
things being equal, why not select the more flattering characterization?
For practical purposes, the only way to avoid associating an exceptionally broad
moral principle with the sweeping, enigmatic phrases of the Fourteenth
Amendment is to identify some reason which would lead the framers, at their very
best, to refrain from writing full, robust principles of equality and liberty into the
Constitution. Here lies the true engine that drives Dworkin’s philosophical treat-
ment of the Constitution. It is a powerful motor indeed. The logic that got us to
this stage in the argument is simple. The Constitution includes ambiguous phrases
that might refer to sweeping principles of political morality. The Constitution is
the standard against which Americans judge their government. Those two proposi-
tions, virtually uncontestable, create a strong presumption in favor of using moral
and political philosophy to interpret the Constitution’s abstract phrases: standards
for judging government ought to be good ones rather than bad ones. Dworkin has
seen these points clearly and exploited them powerfully.
The moral ambition of Dworkin’s constitutional method is thus not merely the
product of his intellectual taste. Nor, however, does it derive directly from the sur-
prisingly modest entailments of the “moral reading” of the Constitution. Instead,
Dworkin’s philosophical approach to adjudication results from a particular view of
constitutionalism: Dworkin tacitly assumes that the best framers would write
abstract, sweeping moral principles into their constitutions. This assumption has
considerable appeal. The best constitution-maker might well be the one who drafts
the most clarion and expansive statements of political morality. On the other hand,
American constitutional processes permit, and have in fact sponsored, the writing of
different kinds of provisions, some of which are detailed and others of which
(including the Equal Protection and Due Process Clauses) are murky. Is that because
Americans have been second-rate constitution-makers? Or might they reasonably
have aspired to do something besides stating principles of political morality?
and fairness as a political value. He tells us that integrity constrains what real, his-
torical polities can do. Utopian theorists may describe what political arrange-
ments best satisfy the demands of equality and fairness, but leaders of an ongoing
political enterprise must also concern themselves with the relation between their
present policies and earlier ones.⁴²
If there exists a value such as integrity, then surely it should matter to constitution-
makers, who aspire to design real governments, not utopian theories. Dworkin dis-
cusses integrity mainly in connection with the obligation of judges to respect past
precedents, and so one might suppose that constitution-makers need take it into
account only when fashioning judicial institutions. Yet, Dworkin’s theory does not
explain why integrity should be uniquely applicable to adjudication.⁴³ We might
conclude that it applies to government action more generally. If so, integrity could
give good constitution-makers a reason to choose principles that incorporated the
requirements of integrity along with those of equality and fairness. For example,
they might entrench a commitment to “traditional American principles of equality
and fairness” rather than simply to “equality and fairness.” And that, in turn, would
give us reason to interpret ambiguous constitutional language (such as “no state shall
deprive any person of life, liberty or property without due process of law”) to include
a reference to American tradition—because, on the assumptions just stated, that
would be the most charitable interpretation of what the framers said.
This line of argument discloses an irony in Dworkin’s defense of the moral
reading. Dworkin launched his extraordinary work in legal philosophy three
decades ago by observing that judges scrutinize precedent more intently in the
hardest cases, cases that cannot be resolved on the basis of precedent alone and so
force judges to draw visibly upon political and moral values. Dworkin refused to
dismiss the judicial fascination with precedent as mere delusion or smokescreen;
he devoted his jurisprudential career to identifying a conceptually rigorous middle
ground between deferring to past decisions and making fresh judgments of politi-
cal morality.⁴⁴ That is what led him to discover the value of integrity.⁴⁵ Now
Dworkin protests when constitutional scholars insist upon doing in the domain
of constitutional interpretation what he himself did when analyzing stare decisis.
That is, of course, merely ironic, not contradictory. Adjudication and constitu-
tional interpretation are different practices, and a solution appropriate to one
might fail with respect to the other. Nevertheless, Dworkin’s position ought to
make him mildly uncomfortable, for he argues not merely that some third posi-
tion between originalism and the moral reading is wrong but that none exists.
⁴² Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 41, at 164–165.
⁴³ I owe this observation to Lewis Kornhauser. Dworkin does in fact recognize a principle that he
calls “integrity in legislation,” but it is the different principle of “integrity in adjudication” that
“explains how and why the past must be allowed some special power of its own in court.” Dworkin,
Law’s Empire, supra note 41, at 167.
⁴⁴ See, e.g., Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 3, at 81, 87, 112. See also R. M.
Dworkin, A Matter of Principle 147 (1985); Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 41, at 15, 20,
130–131, 228.
⁴⁵ Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 41, at 166.
Should Constitutional Judges be Philosophers? 17
One has to wonder why there is a middle ground when reading precedent but not
when reading the Constitution.
In fact, I think the two practices too similar to justify the different conclusions
Dworkin reaches about them. If adjudicators have principled reasons to temper
moral demands (and constitutional principles) by reference to past practice, than
so too might constitution-makers and constitutional interpreters. That does not
count as a reason for rejecting the moral reading; the argument I have offered about
integrity accepts the two propositions discussed earlier (namely, that the
Constitution means what the framers intended to say, and that they intended to
state moral principles). The argument, in other words, is consistent with Dworkin’s
claim that there is no middle ground between the moral reading and strict versions
of originalism. The argument does show, however, that there exists a conceptually
coherent middle ground between strict originalism and Dworkin’s own application
of the moral reading—that is, between fidelity to highly specific historical practices
on the one hand and to the most abstract possible moral principles on the other.
makes amendment extremely difficult. The Constitution’s obduracy (that is, its
barriers against amendment) and its specificity are striking, and any good theory
about the Constitution’s role in the American political system must explain them.
People have used these features of the Constitution to argue that the point of
the Constitution is to strip present-day Americans of the ability to govern them-
selves and compel them to honor instead the specific judgments of earlier gener-
ations. Put more floridly, these theories maintain that the Constitution’s purpose
is to empower “the dead hand of the past.” For example, Supreme Court Justice
Antonin Scalia says that the Constitution’s “whole purpose is to prevent change—
to embed certain rights in such a manner that future generations cannot take
them away.”⁴⁷ In Scalia’s view, the decision to establish a written, obdurate consti-
tution reflects a lack of confidence in future generations. “A society that adopts a
bill of rights is skeptical that ‘evolving standards of decency’ always ‘mark
progress,’ and that societies always ‘mature,’ as opposed to rot.”⁴⁸
Scalia’s theory supplies a reason why later generations should refrain from using
their own, best moral judgment to interpret the Constitution’s abstract phrases;
indeed, on Scalia’s account, the whole point of constitutionalism is to avert the
exercise of judgment by later generations, whose judgment (it is feared) might be
rotten. Scalia’s theory belongs to a larger family of constitutional theories all of
which assert that the purpose of written constitutions is, for one reason or
another, to preclude Americans from engaging in open-ended moral argument.
For example, Walter Berns maintains that the purpose of the American
Constitution was to “negate and minimize” moral controversies which might dis-
rupt the peace that is an essential pre-condition of liberty and democracy.⁴⁹ He
argues that the exercise of “lawyer[s’] . . . private [moral] judgment” in constitu-
tional adjudication is inconsistent with that goal.⁵⁰
Dworkin, by contrast, does not offer any theory to justify the extraordinary
rigidity of the American Constitution. As a result, his expansive view of constitu-
tional rights appears to be the product of historical and textual accidents. The
Framers of the Constitution entrenched specific and now obsolete judgments
about (among other things) contractual liberty, guns, and juries. Nevertheless, the
Constitution came to include certain clauses which (according to Dworkin) pro-
tect every right we should demand from a government. America’s hard-to-amend
Constitution seems calculated to favor stability and conserve past practices, but it
turns out to contain sweeping moral principles which demand potentially radical
reforms. What stunning good fortune!
to perfect their institutions, or because they want to increase their own power.
Of course, the opposite problem also exists: if amendment procedures are too
demanding, people may find it impossible to make needed reforms. Nevertheless,
it is at least possible that super-majoritarian amendment procedures may help
people to establish and maintain effective political institutions. Once again, this
rationale for super-majoritarian procedures does not depend upon the idea that it
is desirable to preserve past practices or avoid the exercise of present-day judg-
ments about justice: on the contrary, it rests upon a recognition that people must
have stable political institutions in order to make and implement such judgments.
Thirdly, super-majoritarian amendment procedures create incentives that may
improve the quality of institutional reform. As Lawrence G. Sager has pointed out,
the American Constitution’s demanding amendment procedures encourage consti-
tution-makers and constitution-amenders to think about the longterm consequences
of reform.⁵² Because the Constitution is hard to change, constitution-makers are
reminded that their children and grandchildren must live with the consequences of
their decisions. If the Constitution were easier to amend, framers and ratifiers might
instead focus on short-term objectives, assuming that future majorities were free to
undo their work if it proved uncongenial to later circumstances. That would be a mis-
take: institutional reforms have lasting consequences even when they are not consti-
tutionally entrenched. For example, there is no constitutional provision that protects
the Department of Energy, but that does not mean that the Department is easily
abolished once it is created. On Sager’s account, the point of super-majoritarian
amendment procedures is not to preserve past practices, but rather to discipline
reforms so they do not favor short-term, specific practices and judgments at the
expense of evolving views about justice and the common good.
In Constitutional Self-Government, I argue that all three of these functions,
including the first one, should be understood as pro-democratic. More specific-
ally, I argue that democracy differs from pure majoritarianism, so that democracy
requires solicitude for the rights and interests of minorities as well as majorities.⁵³
For present purposes, we need not concern ourselves with these claims about
democracy. We can reject the “dead hand” theory, and accept Dworkin’s approach
to constitutional language, so long as we can regard the Constitution’s super-
majoritarian amendment procedures as serving purposes consistent with the goal
of creating a government that respects very abstract standards of justice. It is then
a separate question whether we should conceive of that government as demo-
cratic, or whether we should instead regard it as another form of government—
say, “constitutional democracy”—that limits democracy in order to promote
liberty or some other aspect of constitutional justice.
VIII. Conclusion
In my view, Ronald Dworkin has analyzed the structure of judicial reasoning in
American constitutional law more perspicuously than has any other commentator.
My aim here has been not to contest his position, but rather to clarify some of its pre-
suppositions. My interpretation of Dworkin’s “moral reading” has two important
consequences, both of which I hope that Dworkin might accept. First, although
Dworkin long ago called for a “fusion of constitutional law and moral philosophy,”
the moral reading does not require that result. The moral reading requires judges who
decide constitutional cases to focus on moral principle, but they might do so without
engaging in philosophical analysis. What matters most is not whether judges view the
Constitution through the lens of history or philosophy or something else, but
whether they aim at moral principle. There is a great difference between consulting
history at the expense of our judgments about justice (as Scalia purports to do)⁵⁷ and
consulting history to discipline and improve our judgments about justice. That dif-
ference, I believe, swamps the significance of methodological differences among
judges who agree that the Constitution demands judgments about moral principle,
but who disagree about whether those judgments should take the form of philosoph-
ical analysis or interpretations of American history. My argument thus permits a
negative answer to the question that forms the title of this essay: it is at least possible
that judges have no cause to study moral philosophy, and should continue, as lawyers
have traditionally done, to steep themselves in the lessons of political history instead.
Secondly, if judges fail to approach the Constitution in the proper spirit, they are
likely to do so because they subscribe to a mistaken view about the Constitution’s
purpose. Many people believe, as Scalia apparently does, that the point of constitu-
tionalism is to empower the “dead hand of the past” and so to deny the ability of later
generations to govern themselves on the basis of their own best judgments about
justice and the common good. It is easy to see why people reach that mistaken con-
clusion, and once they are in its grip, they believe themselves duty-bound to vindicate
historical opinion even at the expense of justice. To correct this mistake, one needs a
persuasive account of how constitutionalism facilitates government on the basis of
abstract standards of justice. One must explain, in particular, why the Constitution
quite reasonably prescribes specific, obdurate rules with respect to some issues, but
leaves other issues open to vigorous and heated debate. Dworkin’s argument for the
“moral reading of the Constitution,” with its almost exclusive emphasis upon what
the Constitution says, does not address the purpose of constitutionalism.
⁵⁷ Larry Kramer has described Scalia as embracing a kind of “judicial asceticism” under which “it
literally becomes necessary [for Scalia] to reach some results that [he] knows are unjust.” L. Kramer,
Judicial Asceticism, 12 Cardozo L. Rev. 1789, 1795 (1991).
2
The Place of History and Philosophy
in the Moral Reading of the
American Constitution
James E. Fleming*
I. Introduction
Ronald Dworkin has long recognized that the fundamental questions of “What is
the Constitution?” and “How should it be interpreted?” are the central questions
of fidelity in constitutional interpretation.¹ From his first book, Taking Rights
Seriously,² to his book, Freedom’s Law,³ Dworkin has argued that commitment to
interpretive fidelity requires that we recognize that the Constitution embodies
abstract moral principles rather than laying down particular historical concep-
tions and that interpreting and applying those principles require fresh judgments
of political theory about how they are best understood. He now calls this interpre-
tive strategy the “moral reading” of the Constitution. Yet, narrow originalists such
as Robert H. Bork and Justice Antonin Scalia have asserted a monopoly on con-
cern for fidelity in constitutional interpretation, claiming that fidelity requires fol-
lowing the rules laid down by, or giving effect to the relatively specific original
understanding of, the framers and ratifiers of the Constitution.⁴ They have
* I prepared this essay for the conference, “Exploring Law’s Empire: The Jurisprudence of Ronald
Dworkin,” held at Princeton University on September 18, 2004. The essay is largely drawn from my
article, Fidelity to Our Imperfect Constitution, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1335 (1997), which I prepared for
a symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1247–1818 (1997), for which
Ronald Dworkin gave the keynote address.
¹ These questions of “What?” and “How?,” along with the question of “Who is to interpret?,” are
the basic interrogatives of constitutional interpretation. See W. F. Murphy et al., American
Constitutional Interpretation 17–20 (3d ed. 2003).
² R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 131–149 (1977) [hereinafter Dworkin, Taking
Rights Seriously].
³ R. Dworkin, Freedom’s Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution 1–38,
72–83 (1996) [hereinafter Dworkin, Freedom’s Law]; see also R. Dworkin, The Arduous Virtue of
Fidelity: Originalism, Scalia, Tribe, and Nerve, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1249 (1997), reprinted in
R. Dworkin, Justice in Robes 117 (2006).
⁴ See R. H. Bork, The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law (1990);
A. Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation (1997); A. Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. Cin.
L. Rev. 849 (1989).
The Place of History and Philosophy in the Moral Reading of the American Constitution. James E.
Fleming.
© Oxford University Press 2006. Published 2006 by Oxford University Press.
24 James E. Fleming
charged that constitutional theorists who reject these claims are “revisionists” who
disregard fidelity, thereby subverting the Constitution. Dworkin has vigorously
and cogently punctured the narrow originalists’ pretensions to a monopoly on
fidelity, arguing that commitment to fidelity entails that we pursue integrity with
the moral reading of the Constitution and that they, the narrow originalists, are
the real “revisionists.”⁵
I shall analyze two strategies for responding to the narrow originalists’ claim to
a monopoly on fidelity. Dworkin takes the first: Turn the tables on the narrow
originalists. He argues that commitment to fidelity entails the very approach that
they are at pains to insist it forbids, and prohibits the very approach that they
imperiously maintain it mandates. The second is taken by Bruce Ackerman and
Lawrence Lessig, to say nothing of Lessig’s sometime co-author, Cass R. Sunstein:
Beat the narrow originalists at their own game.⁶ Ackerman, Lessig, and Sunstein
advance fidelity as synthesis and fidelity as translation as “broad” or “soft” forms of
originalism that are superior, as conceptions of originalism, to narrow originalism.
What is “broad” or “soft” about their forms of originalism is that these theorists
conceive original understanding at a considerably higher level of abstraction than
do the narrow originalists.⁷ At the same time, they argue that the quest for fidelity
requires that we reject Dworkin’s moral reading.⁸ Indeed, Lessig and Sunstein
make the Borkish suggestion that Dworkin’s project is not one of fidelity, but one
of improvement.⁹ Thus, the broad originalists attempt to develop an intermediate
theory between narrow originalism and the moral reading.
Dworkin argues that the search for an intermediate theory is pointless and that
the moral reading is the only coherent strategy for interpreting the Constitution.¹⁰
I shall explore the reasons for constitutional theorists’ resistance to the moral read-
ing, and for their persistence in searching for an intermediate theory in the form
of a broad originalism. Dworkin offers one reason: They are in the grip of an
unfounded assumption, the “majoritarian premise,” which leads them to reject
the moral reading on democratic grounds. In Part II, I critique his analysis and,
more generally, assess his constitutional conception of democracy and his moral
reading as a substantive theory of the Constitution. Then, in Part III, I put for-
ward a second reason, which centers on the idea of fidelity: They are in the hold of
another problematic assumption, the “originalist premise,” which causes them to
reject the moral reading on “fidelist” grounds. There I assess Dworkin’s moral
reading as a theory of constitutional interpretation. I contend that the broad ori-
ginalists, like the narrow originalists, fundamentally misconceive fidelity. The com-
mitment to fidelity to the Constitution entails, as Dworkin argues, that we should
interpret it so as to make it the best it can be.¹¹ But broad originalists such as
Lessig mistake this commitment to fidelity as proof that Dworkin is an “infidel.”¹²
Ironically, in the name of interpretive fidelity, the broad originalists, like the nar-
row originalists, would enshrine an imperfect Constitution that does not deserve
our fidelity. Only under the moral reading do we have much hope of interpreting
our imperfect Constitution in a manner that might deserve our fidelity.¹³ Finally,
in Part IV, I suggest that the moral reading is a big tent, and urge liberal and pro-
gressive theorists who have resisted the moral reading in favor of questing for a
broad originalism to reconceive their work as coming within it: in particular, as
being in service of the moral reading by providing a firmer grounding for the
moral reading in fit with historical materials than Dworkin has offered.
II. The Moral Reading and the Majoritarian Premise: or, The
Moral Reading as a Substantive Theory of the Constitution
In Freedom’s Law, Dworkin argues that the moral reading of the Constitution is
more faithful than the originalist strategy is to the text of the Constitution and the
conception of democracy it presupposes. He contends that “the only substantial
objection to the moral reading, which takes the text seriously, is that it offends
democracy.”¹⁴ Moreover, he argues that constitutional lawyers and scholars who
make this objection are in the grip of an unfounded assumption, the “majoritarian
premise.”¹⁵ This is the assumption that the fundamental value or point of democ-
racy is commitment to the goal of majority will. This premise undergirds a majori-
tarian conception of democracy that is not true to our scheme of government and
that indeed obscures the true character and importance of our system.¹⁶ As an
alternative, Dworkin offers a constitutional conception of democracy which con-
ceives the fundamental point or value of democracy to be concern for the equal sta-
tus of citizens.¹⁷ He then considers and rejects three arguments for the majoritarian
premise, which are rooted in liberty, equality, and community.¹⁸ I believe that
Dworkin’s arguments for the moral reading and against democratic objections
rooted in the majoritarian premise are sound. But I shall criticize his formulation of
a constitutional conception of democracy—or constitutional democracy—and his
own moral reading as a substantive theory of the Constitution.
First, Dworkin is right to lay bare and criticize the majoritarian premise and
the majoritarian conception of democracy that stems from it. For too long, that
premise and conception have hobbled constitutional theory by providing a mis-
guided and misleading account of our constitutional scheme. They have driven
constitutional theorists to regard as deviant or anomalous certain integral fea-
tures of that scheme. Most famously, that premise and conception underlie
Alexander M. Bickel’s anxious claim that judicial review is a “deviant institution”
that poses a “counter-majoritarian difficulty” in our democracy.¹⁹ Dworkin in
effect turns Bickel on his head,²⁰ for Dworkin’s formulation of the “majoritarian
premise” as an unfounded assumption is the inverted mirror image of Bickel’s
formulation of the “counter-majoritarian difficulty” as the root problem. On
Dworkin’s view, the fact that many constitutional theorists are obsessed with the
“counter-majoritarian difficulty” presents a serious problem, because it obscures
from them the true character of our system and prevents them from embracing
the moral reading.
¹⁴ Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 3, at 15. ¹⁵ Id. at 16. ¹⁶ Id. at 15–17.
¹⁷ Id. at 17–18. ¹⁸ Id. at 21–31.
¹⁹ A. M. Bickel, The Least Dangerous Branch: The Supreme Court at the Bar of Politics
16, 18 (2d ed. 1986).
²⁰ Similarly, Sunstein has suggested that Dworkin has stood Judge Learned Hand on his head. See
Sunstein, supra note 8, at 36.
History and Philosophy in Moral Reading of the Constitution 27
presuppose the unfounded majoritarian premise may be true, but unhelpful if the
aim is to persuade them to abandon it.
I believe that there is a more straightforward and plausible theoretical structure
through which to present conceptions of constitutional democracy like
Dworkin’s. Elsewhere, I criticize the architecture of constitutional theories such as
those of Ely and Sunstein, which attempt to frame or recast all of our basic liber-
ties, both substantive and procedural, as preconditions for representative or delib-
erative democracy.²⁷ I argue instead for a constitutional constructivism,²⁸ a
conception of constitutional democracy with two fundamental themes: first,
securing the basic liberties that are preconditions for deliberative democracy, to
enable citizens to apply their capacity for a conception of justice to deliberating
about the justice of basic institutions and social policies, and secondly, securing the
basic liberties that are preconditions for deliberative autonomy, to enable citizens
to apply their capacity for a conception of the good to deliberating about and
deciding how to live their own lives. Together, these themes for securing constitu-
tional democracy afford everyone the common and guaranteed status of free and
equal citizenship in our morally pluralistic constitutional democracy.²⁹ (This con-
ception has affinities to Dworkin’s view that the fundamental point or value of our
scheme of government is concern for the equal status of citizens.)³⁰ I offer my
account, constitutional constructivism, as the guiding framework that best fits
and justifies our constitutional text and underlying constitutional order.³¹
Moreover, I contend elsewhere that there are good reasons for conceiving our
basic liberties in terms of securing the preconditions for deliberative democracy
and deliberative autonomy instead of framing them as, or reducing them into,
preconditions for democracy.³² The first reason is prophylactic: Articulating a
constitutional constructivism with these two themes protects us against taking
“constitutive account”). In his recent book, Sager analyzes and criticizes Dworkin’s theory as being,
like Ely’s and Michelman’s theories, a “democratarian account.” L. G. Sager, Justice in
Plainclothes: A Theory of American Constitutional Practice 132–137 (2004) [hereinafter
Sager, Justice in Plainclothes].
²⁷ Fleming, supra note 13, at 4–5, 29–34, 43–51.
²⁸ I mean constitutional constructivism in two senses. First, I intend a general methodological
sense of constructivism, illustrated by Dworkin’s conception of constitutional interpretation as con-
structing schemes of principles that best fit and justify our constitutional document and underlying
constitutional order as a whole. Dworkin originally put forth this conception by analogy to Rawls’s
conception of justification in political philosophy as a quest for reflective equilibrium. Dworkin,
Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 2, at 159–168. Secondly, I intend a specific substantive sense
of constructivism, exemplified by John Rawls’s conception of the equal basic liberties in a
constitutional democracy such as our own as being grounded on a conception of citizens as free and
equal persons, together with a conception of society as a fair system of social cooperation. J. Rawls,
Political Liberalism (1993).
²⁹ Fleming, supra note 13, at 3–6, 61–74. I develop this theory by analogy to Rawls’s political
constructivism. See Rawls, supra note 28.
³⁰ See Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 3, at 17.
³¹ For examples of Dworkin’s formulations of the two dimensions of best interpretation, fit and
justification, see Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 5, at 239; Dworkin, A Matter of Principle,
supra note 11, at 143–145; Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 2, at 107.
³² Fleming, supra note 13, at 78–79.
History and Philosophy in Moral Reading of the Constitution 29
III. The Moral Reading and the Originalist Premise: or, The
Moral Reading as a Theory of Constitutional Interpretation
Next, I shall consider another reason why the broad originalists have resisted the
moral reading, which centers on the idea of fidelity: They are in the grip of what I
shall call the “originalist premise.” This is the assumption that originalism, rightly
conceived, is the best, or indeed the only, conception of fidelity in constitutional
interpretation. On this view, fidelity by definition, or at least as practiced in our
constitutional culture, must be concerned with following the original meaning of
the text, the original understanding of the framers and ratifiers, or the like. The
originalist premise leads to objections to the moral reading on the ground that it is
“nonoriginalist,” “revisionist,” or not “fidelist.”
The originalist premise is expressed in its most extreme form by Bork, who
asserts that originalism is the only possible approach to constitutional interpreta-
tion that is faithful to the historic Constitution and consonant with the constitu-
tional design. He rejects all other approaches, most especially those like
Dworkin’s, as “revisionist.”⁴¹ In recent years, the originalist premise has also been
manifested in the emerging strain of broad originalism in liberal and progressive
constitutional theory. For example, Lessig evidently takes the view that original-
ism, by definition, is the only method of fidelity. Most strikingly, he has made the
Borkish assertion that Dworkin is an “infidel,” and he and Sunstein have sug-
gested that Dworkin does not even have a method of fidelity.⁴² I believe that the
originalist premise, as much as the majoritarian premise, drives the broad original-
ists’ resistance to Dworkin’s moral reading.
In unpacking what I have loosely called the originalist premise, I shall examine
several reasons why some liberal and progressive constitutional theorists have
resisted Dworkin’s moral reading in favor of searching for an intermediate theory in
⁴⁰ For a justice-seeking account or moral reading of the Constitution that is thicker, or counte-
nances less moral shortfall through judicial underenforcement than does Sager’s view, see S. A.
Barber, Welfare and the Constitution (2003); S. A. Barber, The Constitution of Judicial
Power (1993) [hereinafter Barber, Power]; S. A. Barber, On What the Constitution Means
(1984) [hereinafter Barber, Constitution]; S. A. Barber, Justice-Seeking Constitutionalism and Its
Critics, paper presented at the New York University School of Law Colloquium on Constitutional
Theory (Apr. 20, 1995) (unpublished manuscript on file with the author).
⁴¹ Bork, supra note 4, at 187–240. This is the obligatory footnote where I must acknowledge that
Raoul Berger is more extreme than Bork (or, for that matter, Scalia). See R. Berger, Government by
Judiciary: The Transformation of the Fourteenth Amendment (1977).
⁴² Lessig, Fidelity, supra note 6, at 1260; Lessig & Sunstein, supra note 6, at 11 n.35, 85 n.336.
32 James E. Fleming
the form of a broad originalism. More generally, I discuss the reasons for the
emergence of this strain of broad originalism. I contend that none of these reasons
is a good reason for the broad originalists not to endorse the moral reading, prop-
erly conceived. My general stance is to support broad originalism to the extent that
its proponents undertake it in service of the moral reading, but to criticize it to the
extent that they believe it is sustainable as an alternative to the moral reading.
arguments in text, history, and structure, not to mention practice, tradition, and
culture. But this turn is not necessarily a turn to originalism and against the moral
reading. Indeed, recourse to structure in constitutional interpretation typically
involves drawing inferences from political theory, not merely recovering, translat-
ing, or extrapolating from the original meaning of the text.⁴⁷ The turn to text,
history, and structure becomes a turn against the moral reading only if its pro-
ponents claim to be elaborating text, history, and structure without making
recourse to political theory. Such a claim would be problematic and implausible.
Why, then, do the liberal and progressive enthusiasts of text, history, and structure
cast their arguments as broad originalist arguments rather than as arguments in
support of better grounding the moral reading?
Thirdly, I suggest that the answer to the question—Why have the turns to history
and to text, history, and structure become turns to broad originalism and against
the moral reading?—is to be found in considerations of litigation strategy or judg-
ments about the types of arguments that are appropriate in our constitutional cul-
ture. The thought seems to be that our constitutional culture is largely originalist
(or positivist), and therefore that arguments in constitutional law, to be successful,
simply must be framed in an originalist mold. A view of this sort seems to animate
the work of broad originalists such as Ackerman, Lessig, and Akhil Amar. I have
heard a strong version of this view articulated roughly as follows: The only way that
liberals and progressives have any hope of persuading Justice Scalia to accept their
interpretations of the Constitution is to make originalist arguments.
To this view I have four responses. (1) The attempt to persuade Scalia that
fidelity to the Constitution leads to any liberal or progressive conclusions is a fool’s
errand. There can be no serious doubt that Scalia’s mind is ideologically impervi-
ous to liberal or progressive constitutional arguments.⁴⁸ Worse yet, this attempt
disfigures and debases constitutional theory by causing theorists to recast their
arguments in a narrow originalist mold dictated by Scalia.
(2) It is telling that the greatest liberal constitutional theorist-litigator of our
time, Laurence H. Tribe, has not adapted his constitutional theory to such an
originalist litigation strategy. To be sure, he has eschewed grand theory, as if to say,
“no theorists here, just us common lawyers.” But his conception of constitutional
interpretation in his academic writing is much closer to Dworkin’s theory than to
the broad originalist views of Ackerman, Lessig, and Amar.⁴⁹
⁴⁷ For examples of accounts of inferences from structure that recognize this, see C. L. Black, Jr.,
Structure and Relationship in Constitutional Law (1969); W. F. Harris, II, The
Interpretable Constitution 144–158 (1993); Fleming, supra note 13, at 90–91 (furthering the
“unfinished business of Charles Black”).
⁴⁸ Notwithstanding possible appearances to the contrary, Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397 (1989),
and R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, 505 U.S. 377 (1992), cases in which Scalia supported stringent judicial
protection of freedom of speech, are not counterexamples. For instructive analyses of Scalia’s First
Amendment jurisprudence, as manifested in such decisions, see M. Tushnet, A Court Divided:
The Rehnquist Court and the Future of Constitutional Law 130–155 (2005).
⁴⁹ See L. H. Tribe & M. C. Dorf, On Reading the Constitution 17, 81–87 (1991); L. H. Tribe,
Taking Text and Structure Seriously: Reflections on Free-Form Method in Constitutional Interpretation,
34 James E. Fleming
(3) Our constitutional culture is not as originalist as the broad originalists seem
to assume. It certainly requires constitutional lawyers and scholars to pay homage
to history and to fit with historical materials, but that is not to say that it is origi-
nalist.⁵⁰ Originalism is an ism, a conservative ideology that emerged in reaction
against the Warren Court. Before Richard Nixon and Robert Bork launched
their attacks on the Warren Court, originalism as we know it did not exist.⁵¹
Constitutional interpretation in light of original understanding did exist, but
original understanding was regarded as merely one source of constitutional mean-
ing among several, not a general theory of constitutional interpretation, much less
the exclusive legitimate theory. Indeed, history was regarded as secondary to, and
merely as extrinsic evidence of, the meaning of text and structure.⁵² Scholars
wrote about the “uses of history” in constitutional interpretation rather than con-
tending that enforcing original understanding was the only defensible conception
of fidelity.⁵³ Moreover, original understanding, especially at a relatively specific
level, was understood to be largely indeterminate and inconclusive. As Justice
Jackson famously put it in concurrence in Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v.
Sawyer:⁵⁴
Just what our forefathers did envision, or would have envisioned had they foreseen modern
conditions, must be divined from materials almost as enigmatic as the dreams Joseph was
called upon to interpret for Pharaoh. A century and a half of partisan debate and scholarly
speculation yields no net result but only supplies more or less apt quotations from
respected sources on each side of any question. They largely cancel each other. And court
decisions are indecisive because of the judicial practice of dealing with the largest questions
in the most narrow way.⁵⁵
Regrettably, many constitutional lawyers and scholars in recent years seem to
have lost sight of this great wisdom. It is important to note that Laura Kalman, in her
fine intellectual history of recent constitutional theory, has practically suggested that
108 Harv. L. Rev. 1223 (1995) (criticizing the (broad originalist) theories of Ackerman and Amar);
L. H. Tribe, The Puzzling Persistence of Process-Based Constitutional Theories, 89 Yale L.J. 1063,
1072–1077 (1980), reprinted in L. H. Tribe, Constitutional Choices 9 (1985) (retitled The
Pointless Flight from Substance) (criticizing Ely’s theory for taking a “pointless flight from substance,”
just as Dworkin critiqued Ely’s theory for doing so, see Dworkin, The Forum of Principle, supra note
25). For a critique of the broad originalist theories of Ackerman and Lessig from a theoretical per-
spective similar to Tribe’s, see M. C. Dorf, Integrating Normative and Descriptive Constitutional
Theory: The Case of Original Meaning, 85 Geo. L.J. 1765 (1997).
⁵⁰ The Senate’s rejection of the Bork nomination was at least in part a rejection of Bork’s narrow
originalism. See Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 3, at 276–286, 287–305.
⁵¹ W. W. Crosskey may be an exception, but he was roundly criticized as exceptional. See, e.g.,
H. M. Hart, Jr., Professor Crosskey and Judicial Review, 67 Harv. L. Rev. 1456 (1954) (reviewing
W. W. Crosskey, Politics and the Constitution in the History of the United States (1953)).
⁵² See J. tenBroek, Admissibility and Use by the United States Supreme Court of Extrinsic Aids in
Constitutional Construction, 26 Cal. L. Rev. 287 (1938).
⁵³ See C. A. Miller, The Supreme Court and the Uses of History (1969); J. G. Wofford, The
Blinding Light: The Uses of History in Constitutional Interpretation, 31 U. Chi. L. Rev. 502 (1964).
⁵⁴ 343 U.S. 579 (1952). ⁵⁵ Id. at 634–635 (Jackson, J., concurring).
History and Philosophy in Moral Reading of the Constitution 35
the best professional historians know better than to be originalists, but that some
constitutional lawyers and scholars who have taken the turn to history do not.⁵⁶
(4) Finally, we should put the following question to the broad originalists: If
our constitutional culture is so originalist, why do so many originalists complain
that so many constitutional law cases and so many features of our constitutional
practice cannot be justified on the basis of originalism?⁵⁷ The answer is that our
constitutional culture is not as originalist as the broad originalists have supposed.
Or that its commitment to originalism is more honored in the breach than in the
observance. Or that Dworkin is right in arguing that “[s]o far as American lawyers
and judges follow any coherent strategy of interpreting the Constitution at all,
they already use the moral reading,” but that there is a confused “mismatch”
between the role of the moral reading, which is embedded in our constitutional
practice, and its reputation, which is that it is illegitimate.⁵⁸
⁵⁶ Kalman, supra note 43, at 167–190; see J. N. Rakove, Original Meanings 3–22 (1996);
J. Appleby, Constitutional Conventions, N.Y. Times (July 21, 1996), §7 (Book Review), at 20 (reviewing
Rakove, supra). But see Rakove, supra at 7 (criticizing Jackson for overstating the point in the passage
from Youngstown quoted in text).
⁵⁷ See Bork, supra note 4; H. P. Monaghan, Stare Decisis and Constitutional Adjudication, 88
Colum. L. Rev. 723 (1988). For a highly instructive analysis of the gap between originalist theory
and our constitutional practice, see Dorf, supra note 49.
⁵⁸ Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 3, at 2, 4.
⁵⁹ For a broad originalist claim that Dworkin does not take fit seriously enough, see Flaherty,
supra note 6. For a positivist claim that Dworkin’s theory suffers from a “problem of fit,” see A. J. Sebok,
The Insatiable Constitution, 70 S. Cal. L. Rev. 417 (1997). For a narrow originalist critique along
these lines, see M. W. McConnell, The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on
Ronald Dworkin’s “Moral Reading” of the Constitution, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1269 (1997).
36 James E. Fleming
calls for, or that he may do it too abstractly to satisfy these critics that he takes fit as
seriously as he should. Dworkin’s splendid essays in constitutional theory in the
New York Review of Books may aggravate such concerns. He writes these essays in a
style designed to reach and persuade a larger audience of citizens, not in a techni-
cal style to demonstrate to constitutional lawyers and scholars that he has done his
historical homework. Ironically, to the extent that Dworkin has indeed become,
in T.M. Scanlon’s estimation, “our leading public philosopher,”⁶⁰ he may have
diminished the appeal of his theory and his work to some constitutional lawyers
and scholars. For in their view, his “public philosophy” may not provide a good
model for the kind of scholarship that shows the proper regard for the aspiration
to fidelity, and that gives fit as well as justification its due.
Furthermore, some broad originalists evidently resist Dworkin’s moral reading
because they believe, as Bruce Ackerman once put it, that “fit is everything.”⁶¹ To
state the matter in terms of Dworkin’s well-known argument that the best inter-
pretation has two dimensions—fit and justification—they seem to believe that
fidelity is purely a matter of fit with historical materials, rather than also a matter
of justification in political theory.⁶² Fit and history do have a role in the quest for
fidelity to the Constitution, but a limited one. We should acknowledge the place
of history in constitutional interpretation—as a constraint that comes into play in
the dimension of fit—but should keep it in its place. Broad originalists tend to
exaggerate the place of history and to give it a greater role than it deserves and than
it is capable of playing.
History is, can only be, and should only be a starting point in constitutional
interpretation. It has a threshold role, which is often not dispositive. In the dimen-
sion of fit, history helps (or should help) screen out “off-the-wall” interpretations
or purely utopian interpretations, but often does not lead conclusively to any
interpretation, let alone the best interpretation. History usually provides a
foothold for competing interpretations or competing theories. It alone cannot
resolve the clash among these competing interpretations or competing theories.
Deciding which theory provides the best interpretation is not an historical matter
of reading more cases, tracts, or speeches or more scrupulously doing good profes-
sional history. To resolve the clash among competing interpretations or competing
theories, we must move beyond the threshold dimension of fit to the dimension of
justification. History rarely has anything useful, much less dispositive, to say at
that point.⁶³ In deciding which interpretation among competing acceptably
fitting interpretations is most faithful to the Constitution, we must ask further
questions: Which interpretation provides the best justification, which makes our
⁶⁰ T. M. Scanlon, Partisan for Life, N.Y. Rev. Books (July 15, 1993), at 45, 45 (reviewing
Dworkin, Life’s Dominion, supra note 5).
⁶¹ See Bruce Ackerman, Remarks at the New York University School of Law Colloquium on
Constitutional Theory, Nov. 16, 1993 (colloquy between Ackerman and Dworkin).
⁶² For Dworkin’s formulations of the two dimensions of best interpretation, fit and justification,
see sources cited supra in note 31.
⁶³ Indeed, as stated above, the best professional historians know better than to be originalists;
unfortunately, some constitutional lawyers and scholars do not. See supra text accompanying note 56.
History and Philosophy in Moral Reading of the Constitution 37
constitutional scheme the best it can be, which does it more credit, or which
answers better to our best aspirations as a people?⁶⁴ These questions are not those
of an “infidel,” Lessig notwithstanding.⁶⁵ They are required by the quest for
fidelity in the sense of honoring our aspirational principles, not merely following
our historical practices or the original meaning of the text.⁶⁶ And the commit-
ment to fidelity is an aspiration to the best interpretation of the Constitution, not
merely to best fit with the historical materials or original meaning (or best transla-
tion of them). The view that fidelity is merely a matter of fit—or that “fit is every-
thing”—mistakenly assumes that the Constitution is defined, and exhausted, by
the historical materials.
More generally, some broad originalists may resist the moral reading because
they believe that fidelity requires following historical materials and eschewing
political theory. But broad originalists understand constitutional interpretation in
terms of “liberating abstraction,” or conceive original understanding at a relatively
high level of abstraction.⁶⁷ When they elaborate abstract original understanding,
they will find that they are not able to do so purely as a matter of historical
research, translation, or extrapolation. Instead, they will have to do so as a matter
of—and through recourse to—bounded political theory.
The upshot of my analysis of the reasons why the broad originalists have resisted
the moral reading in favor of trying to develop an intermediate theory is that we
should conceive the moral reading as a big tent that can encompass broad original-
ist conceptions such as those of Ackerman, Sunstein, and perhaps even that of
Lessig. Broad originalists have employed the argumentative strategy of using Bork
and Scalia, on the one hand, and Dworkin, on the other, as rhetorical foils or
extremes against which to set up their arguments.⁶⁸ This strategy leads to the unfor-
tunate results of caricaturing Dworkin’s arguments and, worse yet, obscuring simi-
larities and common ground between the moral reading and broad originalism.
⁶⁴ See Dworkin, Freedom’s Law, supra note 3, at 8–11; Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 5,
at 176–275. ⁶⁵ Lessig, Fidelity, supra note 6, at 1260.
⁶⁶ For development of the idea that the Constitution embodies aspirational principles rather than
merely codifying historical practices, see Fleming, supra note 13, at 112–116, 226–227. For similar ideas,
see Barber, Power, supra note 40, at 60–61; Barber, Constitution, supra note 40, at 84–85; F. I.
Michelman, Super Liberal: Romance, Community, and Tradition in William J. Brennan, Jr.’s Constitutional
Thought, 77 Va. L. Rev. 1261, 1312–1320 (1991); Michelman, supra note 8, at 1496, 1514.
⁶⁷ See Sunstein, Legal Reasoning, supra note 6, at 171–182; Ackerman, Liberating Abstraction,
supra note 7.
⁶⁸ Compare Ackerman, We the People, supra note 6, at 10–16 (criticizing Dworkin) with
B. Ackerman, Robert Bork’s Grand Inquisition, 99 Yale L.J. 1419 (1990) (reviewing and criticizing
Bork, supra note 4); compare Sunstein, Legal Reasoning, supra note 6, at 48–53 (criticizing
Dworkin) with Sunstein, Partial Constitution, supra note 21, at 96–110 (criticizing Bork); see
also Lessig, Fidelity, supra note 6, at 1260 (“From the perspective of the two-step fidelitist, both the
originalist [such as Scalia] and the Dworkinian are infidels”).
38 James E. Fleming
Again, I would urge the broad originalists to reconceive their projects as being in
support of the moral reading, not as offering alternatives to it. They can help by
providing firmer grounding than Dworkin has offered for the moral reading in fit
with historical materials. (I do not mean to suggest that their own moral readings
are the same as Dworkin’s particular moral reading.) I shall close by giving three
reasons for embracing the moral reading, conceived as a big tent.
The first reason is hortatory: The moral reading exhorts judges, elected officials,
and citizens to reflect upon and deliberate about our deepest principles and high-
est aspirations as a people.⁶⁹ It does not command them to follow the authority of
the past. In a word, it rejects the authoritarianism of originalism, narrow or broad,
as inappropriate and unjustifiable in a constitutional democracy. As Christopher
L. Eisgruber points out, it is ironic if not absurd that originalists would impose the
“dead hand” of the past upon us in the name of popular sovereignty.⁷⁰ The moral
reading exhorts us to conceive fidelity in terms of honoring our aspirational prin-
ciples rather than merely following our historical practices and concrete original
understanding, which no doubt have fallen short of those principles. On this view,
fidelity is not subservient fealty.
The second, related reason is critical: The moral reading encourages, indeed
requires, a reflective, critical attitude toward our history and practices rather than
enshrining them. It recognizes that our principles may fit and justify most of our
practices or precedents but that they will criticize some of them for failing to live
up to our constitutional commitments to principles such as liberty and equality.⁷¹
Put another way, the moral reading does not confuse or conflate our principles
and traditions with our history, our aspirational principles with our historical
practices.⁷² Again, it recognizes that fidelity to the Constitution requires honoring
our aspirational principles, not following our historical practices and concrete
original understanding. That is, fidelity to the Constitution requires that we disre-
gard or criticize certain aspects of our history and practices in order to be faithful
to the principles embodied in the Constitution.
The final reason is justificatory: The moral reading, because it understands that
the quest for fidelity in interpreting our imperfect Constitution exhorts us to
interpret it so as to make it the best it can be, offers hope that the Constitution
may deserve our fidelity, or at least may be able to earn it. Ironically, despite their
pretensions to a monopoly on concern for fidelity, the originalists would enshrine
an imperfect Constitution that does not deserve our fidelity.⁷³
⁶⁹ I do not mean to imply that the moral reading necessarily requires completely theorized agree-
ments. But see Sunstein, Legal Reasoning, supra note 6, at 48–53 (criticizing Dworkin’s grand,
abstract theorizing and calling instead for “incompletely theorized agreements”).
⁷⁰ C. L. Eisgruber, The Living Hand of the Past: History and Constitutional Justice, 65 Fordham L.
Rev. 1611, 1613–1617 (1997). See also C. L. Eisgruber, Constitutional Self-Government (2001).
⁷¹ See Fleming, supra note 13, at 6, 98. ⁷² See id. at 227.
⁷³ Originalism, as an ism, has no firm footing in our constitutional culture, and it has no place there.
It is a species of authoritarianism that is antithetical to a free and equal citizenry. A regime of purportedly
dispositive original meanings is, at best, beside the point of constitutional interpretation and, at worst,
an authoritarian regime that is unfit to rule a free and equal people. For a similar view, see S. Freeman,
Original Meaning, Democratic Interpretation, and the Constitution, 21 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 3 (1992).
History and Philosophy in Moral Reading of the Constitution 39
Like rain falling to a parched earth, Ronald Dworkin’s early work lighted upon a
field of constitutional thought desiccated by embarrassment over Brown v.
Board of Education.¹ From a distance of a half century, it is difficult to appreciate
the profound chagrin that had arisen from what now seems a simple judicial
declaration of equality. Yet the decision had hurled the world of constitutional
theory into decades of existential angst, leading it, temporarily, to lose a grasp
on its soul.
Taking Rights Seriously came on the scene in the 1970s and quickly began to
enrich the impoverished debate. Subsequent writings, culminating with Freedom’s
Law and its moral reading of the Constitution, increasingly refined Dworkin’s
ideas about law to apply more specifically to the interpretation of constitutional
text.² Ironically, while the academy had nearly imploded over the issue of how to
understand the Constitution’s promise of equality, it was Dworkin’s exposition of
a deep and foundational notion of equality that helped direct constitutional the-
ory toward recapturing its animating spirit. That rehabilitative effect, I suggest, is
at the heart of Dworkin’s contribution to constitutional theory.
* The author gratefully acknowledges the helpful contributions of Lisa Bressman, John
Goldberg, Bob Rasmussen, Christopher Yoo, and the participants in the Georgetown University
Law Center Constitutional Law Colloquium and University of Colorado School of Law faculty
workshop.
¹ 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
² In this essay I have taken the liberty of seeking to present intellectual, rather than chronological,
sequences in Dworkin’s work. This undoubtedly does some violence to the chronology of his corpus as
it actually unfolded. The Dworkin works on which I am primarily relying in this essay are Taking
Rights Seriously (1977); A Matter of Principle (1985); Law’s Empire (1986); Life’s Dominion:
An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom (1994); Freedom’s Law:
The Moral Reading of the American Constitution (1996) [hereinafter Freedom’s Law];
Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (2000) [hereinafter Sovereign
Virtue].
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul: The Contributions of Ronald Dworkin. Rebecca L.
Brown.
© Oxford University Press 2006. Published 2006 by Oxford University Press.
42 Rebecca L. Brown
³ See B. Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context 94–97 (1996) (discussing the nature of
Dworkin’s “right answer thesis”). ⁴ 198 U.S. 45 (1905).
⁵ L. Kalman, The Strange Career of Legal Liberalism 18 (1996). The famous quote from
Justice Roberts in United States v. Butler captures the objectionably parsimonious description of the
Court’s task: “to lay the article of the Constitution which is invoked beside the statute which is chal-
lenged and to decide whether the latter squares with the former.” 297 U.S. 1, 62 (1936).
⁶ See, e.g., H. S. Commager, Majority Rule and Minority Rights 62 (1943) (arguing that
“majority will does not imperil minority rights” because “the people can be trusted” to protect minor-
ity interests).
⁷ Kalman, supra note 5, at 17–18 (describing the devotion of the realists to the regulatory state,
seeking to advance the public interest through administrative programs).
⁸ E. S. Corwin, Constitutional Revolution 89–90 (1941) (arguing that rights must generally
depend for their protection on legislatures).
⁹ R. Pound, Contemporary Juristic Theory 83 (1940).
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 43
than constraining them from seeking societal change. Thus, constitutional theorists
were willing to accept the administrative state without serious constitutional objec-
tion because of its potential to expand the opportunity for good government.¹⁰
The Supreme Court’s approach to liberty claims during this period is quite
consistent with the view that the Constitution is best interpreted as imposing the
fewest obstacles on the political branches in the achievement of needed reforms.
The constitutional standard for assessing liberty claims held that individual liber-
ties would prevail unless restrictions were necessary in the common good. The
Lochner case, conceiving of the police power and the common good narrowly,
struck down regulatory measures in 1905. By 1937, however, the Court was ready
to understand the police power more broadly, with the common good recon-
ceived to include regulatory interference with private economic relations where
necessary to respond to the changing social and economic order.¹¹ Still purporting
to adhere to the balance of ordered liberty, the Court’s assessments of the relative
weights in the pans of the scale had altered considerably for the avowed purpose of
facilitating progressive legislative programs.
The ideals of democracy and rights shared a delicate coexistence as long as legis-
latures could plausibly be considered the most trustworthy repositories of the rights
of the people. Justice Frankfurter’s ode to populism spoke a powerful message. He
wrote that “[t]o fight out the wise use of legislative authority in the forum of public
opinion and before legislative assemblies rather than to transfer such a contest to
the judicial arena, serves to vindicate the self-confidence of a free people.”¹² At a
time when democracy was struggling for world opinion against, first dictatorship
and then communism, it is no wonder the prevailing commitment was a belief that
giving the people their voice would be a better source of freedom. This vesting of
public policy decisions in a holistic entity thought of as “the people,” through their
elected representatives, was hailed as the hallmark of democracy. The people would
enact and live under law, understood to be a system of rules, authoritative by virtue
of their source in the political branches of government.
This belief system proved fragile, unable to withstand the frontal assault created
by the forced acknowledgement of racial segregation.¹³ Such segregation, of
course, was nothing new, but (much as did slavery for the founders) it seemed to
have existed, for most of the century, by the side of the Constitution and its
accompanying promises of liberty and equality, without forcing anyone to notice
that perhaps rhetoric and reality did not square. The New Deal, with its emphasis
on addressing severe social and economic problems that united the country, took
¹⁰ See J. M. Landis, The Administrative Process 2 (1938) (“Without too much political theory
but with a keen sense of the practicalities of the situation, agencies were created whose functions
embraced the three aspects of government”).
¹¹ R. L. Brown, Activism is not a Four-Letter Word, 73 U. Colo. L. Rev. 1257 (2002) (arguing that
the mistake of Lochner was not in activist protection of liberty, but in artificially constrained notion of
“common good”). ¹² Minersville Sch. Dist. v. Gobitis, 310 U.S. 586, 600 (1940).
¹³ See R. G. McCloskey, The American Supreme Court 193 (1960) (racism of Adolf Hitler con-
tributed to a “feeling of dissatisfaction and guilt over America’s own patterns of race discrimination”).
44 Rebecca L. Brown
the spotlight away from those even uglier problems that divided it. Brown v.
Board of Education, to put it mildly, raised such a problem.
The blow to constitutional theory as a discipline was not a single coup de grace,
but rather a series of inner conflicts experienced and expressed in different, but
related, ways by several leading scholars of the time. Many have described this
period of intellectual history with depth and perspicacity;¹⁴ I wish only to high-
light some of the significant themes in order to lay the broad-based groundwork
for the symbolic role that I suggest Ronald Dworkin later came to play.
Learned Hand’s 1958 Holmes Lecture is widely viewed as the focal point of
debate. In that speech, he called into question the legitimacy of judicial review
itself,¹⁵ and challenged Brown as legislation from the bench.¹⁶ In a somewhat
more limited way, Herbert Wechsler also criticized Brown as unprincipled in its
unjustified preference of one group’s freedom of association over another’s.¹⁷ After
those two very public attacks on the legitimacy of the Supreme Court’s decision,
as one commentator describes it, “the dam of academic criticism of the Court
burst wide-open.”¹⁸ While many academics spoke in support of the outcome of
the Brown decision, they seemed apologetic for a possible appearance of lack of
principle, uncomfortable with any assertion of a necessary correlation between
segregation and inequality. Academics increasingly leveled criticism at other
activist decisions of the Court, consistently questioning the Court’s commitment
to principle and institutional integrity.¹⁹ Charles Black, departing from this trend,
courageously stepped forward and challenged the charade that allowed people to
doubt that segregation caused inequality: “How long must we keep a straight
face?”²⁰ he demanded, in reference to the claims that segregation had no connota-
tion of oppression or inferiority. He took on the unusual role of reassuring his col-
leagues about the legitimacy of both the outcome as a social policy and the role of
the Court in mandating it. “We as lawyers can without fake or apology present to
the lay community, and to ourselves, a rationale of the segregation decisions that
rises to the height of a great argument.”²¹
The words “fake or apology” seem particularly apt. They describe an academy
deeply unsure of itself, prone to taking different positions publicly and privately.
Most constitutional scholars recognized the moral wrong of segregation at some
level, but were highly uncertain of the legitimacy of enlisting the Constitution to
¹⁴ E.g., L. M. Seidman, Brown and Miranda, 80 Cal. L. Rev. 673 (1992); M. Tushnet, ed., The
Warren Court in Historical and Political Perspective (1993); B. Friedman, The Birth of an
Academic Obsession: The History of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty, Part Five, 112 Yale L.J. 153
(2002); Kalman, supra note 5.
¹⁵ Learned Hand, The Bill of Rights 10, 28–29 (1958) (suggesting that the inference of judi-
cial review from the Constitution was “not a lawless act” as long as it was limited to instances neces-
sary to prevent the collapse of constitutional government). ¹⁶ Id. at 54–55.
¹⁷ H. Wechsler, Toward Neutral Principles of Constitutional Law, 73 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 31–35 (1959).
¹⁸ Friedman, supra note 14, at 198.
¹⁹ See id. at 199–200 (discussing news reports regarding the increase in criticism of the Court
from recognized authorities on jurisprudence).
²⁰ C. Black, Jr., The Lawfulness of the Segregation Decisions, 60 Yale L.J. 421, 425 (1960).
²¹ Id. at 429.
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 45
his vision enabled him to see was that the underlying conflict about Brown was
really an identity crisis about democracy itself. In The Least Dangerous Branch, he
chose to press a highly simple resolution.³⁰ Democracy was easy to understand as
long as the important decisions were being made by the Congress or state legisla-
tures.³¹ Indeed, Bickel declared confidently that “the policy-making power of rep-
resentative institutions, born of the electoral process, is the distinguishing
characteristic of the system.”³² His emphasis on elections, along with his choice of
the word “distinguishing,” suggests that perhaps he was tacitly seeking to articu-
late democracy’s distinction from Communism, a salient competitor during this
Cold War period. On the matter of electoral accountability, clearly America’s sys-
tem of government had a strong claim to superiority, while on a metric of individ-
ual rights or entitlements, perhaps—unmentioned in Bickel’s definition of
democracy—the competitive advantage might be less clear.
Whatever Bickel’s motivation, his simplification of the concept of democracy,
reducing it to its most elemental populist foundations, captured a powerful and
widely felt sentiment. But if this was democracy, then the concept of individual
rights was in trouble. If democracy means the enactment into law of policies that a
majority of the people favor, and that preference is, by definition, reflected in the
decisions of representative institutions, then it follows that any effort to thwart or
overturn legislative decisions is anti-democratic. Indeed, that was precisely
Bickel’s conclusion about judicial review: he chose the words “undemocratic”³³
and “deviant,”³⁴ in addition to the perhaps less pejorative, and more famous,
“counter-majoritarian difficulty.”³⁵ Courts would be the last-resort guardians of
the most “clear cut” constitutional values, but would restrain themselves from
involvement in controversial political matters best left to the politically account-
able branches. “The more fundamental the issue,” Bickel wrote, “the nearer it is to
principle, the more important it is that it be decided in the first instance by the
legislature.”³⁶
The Least Dangerous Branch served to facilitate a seductive forgetfulness about
what a constitutional democracy is. It would not be understood as the “inarticulate
and complex”³⁷ idea encompassing a collection of interacting mechanisms work-
ing in different directions to ensure a combination of procedurally sound represen-
tative political government, along with “insight and wisdom and justice.”³⁸
³⁰ This book was not by any means the end of Bickel’s thinking on the subject, and in later works
he revised and, to some extent, complicated his views about democracy. See A. Bickel, The Supreme
Court and the Idea of Progress 175–181 (1970); A. Bickel, The Morality of Consent
(1975). My focus here is on the impact of the 1962 book.
³¹ Bickel paid little heed to the growing insights about the inexact correspondence between legis-
lative decisions and majority will, propounded by such theorists as Robert Dahl and David Truman.
See Kalman, supra note 5, at 38–39 (describing Bickel’s apparent rejection of pluralism) See also
Bickel, The Supreme Court and the Idea of Progress, supra note 30, at 84–86 (later recognizing
some basic interest group role, but still emphasizing the preeminence of the vote as the sole concern
of the Court). ³² Bickel, supra note 27, at 19.
³³ Id. at 17. ³⁴ Id. at 18. ³⁵ Id. at 16. ³⁶ Id. 161.
³⁷ Black, supra note 26, at 179. ³⁸ Id. at 182.
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 47
complexity, concrete answers over abstract ideals, losing track of what the
American Constitution had been since its inception. The academy’s schizophrenic
reaction to Brown—recognizing the necessity of its outcome, while still resisting
the institutional muscle that permitted the judiciary to reach it legitimately—is
symptomatic of this loss of core mission. Scholarship argued back and forth about
how best to hold the Court back, how to restrain it, from overstepping the narrow
bounds permitted it by a system conceived in majoritarian supremacy.⁴³ Judicial
review, and, with it, the enforcement of individual rights, was an embarrassment to
the Constitution rather than its highest calling. What served instead, as a final
cause, was elusive. The candor and commitment necessary to face up to a banish-
ment of rights from the democracy were lacking, yet the preservation of a shell with
no defining contours left a vacuum of direction and purpose. Thus, it plausibly
could be said in these times that “the institution of judicial review has somehow
faded out of the picture—or, what is far worse, has been converted into a mere rit-
ual of acquiescence, or in plainer terms a solemn if not particularly pious fraud.”⁴⁴
It was not appropriate to talk too much about rights, or even justice.⁴⁵ Anyone
who presumed to do so ran the risk of being accused of offending democracy or favor-
ing “judicial tyranny.”⁴⁶ Political rhetoric, following the lead of the academy, spoke of
aspirations of “strict construction” and “judicial restraint,”⁴⁷ both of which were code
words for reading rights in the Constitution as parsimoniously as possible.⁴⁸
Anything else, it was claimed, was “making” law rather than “interpreting” it.⁴⁹
With Ronald Dworkin came the restorative balm of candor and the frank com-
mitment to constitutional ideals. He was not literally alone, of course, in his aggres-
sive program of taking rights seriously. But his work stands out for its relentless
challenge to the false dichotomies that had become commonplace in constitutional
thinking: between making and interpreting law, between rank rights skepticism
⁴³ See E. Chemerinsky, The Supreme Court, 1988 Term—Foreword: The Vanishing Constitution, 103
Harv. L. Rev. 43, 73 (1989) (documenting the widespread adoption of the “majoritarian paradigm”,
“the idea that judicial review . . . is in tension with American democracy”).
⁴⁴ Black, supra note 26, at 191.
⁴⁵ See M. Horwitz, The Warren Court and the Pursuit of Justice, 50 WM. & Mary L. Rev. 5, 11
(1993) (describing how Chief Justice Warren was ridiculed for asking attorneys whether their posi-
tion was just: “Sophisticated legal scholars did not speak that way”).
⁴⁶ See, e.g., R. H. Bork, Neutral Principles and some First Amendment Problems, 47 Ind. L. J. 2–3
(1971) (arguing that judges necessarily abet “tyranny” if they exceed their proper sphere).
⁴⁷ See Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 2, at 31–37.
⁴⁸ See J. F. Simon, In His Own Image: The Supreme Court in Richard Nixon’s America 8–9
(1973) (by “strict constructionists,” President Nixon “meant that he would appoint judges who took
less active and reform-minded views”).
⁴⁹ See Changes Nixon May Make in Federal Courts, U.S. News & World Rep., Dec. 2, 1968, at 42
(quoting President Nixon as stating, “In my view, the duty of a Justice of the Supreme Court is to
interpret the law, not to make law, and the men I appoint will share that view”). The alleged
dichotomy has persisted. See President’s Remarks Announcing the Nomination of Clarence Thomas
to Be an Associate Justice of the Supreme Court of the United States and a News Conference in
Kennebunkport, Maine, 27 Weekly Comp. Pres. Doc. 868 871 (July 1, 1991) (then-President
George H. W. Bush’s suggestion that the nominee would “faithfully interpret the Constitution and
avoid the tendency to legislate from the bench”).
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 49
Ronald Dworkin set a place for principle at the table of constitutional theory. He
argued that the moral skeptics of the 1930s and 1940s were impoverished in their
rejection of morality as part of law. The positivist emphasis on law as command,
with authority commensurate to its source in the people, erroneously limited law to
a formal set of rules that had no use for morality in its enforcement and application.
To Dworkin, this was an unacceptable mask to impose on law of any kind, but his
attacks on positivism and utilitarianism had particular resonance for constitutional
law. Because Dworkin saw all law as a system of rights recognition and protection,
his vision readily lent itself to employment in the development of constitutional law
and theory. His understanding of law as comprising not just legal rules, but also
principles, provided an apt foundation from which to construct an interpretative
edifice for the Constitution itself, for Dworkin a rich source of such principle.
Dworkin’s method calls upon the judge faced with an adjudicative issue to dis-
cover principles by looking backward in time to the practices and traditions in the
nation’s history.⁵¹ Evolving from common law to constitutional law, the “moral
reading” of the Constitution asks judges to find what Dworkin calls the “best”
conception of constitutional moral principles that would fit the historical record,
which includes constitutional text, evidence of contemporaneous understanding,
precedent, and societal experience over time. These principles, in turn, inform the
resolution of current issues of the day, without necessarily determining outcomes.
For the first time, the idea of balancing individual liberty against the commu-
nity’s needs came under critical scrutiny. Dworkin argued for recognition of moral
rights against the government—those that it would be wrong for a government to
transgress even for the best of reasons rooted in the common good.⁵² These moral
claims that all individuals hold against their government are determined by a
political judgment regarding the limits of government power in the free society
that our Constitution establishes and maintains. This is an appropriate task for a
applying principle, he does deserve credit for seeking mightily to frame the inquiry
so as to avoid the appeal to the personal. He charges the judge with asking ques-
tions about the Constitution and the constitutional structure that we have, and
grounding the answer to that inquiry in reason brought to bear on shared experi-
ence and value, rather than personal experience and value.⁵⁵ His steadfast insistence
on the existence of accessible moral truth, while subjecting him to ridicule,⁵⁶
enriched the project of ascertaining appropriate limits on government power.
While the source of principle is in the past and present, its trajectory points
toward the future by relying on a judgment of how best to reconcile past practice
with the aspirations of the polity. What could be more inspiring to a discipline strug-
gling to find itself than a plea for “moral progress, and though history may show how
difficult it is to decide where moral progress lies, and how difficult to persuade others
once one has decided, it cannot follow from this that those who govern us have no
responsibility to face that decision or to attempt that persuasion.”⁵⁷
Dworkin’s method does not abandon law; but rather redefines what counts as
law. Unlike Hart, he does not ask the judge to step beyond the law and decide hard
cases on the basis of something other than law, like policy. Instead, he endows law
with a key component, principle, that prevents it from ever running out. The
moral reading of the Constitution, in particular, claims an authority deriving
from the Framers of the Constitution themselves, boasting not only consistency
with their original intent, but also fidelity to the text that they adopted as funda-
mental law. This claim attaches to every significant stage of constitutional draft-
ing: the original document, the Bill of Rights, and the Civil War Amendments.
The language of these rights-protecting provisions of the Constitution, phrased as
they are in “exceedingly abstract moral language”⁵⁸ such as the “right” of free
speech, “due” process, and “equal” protection, incorporates a set of abstract moral
principles as limits on governmental power.⁵⁹ He can thus accommodate prin-
ciple in the interpretative process without compromising the authority many
claim is vital to judicial legitimacy. If these constitutional principles seem, too
coincidentally, to correspond to basic tenets of liberal political thought, it is the
result, not of Dworkin’s preferences, but of the Framers’. They constructed our
nation’s basic commitments, after all, “in the bright morning of liberal thought.”⁶⁰
Central to the moral reading is the decision to conceive this set of constitu-
tional principles at its most general and aggregate level so as to establish an over-
arching guide for specific interpretations of the document. Dworkin has read the
principles set out in the Constitution, taken together, to commit the United States
to the proposition that “the government must treat all those subject to its domin-
ion as having equal moral and political status; it must attempt, in good faith, to
treat them all with equal concern; and it must respect whatever individual free-
doms are indispensable to those ends . . . .”⁶¹ This foundational insight has come
to be known as Dworkin’s notion of “equal concern and respect,” which he has
developed throughout his work, and has been, to some degree, the trademark of
his approach to constitutional interpretation. Although he initially attributed the
principle to Rawls,⁶² it is Dworkin who gave that principle life as a foundation for
constitutional theory.
It is the principle of equal concern and respect, enshrined into positive law in
the Constitution, that provides the starting place for analysis of all individual
rights. It is a principle much deeper and more substantive than a mere formal
equality. It contemplates real limits on government’s use of its powers in its treat-
ment of people: “Government must treat those whom it governs with concern,
that is, as human beings who are capable of suffering and frustration, and with
respect, that is, as human beings who are capable of forming and acting on intelli-
gent conceptions of how their lives should be lived.”⁶³ It thus embraces more than
mere equality of treatment, including also the rights we generally think of as
autonomy and liberty rights. These concepts of individual liberty are implicit in
the equality-based proposition that government can never constrain one person’s
pursuit of the good life on the rationale that another’s conception of a life well led
is superior.⁶⁴ This proposition helps to suggest both the contours of what kinds of
particular liberties must be respected and what kinds of reasons governments
must (or may not) offer in support of any state effort to curtail them. Both this
identification of protected liberty rights and the inquiry into state reasons are
evident in the Supreme Court jurisprudence under the Due Process Clause.
Sounding in liberty, these inquiries are latent in that thick conception of equality—
“the most radical conception of equality there is.”⁶⁵
Dworkin’s reliance on the text of the Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth
Amendment to supply the pedigree for the principle of equal concern and respect,
although apparently genuine, should not be overstated.⁶⁶ It is quite evident that
⁶¹ Id. at 8.
⁶² Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 2, at 181. Indeed, Dworkin devoted considerable atten-
tion to arguing that Rawls can be explained only by attributing to him a deep recognition of equal
concern and respect as a natural entitlement with which all persons are endowed, rather than as a
product of contract. Id. at 178–183. Whether or not this is the correct reading of Rawls, Dworkin
made clear that it is the correct reading of Dworkin. See id. at 272–273 (explaining the concept of
equal concern and respect as a “postulate[] of political morality”). ⁶³ Id. at 272.
⁶⁴ Dworkin has articulated the relationship between liberty and equality in different ways. At
times, he has seemed to suggest that equality may be viewed as prior to liberty because a just govern-
ment could not recognize a right to liberty that would conflict with a proper understanding of equality.
See R. Dworkin, What is Equality? Part 3: The Place of Liberty, 73 Iowa L. Rev. 1, 10 (1987). Yet he has
always resisted the idea that either liberty or equality is instrumental to the other, arguing that the two
are reconcilable ideals that merge into a fuller account of treating all persons with equal concern. See
Sovereign Virtue, supra note 2, at 123. ⁶⁵ Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 2, at 182.
⁶⁶ See E. B. Foley, Interpretation and Philosophy: Dworkin’s Constitution, 14 Const. Comment.
151, 154 (1997) (reviewing Freedom’s Law) (questioning the candor of Dworkin’s reliance on text).
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 53
citizens.⁷⁰ In contrast, Dworkin sees the invalidation of unjust laws as the fulfill-
ment of the very end of legitimate government. When injustices are overturned or
avoided, government has achieved its highest aspiration, which is a cause for
moral celebration, not moral regret. Accordingly, his view makes possible an ener-
getic, rather than an apologetic, Constitution.
At the same time that Dworkin cut the constricting bonds of Bickelian restraint
and allowed the circulation to flow into the judiciary by charging it with an active
role in the protection of individual rights, he also exercised care to preserve his
interpretations of the Constitution as interpretations, not rewritings, of that
document. He has consistently refuted the critics’ attribution to him of a claim to
untether the judiciary from all constraint. The caricature of Dworkin’s view has
him arguing that only the judge’s opinion about objective moral reality is perti-
nent to his or her decision on a matter of constitutional interpretation. Dworkin,
however, has steadfastly persisted in his commitment to the “integrity” of the law,
by which he means that judges “must not deploy moral principles, no matter how
much they are personally committed to such principles, that cannot be defended
as consistent with the general history of past Supreme Court decisions and the
general structure of American political practice.”⁷¹ The task, as Dworkin has con-
sistently defined it, is the daunting job of gleaning both principles and their
appropriate application from the Constitution and society that we, at the present
time, have, recognizing that these are the product of influences bearing on the
present from many forces in our past.
This is a job that requires honest acknowledgment of not only the principles that
provide the ideals of a free society, but also the instances in our past that may not
represent our highest attainment of those ideals. This opportunity for judges to be
realistic and use what they know makes possible the open use of judgment and the
critique thereof, actually facilitating public debate about our societal ideals. It is a
dynamic approach to constitutional theory that restores to the Constitution a sense
of purpose and grants to the society that it enables the opportunity to evolve.
Where the prior constitutional theory had struggled with “fake and apology,”⁷²
Dworkin’s was candid. Where prior theory was schizophrenic, Dworkin’s was
single-minded. Where prior theory had sunk to “despair,”⁷³ Dworkin’s was opti-
mistic. Where prior theory accorded no affirmative role to the Constitution in con-
tributing to the aspirations of society, Dworkin’s expressly sought out the “best” of
⁷⁰ Some go so far as to suggest that invalidation of a law on constitutional grounds violates the
rights of those who supported it. See, e.g., R. H. Bork, The Tempting of America: The Political
Seduction of the Law 147 (1990) (when a judge recognizes new constitutional rights, “he violates
not only the limits to his own authority but, and for that reason, also violates the rights of the legisla-
ture and the people.”).
⁷¹ Freedom’s Law, supra note 2, at 319. The fuller concept of law as integrity is explored in Law’s
Empire, supra note 2. ⁷² See supra note 21, and accompanying text.
⁷³ See Black, supra note 20, at 428 (suggesting that “legal acumen has only one proper task—that
of developing ways to make it permissible for the Court to use what it knows; any other counsel is of
despair”).
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 55
of the time had found no place for moral argument in their thinking about society’s
constitutive commitments.⁷⁹ Dworkin’s conception of democracy, by contrast, was
deeply responsive to the moral demands of society at that time, and since.
III. Contributions
For some critics, Dworkin’s insistence upon the existence of right answers stirs
echoes in their minds of the formalists of the early twentieth century.⁸⁰ But the
ears of those who hear that echo deceive them. Dworkin does not claim that the
Constitution determinately answers all questions. To the contrary, he calls con-
stantly for human judgment to be interposed between the issue and the
Constitution for identification of the relevant principle. He explicitly recognizes
that the process of identifying principle “will leave many possibilities open.”⁸¹
“[T]houghtful judges must then decide on their own which conception does most
credit to the nation.”⁸² Right answers do exist, but no one necessarily has a way to
know what they are.⁸³ Their existence provides the aspiration for judges acting in
good faith.
While this may seem superficially detached, it is in fact grounded in American
identity and values. The people who constitute this democracy are given a voice in
constitutional discourse in at least two important ways. First, judges are charged
with finding “our” principles when they seek to apply a constitutional provision to
a case. Remaining faithful to constitutional practice by supplying a filtering func-
tion, the theory finds constitutional principle, not by direct appeal to people’s
preferences, but by interposing the judgment of a judge who is charged with tak-
ing the longer view, to locate principle in whatever evidence is available.
A second way Dworkin draws popular political views into the dynamic reading
of constitutional text is through a vigorous confirmation process. By offering a
robust and complex job description for those appointed to the bench, he provides
much opportunity for discussion of substantive issues and qualifications related to
⁷⁹ This is not to deny the significant contributions, of course, of fellow travelers in the journey
toward more robust recognition of individual rights under the Constitution. Any list of important
theorists who sought to advance the cause of rights during this time must include, among others,
T. Grey, Do We Have an Unwritten Constitution?, 27 Stan. L. Rev. 703 (1975); J. Skelly Wright,
Professor Bickel, the Scholarly Tradition, and the Supreme Court, 85 Harv. L. Rev. 769 (1971); L. Tribe,
Structural Due Process, 10 Harv. Civ. Rts-Civ. Lib. L. Rev. 269 (1975); F. Michelman, The Supreme
Court, 1968 Term—Foreword: On Protecting the Poor Through the Fourteenth Amendment, 83 Harv.
L. Rev. 7 (1969); C. Black, Structure and Relationship in Constitutional Law (1965);
Wellington, Common Law Rules and Constitutional Double Standards: Some Notes on Adjudication,
83 Yale L.J. 221 (1973).
⁸⁰ E.g., M. McConnell, The Importance of Humility in Judicial Review: A Comment on Ronald
Dworkin’s “Moral Reading” of the Constitution, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 1269, 1278 (1997).
⁸¹ Freedom’s Law, supra note 2, at 9. ⁸² Id. at 11.
⁸³ See Law’s Empire, supra note 2, at ix (explaining that “whether we have reason to think an
answer is right is different from the question whether it can be demonstrated to be right”).
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 57
that job description. If a judge is expected to use judgment rather than eschew it,
his or her competence for that position should be tested by inquiries into all the
facets of human judgment that could be expected to influence the judge’s identifi-
cation and application of principle.
The strongest evidence that Dworkin’s is a theory about our Constitution and
our society, rather than some “Utopia” of his own fabrication,⁸⁴ is that he has
made a difference in the law of the land. It seems clear, at the least, that his ener-
getic defense of the role of rights in the constitutional scheme has changed the
terms of the theoretical and doctrinal debates to focus more on which rights to
protect, and how, rather than whether to protect them.
Chronologically, the first major sign that Dworkin was on to something
important in constitutional theory came in a somewhat hostile setting, John Hart
Ely’s extremely influential Democracy and Distrust. This is a book conspicuously
and explicitly committed to rejecting the attribution of substantive values to the
Constitution. Thus, one might not expect to find there a reliance on a core idea of
the one theorist perhaps most closely associated with a substantive reading of the
Constitution.⁸⁵ Yet in an unadorned footnote, the simple citation speaks volumes:
“34. R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 180 (1977).”⁸⁶ As the following discus-
sion shows, this indispensable citation, no mere flourish, supports the pivot upon
which turns Ely’s argument for a representation-reinforcing understanding of judi-
cial review. In order to show the (unacknowledged) significance of the role of
Dworkin’s idea to Ely’s work, it will be necessary to sketch out a short description of
the intellectual moves that contribute to the thesis of Democracy and Distrust.
Ely’s argument began with the observation that the concept of representation,
as understood by those who founded the American nation, was richer and more
complex than simply a structure of rulers and ruled. Indeed, as he recognized, it
embraced a unique amalgam of the two interests.⁸⁷ The idea was that the legisla-
tors “would live under the regime of the laws they passed and not exempt them-
selves from their operation: this obligation to include themselves among the ruled
would ensure a community of interest and guard against oppressive legislation.”⁸⁸
⁸⁴ Among those who have leveled this argument is J. C. Harrison, Utopia’s Law, Politics’
Constitution (Reviewing Freedom’s Law), 19 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 917 (1995–1996).
⁸⁵ See J. Hart Ely, Democracy and Distrust 56–57 (1980) (discussing and rejecting the three-
part proposition that “moral philosophy is what constitutional law is properly about, that there exists
a correct way of doing such philosophy, and that judges are better than others at identifying and
engaging in it.”). ⁸⁶ Id., at 82 n.34.
⁸⁷ Ely’s book is notoriously short on historical support, but on this point it turns out that there is
good evidence of the claim that the American notion of representation was new and unique in ways
critical to the argument Ely was constructing. See R. L. Brown, Liberty, the New Equality, 77 NYU
L. Rev. 1491, 1512–1520 (2002) (exploring the historical foundations and implications of the repre-
sentation argument).
⁸⁸ Ely, supra note 85, at 78 & n.16; see Brown, supra note 87, at 1520–1528 (explaining the com-
munity of interests idea and arguing for its extension to support judicial review of modern-day liberty
claims).
58 Rebecca L. Brown
both Brown and much of the other judicial activism practiced by the Warren
Court. What the theory needed was a way to understand the process of “represen-
tation” as encompassing an obligation to engage in some basic substantive consid-
eration of the interests of those who may be on the losing side of policy decisions.
Without that more capacious definition of representation, it would seem that a
court limited to representation reinforcement would strike down no law unless
someone were excluded from the process altogether. The biggest challenge to con-
struction of this new understanding of representation was to anchor it in the
Constitution by showing where such an obligation on legislators to minority con-
stituents might reside.
Yet Ely took care of the problem in one bizarre sentence making no direct refer-
ence to the Constitution. The sentence addressed this very issue, the need to
maintain a community of interests between the representative and his or her
minority constituents in the quest to avoid majority tyranny. “Naturally,” wrote
Ely, “that cannot mean that groups that constitute minorities of the population
can never be treated less favorably than the rest, but it does preclude a refusal to
represent them, the denial to minorities of what Professor Dworkin has called
‘equal concern and respect in the design and administration of the political insti-
tutions that bind them.’”⁹²
And so it was that representation-reinforcement theory’s chasm, the need for a
new understanding of representation that could be policed by self-restrained
courts, was bridged by Dworkin’s idea of equal concern and respect. The critical
new definition of “representation”—which, in turn, would supply the boundaries
of legitimate judicial review—was built upon this core insight.
Once across this bridge, Ely was then free to proceed with a theory of represen-
tation reinforcement. If the notion of a democratic government imposes on repre-
sentatives an obligation to accord equal concern and respect to all their
constituents, then any legislation passed out of either disregard for, or intentional
malice toward, any group fails the test for “procedural” integrity and justifies judi-
cial intervention.
In pressing the importance of Dworkin to Ely, my purpose is not to join those
who have criticized Ely for claiming the impossible when he purported to liberate
the Constitution from substantive commitments.⁹³ I seek only to suggest that
Dworkin’s insight as to equal concern and respect is virtually indispensable to the
construction of any kind of theory that seeks to reconcile democracy and constitu-
tionalism, as Ely’s did. Even a constitutional theory that struggles mightily to
⁹² Ely, supra note 85, at 82 (citing R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 180 (1977)) (empha-
sis in original). An omitted internal footnote mentioned that, for persons to be “represented,” “their
interests are not to be left out of account or valued negatively in the lawmaking process.” Id. at 82 n.33.
⁹³ See L. H. Tribe, The Puzzling Persistence of Process-Based Constitutional Theories, 89 Yale L.J.
1063, 1077 (1980); M. Tushnet, Darkness on the Edge of Town: The Contributions of John Hart Ely to
Constitutional Theory, 89 Yale L.J. 1037 (1980).
60 Rebecca L. Brown
eschew Dworkin finds him pivotal to its effort to escape the leveling crush of pure
majoritarianism—a formidable tribute to a core idea.
But Dworkin’s conquest of Ely, and with him, much of the Legal Process school
of thought, is not the end of the story. As the agony over Brown slowly faded into
the distant past, the would-be heirs to the Legal Process school have undergone
fertilization, infancy and development into distinct, but identifiable, offspring. In
1996, Dworkin wrote Freedom’s Law, dedicated to attacking the “majoritarian
premise,” just as Taking Rights Seriously had styled itself, nearly twenty years
earlier, as an attack on positivism and utilitarianism. In many respects, little had
changed other than the names of the antagonists. The majoritarian premise,
which had led to the call for “strict construction” during the Nixon years, has
supported development or cultivation of such repackaged schools of thought as
judicial minimalism, originalism, pragmatism and the new institutionalism of
administrative law.
Just as Bickel called for judges to exercise their “passive virtues” to keep them-
selves out of societal contests, judicial minimalism calls for courts to leave as much
as possible undecided, leaving room for moral issues to be resolved through the
political processes.⁹⁴ This approach, I have suggested, is not respectful of the equal
status of all citizens, but rather entrenches enacted law without regard to the
strength or validity of the interests of those burdened by the codification of major-
ity preferences.⁹⁵ Despite protestations to the contrary, its failure to require judi-
cially evaluated reasons for divisive legislation renders it strongly majoritarian in
its effect. It is the heir to the “Passive Virtues” name.
The majoritarian premise has infected much of structural constitutional theory
as well.⁹⁶ Administrative law scholarship seeks to justify decisions based on who
makes them, and how accountable the decision-maker is to popular control, rather
than judging them on how well they are protecting the rights of individuals and
achieving good government. Calls for the President to have more control of admin-
istrative agencies, based on an accountability argument, have become a familiar
part of the constitutional separation-of-powers literature.⁹⁷ The administrative
issues involving deference to agency interpretations of statutes reflect the same
trend, both in the Chevron case itself and in the many scholarly paeans to it.⁹⁸
⁹⁴ Sunstein, supra note 40, at 3–6. ⁹⁵ See Brown, supra note 87, at 1538.
⁹⁶ See L. Schultz Bressman, Beyond Accountability: Arbitrariness and Legitimacy in the
Administrative State, 78 NYU L. Rev. 461 (2003) (describing the new views of the administrative
state as profoundly majoritarian).
⁹⁷ See, e.g., L. Lessig & C. R. Sunstein, The President and the Administration, 94 Colum. L. Rev. 1,
94 (1994) (the President must have control over agencies to preserve accountability, one of two “cen-
tral values of the framers’ original executive”); S. G. Calabresi & S. B. Prakash, The President’s Power to
Execute the Laws, 104 Yale L.J. 541 (1994) (arguing for a unitary theory of the executive branch,
based largely on accountability arguments); E. Kagan, Presidential Administration, 114 Harv. L. Rev.
2245 (2001) (arguing that increased presidential involvement in agency decisions can increase the
legitimacy of agencies by increasing majoritarian control of administrative lawmaking).
⁹⁸ See Chevron v. NRDC, 467 U.S. 837 (1984); A. Scalia, Judicial Deference to Administrative
Interpretations of Law, Duke L.J. 511, 518 (1989); L. H. Silberman, Chevron—The Intersection of
Law and Policy, 58 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 821 (1990).
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 61
⁹⁹ See R. Dworkin, Darwin’s New Bulldog, 111 Harv. L. Rev. 1718, 1719 (1998) (in challenge to
the claims of Richard Posner, lamenting uncertainty about “when the antitheory episode in our intel-
lectual history will have run its course.”). There are other forms of pragmatism that may be less
squarely in conflict with Dworkin, such as certain forms of practical reasoning which seek to identify
moral norms for use in the resolution of statutory issues. See W. N. Eskridge & P. P. Frickey, Statutory
Interpretation as Practical Reasoning, 42 Stan. L. Rev. 321 (1990).
¹⁰⁰ See A. Scalia, Originalism, The Lesser Evil, 57 U. Cinn. L. Rev. 849 (1989); A. Scalia, The Rule
of Law is the Law of Rules, 56 U. Chi. L. Rev. 1175 (1989).
¹⁰¹ See Freedom’s Law, supra note 2, at 14.
¹⁰² See, e.g., U S v. Carolene Prods., 304 U.S. 144, 152–153 n.4 (1938); City of Cleburne v.
Cleburne Living Center, 473 U.S. 432 (1985) (applying Ely’s factors to deny heightened scrutiny).
62 Rebecca L. Brown
The case I have in mind most conspicuously is Adarand v. Pena,¹⁰³ in which the
Supreme Court held that any government use of race in decision-making must be
subjected to strict scrutiny, regardless of motivation. Significant there was the heed-
lessness of the Supreme Court of the circumstance that the individuals claiming to
be burdened by the minority set-aside provision at issue possessed none of the classic
“suspect” features that would ordinarily lead a Court to fear that their interests
might not get adequate representation in the political process, features that had once
been a pre-condition to a heightened degree of judicial intervention. That would
have been the traditional analysis of such a case under a Bickelian or Elysian legisla-
tive-supremacy, representation-reinforcing view. Yet the Court took an entirely dif-
ferent approach. Instead it identified a moral principle, color-blindness, sought
(unsuccessfully, in Dworkin’s view) to ground it in constitutional text and prece-
dent, and determined that any compromise of that principle was deserving of the
most intrusive level of judicial scrutiny. This case is difficult to explain except on a
moral reading of the Constitution, even if the justices in the case may be criticized
for selecting a principle that is not well defended by reference to our nation’s history
and practices.
Fingerprints of the moral reading can be detected in the joint opinion in
Planned Parenthood v. Casey as well.¹⁰⁴ That opinion reflects a significant depart-
ure both from the earlier case that it purported to affirm (Roe v. Wade,¹⁰⁵ 1973)
and from other fundamental rights precedent. It acknowledged for the first time
“a realm of personal liberty which the government may not enter,” grounded in
American law by some authority other than a strictly textual application of the Bill
of Rights, an authority bearing many indicia of a Dworkinian principle.¹⁰⁶
Dworkin’s thick portrayal of equality continues to exert an important influence
today. The use of a principle of equal concern and respect, as a foundation for
implementing democracy, is as sound and robust today as it was thirty years ago.
Perhaps it is even more important than ever, as the society becomes increasingly
heterogeneous (the reason Ely was forced to make use of the principle), the legisla-
tive and electoral processes increasingly inaccessible, and the challenge of securing
good and fair laws through representative democracy increasingly daunting.
Perhaps most valuable to current constitutional law is the use of equality com-
mitments to give life to the protection of fundamental liberties. A recent Term of
the United States Supreme Court brought a stunning example of the importance
of Dworkin’s substratum of equal concern and respect to one of the divisive issues
¹⁰⁷ A second case in the same Term, Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U.S. 306 (2003), fulfilled a predic-
tion made by Dworkin in his discussion of whether racial diversity in a university setting would give
rise to a compelling state interest sufficient to justify race-conscious admissions policies. See
Sovereign Virtue, supra note 2, at 420–426 (accurately suggesting that the Bakke principle remains
good law, and recommending an emphasis, borne out in the case, on diversity as the predominant
state interest supporting such programs). I do not take the Court’s opinion in Grutter, however, to be
an application of his moral reading, particularly since it applies strict scrutiny as a result of Adarand v.
Pena, a precedent that Dworkin would not endorse (even if it does employ a moral reasoning of its
own). See id. at 417. ¹⁰⁸ 539 U.S. 558 (2003).
¹⁰⁹ Railway Express Agency, Inc. v. New York, 336 U.S. 106, 112 (1949) (Jackson, J., concurring).
¹¹⁰ Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dep’t of Health, 497 U.S. 261, 300 (1990) (Scalia, J., concurring).
¹¹¹ See Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967) (deciding liberty claim with reference to the misce-
genation law’s affront to equality).
¹¹² See Brown, supra note 87, at 1491–1500 (discussing inter-relations between liberty and equal-
ity, the traditional judicial preference for equality, and the need for a more satisfactory merging of the
two ideals).
64 Rebecca L. Brown
¹¹³ See, e.g., Washington v. Glucksberg, 521 U.S. 707 (1997) (holding right of terminally ill to
assisted suicide not fundamental because not deeply rooted in tradition); Bowers v. Hardwick, 478
U.S. 186 (1986) (holding right to engage in homosexual conduct not fundamental because not
deeply rooted in tradition); Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491 U.S. 505 (1989) (plurality finding right of
biological father to relationship with child conceived in adultery not fundamental because not deeply
rooted in tradition).
¹¹⁴ This was the then-novel position taken in Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986).
¹¹⁵ 539 U.S. at 526.
¹¹⁶ Lawrence v. Texas, No. 02–102, Respondent’s Brief, Feb. 17, 2003, at 41.
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 65
balancing. In the Court’s written opinion, one could almost detect the whisper of
Dworkin’s 1977 warning that government “must not constrain liberty on the
ground that one citizen’s conception of the good life . . . is nobler or superior to
another’s.” This postulate, he had emphasized, “is a conception of equality, not of
liberty . . . .”¹¹⁷ It appears that a quarter-century later, these insights have found
expression in the law of the land.
This aspect of Dworkin’s work shows great promise for addressing one of the
most difficult contemporary constitutional issues arising under the Due Process
Clause, the problem of evaluating the relative strengths of, on the one hand, a
claim to liberty, and, on the other, a state assertion of the need to restrict it. The
Court has been unable to ground this inquiry, on either side of the balance, in any
teleological commitments that would help frame the determination of a statute’s
validity. Wanting to avoid the charge that it is legislating from the bench, it has
struggled to identify some metric against which a claimed liberty right could be
evaluated, but has been unable to settle on one because it has articulated no over-
arching theory of what it is protecting or why. This noncommittal protection of
liberty rights has resulted in an often formalistic fragmentation of liberty into two
categories, some being “fundamental” and others “ordinary.”¹¹⁸ The conse-
quences of attaching one of these labels are huge, yet the normative impulses
underlying the dichotomy are elusive. This leads the Court more and more to
relegate claims to the default category of “ordinary” liberties, leaving them to the
mercies of legislative grace.
When the Court has attempted qualitative evaluation of liberties, its analysis has
been unsatisfying. For example, while acknowledging that some of the liberties it
has recognized as fundamental in the past have had something to do with auton-
omy, the Court, in the assisted suicide case, explicitly rejected autonomy as a defin-
ing feature of a fundamental right.¹¹⁹ The Court has buffeted around the idea of
societal tradition as a way to identify protected interests, but that has caused more
problems than it has solved. This approach to identifying fundamental rights has
persistently sparked the still unresolved controversy about the level of generality at
which to search for societal traditions, as well as the thorny question of which
history to select in cases of conflicting evidence.¹²⁰ Moreover, the tradition method
has never adequately responded to the more normative question why the
backward-looking reliance on past societal practice should provide the limits of
protected liberty going forward in an evolving society.¹²¹ Thus, the Court has not
succeeded in ordering different liberties into an intelligible hierarchy.
On the state’s side of the ledger, the doctrinal picture has been equally dim. The
cases have supplied no framework within which to measure the strength or validity
of state interests offered in support of regulatory restrictions on liberty. Moral argu-
ments, such as that made by Texas in support of its sodomy statute, are especially
difficult to quantify as “rational” or “compelling,” in the absence of some broader
theory addressing the appropriate use of state power in a free society. This lack of
guidance for evaluating the limits of regulatory authority has enabled those on the
side of regulating states to launch a liberty claim of their own. The claim is that the
citizens who support a statutory restriction on liberty have a “right” to enact their
beliefs into law without interference from the Constitution. According to this view,
it is a violation of their liberty to strike down laws they have passed to constrain the
objectionable behavior of others.¹²² The “freedom of association” claim, raised in
opposition to the Brown decision,¹²³ is one version of this argument. The Court,
having constructed no theory of how our Constitution protects liberty, has been
without the means to repudiate the devastating implications of this argument.
Dworkin’s work gives courts the tools with which to begin addressing both
types of deficit in the case law. On the liberty side, the principle of equal concern
and respect suggests some contours for a method of discerning which types of
liberty must be specially guarded in a constitutional democracy. Dworkin has
constructed arguments along these lines in addressing several of the major liberty
issues to arise in recent years; the analysis that these arguments share is the norma-
tive vision of liberty protection as a way to secure a certain minimal degree of dig-
nity and equal moral status for all citizens, a value traceable to both liberty and
equality ideals.¹²⁴ This anchoring of liberty to political theory provides guidance
in the understanding of why some claims might be more compelling than others.
Dworkin solves the problems of level of generality and conflicting traditions, so
irksome to court precedent, with his elements of fit and integrity in the interpreta-
tion of the Constitution.
Dworkin’s approach also provides a start for developing a principled way of
evaluating asserted state interests. His response, in particular, to those who make
the claim described above—that collective self-determination is compromised
by enforcement of individual rights—suggests contours for a method of evaluat-
ing state justifications for laws generally. He does not reject the community self-
determination argument on its face. After all, its claim, that a majority of a
¹²¹ See R. L. Brown, Tradition and Insight, 103 Yale L.J. 177, 200–205 (1993) (discussing several
theoretical objections to use of tradition as defining point for individual rights).
¹²² Freedom’s Law, supra note 2, at 21. Bork, for one, has explicitly made this claim. See supra
note 70.
¹²³ See Wechsler, supra note 17, at 35 (characterizing the “heart of the issue” in Brown as the choice
by a state between denying association to those who wish it and imposing it on those who would
avoid it). ¹²⁴ See Freedom’s Law, supra note 2, at 111.
How Constitutional Theory Found its Soul 67
community has the right to determine the nature of the entire community through
law, is an essentially moral argument and, as such, must be taken seriously. In
order for the claim to succeed, however, the underlying interest in collective self-
government must itself meet moral standards. Thus, the community seeking to
determine its own values through legal restrictions on liberty must meet the mini-
mal obligation to respect the needs and prospects of all members of the affected
community. Accordingly, just as a community would obviously not have a moral
entitlement to employ its right to self-government so as to enslave some members
of the community for the benefit of the others (even if 99 per cent voted to enslave
the remaining 1per cent), it would also be precluded, more generally, from dictat-
ing what its citizens think about matters of political, moral or ethical judgment,
no matter how many members might share one view.
This recognition of a basic moral obligation on government provides a way of
beginning to distinguish and evaluate asserted government interests. A require-
ment that all laws accord equal concern and respect to all members of a community
can begin the process of distinguishing laws that legitimately seek to protect the
public good from those that simply impose contested visions of the good life on an
unwilling minority. Although admittedly difficult, this inquiry is far more substan-
tive and meaningful than the apparently ad hoc jurisprudence that led the Supreme
Court, without elaboration, to pronounce one day that a community’s moral
preferences are sufficient to support restraints on individual liberty (in Bowers v.
Hardwick), and then another day that they are not sufficient (in Lawrence v. Texas).
Dworkin’s work makes possible a meaningful, normative inquiry, and thus holds
the key to a coherent liberty jurisprudence for the twenty-first century.
IV. Conclusion
¹²⁵ See E. J. McCaffery, Ronald Dworkin, Inside-Out (reviewing Freedom’s Law), 85 Cal. L.
Rev. 1043, 1058 (1997) (describing Dworkin’s resolute nonskepticism and belief in moral and social
improvement). ¹²⁶ Freedom’s Law, supra note 2, at 38.
4
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent
S. L. Hurley*
* For helpful suggestions and comments on earlier drafts that saved me from various errors and
unclarities, I am grateful to Ronald Dworkin, Mark Greenberg, and Joseph Raz: needless to say,
responsibility for all remaining errors is entirely my own. This paper was originally, published in
10 (2) OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 221–251 (1990) and is reproduced here with permission.
¹ See J. RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE (1971); and R. L. KEENEY AND H. RAIFFA, DECISIONS WITH
MULTIPLE OBJECTIVES: PREFERENCES AND VALUE TRADEOFFS (1976).
² See my NATURAL REASONS (1989), chapters 4, 10, 11, 12, etc. Many background issues about
the nature and objectivity of coherentist practical reasoning are raised by the argument of this article
which I cannot here address at length in NATURAL REASONS. They include: the need for substantive
constraints on the description of the problem in terms of conflicting reasons, the relationships of
these constraints to the structure and process of coherentist deliberation and the explanatory charac-
ter of the resulting theories, the nature and limitations of the authority of theories about conflicting
reasons, and many others.
Secondly, consider various further examples of legal and ethical reasoning and
indicate briefly the way in which they provide instances of my general coherentist
characterization of deliberation;
Thirdly, point out the generally similar roles within coherentist accounts of
practical reasoning of settled actual cases and settled hypothetical cases as data to
be accounted for the sought-after theory or principles;
Fourthly, present an objection to coherence accounts of legal reasoning in
particular discussed by Kenneth Kress, who argues that they may give rise to
retroactive application of legal principles when new cases are decided between
the occurrence of the events litigated and litigation of them (the problem of
intervening cases); and
Finally, consider various possible responses to Kress’s argument. I shall briefly
evaluate and put aside the possible responses of giving intervening cases prospec-
tive effect only, and of accepting intervening case retroactivity as not so bad. I shall
then go on to diagnose the source of the problem by evaluating the relationships
among concept of coherence, hypothetical cases, and the doctrine of precedent.
I will show that the weaker coherentist requirement of treating like cases alike
within practical reasoning in general is not sufficient to give rise to the problem of
intervening cases, but that the stronger requirement imposed by the doctrine of
precedent within legal reasoning in particular is necessary for the problem to arise.
The distinction between the weaker and stronger requirements turns on the
asymmetrical treatment of actual and hypothetical cases by the doctrine of
precedent, by contrast with their symmetrical treatment in coherentist practical
reasoning in general. However, I shall then argue that, when this asymmetry is
properly understood, neither is the doctrine of precedent by itself sufficient to give
rise to the problem of intervening cases, but only does so when the intervening
legal decision is not ex ante correct, and that the role of hypothetical cases in
coherentist practical reasoning in fact limits the problem of intervening case
retroactivity. I shall conclude, following suggestions made by Dworkin, that
intervening case retroactivity does not present a problem for coherence accounts
such as his in particular.
³ For discussion of such conditions, see my NATURAL REASONS, supra note 2, chapter 12.
72 S. L. Hurley
for settled cases. They may have actually been decided, or may be posed as hypo-
thetical issues, the resolution of which can be taken as evident. By a “settled”
case, I mean a case which, if actual, is such that its resolution is clear to the
relevant decision-maker or decision-makers, and which, if hypothetical, is such
that its resolution would be clear to the relevant decision-maker or decision-
makers were the case to be considered. (That a resolution of a particular case is or
would be clear does not mean that it cannot be mistaken; settledness in particular
cases is a matter of what is or would be believed to be correct, not necessarily of
what is correct. However, it is of the nature of a coherentist account of what
should be done, in terms of coherence with settled cases in general, that not all
settled cases can be mistaken. I will return to this point below.) Thus, at least as a
conceptual matter, not all actually decided cases are settled, and some settled
cases are hypothetical, not actual (see Section VIII below for more on this use of
“settled”). We may give settled actual cases more weight than settled hypothetical
cases, or we may give them equal weight. The doctrine of precedent in law gives
settled actual cases more weight than settled hypothetical cases, though usually
only when the settled cases are those of the same court or higher courts of the
same jurisdiction; actual cases of lower courts or courts of other jurisdictions may
be treated on a par with settled hypothetical cases. However, as we shall see, this
difference in weight may only be significant under certain circumstances.
The fourth stage is the heart of the deliberative process. At this stage we engage
in all-out theorizing, looking for hypotheses which account for the resolutions of
issues we found at stage three. That is, we are trying to formulate hypotheses
about the relationships between the conflicting reasons under various different
circumstances present in the stage three cases, which account for those resolu-
tions. To this end we examine the stage three cases for distinctive circumstances or
dimensions which seem to enhance or diminish the weight of one of the conflict-
ing reasons in relation to the other. When we have formulated such an hypothesis,
we try to test it, by going back to stage three and looking for further settled cases in
which the same reasons apply and in which the circumstances identified by the
hypothesis are present. We thus go back and forth between stages three and four,
looking for settled actual and hypothetical cases that help us to refine our
hypotheses about the relationships between the conflicting reasons in various
circumstances.
Finally, at the fifth stage, we work out the consequences of the best hypothesis we
have arrived at for the original case at issue. That is, we apply that hypothesis about
the relationships between the applicable reasons to the circumstances present in the
case at issue. This hypothesis is a partial specification of a coherence function, which
takes us from the rankings of alternatives involving various circumstances or dimen-
sions by the conflicting reasons to an all-things-considered ranking.
This characterization of deliberation can be pictured in terms of a deliberative
matrix. The data gathered at stage three can be represented as follows, where in each
row, alternatives are ranked above or below one another by the applicable reasons.
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 73
Table 4.1.: The deliberative matrix
Resolution, all-things-
Reason X Reason Y considered
I present the matrix with only two conflicting reasons, X and Y, merely for
convenience; there is no restriction on the number of reasons that may be repre-
sented. (Indeed, multi-dimensional conflicts give rise to interesting theoretical
questions.)⁴ During stage four the alternatives are analysed and more fully char-
acterized in terms of various circumstances and dimensions of the cases which
may help to explain their resolution. These circumstances may be represented
by adding propositions, p, q, etc, to the alternatives in each row. The content of
such a proposition may be quantitative or non-quantitative. A hypothesis
would then take the form: “Reason X tends to outweigh Reason Y when it is the
case that p, while Reason Y tends to outweigh Reason X when it is the case that
q; when it is the case that both p and q, but not r, Reason X has more weight, but
when r is present as well, Reason Y has more weight,” and so on.⁵
⁴ Which I pursue in NATIONAL REASONS, supra note 2, chapters 12 and 13.
⁵ This schematization, applied to legal deliberation, may be compared to that employed by the
programme HYPO, developed by Edwina Rissland and her student Kevin Ashley, and discussed in a
Harvard Law School seminar on artificial intelligence and legal reasoning, conducted by Rissland
Autumn Term 1987. See K. D. Ashley, Modelling Legal Argument: Reasoning with Cases and
Hypotheticals, PhD dissertation, 1987, University of Massachusetts, Dept of Computer and
Information Science. While there are many differences in detail between the two approaches, I do
not believe there is any incompatibility in principle between them. The role of HYPO’s “dimen-
sions” is similar to the role of my propositions p, q, etc in the analysis of actual and hypothetical set-
tled cases at stage four. Perhaps I try to say a bit more than Rissland and Ashley do about the role of
hypotheticals in reaching legal conclusions, in that the answers to hypothetical questions feed back
into the resolution of the case at issue via the coherence function, but again I do not believe that
what I say is incompatible with their approach. Perhaps the most striking difference is that over
whether to use favourableness to conflicting legal doctrines or favourableness to plaintiff as opposed
to defendant, as the basic means of organizing the data. Often, within a narrowly limited area of the
law, such as trade secrets law, plaintiffs will typically represent one legal doctrine, and defendants
another, so that the two approaches are in principle quite similar. However, the doctrine-oriented
rather than party-oriented method of organization may have advantages when one comes to gener-
alize beyond a narrow limited area of the law, so that plaintiff and defendant no longer typically
74 S. L. Hurley
Two points of clarification may be helpful. First, I do not in this paper aim to
give a full account of what is distinctive about legal reasoning in particular, but
rather to consider what follows about legal reasoning from the fact that it has the
general features of practical reasoning, understood along coherentist lines. My
examples in the next section are intended to illustrate the application of the
coherentist account of practical reasoning in general to legal problems, rather
than to illuminate what is distinctive about legal reasoning in particular. I will go
on to consider the distinctively legal doctrine of precedent in the context set by a
view of legal reasoning as having the general features of coherentist practical
reasoning. This is important to understand for purposes of my discussion below
of the problem of intervening cases, since my eventual response to Kress in
Sections VII and VIII turns on the features that legal reasoning shares with prac-
tical reason in general, on a coherentist view of it, with respect to the role of
hypothetical cases. Such general features of coherentist practical reasoning limit
the effects of the distinctively legal doctrine of precedent in giving rise to inter-
vening case retroactivity, and thus illuminate the source of the problem. But I
would certainly not claim that the generally coherentist character of legal reason-
ing as a kind of practical reasoning plus the features of precedent I consider
provide a full account of what is distinctive about legal reasoning in particular;
this is not my purpose. Secondly, I would expect the account and illustrations of
practical reasoning to be controversial to the extent they represent a kind of
deliberative rationality with respect to conflicting ends, values or reasons, the
possibility of which has often been denied, for example, in favour of a view of
practical reasoning as exclusively instrumental, or in favour of more radically
sceptical or nihilistic views about practical rationality (in the legal context, con-
sider certain views associated with the critical legal studies movement, or par-
odies thereof ). However, I cannot join these issues here.
I have elsewhere considered in detail and at length a legal illustration of this gen-
eral account of practical reasoning, the stages of deliberation, and the deliberative
matrix. That discussion involved deliberation about the relationships between the
conflicting legal doctrines of estoppel and of consideration in cases now usually
represent particular legal doctrines. By organizing the cases according to legal doctrines directly
rather than by plaintiffs’ and defendants’ positions, one may hope to keep theoretical score as one
moves from one area of law to another in which the same doctrines apply, and to bring insights
about the relationships between legal doctrines from one area to the next.
Of course, different ways of perceiving what legal doctrines apply will yield different analyses, but
that is the way the law is, and an analysis which reflects this relativity of conclusion to starting point
may be illuminating. Moreover, we can in principle start with as many different legal doctrines as we
think may be relevant; again, there is no need to restrict the number of reasons weighed against one
another by the coherence function to two.
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 75
covered by the doctrine of promissory estoppel.⁶ I will not here give another
lengthy and detailed illustration, but rather will give several sketchy illustrations.
I hope in the former discussion to have persuaded readers that my account can be
made to work in detail. In this discussion I rather aim to persuade readers that the
account applies readily and intuitively in a wide range of cases. Accordingly I shall
not work out the details of my applications here, but shall merely briefly indicate
how the framework of my account would fit the examples.
Let us begin with the case of California v. Carney.⁷ In Carney, Fourth
Amendment issues were raised by a warrantless police search of a motor home,
parked in a downtown San Diego parking lot. The police had reason to believe
that Carney, the owner of the motor home, was exchanging marijuana for sex
acts. They observed a young boy enter the motor home and leave again an hour
and a quarter later. On questioning by the police, the boy said that such an
exchange had just occurred. The police then knocked on the door, and when
Carney came out they entered the motor home without a warrant and found
marijuana. A further search of the vehicle at the police station revealed more
marijuana, in cupboards and in the refrigerator. The parking lot where the war-
rantless search occurred was a short distance from a courthouse where a warrant
could easily have been obtained.
The case and its oral argument, rich in hypothetical cases, have been analysed
by Edwina Rissland to illustrate the idea of a “dimension,” which is used by the
case-based reasoning programme HYPO to generate hypothetical cases.⁸ My
treatment of the case essentially adapts her analysis to my framework, and illus-
trates, I believe, the compatibility of my framework and the notions of a deliber-
ate matrix and a coherence function, with Rissland’s dimension-based analysis.
As she points out, Carney is a case in which there is a conflict between a citizen’s
expectations of privacy, protected by the Fourth Amendment’s prohibition of
unreasonable searches and seizures, and the responsibilities and desires of the
police to investigate and control drug use and other prohibited activities. Thus,
the first row of our matrix for the case at issue involves at least two kinds of legal
reasons: I shall refer to them as reasons of Privacy, and reasons of the Police
Power. The alternatives in the case at issue are to allow or to disallow the warrant-
less search of the motor home in Carney under the Fourth Amendment. Reasons
of Privacy would favour disallowing the search, while reasons of the Police Power
would favour allowing it. We want to discover how reasons of Privacy and
reasons of the Police Power are related to one another with respect to warrantless
searches. Settled actual cases at the next several rows of the matrix tell us that
reasons of Privacy are augmented relative to those of the Police Power in circum-
stances in which the warrantless search at issue is of someone’s home; if we sum
In the taxi licence hypothetical, men and women would not be similarly situated,
owing to their differing legally imposed abilities, i.e. their differing abilities to
enrol in the course. But here it is clearly absurd to suppose that this prior discrim-
ination, unscrutinized, could provide a justification for further discrimination in
the form of a statutory classification requiring only women to pass the course in
order to get a licence. Thus the hypothetical case provides a counter-example to
the plurality’s hypothesis. The implication of the dissenting opinion is that the
embedded distinction must itself be scrutinized, and not merely taken as given. In
Parham, the embedded distinction was one with respect to the ability to file papers
to legitimize: only men were able to do so. It is hard to see how a rule making it
impossible for women to file papers to legitimize children serves either the state
interest in promoting the legitimate family unit or in avoiding proof of paternity
issues. Permitting women to file as well as men would have no adverse effects
whatsoever on either of these state interests.
The dissent goes on to appeal to another counter-example, this time a type of
actual rather than hypothetical case, to the hypothesis that reasons of Legitimacy
outweigh those of Nondiscrimination if allowing members of one class but not
another to sue for wrongful death serves the state interest in promoting the
integrity of the legitimate family unit. The dissent points out that unmarried
mothers and fathers who file to legitimize but remain unmarried defy the integrity
of the legitimate family unit, just as do fathers who fail to file, but the former are
allowed to sue for wrongful death while the latter are not.
In Craig v. Boren, the question was whether a statute prohibiting the sale of
weakly alcoholic beer to males under 21 and females under 18 constituted denial
to males aged 18 to 21 of equal protection of the law. On behalf of the statute it
was urged that statistical evidence about the relative tendencies of males and
females aged 18 to 21 to drink and drive supported the gender line. Thus we have
a conflict between reasons of Nondiscrimination and the state interest in
Preventing Drunk Driving. The Court rejects the hypothesis that reasons of
Nondiscrimination can be overcome by the interest in Preventing Drunk Driving
when the latter is served by “statistically measured but loose-fitting generalities
concerning the drinking tendencies of aggregate groups.” In doing so it appeals to
hypothetical variations on the Craig v. Boren statute involving statistically
supported ethnic or racial lines instead of gender lines aimed at alcohol regulation.
The assumption made is that such ethnic or racial lines would not be acceptable,
despite statistical support, and that reasons of Nondiscrimination would predom-
inate in such cases: “In fact, social science studies that have uncovered quantifiable
differences in drinking tendencies dividing along both racial and ethnic lines
strongly suggest the need for application of the Equal Protection Clause in
preventing discriminatory treatment that almost certainly would be perceived as
invidious.” The Court illustrates its comments with reference to statistical
evidence to the effect that Jews, Italian Catholics, and black teenagers tend not to
be problem drinkers, in contrast to whites and North American Indians.
80 S. L. Hurley
Finally, consider the uses of hypothetical and actual cases in ethical argument,
as illustrated by the debate between Stephen Pepper and David Luban over
whether lawyers in an adversary system should help their clients to do legal but
unethical acts. Pepper argues that under many circumstances the answer is “yes.”
He argues roughly as follows. We hold the value of individual autonomy to be
more important than getting people to do the ethically right act in a wide range
of cases; for example, we allow that people should have the legal power to disin-
herit a child for marrying outside the faith, even though we may agree that it
would be wrong to do so. Individual autonomy in our complex society requires,
in many cases, legal assistance; only with the help of lawyers can people, in many
circumstances, be “first class citizens.” Therefore lawyers should give their clients
the legal help required for individual autonomy even when it permits them to do
unethical acts.
Luban replies by arguing that, while it is true that, since exercising autonomy is
good, helping people exercise autonomy is good, this is only half the story. “The
other half is that since doing bad things is bad, helping people do bad things is
bad. The two factors must be weighed against each other, and this Pepper does not
do.” That is, Pepper’s general hypothesis that when helping someone to do a legal
but unethical act is favoured by reasons of autonomy, reasons of autonomy
prevail, is too crude. Luban appeals to an analogous hypothetical case to defeat the
unqualified hypothesis:
Compare this case: The automobile, by making it easier to get around, increases human
autonomy; hence, other things equal, it is morally good to repair the car of someone who is
unable by himself to get it to run. But such considerations can hardly be invoked to defend
the morality of fixing the getaway car of an armed robber, assuming that you know in
advance what the purpose of the car is. The moral wrong of assisting the robber outweighs
the abstract moral goodness of augmenting the robber’s autonomy.¹⁰
Not only may reasons of autonomy sometimes be outweighed by the wrongness of
the act in question, but even if the balance of reasons favours allowing the agent to
do the unethical act himself, it does not necessarily follow that it will also favour
helping him to do it. The balance between autonomy and conflicting reasons may
be struck differently in different circumstances, i.e. with respect to omitting to
prevent as opposed to positively aiding.
Another argument Pepper makes is that allowing lawyers to weigh the wrong-
ness of acts and thus act as screens to filter out certain legally permissible acts is to
submit individuals to “rule by an oligarchy of lawyers.”¹¹ The implication of the
term “oligarchy” is that such weighing and screening by lawyers would constitute
an elitist centralization of ethical decision-making highly threatening to the
value of individual autonomy, and that, when this would be the result, reasons of
autonomy should prevail. Luban offers a counter-example to this implied
hypothesis:
. . . there is no oligarchy of lawyers, actual or potential, to worry about. An oligarchy is a
group of people ruling in concert, whereas lawyers who refuse to execute projects to which
they object on moral grounds will do so as individuals, without deliberating collectively
with other lawyers. The worry about a hidden Central Committee of lawyers evaporates
when we realize that the committee will never hold a meeting, and that its members don’t
even know they are on it. An analogy will clarify this. No doubt throughout history people
have often been dissuaded from undertaking immoral projects by the anger, threats, and
uncooperativeness of their spouses. It would scarcely make sense, however, to worry that
this amounts to subjecting autonomous action “to rule by an oligarchy of spouses.” There
is no oligarchy of spouses.
Luban seems to accept for the sake of argument that screening by a true Central
Committee might well be intolerable. But if weighing and screening by spouses does
not constitute an elitist centralization of ethical decision-making highly threatening
to the value of individual autonomy, it is not clear how this can be regarded as the
result when we substitute “lawyers” for “spouses.” Indeed, Luban suggests that infor-
mal social pressures are an essential complement to legal rules in regulating harmful
behaviour. (Note that I am not here endorsing Luban’s conclusions, but only using
his arguments to illustrate certain characteristic features of deliberation.)
The role of the settled cases appealed to in the above examples of deliberation is
analogous in some respects to the role of data in scientific theorizing. In both
areas, that is, one looks both for relevant data, or clear cases, and for generaliza-
tions that account for what seems to be clearly the case (though of course such
apparent clarity is not infallible in either area), and uses the latter generalizations
to make determinations about further cases. In neither area is the best account of
the data deductively entailed by the data. Nevertheless, in both areas the data in
some sense determines the best theory (or theories, in the case of a tie or moderate
degree of underdetermination of theory by data). The best theory (or theories—
I will hereafter omit the qualification, but it continues to apply) is some function
of the data, in the sense that if the best theory were other than what it is, the data
would have to be different in some way. This is just another way of
saying that situations that are relevantly similar in respect of data must be treated
consistently in theoretical respects, or, more briefly, that like cases should be
treated alike. With respect to legal deliberation, this general consistency require-
ment is that cases relevantly similar, in respect of applicable legal doctrines and
distinguishing circumstances, should be similarly resolved.
82 S. L. Hurley
Of course, the analogy should not be strained; some of the general roles of
ethical and legal deliberation and theorizing are very different from those of
scientific theorizing. Scientific theories are used to predict what will happen on the
basis of causal theories that account for what has happened in well-designed experi-
ments, and sometimes also for what it is thought would have happened under sig-
nificant counterfactual circumstances. The basis for scientific hypotheses are thus
experimental data and sometimes intuitions gathered in “thought experiments,”
such as Einstein’s famous thought experiments about flashlights emitting beams of
light in trains travelling at close to the speed of light. Scientific hypotheses generate
predictions which are then tested against the results of further experiments.
By contrast, ethical and legal deliberation can hardly be described as having the
role of predicting what will be done on the basis of causal theories. Rather, it has a
normative role: to give guidance in extending consistently to the case at issue a
series of settled ethical or legal judgments about what should be done when the
applicable ethical or legal reasons conflict. Its normative hypotheses thus aim to
account for clear resolutions of past cases in which the relevant reasons stood in
conflict, and also for clear resolutions of significant hypothetical cases, designed to
test the relationships between the conflicting reasons. Deliberative hypotheses are
used to generate not mere predictions of decisions and actions, but decisions and
actions themselves; hypotheses cannot be tested against the very decisions and
actions they generate. Rather, they are tested against cases, both actual and hypo-
thetical, in which the right answer about how a conflict of reasons should be
resolved is settled.¹²
Despite the differences between scientific, causal theorizing, and deliberative,
normative theorizing, it is important to recognize the way in which both kinds of
theorizing are responsible to the data to be explained. The requirement that the
sought-after hypothesis explains the data can be seen as the source of the deliber-
ative requirement of consistency, the general requirement that like cases be
treated alike. Some philosophers have regarded it as puzzling how one could hold
that both:
(1) the right answer about which alternative should be done is not entailed by
the nonevaluative facts about the alternatives (nonreductionism: what should be
done does not reduce to nonevaluative facts about the alternatives)
and:
(2) one must treat alike cases that are alike in respect of nonevaluative facts, so
that if there is a difference between two cases in respect of what should be done,
¹² I do not suggest that scientific, ethical or legal deliberation are to be understood instrumentally
rather than realistically; it is common ground between instrumentalism and realism that theoretical
propositions should be able to be used in practical roles, e.g. to predict, explain or guide. I am con-
cerned here to avoid overstating the analogy between the practical roles of scientific and deliberative
theorizing rather than to take a position on the further issues that divide instrumental and realistic
views of theories.
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 83
there must be some difference between them with respect to the nonevaluative
facts about the alternatives as well (supervenience: what should be done supervenes
on nonevaluative facts about the alternatives).
While there is no logical incompatibility between (1) and (2), the puzzlement
about how they can both hold can be expressed by asking: If the right answer is
not entailed by the nonevaluative facts, then what is the source of the require-
ment that cases alike in nonevaluative respects be treated alike?¹³ However,
recognition of the way in which right answers to questions about what should
be done reflects hypotheses that are required to explain the data about settled
cases provides a response to this puzzlement. The best theory about the data is
not entailed by—cannot be deduced from—the data. Nevertheless, it is essen-
tial to the notion of a theory responsible to data that the best theory, whatever
it may be, treats like cases alike. The source of this requirement is the essential
explanatory aspirations of theories: a theory the content of which varies inde-
pendently of the data it purports to account for to that extent does no explana-
tory work. This remains true even though the best theory is not entailed by
the data.¹⁴
Thus, the requirement that like cases be treated alike has its source in the
theoretical nature of judgments about what should be done when reasons conflict,
which is highlighted by coherence accounts. Moreover, the data to which theories
about what should be done are responsible are settled cases, both actual and
hypothetical. If in general the role of settled cases in deliberation is somewhat
analogous to that of experimental data in scientific theorizing, then the role of
hypothetical cases in particular may be regarded as somewhat analogous to that of
thought experiments.¹⁵ It is important for our understanding of the requirement
that like cases be treated alike that we include settled hypothetical cases, cases the
answer to which would be clear were they to arise, as well as settled actual cases
among the data to be explained. For reasons that will emerge in what follows, this
is particularly important in the case of legal deliberation, where the general
requirement that like cases be treated alike must be distinguished from the further
specific requirement imposed by the doctrine of precedent. My examples in the
previous section make clear that, since legal deliberation and argument often turn
not merely on settled actual cases but also on settled hypothetical cases, effective
legal reasoning often requires one to discover or construct revealing hypothetical
cases;¹⁶ a coherence account provides a framework for understanding the function
of hypothetical cases in legal reasoning. Hypothetical cases are not merely posed by
lawyers and judges, but answers to questions about how they should be resolved
are often taken for granted in a way which the argument of the case at issue
depends on. The answers to hypothetical cases may be implicitly assumed rather
than explicitly stated, but nevertheless they are often depended on in the reason-
ing of opinions, in a way that may be explicitly represented within a deliberative
matrix. This is to say that legal hypotheses are responsible to data about settled
hypothetical cases as well as settled actual cases; both are among the cases with
respect to which the requirement that like cases be treated alike must be under-
stood. Nevertheless, as we shall see, the doctrine of precedent imposes a further
constraint on legal deliberation in giving actual settled cases more weight than that
of hypothetical settled cases for purposes of determining what counts as treating
like cases alike.
latter is particularly influenced by characteristic features of the legal system in the United States,
such as the prominent role of the posing of “hypos” in Supreme Court oral argument, in legal
education, etc.
¹⁷ K. J. Kress, Legal Reasoning and Coherence Theories: Dworkin’s Rights Thesis, Retroactivity, and
the Linear Order of Decisions, 72 CAL L.R. 369, 380 (1984).
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 85
I shall refer to the problem Kress identifies as the problem of intervening cases.
Kress regards this as a particularly serious problem for Dworkin’s rights-oriented
version of a coherence account of legal reasoning, since Dworkin works his
account up in the course of criticizing Hart’s account for the scope it gives to
judicial discretion and for the retroactive applications of the law which judicial
discretion involves.
However, Kress regards the problem as generalizable: it applies to any coher-
ence account which is conservative in the sense that it adheres to the dominant
conception of precedent. According to the latter, legal truths depend in part on
prior legal decisions. The general form of the problem is that the best theory about
settled law may change between the time the events occurred and the time they are
litigated, owing to intervening legal decisions. “The mere historical fact of a prior
decision influences the decisions in later cases, and thus the law, because it
enlarges the settled law with which later decisions must cohere.”¹⁸ This is in effect
just to say that the prevalent conception of precedent gives more weight to settled
actual cases than to settled hypothetical cases for purposes of determining what
counts as treating like cases alike.
¹⁸ Id. at 400.
¹⁹ Id. at 386–387: “It is unlikely that the revised . . . theory could be developed in detail, or utilized
by judges if it could, for several reasons. First, the possibility of temporally extended events and trans-
actions raises difficult problems in determining the date of the law to be applied. These problems are
compounded if several related but separable transactions are being litigated and there are multiple
issues. The prospect of applying the law at different times to different but related aspects of a compli-
cated transaction raises unappealing complexity. Further and perhaps insuperable complexity arises if
it is possible to analyze the overall transaction in multiple ways into different temporal components.
Unless we can be sure that one temporal analysis will be superior to all others, we will need rules to
choose among the various analyses. More important, it is unclear what precedential effect should be
given to a decision that applies law from many time periods, law that by definition differs from the law
that would be applied to an event that occurred at that time of adjudication if litigated at that time.”
86 S. L. Hurley
See especially Kress’s note 77, commenting on the line of criminal procedure cases involving
prospective-only application. Kress distinguishes the “more common form” of prospective-only
application, which nevertheless applies intervening decisions to pending cases, from the more
extreme form that would be necessary to avoid ripple effect retroactivity, which would deny the “new”
rule to pending cases as well. For the “more common form,” see Linkletter v. Walker, 381 U.S. 618
(1965), which did apply the intervening decision to pending cases.
It may be objected to that Kress has not addressed the line of criminal procedure cases subsequent
to Linkletter which explicitly discuss the application of intervening decisions to pending cases. See
Stovall v. Denno, 388 U.S. 293 (1967); Desist v. United States, 394 U.S. 244 (1969), especially Justice
Harlan’s dissent; Shea v. Lousianna, 470 U.S. 51 (1985), especially Justice White’s dissent. The Court
divides over the problem of intervening cases, and moreover, seems to change its own position.
Stovall and Desist come down in favour of nonretroactivity by refusing to apply the intervening deci-
sions to pending cases in which the relevant events of police conduct occurred prior to the interven-
ing decisions. However, Justice Harlan’s dissent in Desist, favouring precedent over nonretroactivity,
becomes the Court’s position in Shea, where Justice White dissents, arguing on nonretroactivity
grounds. A nice self-referential problem of intervening cases about the problem of intervening cases,
the logic of which I will not even attempt to untangle!
In reply, it should be kept in mind that the degree to which the Court is willing to consider
and countenance intervening case retroactivity in the criminal procedure context, where
police reliance on earlier cases is in question, may well not generalize. Thus, an acceptable degree
of retroactivity with respect to police reliance, which cuts in favour of criminal defendants,
may not be acceptable in general, that is, where the intervening case might cut against
criminal defendants and undermine their reliance rather than police reliance, or where it might
change the positions of civil litigants. It would be interesting to develop an integrated view of
retroactivity doctrine within and without the criminal procedure context, and to try to isolate the
special effects of the criminal procedure context on retroactivity doctrine, but I cannot do
so here.
²⁰ Kress does allow for this type of view. Kress, supra note 17, at 386; he does, at 382, distinguish
judicial discretion from judicial creation of law.
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 87
²¹ This tu quoque on behalf of coherence accounts seems to be borne out by the Court’s oscillation
between precedent and nonretroactivity in Stovall, Desist and Shea, supra note 19, where the issues do
not arise as a consequence of any particular theory of adjudication.
²² Kress, supra note 17, at 384.
88 S. L. Hurley
²³ This paper is not intended to address the problem of whether systematically wicked law is really
law; on this see, e.g., R. DWORKIN, LAW’S EMPIRE 102–108 (1986).
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 89
epistemological problem. Let us therefore, for the sake of argument, also put the
“not-so-bad” response aside.
with the set of actual cases. Not all actual cases are settled (some are problematic),
and not all settled cases are actual (some are hypothetical).²⁷
If the stronger requirement of adherence to precedent were not imposed on
legal reasoning in addition to the weaker elements of conservatism imposed by a
coherence account and shared with decision theory, no problem of intervening
cases would arise in law either. To see this, consider a revisionary conception of the
law as equally responsible in principle to both settled actual and settled hypothet-
ical cases, so that the change of a settled case’s status from hypothetical to actual
between occurrence of the events litigated and their adjudication cannot via
precedent change the law about the later case. Such a revisionary conception of
the law is compatible with a generally coherentist approach to practical reasoning,
but it omits the distinctively legal doctrine of precedent. Now, whether a case is
settled or not does not depend on whether it has actually been decided; a settled
case is equally settled whether its current status is actual or hypothetical, and
retroactivity does not arise in the way Kress envisages.
Kress considers the possibility that the law does not change purely in conse-
quence of legal decisions, but points out that this would be to purchase unchan-
ging right answers at the cost of dispensing with the doctrine of precedent. He
writes: “Judicial decisions change the settled law” and: “To deny that law and
legal rights change at all in response to new decisions is to deny that legal rights
are, at least in part, determined by settled law.”²⁸ While I think he is correct to
regard the denial of any change of law in response to new actual decisions as
giving up the doctrine of precedent, nevertheless, it is logically possible to hold
that legal rights are, at least in part, determined by settled law, without holding
that a change in a case’s status from hypothetical to actual is per se a change from
unsettled to settled. It is just this logical space that is occupied by the revisionary
conception of law we are now considering, which in effect does not incorporate
the doctrine of precedent as we know it. Of course, new legal decisions may
reflect extra-judicial changes in the settled law. But absent extra-judicial changes,
under the revisionary conception new legal decisions would not change settled
law, though they might change our awareness of it.
Kress further points out that, within Dworkin’s theory at least, “While at each
point in time, there are right answers to all or nearly all legal issues, the right
answer that is given may not be the same as that which would be given at another
point in time, in consequence of changes in institutional history.” However,
giving hypothetical and actual settled cases equal weight would not mean that the
law cannot develop and change, but merely that such developments and changes,
²⁷ Cf. Kress on the analogy between legal and scientific theorizing, id. at 392n, and on the charac-
ter of settled law, id. at 278. My use of the term “settled” here does not coincide with his, but I believe
that something like my use is essential to convey what is distinctive about coherentist views of prac-
tical reasoning, and of legal reasoning in so far as it is a species of practical reasoning.
²⁸ Id. at 380, 393.
92 S. L. Hurley
the judicial role is to discover the law, not to make it, changes in judicial perception
of the content of settled cases, whether actual or hypothetical, ought to reflect extra-
judicial legal developments, such as changes in social practices and customs with
constitutive bearing on the law,³⁰ or in legislative or administrative background.
Such extra-judicial developments put members of society on fair notice, and
changes in legal theory which reflect such intervening changes should in principle be
applied prospectively only.³¹ However, legislative and administrative changes
usually are applied prospectively only. Moreover, changes in social practices usually
occur gradually enough that worry about such a change intervening between the
time of the events litigated and their adjudication may often seem contrived and
artificial. Perhaps there are occasionally abrupt, revolutionary changes in social
practices, but they are surely unusual. Perhaps in these unusual cases changes in
settled hypothetical cases which reflect the change in social practice should in theory
be given effect prospectively only (although there may be practical difficulties in
identifying such cases and the time of the change of social practice involved). Such
exceptions would have a rationale in the extra-judicial source of the change, and
could be admitted without threatening the normal judicial practice to the contrary.
Thus, extra-judicial changes in law do not threaten my claim that the problem of
intervening cases does not arise from the coherentist character of legal reasoning per
se, but rather from the distinctive asymmetrical treatment of actual and hypothetical
cases by the doctrine of precedent in particular.
In summary, the purely coherentist revisionary conception of law as lacking the
stronger requirement, imposed by the doctrine of precedent, would support the
following argument. Either cases intervening between the occurrence of events and
precedent. I will briefly consider some cases to illustrate the point that status as
actual and status as settled do not in fact coincide. I will then go on to try to
sharpen the diagnosis of the intervening case retroactivity. I shall argue, largely
following suggestions made by Dworkin, that only actual intervening decisions
that are ex ante mistaken, or at least not uniquely correct (in cases of underdeter-
mination), but which the doctrine of precedent nevertheless presumptively
constitutes as judicially-initiated changes in the law, give rise to retroactivity.
Not all actually decided cases are settled; indeed, some actual cases, even some
that are settled, may be mistaken,³⁴ in virtue of their failure to cohere with other
settled, including actual, cases. Dependence on some actual cases is avoided, even
if they have not been explicitly overruled as mistaken, because they are highly
controversial, and/or considered uncertain, dubious, or poor authority. Moreover,
the doctrine of precedent may not treat actual cases of courts of other jurisdictions
as settled. An example of an intervening actual case which was nevertheless not
settled is that of Brown v. Porcher.³⁵ In Brown, the US Court of Appeals held that
the construal of a South Carolina statute to disqualify any claimant who voluntar-
ily left her most recent employment because of pregnancy violated a federal
statute providing that no person shall be denied unemployment compensation
under state law solely on the basis of pregnancy. Brown was decided in 1981; the
US Supreme Court denied certiorari in 1983. In 1980, however, events had
already occurred which gave rise to the closely related case on the same issue of
Wimberly v. Labor and Industrial Relations Commission, which went up on appeal
through the Missouri court system to the Missouri Supreme Court (in 1985), and
eventually reached the US Supreme Court (in 1987).³⁶ The Missouri Court of
Appeals had followed Brown, despite reservations concerning the soundness of its
reasoning; but the Missouri Supreme Court reversed, declaring that it had never
subscribed to the notion that Missouri state courts were bound to follow the deci-
sions of lower federal courts in construing federal statutes.³⁷ The Missouri
Supreme Court declined to follow Brown. “We do not mean to suggest that a
lower federal court’s construction of a federal statute is wholly irrelevant. The
courts of this state should ‘look respectfully to such opinions for such aid and
guidance as may be found therein’ . . . In some circumstances it may be appropri-
ate for a state court to defer to long established and widely accepted federal court
interpretations of federal statutes.” But it evidently felt that Brown was not a
settled case in this sense. The US Supreme Court eventually resolved Wimberly in
favour of the Missouri view and against Brown. But the point to be made here is
not that Brown was mistaken; perhaps it was correct. It is rather that Brown, the
intervening case, did not change the settled law because it was not a settled case,
from the perspective of the Missouri Supreme Court. Thus, whether or not Brown
was correct, the best theory about settled law, which should determine the
outcome in the similar case which comes to trial after Brown, was not altered by
the intervening case. If the result in Brown were to have been upheld as the correct
result, there would nevertheless have been no retroactive application of the
decision in the intervening case, since, as the Missouri Supreme Court implied, it
was not a settled case. Continuing uncertainty about the right answer is just that,
not retroactivity.
Furthermore, there are many settled hypothetical cases which are more deeply
entrenched and would be more difficult to justify regarding as mistaken than
many actual cases: we are lucky that such cases have remained hypothetical rather
than actual. They have not become actual, in some cases, because the flagrant
violations of rights they would involve luckily have not occurred in our commu-
nities. But they are nonetheless clearly settled for being hypothetical. A good
example is found in Justice Marshall’s eloquent dissent in the recent case of
United States v. Salerno and Cafaro. The majority had upheld a statute permitting
the denial of bail altogether in certain cases against Due Process and Excessive
Bail Clause challenges, on the grounds in part that the statute is a regulatory
rather than a punitive measure. Justice Marshall writes:
The ease with which the conclusion is reached suggests the worthlessness of the achieve-
ment. The major premise is that “[u]nless Congress expressly intended to impose
punitive restrictions, the punitive/regulatory distinction turns on ‘whether an alternative
purpose to which [the restriction] may rationally be connected is assignable for it, and
whether it appears excessive in relation to the alternative purpose assigned [to it].’” The
majority finds that “Congress did not formulate the pretrial detention provisions as pun-
ishment for dangerous individuals”, but instead was pursuing the “legitimate regulatory
goal” of “preventing danger to the community” . . . Concluding that pretrial detention is
not an excessive solution to the problem of preventing danger to the community, the
majority thus finds that no substantive element of the guarantee of due process invali-
dates the statute.
Justice Marshall produces a settled hypothetical case as a counter-example to the
majority’s hypothesis about the punitive/regulatory distinction. He goes on:
This argument does not demonstrate the conclusion it purports to justify. Let us apply
the majority’s reasoning to a similar, hypothetical case. After investigation, Congress
determines (not unrealistically) that a large proportion of violent crime is perpetrated by
persons who are unemployed. It also determines, equally realistically, that much violent
crime is committed at night. From amongst the panoply of “potential solutions”,
Congress chooses a statute which permits, after judicial proceedings, the imposition of a
dusk-to-dawn curfew on anyone who is unemployed. Since this is not a measure enacted
for the purpose of punishing the unemployed, and since the majority finds that prevent-
ing danger to the community is a legitimate regulatory goal, the curfew statute would,
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 97
according to the majority’s analysis, be a mere “regulatory” detention statute, entirely
compatible with the substantive components of the Due Process Clause.³⁸
He regards the absurdity of this conclusion as a settled aspect of the law, and
nonetheless settled for the fact that the case envisaged is merely hypothetical. Here
is a settled hypothetical case that is more entrenched, and less likely to be regarded
as mistaken by the best legal theory, than many actual cases.
We have considered two cases in which the dissenting opinions appeal persua-
sively to hypothetical cases to defeat hypotheses on which the majority opinion
seems to turn, Parham and Salerno. Suppose for the sake of argument that these
decisions were mistaken up to the time of the decision, or ex ante mistaken.
Nevertheless the doctrine of precedent tells us we cannot assume them to be
ex post mistaken; we cannot infer an ex post mistake from an ex ante mistake
because the fact of the actual decision may change the law. It is possible that an
ex ante mistake is so serious that the enormity of the mistake outweighs its prece-
dential force, and it remains a mistake even ex post; but the mere fact of the deci-
sion has loaded the balance against this possibility. A mistake must be more
serious, must be more deeply incoherent with the settled law, including hypothet-
ical as well as actual cases, to be an ex post mistake than to be an ex ante mistake;
the difference is a matter of degree, a matter of how much must be uprooted to
accommodate the law to the mistake.
We see then that the doctrine of precedent permits determinately ex ante mis-
taken decisions to change the law;³⁹ such decisions, as intervening cases, may give
rise to retroactivity. Of course, the doctrine of precedent is not addressed to mis-
takes in particular; it does not perversely dignify ex ante mistaken actual decisions
as opposed to ex ante correct actual decisions by presumptively constituting only
the former as law henceforward. But precedential force is not needed to constitute
an ex ante correct decision as correct ex post; in this respect it is redundant (though
of course it may feature non-redundantly in the reasoning from previous prece-
dents that makes the decision ex ante correct). No special method of transition
between ex ante standing and ex post standing is needed in the case of correct deci-
sions; precedent has no law-changing work to do in these cases. Since resolutions
that are ex ante correct all things considered do not conflict with one another to
begin with, increasing the weight of a correct settled case as it changes from hypo-
thetical to actual makes no difference. Of course, courts may not know whether
the actual cases they defer to as having precedential force were ex ante mistaken or
not. Nevertheless, we may issue a challenge: how, on coherentist assumptions,
³⁸ U S v. Salerno, 107 SCt 2095, 2107–2108 (1987), 481 U.S. 739, 758–759 (1987).
³⁹ Cf. Kress’s claim, supra note 17, at 394, that “wholesale and final determination of the truth or
falsity of all possible legal propositions leaves no room for the operation of the dominant notion of
precedent.”
98 S. L. Hurley
could the precedential force of a decision, other than one reflecting extra-judicial
legal developments, change the law itself, as opposed to our beliefs about it, if that
decision were ex ante correct?
This in effect is Dworkin’s response to the problem of intervening cases. He
argues as follows.⁴⁰ He does consider that integrity requires us to give weight to
the fact that a case was actually decided so, even if it was decided wrongly. Either
an intervening case is wrongly or rightly decided. Suppose it is wrongly decided.
Then it will indeed change the law retroactively, and for the worse, since it was
wrongly decided. That is one reason it is so important for judges to reach the right
answer! We can accept that there is objectionable retroactivity in this case, but that
is not a consequence of the coherentist account of adjudication, or of the doctrine
of precedent, but rather of the fact that the wrong answer was reached. Suppose,
on the other hand, that the intervening case was rightly decided; then we are
presented with a challenge. How could a correct decision in an intervening case
make for retroactive change of the law?⁴¹ How could the affirmation of a correct
hypothesis itself change hypotheses in subsequent cases from right to wrong or
vice versa? It might make the correct answers to later cases more evident or
predictable, but this is not what Kress needs for his claim; retroactivity involves a
change in the law, not merely a change in our beliefs about the law.
For the moment put aside the possibility, which I will return to, that the correct
decision (not merely our beliefs about it) was ex ante underdetermined, rather
⁴⁰ In discussion.
⁴¹ Kress gives an example, in which the force of precedent is conceived in a mechanical way to
involve counting the number of steps required for privity of contract, which he claims is a paradigm
case of coherentist reasoning. See id. at 382–383. However, it can be dismissed as not an example of
Dworkinian, or more generally, coherentist reasoning at all since it does not involve consideration of
the reasons or principles that support particular results.
Some implicit support is founded in Supreme Court cases for Dworkin’s view that a correct deci-
sion in an intervening case does not change the law. In the criminal procedure context, see in particu-
lar the dissents by Justice Harland and Justice Fortas in Desist, supra note 19, Justice Harlan writes:
“ . . . If a ‘new’ constitutional doctrine is truly right, we should not reverse lower courts which have
accepted it; nor should we affirm those which have rejected the very arguments we have embraced.
Anything else would belie the truism that it is the task of this Court, like that of any other, to do jus-
tice to each litigant on the merits of his own case. It is only if each of our decisions can be justified in
terms of this fundamental premise that they may properly be considered the legitimate products of a
court of law, rather than the commands of a super-legislature.” See also H. Schwartz, Retroactivity,
Reliability and Due Process, 33 U. CHI. L. REV. 719, 748–749 (1966). In Hanover Shoe v. United Shoe
Machinery Corp, 392 U.S. 481 (1968), an antitrust case, the US Supreme Court discussed the inter-
vening case issue explicitly writing: “The theory of the Court of Appeals seems to have been that
when a party has significantly relied upon a clear and established doctrine, and the retrospective
application of a newly declared doctrine would upset that justifiable reliance to his substantial injury,
considerations of justice and fairness require that the new rule apply prospectively only.” The
Supreme Court, however, did not find before it a situation in which there was a clearly declared judi-
cial doctrine upon which a party had relied and which was overruled in favour of a new rule. The
intervening cases in question did not indicate that the issues they decided were novel, or that they
involved a departure from an earlier line of case or the need for innovative principles. “Whatever
development in antitrust law was brought about was based to a great extent on existing authorities
and was an extension of doctrines which had been growing and developing over the years.” Id. at
496–499.
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 99
be settled in accord with the correct decision. Could this change in belief, absent
a change in the law, be sufficient to change what the law is in a subsequent case?
Whatever considerations they were in virtue of which the intervening decision
was correct still obtain, and, to the extent they ever applied to the subsequent
case, apply equally after the intervening case is decided. How could the mere
addition of true beliefs about these unchanged considerations change the correct
decision in the subsequent case, as opposed to making it more evident? On the
other hand, beliefs about the law may have been mistaken before the intervening
case, and they may have changed to accord with the correct decision in the case.
How could this change from false to true beliefs about the intervening case
change the law, as opposed to beliefs about it, in the subsequent case? It does not
help to point out that according to a coherence account not too many settled
cases can be mistaken, because we are now supposing the prior beliefs were false;
if they were true, we are back to case three above, and there is no retroactivity.
Whatever considerations they were in virtue of which the prior beliefs about the
hypothetical version of the intervening case were false would apply also to the
subsequent case, to the extent relevant. If we continue to assume that the law in
the subsequent case was either determinately one thing or another at each point,
and no change of law with respect to the intervening case was brought about by
its correct decision, the challenge on coherentist assumptions still stands: how
could a decision in the subsequent case be changed from correct to mistaken or
vice versa merely as a result of a change in beliefs about the law in the intervening
case from false to true, given no change in the law itself with respect to that case?
Note that it is incorrect to object here that the determinacy assumption leaves no
room for the operation of precedent, since we have seen that it does leave room
for it in cases of mistaken decisions. What is at issue is whether precedent can
make a difference given correct intervening decisions.
At this point we should consider the consequences of suspending the assump-
tion of determinacy. If we allow that prior to a decision the right answer (not
merely beliefs about it) may be underdetermined, then precedent may make a
difference not just as a result of ex ante mistake, but also as a result of resolving
ex ante underdetermination. Dworkin, of course, would resist the possibility of
underdetermination in arguing for his right answer thesis, so it does not, in the
absence of an independent argument against the right answer determinacy thesis,
help Kress make a case against Dworkin in particular. But some coherentists
might accept the possibility of underdetermination, so it is relevant to the
general discussion with respect to coherentism.
Thus, from a theoretical point of view at least, intervening case retroactivity
can be laid at the feet, not of coherentist legal reasoning, or even of the doctrine
of precedent, but rather of mistaken decisions, and perhaps also of underdeter-
mination of the law, to the extent a given version of coherentism admits this
possibility. That legal mistakes are unfair to people is hardly news; the theoretical
novelty and interest of the problem of intervening cases thus looks to diminish to
Coherence, Hypothetical Cases, and Precedent 101
the extent mistakes are its source. Moreover, the use of the problem as a means of
criticizing Dworkin’s version of coherentism in particular is limited by his
rejection of the possibility of underdetermination. The general shape of my
response to Kress with respect to the problem of intervening cases has been to
draw out the consequences of a coherentist view of practical reasoning in general
for legal reasoning and the doctrine of precedent in particular, which conse-
quences limit intervening case retroactivity. The argument has proceeded by
presenting a challenge to show how, given the role of hypothetical cases within
coherentist views of practical reasoning, a correct, as opposed to ex ante mistaken or
indeterminate, intervening case could give rise to retroactivity. Of course, we may
reject coherentist views and their consequences with respect to the doctrine of
precedent altogether, but then we depart from Kress’s subject matter. Note that
my aim has not been to dispute the interest of the retroactivity problem which
Kress has highlighted, but rather his conception of coherentism in general and
Dworkin’s version thereof in particular as the proper targets of the argument.
In pursuing my course of argument, however, I have at several points had to put
considerable weight on the distinction between changes in the law and changes in
our beliefs about the law in particular cases. Coherentism admits this theoretical
distinction on a case-by-case basis, even though it ties the right answers and beliefs
about them together globally in the way indicated in Section VII above, in that not
too many settled cases can be mistaken. However, perhaps from a more pragmatic
point of view, one more concerned with matters of notice and predictability,
which may be closer to that of litigants and potential litigants, this distinction has
been strained even so. Perhaps it is from this more pragmatic point of view that a
distinctive problem about intervening cases arises.
5
Integrity and Stare Decisis
Scott Hershovitz*
Many think that stare decisis binds even the highest court in a jurisdiction to
follow precedents that were decided incorrectly. Indeed, the view is commonly
held by legal scholars¹ and judges² alike. But if that is what stare decisis really
requires, it is puzzling. What could justify a principle that requires courts to make
the same mistakes over and over again? Surely a better principle (one that most of
us endorse) is that people should own up to their mistakes and seek not to repeat
them. Could legal reasoning really be so different from everyday reasoning that
principle requires courts to make mistakes repeatedly rather than correct them?
We need to clarify the question before we can answer it. There are two varieties
of stare decisis—horizontal and vertical. Vertical stare decisis requires that lower
courts follow the decisions of higher courts. Horizontal stare decisis requires that a
court follow its own precedents. Vertical stare decisis is less mysterious than hori-
zontal. The deference lower courts show to higher courts facilitates coordination
among judges, and it has the potential to improve judicial decision making to the
extent that higher court judges have greater expertise than lower court judges.
Neither coordination nor expertise, however, can explain the practice of a court
considering itself bound by its own precedents. This essay explores the mystery of
horizontal stare decisis. For ease of exposition, I shall use “stare decisis” to refer to
horizontal stare decisis.
The view that stare decisis condemns courts to repeat their mistakes neither fits
nor justifies our legal practice. Fit is problematic because, with some regularity,
* Thanks to Jules Coleman, William Fetcher, Lewis Kornhauser, Scott Sharpiro, Seana Shiffrin,
and Nicos Stavropouls for helpful comments and conversations.
¹ See, e.g., L. Kornhauser, An Economic Perspective on Stare Decisis, 65 Chi.-Kent L.Rev. 63, 65
(1989) (describing stare decisis as “a practice that, paradoxically, demands that a court adhere to a
prior decision it considers wrong”); L. Alexander, Constrained by Precedent, 63 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1, 4
(1989) (“I shall focus on those situations . . . in which a subsequent court believes that, though a pre-
vious case was decided incorrectly, it must, nevertheless . . . decide the case confronting it in a man-
ner that it otherwise believes is incorrect”).
² “[T]here is nothing to do except stand by the errors of our brethren of the week before, whether
we relish them or not.” B. Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process 150 (1921).
Many investigations of stare decisis ask some version of the question, “What justi-
fies adherence to a decision known to be wrong?”³ The canonical expression of the
principle—stare decisis et not quieta movere—does not, on its face, require follow-
ing decisions known to be wrong. The Latin means “to stand by things decided,
and not to disturb settled points.”⁴ Of course, it is reasonable to assume that some
things that have been decided were decided incorrectly. So stare decisis will, on
occasion, require courts to conform to incorrectly decided precedents.
This observation, however, is insufficient to motivate the idea that to justify stare
decisis we need to explain why courts should adhere to precedents they regard as
wrongly decided. After all, by the same implication, the canonical formulation also
demands that courts follow precedents they regard as correct. Indeed, it demands
that courts follow settled points of law without reference to the correctness of the
decisions that settled them. So it is somewhat of a puzzle why those investigating
stare decisis tend to ask what justifies following incorrectly decided precedents
rather than, say, what justifies adhering to a decision irrespective of its merit.
³ See e.g., J. Macey, The Internal and External Costs and Benefits of Stare Decisis, 65 CHI.-KENT
L. REV. 93, 94 (1989) (“Professor Kornhauser approaches the issue of stare decisis by pondering the
question of what justifies adherence to a prior legal decision known to be wrong”) (discussing
Kornhauser, supra note 1); Alexander, supra note 1, at 4.
⁴ BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY (8th ed., 2004).
Integrity and Stare Decisis 105
The answer, I think, lies in a particular view many have of stare decisis. Richard
Fallon expresses the view as follows:
Because a court that believes a prior decision to have been correct can always reaffirm the cor-
rectness of its ruling without reliance on its precedential status, the force of the doctrine of
stare decisis lies in its capacity to perpetuate what was once judicial error or to forestall
inquiry into the possibility of legal error.⁵
Fallon actually expresses two views of stare decisis in this passage. The first is
that the force of stare decisis “lies in its capacity to perpetuate what was once judi-
cial error.” The second is that the force of stare decisis lies in its capacity to “fore-
stall inquiry into the possibility of legal error.” The first view is the one that is of
immediate interest.
The view that the force of stare decisis “lies in its capacity to perpetuate what was
once judicial error” is a common one. In response to a litigant who argued that a
precedent should be overturned because it was incorrect, Judge Posner recently
opined that stare decisis would be “out the window” if the incorrectness of a deci-
sion was a sufficient ground for overruling it.⁶ According to Posner, “no doctrine of
deference to precedent is needed to induce a court to follow the precedents that it
agrees with; a court has no incentive to overrule them even if it is completely free to
do so.”⁷ On this view, stare decisis has no force—does not make a difference—
insofar as it requires courts to follow correctly decided precedents. It is only when
stare decisis requires courts to follow incorrectly decided precedents that it makes a
difference to judicial reasoning. If this is right, to justify stare decisis, we would
need to justify a practice of following incorrectly decided precedents.
The structure of this argument will be familiar to students of jurisprudence.
Some argue that legitimate authorities are incapable of making a difference in
what their subjects ought to do. Either an authority directs a subject to do some-
thing she ought to do anyway, in which case the directive makes no difference in
the subject’s normative situation, or the authority directs a subject to do some-
thing she ought not to do. On the assumption that authorities that direct people
to do things they ought not to do are illegitimate, it appears that legitimate
authorities can make no difference in what their subjects ought to do. This claim
is known as the no difference thesis.⁸ Proponents of the no difference thesis are apt
to hold the view that the normative force of an authority lies in its capacity to bind
people to do things they ought not to do.
⁵ R. H. Fallon, Jr., Legitimacy and the Constitution, 118 HARV. L. REV. 1787, 1823 n.3 (2005)
(citing Michael Stokes Paulsen, Abrogating Stare Decisis by Statute: May Congress Remove the
Precedential Effect of Roe and Casey?, 109 YALE L.J. 1535, 1538 n.8 (2000) (“The essence of the
doctrine [of stare decisis] . . . is adherence to earlier decisions, in subsequent cases . . . even though
the court in the subsequent case would be prepared to say, based on other interpretive criteria, that
the precedent decision’s interpretation of law is wrong”)).
⁶ Tate v. Showboat Casino Marina Partnership, 431 F.3d 580, 582 (7th Cir 2005).
⁷ Id. at 582–583.
⁸ See J. RAZ, THE MORALITY OF FREEDOM 48 (1986) (“The no difference thesis asserts that the
exercise of authority should make no difference to what its subjects ought to do, for it ought to direct them
to do what they ought to do in any event”).
106 Scott Hershovitz
The most important problem with the no difference thesis is that sometimes
what a subject ought to do is underdetermined by the reasons she has. For example,
drivers have a reason to drive on the same side of the road as everyone else, but no
particular reason to drive on the left or right. An authority can make a difference by
giving drivers a reason to drive on the right, say, without requiring drivers to do
anything they ought not to do.⁹
The argument that stare decisis only makes a difference when it requires courts
to follow incorrectly decided precedents suffers from a similar defect. Stare decisis
can make a difference by requiring courts to follow precedents that were neither
correct nor incorrect when decided. Some dispute that there are such cases, but
they are a logical possibility if not a legal one. If a particular precedent represents
merely one among a number of permissible decisions that an earlier court could
have selected, writing, as it were, on a blank slate, then a principle requiring a later
court to follow that precedent makes a difference without demanding that the
court follow a precedent that was decided incorrectly.
Another problem with the view that the force of stare decisis lies in its capacity
to perpetuate judicial error is that it construes too narrowly the impact stare deci-
sis can have on the outcome of cases. Fallon points out that a court following a
precedent it regards as correctly decided can reach the same result without follow-
ing the precedent. At most, this supports the view that stare decisis makes no dif-
ference in what a court ought to decide (though we have just seen that even this is
not true). But even when a case is governed by a correctly decided precedent, stare
decisis may well make a difference to what the court considering it actually
decides. Stare decisis, after all, makes the later court more likely to read the earlier,
correctly decided precedent, and doing so may save that court from making errors
of its own.
The upshot is that the force of stare decisis does not lie in “its capacity to per-
petuate what was once judicial error.” Stare decisis can make a difference, even
when it requires adherence to correctly decided precedent. Thus, there is no rea-
son to think that to justify the practice of stare decisis, we need to justify the prac-
tice of following incorrectly decided precedents. We may need to justify following
incorrectly decided precedents as part of justifying the broader practice of simply
following precedent. However, if we start out by asking what justifies following
incorrectly decided precedents, we misconstrue the import of stare decisis and cut
ourselves off from the resources necessary to understand it.
II
better than our first, but it is also misleading in that we do not actually have a
practice of adhering to precedent without regard to merit. Courts in the United
States and (more recently) in the United Kingdom do, from time to time, over-
turn even long-standing precedent. Below, I shall argue that overturning prece-
dents is part and parcel of the practice of stare decisis, notwithstanding the fact
that when a precedent is overturned we often speak as if the demands of stare deci-
sis have been ignored or trumped. However, since much of the best work on stare
decisis sets out to explain why courts ought to follow precedent irrespective of
merit, we shall continue our inquiry into what might justify such a practice.
To justify adhering to judicial decisions irrespective of their merit, one needs to
pull off a challenging trick. One has to show both that judicial decisions are
deserving of deference as a class and that individual decisions deserve deference
even when a subsequent court believes that the earlier, precedential court made a
mistake. This is a difficult task, but it is not a task that we are unfamiliar with from
other contexts. To justify obeying an authority, one must pull off a similar trick.
Authorities provide merit-independent reasons for action.¹⁰ A mother can order
her daughter to play inside or outside. Her order provides a reason for her child to
act quite apart from its merit, quite apart from whether it would be better for the
child to play inside or out. This general truth is not without limits, of course.
A mother who orders her child to ingest arsenic greatly exceeds the scope of her
legitimate authority. But within limits, the merit of the order is irrelevant to the
question of whether it gives the child a reason to act. Every parent who has uttered
the words, “Because I said so” implicitly endorses this view of parental authority.
To explain when and why authoritative orders are deserving of deference,
Joseph Raz offers the normal justification thesis.¹¹ Roughly speaking, the normal
justification thesis holds that an authority is legitimate for a person if she will do a
better job of conforming to the reasons that apply to her by following the author-
ity’s orders than she would by following her own lights. Authorities can satisfy the
normal justification thesis through, among other things, special expertise, or the
ability to solve coordination problems. To illustrate: a doctor is an authority on
medical matters in virtue of her special knowledge; the state is an authority on
traffic matters in virtue of its ability to solve coordination problems.
When the normal justification thesis is satisfied, one has a reason to give an
authority’s orders deference as a class, as well as a reason not to deny deference
when one believes there is reason to doubt the merit of a particular order. If one
refused to follow the order of a legitimate authority whenever one believed that it
was in error, the advantage one would get from following the orders as a class
would be lost. Thus the normal justification thesis pulls off the trick when it
comes to authoritative orders—it justifies deference to authoritative orders as a
class, and deference to particular orders even when one has reason to believe they
are mistaken.
¹⁰ See J. Gardner, Legal Positivism: 51⁄2 Myths, 46 AM. J. JURIS. 199, 208–209 (2001).
¹¹ Raz, supra note 8, at 53. For a short introduction to Raz’s account of authority, see S.
Hershovitz, Legitimacy, Democracy, and Razian Authority, 9 LEGAL THEORY 201 (2003).
108 Scott Hershovitz
If we were interested in justifying vertical stare decisis, we could invoke the nor-
mal justification thesis. Higher courts are authorities for lower courts. The author-
ity is based on an ability to coordinate action, and perhaps (one might hope) on
expertise as well. Each lower court judge has reason to decide cases as most other
judges would decide them, and a practice of treating higher court cases as authori-
tative facilitates this aim. To the extent that higher court judges have superior
expertise to lower court judges (or even simply more time and resources to bring
to bear on a case), lower court deference to the ruling of higher courts will improve
lower court decision making.
Raz’s trick will not work for horizontal stare decisis, however. There is no reason
for the highest court in the land to believe that it will, on the whole, decide cases bet-
ter by conforming to its own previous decisions than it would by following its own
current lights. The coordination justification that works so well for lower courts has
no bearing.¹² Expertise cannot do the work either because later versions of a court
generally have more information available to them than earlier versions, and (again,
one hopes) members of roughly equal skill and knowledge.¹³ Thus, if the trick can
be pulled off for horizontal stare decisis, it has to be done some other way.
III
One common approach to justifying stare decisis is to argue that the practice is
efficient. Justice Cardozo took this tack, suggesting that “the labor of judges
would be increased almost to the breaking point if every past decision could be
reopened in every case.”¹⁴ Cardozo’s observation, if true, would be a premise in a
narrow argument for the efficiency of stare decisis, focusing on the conservation of
judicial resources.
One suspects that Cardozo is correct. If you always start with a blank canvas,
you spend a lot of time painting the background. But it is not entirely obvious that
Cardozo is right. Stare decisis may indeed conserve resources, but it also consumes
¹² When a court is composed of many members, and not all members of the court hear every case,
coordination concerns may well support horizontal stare decisis. Thus, circuit courts of appeals in the
United States, which typically hear cases in three-judge panels selected at random from a larger set of
judges, may use horizontal stare decisis as a means of coordinating action among all the judges on the
court. But such an explanation sheds no light on why the United States Supreme Court, for example,
would consider itself bound to follow its own precedent, since every Justice typically hears every case.
For a discussion of the impact different institutional structures have on the justification of stare deci-
sis, see Kornhauser, supra note 1.
¹³ F. H. Easterbrook, Stability and Reliability in Judicial Decisions, 73 CORNELL L. REV. 422, 423
(1988) (“In principle, modern judges have all the information available to their forbears, plus any dis-
coveries in the interim, and the benefit of hindsight. Judges often decide cases on the basis of predic-
tions about the effects of the legal rule. We can examine these effects—both for other strands of
doctrine and for the world at large—and improve on the treatment of the earlier case”).
¹⁴ CARDOZO, supra note 2, at 149. See also, J. P. Stevens, The Life Span of a Judge-Made Rule, 58
N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 2 (“Perhaps the doctrine is of special interest to judges because it provides special
benefits for judges. It obviously makes their work easier”).
Integrity and Stare Decisis 109
them. In a system with precedent, judges (and lawyers) spend time and money
researching prior cases. The revenues of Lexis and Westlaw are a cost of stare deci-
sis, as are the salaries of judicial clerks and many law firm associates.
Precedent allows judges to rely on previous cases, but it also demands that
judges distinguish cases, an occasionally laborious task. An armchair investigation
suggests that opinions do not grow shorter as the volume of precedent grows
larger. If anything, the trend is towards longer opinions with more citation and
quotation, and this is in part a consequence of stare decisis. Of course, many con-
troversies are settled without judicial involvement because stare decisis makes the
outcome of a case virtually certain. Additionally, stare decisis allows judges to dis-
pose of many cases (and many issues within cases) summarily. So even if published
opinions grow longer as a consequence of stare decisis, it may still be that judicial
resources are conserved by the practice.
Jonathan Macey has gone so far as to argue that stare decisis allows judges to
maximize their own leisure time by allowing them to free-ride on the efforts of
earlier jurists.¹⁵ Whatever its effect on judicial leisure time, it seems likely that
stare decisis conserves judicial resources, or at least allows those resources to be
deployed more efficiently. But the question is more complex than it appears at first
glance, and it would require serious empirical study to resolve. Importantly, even
if it were established that stare decisis conserves judicial resources, that fact would
not go very far towards justifying the practice. Judicial resources are just one kind
of resource among many, and if efficiency is to justify stare decisis, we must know
that the gains in conserving judicial resources are not offset by losses elsewhere.
That is, stare decisis must be efficient for society, not simply efficient for judges.
In an intriguing study of the efficiency of stare decisis, Lewis Kornhauser care-
fully delineates the potential sources of judicial error that could lead us to regard
previous decisions as mistaken (changes in values, changes in the world, improve-
ments in information, and incompetence).¹⁶ Kornhauser provides a nuanced
analysis of the value of stare decisis in the face of different sorts of error and in dif-
ferent institutional contexts. Rather than recap Kornahauser’s analysis, I want
instead to make some general remarks about the conclusions that Kornhauser
reaches and the prospects for an economic justification for the practice of follow-
ing precedents irrespective of their merit.
Kornhauser says that “the desirability of stare decisis will depend on the particu-
lar ‘facts’ of the situation the law seeks to govern.”¹⁷ He illustrates this by consider-
ing the desirability of stare decisis applied to the liability rules governing accidents
between drivers and pedestrians. Suppose that the value of walking is fixed. If the
value of driving is low, then strict liability will be preferred to negligence.
Conversely, if the value of driving is high, then negligence will be preferred.
Suppose further that in a regime with stare decisis, courts stick to the rules they
announce regardless of the actual value of driving, whereas without stare decisis,
in each case, courts announce the legal rule that is optimal given the value of the
injurer’s activity.
To know whether stare decisis is desirable in these circumstances, one must
know certain facts about the relative valuations of the walking and driving.
Kornhauser explains as follows:
Suppose the valuations of the activities are such that both injurer and victim should adopt
moderate (or low) levels of the activity. Under stare decisis, the actor who escapes liability
will always adopt a higher level of activity. Under a practice of no stare decisis, however,
each actor will be uncertain whether she will bear the cost of an accident. This uncertainty
will induce her to adopt an activity level intermediate to the one she would adopt if she
escaped liability for certain. For certain relative values of activities, then, the uncertainty
over the legal rule induces the actors to adopt activity levels closer to the social optimum.¹⁸
Kornhauser’s illustration shows that to know whether stare decisis is an efficient
practice for courts to adopt with respect to the rules governing liability for acci-
dents between pedestrians and drivers, one must know something about walking
and driving.
This is hardly surprising. One would expect that the efficiency of a rule that
entrenches other rules against change would depend in part on the efficiency of
the rules entrenched and the nature of the behavior the rules govern. This has
important ramifications for the possibility of an economic justification of stare
decisis. The principal of stare decisis applies generally. With limited exceptions,
the application of stare decisis does not depend on the substantive area of law
involved. Stare decisis applies in contract as well as tort, in family law as well as
corporate law. It applies to the rules that govern liability between pedestrians and
drivers, as well as the rules that govern liability between farmers and ranchers.
Stare decisis is often said to carry less weight in the realm of constitutional law
because it takes a legislative supermajority to undo a Supreme Court decision.
Notwithstanding that, we do not observe the nuanced application of stare decisis
to specific classes of rules that we would expect to find were the efficiency of the
practice the driving force behind it. As Macey puts it:
[I]n Kornhauser’s model, the adjustment costs facing the relevant parties determine
whether social welfare is being maximized by a legal regime of stare decisis. But courts have
exhibited little, if any, ability or inclination to delve into the adjustment costs facing the
parties before them . . . .¹⁹
Efficiency seems a poor explanation of stare decisis as we know it in part because
the practice is insensitive to the facts that determine whether or not it is efficient
in any given context.
We should be skeptical of attempts to argue that a practice of following prece-
dent regardless of merit is across-the-board efficient because whether or not such a
practice is efficient depends crucially on the rules that the practice entrenches and
on the particulars of the behavior those rules govern. However, one aspect of
efficiency that is sometimes appealed in order to justify stare decisis deserves
special attention: the value of certainty in the law. If judges were unconstrained by
precedent, some say, the law might shift unpredictably and people would be
unable to plan their affairs. This would have undesirable consequences (stunted
markets, stunted psyches, etc.), and to the extent that stare decisis ameliorates
these consequences, it may be instrumentally valuable.
No doubt, for particular areas of law, there is much to be said in favor of cer-
tainty. When it comes to the interpretation of insurance contracts, or the rules
governing secured transactions, it may well be more important to have a consis-
tently applied rule than to have a good rule. When certainty is sufficiently valu-
able to outweigh any loss from the entrenchment of a suboptimal rule, the need
for certainty will support a practice of adhering to precedent irrespective of merit.
We should be careful not to push certainty explanations too far. As Kornhauser
explains: “ ‘Certainty’ justifications for stare decisis often include ‘reliance’ or
‘planning’ arguments, but these arguments are only as strong as the value of the
planned conduct.”²⁰ To take an extreme but illustrative example, note that Plessy
v. Ferguson²¹ allowed Southerners to plan their affairs in the certainty that the fed-
eral government would not interfere with state-created racial caste systems. The
value of the activities planned in reliance on Plessy was hardly sufficient to warrant
continued adherence to the precedent. Indeed, it seems inappropriate to weigh
the “benefit” of segregation-based plans against the cost of segregation-caused
harms at all. Plessy is, as noted, an extreme example, and it represents a paradigm
of a case that ought to have been overruled. But the point is this: if one appeals to
certainty to justify following precedents irrespective of merit, then one must be
prepared to defend the value of the conduct planned in reliance on the rules
entrenched. It is easy to defend the value of conduct planned in reliance on stable
interpretations of insurance contracts, and impossible to defend the value of con-
duct planned in reliance on Plessy. In the middle lies a vast grey area in which the
value of conduct planned in reliance on previously announced legal rules may or
may not be sufficient to warrant a practice of deferring to those rules irrespective
of their merit. Certainty arguments, like efficiency arguments more generally,
may well support stare decisis for particular types of legal rules. But neither cer-
tainty nor efficiency can underwrite an across-the-board practice of deferring to
precedent without regard to merit.
IV
the one that plagues arguments in favor of its efficiency. Fairness may well
demand that courts treat the litigants in like cases alike, and stare decisis
encourages that. But fairness also makes demands regarding the outcome of
particular cases, and stare decisis can entrench unfair results. A practice that
accords deference to the rules announced in Plessy or Korematsu v. United
States,²² for example, entrenches particularly pernicious forms of unfairness
against legal change. Whether stare decisis is on the whole fair depends on the
relative magnitude of the gains in fairness from treating litigants in different
cases alike and the losses from entrenching particular unfair results. It is far
from obvious that, on the whole, stare decisis promotes fairness, and the ques-
tion is, in part, an empirical one.
Fairness does not hold out any more hope of justifying across-the-board stare
decisis than efficiency does, even if we accept the idea that litigants in different
cases ought to be treated alike. And we should have doubts about that claim, at
least as it is relevant to stare decisis. Fairness may demand that we apply the same
rules to litigants in neighboring courtrooms, but it does not clearly demand that
we apply the same rules to litigants separated by decades. Comparative claims of
fairness—claims of the form A deserves X because B received X—are only persua-
sive to the extent that the A and B are similarly situated. Litigants can frequently
claim the benefit of stare decisis even though they are far removed in both time
and place from the source of the precedent.
There are, of course, non-comparative claims of fairness that might support
stare decisis. Non-comparative claims of fairness are claims about how one
deserves to be treated irrespective of how others are treated. Many of the norms
we associate with due process are norms of non-comparative fairness. For
example, it is unfair to detain a person indefinitely without the opportunity for
a hearing before an impartial fact finder, and it would not make it fair to do this
as a matter of routine practice. It is also unfair to punish a person for violating
a criminal statute passed after the alleged violation, and it would not improve
the situation if people were commonly punished for ex post violations. More
relevant to stare decisis, perhaps as a matter of non-comparative fairness,
people ought to be given notice of the rules that will be applied to them, an aim
stare decisis could help facilitate. Or perhaps as a matter of non-comparative
fairness, courts shouldn’t disturb settled expectations. These sorts of claims
may well justify stare decisis in delimited areas of the law. But this is subject to
the point made above. To determine whether stare decisis is fair, gains in fair-
ness from providing notice or protecting settled expectations must be weighed
against the losses from entrenching unfair rules. Because of this, fairness, like
efficiency, is incapable of providing justification for an across-the-board
practice of following precedent irrespective of merit.
²² 323 U.S. 214 (1944).
Integrity and Stare Decisis 113
We started our inquiry with the question, “What justifies adherence to a decision
known to be wrong?” We saw that this question is misleading because it does not
accurately capture what stare decisis requires. So we asked a different question:
“What justifies adherence to a precedent irrespective of its merit?” This question
better captures the canonical formulation of stare decisis, but it still leaves us with
an intractable problem. We can explain why lower courts ought to defer to the
decisions of higher courts simply by invoking Raz’s normal justification thesis.
But we cannot find an analogue that explains why the highest court in a land
should accord its own previous decisions similar deference. Neither efficiency nor
fairness does the trick.
Fortunately, to justify stare decisis, we need not justify adhering to decisions
irrespective of their merits. After all, courts do not do that. With some regularity,
courts overrule precedents and limit their scope by distinguishing them. We can
think of overruling and distinguishing as ways of breaching stare decisis. But we
can also see overruling and distinguishing as part of the practice of stare decisis.
On this broader view, the central demand of stare decisis is that courts engage with
the past and act with integrity.
We owe our understanding of the special connection between law and integrity
to the work of Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin was the first to recognize that integrity
is central to understanding our legal institutions. This was no trivial observation,
because (as we shall see below) integrity may not be a value for all institutions, per-
haps not even all law-like ones.
Before we can explore the connection between stare decisis and integrity, we
must get a fix on what integrity is. Providing a full account is too large an endeavor
to take on here, but some preliminary efforts will help us to get an alternative
account of stare decisis off the ground. According to Dworkin:
We want our neighbors to behave, in their day-to-day dealings with us, in the way we think
right. But we know that people disagree to some extent about the right principles of behav-
ior, so we distinguish that requirement from the different (and weaker) requirement that
they act in important matters with integrity, that is, according to convictions that inform
and shape their lives as a whole, rather than capriciously and whimsically.²³
Acting with integrity does not require that one act correctly. Rather, it requires
that one always act in accord with genuine convictions about what the right way
to act is. Integrity may seem like a second-best sort of value, one to be pursued
only when one cannot be confident of acting correctly. Indeed, Dworkin seems to
invite this understanding of integrity by suggesting that we demand it of others
because we know that we disagree about what is right. Integrity is not a second-
best value, however, and our primary reason for demanding integrity in ourselves
and others is not our inability to agree about what is right. Rather, we demand
integrity because, whatever doubt we have about particular moral views, we are
confident that the demands of morality are coherent.²⁴ We are also confident that
morality does not demand that we act capriciously or whimsically in matters of
importance. Thus, if we are striving to act morally, we will act with integrity.
Let me put the point another way. Someone who acts with integrity may never-
theless do something she ought not to do from time to time. But someone who
acts without integrity, someone who acts incoherently or capriciously in matters
of importance, simply cannot be acting morally except by happenstance. A lack of
integrity signifies a lack of a commitment to act morally.
An individual displays integrity when her actions taken as a whole reflect a
commitment to a coherent and defensible moral view. The moral view must be
coherent because the demands of morality are coherent. However, commitment
to an evil moral view is no virtue simply because the view is coherent. Thus,
integrity also requires that one act in accord with a defensible moral view.
Otherwise, acting with integrity would not be a way of striving to act morally.
Of course, a defensible moral view is not necessarily a true one. This is why
Dworkin is right when he says that the demand that we act with integrity is
weaker than the demand that we act morally. However, acting with integrity is
part of striving to act morally, and that is the source of its value. We respect others
for their integrity even when we disagree with their actions because we recognize
their genuine commitment to acting morally.
Now we get to the important part for understanding stare decisis. Acting with
integrity requires recognizing that what one has done in the past is relevant to
what one ought to do now. Integrity requires a commitment to a moral view, and
one can only display a commitment to a moral view by a pattern of behavior across
time. Constantly shifting moral views are a sign of caprice, not integrity.
Importantly, refusing to change one’s moral views in the face of persuasive rea-
son to do so is also inconsistent with integrity. Remember that integrity is valuable
because it is an aspect of striving to act morally. If you are genuinely striving to act
morally, you will change your beliefs and behavior in response to persuasive argu-
ment or new evidence. A rigid refusal to change one’s moral convictions in the face
of new information is not a sign of integrity; it is a sign of obtuseness.
There are at least two situations in which integrity requires one to repudiate
one’s past. The first is when one’s moral convictions undergo genuine change.
Integrity requires acting in accord with one’s new moral convictions. If a person’s
moral convictions are constantly shifting, we will not say that she acts with integrity
even if she always acts in accord with her genuine moral convictions. This is
²⁴ I am using “morality” in its widest sense, in which the demands of morality are coextensive with
the demands of reason.
Integrity and Stare Decisis 115
because we doubt that she has any commitment to her moral views or to acting
morally. But in the normal case, revisions in one’s beliefs and behaviors are not
only consistent with integrity, they are required by it.
One should also repudiate one’s past when one’s past behavior is inconsistent
with the moral commitments one has made. This is an all too common occurrence
for most of us. Integrity does not require that one repeat one’s mistakes; rather, it
requires correcting them to bring one’s behavior in accord with one’s moral com-
mitments.
These remarks are, of course, only exploratory. A full consideration of the nature
of integrity demands more space and attention than available here. However, we
have made enough progress in understanding what integrity demands of individu-
als that we can turn our attention to what integrity requires of courts.
VI
Courts are moral actors, and a court can display integrity in much the same way
that an individual can. A court displays integrity when its decisions reflect a com-
mitment to a coherent and defensible view of the rights and duties people have
under the law. Such a commitment can only be displayed by a pattern of decisions
across time. If a court’s rulings change capriciously, if it fails to pay heed to its own
pronouncements, we will doubt that it has any genuine commitment to the views
it expresses. On the other hand, if the court takes seriously what it has said in the
past and it displays consistency and coherence in action, we will believe that the
court acts on the basis of genuine convictions about the content of the law.
Why should courts act with integrity? For insight, let us turn once again to
Dworkin. He writes:
Integrity becomes a political ideal when . . . we insist that the state act on a single,
coherent set of principles even when its citizens are divided about what the right princi-
ples of justice and fairness really are. We assume, in both the individual and political
cases, that we can recognize other people’s acts as expressing a conception of justice or
decency even when we do not endorse that conception ourselves. This ability is an
important part of our more general ability to treat others with respect, and it is therefore
a prerequisite of civilization.²⁵
We want the state (and, derivatively, its courts) to act in accord with a single,
coherent set of principles for the same reason we want individuals to do so. We are
confident that morality provides a coherent vision of what we owe to one another,
and that that vision does not demand that the state or its agents act capriciously in
matters of importance. If the state acts incoherently or capriciously in matters of
importance, it cannot be acting morally except by happenstance. We may disagree
about what morality requires of the state, but we want the state to strive to act
morally. Acting with integrity is a sign that it does so.
Dworkin breaks down the demands of integrity into two principles: the principle
of integrity in legislation and the principle of integrity in adjudication. The latter
principle, he says, explains “why judges must conceive of the body of law they
administer as a whole rather than as a set of discrete decisions they are free to make or
amend one by one, with nothing but a strategic interest in the rest.”²⁶ Stare decisis is
a means by which we promote this sort of integrity in judicial decision making.
A court that considers itself bound by the principle of stare decisis recognizes
that what it has done in the past affects what it ought to do now. Of course,
integrity in judicial decision making is no more a matter of slavishly repeating past
decisions, right or wrong, than it is for individuals. Just as individuals must some-
times repudiate their past, courts must do so as well. They must do so whenever
their convictions about the content of the law undergo genuine change, and they
must do so when they discover that their past decisions conflict with their genuine
commitments. Of course, if a court constantly shifts its views, we will doubt that
it has any genuine commitment to them, and we will not regard it as acting with
integrity. But, in the normal case, a court can overturn a precedent it regards as
mistaken without doing any violence to its integrity, and indeed, integrity may
demand that it do so.
There is good reason to think of stare decisis as a broader practice than simply
following precedent. If a court seeking to act with integrity has previously
announced a rule of law, it has three options: it can follow it, it can overrule it, or it
can distinguish the case. Overruling and distinguishing are as much ways of
engaging with the past as following is. They are ways of saying, “we recognize that
our prior decision is relevant in deciding what we ought to do now, but for these
reasons we are not following it here.” A court that did not consider itself bound by
stare decisis would not need to overrule or distinguish cases because it would not
recognize what it had done in the past as relevant to what it ought to do now.
An example of such an institution may help to make the point clear. Up until a
few years ago, allegations of student conduct violations at the University of
Georgia were adjudicated by an organization called the Student Judiciary.²⁷ The
Student Judiciary heard cases running the gamut from trivial infractions like
excessive noise in dorms to serious offenses such as DUI and sexual assault.
Members of the Student Judiciary sat on panels as judges in what were essentially
mini-trials to determine whether a student violated a rule and, if so, to impose an
appropriate sanction. Sanctions ranged from reprimand to expulsion.
The Student Judiciary had no system of precedent. A panel would not consider
the decision of a previous panel, even if a previous decision is precisely on point.
Thus, no case law grew up around the conduct rules or their implementation.
Each panel treated each case as if no others had preceded it.
The Student Judiciary shunned precedent for a variety of reasons. One reason is
that it was seeking to avoid some of the accoutrements of real legal systems. It did
not want to require student defendants to research previous decisions, nor did it
want to expend resources cataloguing them. For the Student Judiciary, efficiency
counseled against stare decisis.
The most important reason for shunning precedent, however, was the way the
Student Judiciary conceived of its mission. It understood itself to share the educa-
tional aims of the broader university. The organization believed that its responsi-
bility was to provide each student who appeared before a panel with the best
educational experience it could. A system of precedent might have gotten in the
way of tailoring each student’s hearing and sanction to their individual educa-
tional needs. Without precedent, maximum flexibility was maintained. The sys-
tem’s rejection of stare decisis was so complete that decisions from prior cases were
not even considered relevant, let alone dispositive.
Integrity was simply not a value the adjudicative practices of the Student
Judiciary recognized. This is interesting, because the Student Judiciary was as
court-like as an institution can be without being part of an actual legal system.
The Student Judiciary administered a system of conduct rules of general applica-
tion through adjudicatory bodies with judges and lawyer-like advocates. The
Student Judiciary was even an organ of the state.²⁸
I suspect that the Student Judiciary was, in fact, concerned with the integrity of
its decision making. Stare decisis is not the only way to promote integrity. The
Student Judiciary demanded that potential members participate in lengthy train-
ing, which promoted consistency and coherence in the decisions of its panels, and
members received continuing education as well. Nevertheless, in the individual
case, the Student Judiciary was designed to be unresponsive to claims that a prior
decision bound it to a course of action. Thus, unlike a court that adheres to stare
decisis, the Student Judiciary never had the need to distinguish or overrule one of
its prior decisions.
In contrast to the Student Judiciary, a court that adheres to stare decisis is differ-
ent not simply because it has a commitment to following its prior decisions, but
because it has committed itself to the idea that what it has done in the past is relevant
to what it ought to do now. Such a court answers to its precedents, by following
them, distinguishing them, and, on occasion, overruling them. Following, distin-
guishing, and overruling are all part of the pursuit of integrity in adjudication.
²⁸ Red & Black Pub. Co., Inc. v. Board of Regents, 427 S.E. 2d 257 (Ga. 1993) (holding that the
Student Judiciary is subject to Georgia’s Open Records Act, which applies to state agencies).
118 Scott Hershovitz
VII
This essay started with a question: could legal reasoning really be so different from
everyday reasoning that principle requires courts to make mistakes repeatedly
rather than correct them? Notwithstanding the traditional view of stare decisis,
the answer is no. Stare decisis does not require a court to blindly follow incorrectly
decided precedents. Nor does it require a court to stand by a precedent irrespective
of its merit. What stare decisis does require is that courts engage with the past and
act with integrity. They do this when they display a commitment to a coherent,
defensible view of the content of the law.
Now that we have an expanded view of the practice of stare decisis, it is reason-
able to wonder whether efficiency and fairness might not play a role in justifying it
after all. Neither efficiency nor fairness seemed promising as a justification for a
practice of following past decisions irrespective of their merit. But the broader
practice of engaging with the past by following, overruling, and distinguishing
precedent may well be both fair and efficient. Whether it is either, of course,
depends on how good a job courts do of it. The efficiency and fairness of stare
decisis conceived broadly still depends, in part, on the efficiency and fairness of
the decisions in particular cases.
The real place for efficiency and fairness in an explanation of stare decisis is not
so much in justifying the practice, but in giving it its contour. This essay has not
addressed the conditions under which a court ought to overturn one of its prece-
dents. In any given case, the question of whether a court should follow a precedent
depends crucially on matters of fairness and efficiency, and on a multitude of
other values as well. The fact that courts bother to engage with precedent at all,
however, is best explained by judicial aspirations to act with integrity.
6
The Many Faces of Political Integrity
Dale Smith*
* I am grateful to Samantha Besson, Ronald Dworkin, Patrick Emerton, Jeff Goldsworthy, Scott
Hershovitz, Lewis Kornhauser and Nicos Stavropoulos for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of
this chapter.
¹ R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986). All references in parentheses are to this work.
other political concepts such as justice and legality.² On this view, we can fully
understand the concept of integrity only by constructing a holistic (and interpre-
tive) account of all our political values, at least part of which involves tracing the
interrelations between integrity and other political values. As Dworkin himself
points out, this is an enormous undertaking, which I cannot possibly perform in
this chapter. However, I hope that this chapter could be seen to represent a modest
and limited contribution towards that overarching goal, advancing to some extent
our understanding of the value of integrity and its relationship to other political
values such as justice and fairness.
Dworkin claims that there are two commonly accepted political values—justice
and fairness.³ However, he offers a somewhat idiosyncratic account of these two
values:
Fairness in politics is a matter of finding political procedures—methods of electing officials
and making their decisions responsive to the electorate—that distribute political power in
the right way. That is now generally understood, in the United States and Britain at least,
to mean procedures and practices that give all citizens more or less equal influence in the
decisions that govern them. Justice, on the contrary, is concerned with the decisions that
the standing political institutions, whether or not they have been chosen fairly, ought to
make. If we accept justice as a political virtue we want our legislators and other officials to
distribute material resources and protect civil liberties so as to secure a morally defensible
outcome. (164–165)
Dworkin claims that there is also a third political ideal—the ideal of integrity.
This ideal “requires government to speak with one voice, to act in a principled
and coherent manner toward all its citizens, to extend to everyone the same
substantive standards of justice or fairness it uses for some” (165). For example,
if the government relies on majoritarian principles to justify its decisions about
who may vote, it must respect the same principles when drawing electoral
boundaries. Similarly, if the government appeals to the principle that people
have a right to receive compensation from those who injure them carelessly as a
reason why manufacturers are liable for defective cars, it must give effect to
that principle in deciding whether accountants are liable for their mistakes as
well (165).
² R. Dworkin, Hart’s Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy, 24 Oxford J. of Legal
Stud. 1, 17 (2004).
³ He mentions a further political ideal—procedural due process—but it plays no role in his argu-
ment, and so I shall leave it to one side.
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 121
Dworkin labels this ideal “political integrity” to highlight the connection with
the notion of personal integrity, which involves acting “according to convictions
that inform and shape [one’s life] as a whole, rather than capriciously or whimsi-
cally” (166). Integrity becomes a political ideal when we insist that the state act on
a single, coherent set of principles even though its citizens disagree about what the
right principles of justice and fairness really are (166).⁴
To justify his claim that integrity is a distinct political ideal, Dworkin seeks to
show that it both fits with, and provides a sound justification of, our political
practices. It is in seeking to show that this ideal fits our political practices that he
introduces the notion of a checkerboard solution. He claims that we can explain
our opposition to checkerboard solutions only on the basis that we accept the
ideal of integrity.
So what is a checkerboard solution? This question will occupy us for much of
this chapter, but let us start with Dworkin’s initial characterization of the
phenomenon. He states that he is not using the word “checkerboard” to describe
statutes that make distinctions that claim to be justified on the basis of a policy
best served by the discriminations in question. Instead, he uses the word “to
describe statutes that display incoherence in principle and that can be justified, if
at all, only on grounds of a fair allocation of political power between different
moral parties” (435, n. 6).
Dworkin uses the connection between fairness and checkerboard solutions
alluded to in the last quotation to set up a puzzle that he believes only integrity can
solve. He points out that, since we all value fairness but disagree about moral
issues, it seems to follow that legislation on moral issues should be a matter “of trades
and compromises so that each body of opinion is represented, to a degree that
matches its numbers, in the final result” (178). For example, if people disagree
about whether justice requires compensation for product defects that the manu-
facturer could not reasonably have prevented, why should not the legislature
impose strict liability on car manufacturers but not on manufacturers of washing
machines?⁵ Or, if we disagree about the permissibility of abortion, why should not
Parliament make abortion criminal for women who are born in even-numbered
years but not for those born in odd-numbered years? (178).
Dworkin claims that this sort of solution to contested moral issues seems
mandated by fairness, since it secures the kind of proportional influence of
citizens over the political process that fairness (on Dworkin’s definition) appears
to recommend (435, n. 3). Allowing each group in society to choose some part of
that society’s abortion law, in proportion to their numbers, “is fairer (in our
⁴ Several commentators have suggested that there are important disanalogies between personal
integrity and what Dworkin calls “political integrity”: e.g. J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain:
Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics 307 (1995). However, I shall not pursue this issue here.
⁵ Though I shall question whether this is really an example of a checkerboard solution: see infra
text for note 18.
122 Dale Smith
sense) than the winner-take-all scheme our instincts prefer, which denies many
people any influence at all over an issue they think desperately important”
(179).⁶
However, Dworkin also claims that most of us would be dismayed by checker-
board statutes that treat relevantly similar actions (for example, abortions by
women born in even-numbered years and those by women born in odd-num-
bered years) differently on arbitrary grounds (179). This is not to say that we
always oppose political compromise, or even that we always oppose arbitrary com-
promises. Dworkin allows that we tolerate arbitrary distinctions with regard to
matters of policy (such as parking regulations), but claims that we do not tolerate
them when matters of principle are at stake. In other words, if we are concerned
only with promoting social welfare, then arbitrary distinctions are permissible,
but they are unacceptable where moral issues (or someone’s rights) are involved.⁷
When matters of principle are at stake, we accept that each point of view should
be allowed a voice in the deliberative process, but the collective decision must
aim to settle on some coherent principle that is then applied in all appropriate
circumstances (179).
Compromise on matters of principle is not always impermissible. Sometimes,
two independent principles that we hold come into conflict, in the sense that we
cannot satisfy both on this particular occasion. In such cases, we might give
weight to each of those principles in a certain relation (for example, by develop-
ing a tax scheme that seeks to respect both property rights and equality of
opportunity, to differing degrees). However, whatever relative weighting we give
those principles must flow throughout the scheme in question, and to other deci-
sions that involve the same two principles (435–436, n. 7). Dworkin claims that
this kind of conflict differs from the contradiction contained in checkerboard
statutes. In the latter case, one principle of justice is not outweighed or qualified
by another in a way that expresses a ranking of the two; instead, only a single
principle is involved, which is affirmed for one group and denied for another. It is
this which Dworkin claims we denounce: “If there must be compromise because
people are divided about justice, then the compromise . . . must be compromise
about which scheme of justice to adopt rather than a compromised scheme of
justice” (179).
⁶ See also (435, n. 3), where Dworkin explicitly states that fairness supports checkerboard solu-
tions. Dworkin does not specify precisely what sort of influence is required by the value of fairness,
but presumably he has in mind the ability to have one’s views reflected in political outcomes. On
this view, one has political influence to the extent that one’s favoured position is reflected in the posi-
tion adopted by the political process, rather than to the extent that one participates in the political
process. Whether this is an appropriate account of fairness falls outside the scope of this chapter: see
infra, note 17.
⁷ This is an over-simplification of Dworkin’s views. While he claims that integrity does not require
any simple form of consistency between policies (in the way that it does with regard to principles), he
claims that it does have some role to play even here (221–222).
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 123
⁸ Dworkin uses the phrases “checkerboard solution” and “internal compromise” interchangeably.
I shall follow this practice.
⁹ As we shall see, Dworkin concedes that sometimes checkerboard solutions may be acceptable,
but only because our distaste for them is outweighed by other considerations.
124 Dale Smith
¹⁰ I shall refer to these as the rape-abortion law and the checkerboard-abortion law, respectively.
Possibly to make it more plausible that the rape-abortion law would permit the same number of
abortions as a checkerboard solution, Dworkin refers to a checkerboard solution whereby only
women born in one specified decade each century could have an abortion (183). However, for sim-
plicity, I shall discuss only one checkerboard solution regarding abortion—namely, the one referred
to in the text.
¹¹ Can we explain the preference on the basis that abortions in non-rape cases are worse (from the
viewpoint of justice) than abortions in rape cases? No, because Dworkin stipulates that, on the view
under consideration, it makes no difference whether the pregnancy is a result of rape (183).
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 125
Are these merely different ways of making the same point? Certainly, there are
significant similarities between several of the items on this list. For example,
treating similar actions differently on arbitrary grounds and treating people differ-
ently when no principle can justify the distinction may simply be two ways of
describing the same thing. However, even here, much depends on what we mean
by “arbitrary”. If “arbitrary” means unpredictable, or without legitimate author-
ity,¹⁴ then it is not so clear that the two descriptions are equivalent. There may be
a principle that justifies differential treatment for two people who perform similar
actions, even if the decision to treat them differently is unpredictable (for example,
because we were unaware of that principle before the decision) or lacks legitimate
authority (for example, because the decision-maker does not have authority to
deal with the relevant issues).¹⁵
Similarly, it is not immediately obvious that one cannot affirm a single prin-
ciple for one group and deny it for another without lapsing into “incoherence in
principle.” For example, many countries affirm the principle of freedom of associ-
ation for most of their citizens, but not for offenders who have been convicted and
sentenced to jail. Do such countries lack coherence in principle? Perhaps there is
more than one principle at stake in this example (and so this is not an example of
affirming a single principle for one group and denying it for another). However, at
least at first sight, more than one principle is at stake in Dworkin’s examples of
checkerboard solutions, as well.¹⁶
It is not clear what we should conclude from this. One possibility is that
Dworkin equivocates as to exactly what is wrong with checkerboard solutions,
switching haphazardly between different explanations. However, another possi-
bility is that—despite appearances—these various characterizations of checker-
board solutions in fact amount to the same thing. Or perhaps there is more than
one thing wrong with checkerboard solutions, reflecting the fact that there is more
than one principle of integrity that they violate (just as there is more than one
principle of justice or fairness).
What is clear, however, is that further consideration of Dworkin’s account of
checkerboard solutions is called for. I shall seek to provide an interpretation of
Dworkin’s position that both fits what he says about checkerboard solutions and is
sufficiently plausible in its own right to warrant consideration. More precisely, my
¹⁴ Both of these are possible meanings of “arbitrary” suggested by J. Waldron, Law and
Disagreement 167–168 (1999).
¹⁵ Dworkin may not be using the word “arbitrary” in either of these senses. If so, however, we need
to determine in what sense he is using the word (see infra Section A).
¹⁶ In fact, it is clear that checkerboard solutions need not concern only a single principle. Imagine
a variation of the checkerboard abortion law, under which abortions are permissible for women born
in the first four months of the year provided the abortion is performed in the first two trimesters of
the pregnancy, are never permissible for women born in the next four months of the year and are per-
missible for women born in the last four months of the year only if their pregnancy is the result of
rape. On any reasonable way of demarcating principles, there is more than one principle at stake in
this law, and yet the law is clearly a checkerboard solution, since women are treated differently
depending on the month in which they were born.
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 127
aim in this Part is to find the best account of checkerboard solutions available to
Dworkin, before (in Part III) considering what implications that account has for
Dworkin’s broader theory. To this end, I shall begin by considering whether there
is a single feature of checkerboard solutions that can explain our attitude towards
such solutions, before considering whether some combination of such features
might underlie our opposition to internal compromise. However, in doing so, I shall
consider only the more promising interpretations of Dworkin’s views, rather than
attempting a comprehensive survey of suggestions as to what is wrong with
checkerboard solutions.¹⁷
Since I am searching for the best interpretation of Dworkin’s discussion of
checkerboard solutions, I shall assume that there really is something wrong with
such solutions. However, even making this assumption, not all of Dworkin’s
examples are equally convincing. Take his example of a statute that introduces
no-fault liability for car manufacturers but not for washing machine manufac-
turers. Might there not be a principled distinction between the two types of
manufacturer? For example, defective cars might cause personal injury more
often than defective washing machines, and we might consider it more import-
ant to compensate for personal injury than for other losses resulting from defective
products. Rather than concluding that this represents an exception to the
general rule that checkerboard solutions are unacceptable, I suggest that—if
there is a principled distinction—this shows that Dworkin’s example is not
really a checkerboard solution after all.¹⁸ Thus, I shall focus on another of
Dworkin’s examples, which clearly is a checkerboard solution—namely, a law
that prohibits abortions for women born in even-numbered years but not for
those born in odd-numbered years. Given the uncertainty about how to charac-
terize checkerboard solutions, I shall seek to derive guidance from this paradigm
example of an internal compromise.
¹⁷ Several commentators have argued that, contrary to Dworkin, we can explain why checker-
board solutions are undesirable by reference to the values of fairness or justice (e.g. S. Wasserstrom,
The Empire’s New Clothes, 75 Geo. L.J. 199, 249, n. 168 (1986); D. Reaume, Is Integrity a Virtue?
Dworkin’s Theory of Legal Obligation, 39 U. Toronto L.J. 380, 391–393 (1989)). However, I am
searching for the best interpretation of Dworkin’s views about checkerboard solutions, and so shall
leave to one side the possibility that Dworkin is wrong in claiming that the distinctive flaw of
checkerboard solutions is not that they are unfair and/or unjust.
¹⁸ A similar approach is adopted by G. C. Christie, Dworkin’s “Empire”, Duke L.J. 157, 185
(1987). Dworkin could argue that the proposed legislation is a checkerboard solution because—even
if a principled distinction could be drawn between car and washing machine manufacturers—this
was not the motivation for the distinction drawn in the legislation. Instead, that distinction was moti-
vated by considerations of political feasibility. However, the problem with checkerboard solutions
seems to lie in the nature of the distinction drawn, not in the motivation for drawing that distinction.
128 Dale Smith
B. Irrelevant Considerations
The most obvious explanation of what is wrong with the checkerboard-abortion
law is that its application depends on an irrelevant consideration, because it
makes the permissibility of abortion depend on whether one was born on an
even-numbered year, a consideration that is morally irrelevant to the issue at
hand. We can render this notion of “moral irrelevance” somewhat more precise
by saying that a morally irrelevant consideration is one that does not provide
even a pro tanto moral reason. Thus, to say that whether one was born on an
even-numbered year is morally irrelevant to whether one should be permitted to
have an abortion is to say that it does not provide even a pro tanto moral reason
for permitting (or not permitting) one to have an abortion.²²
It is interesting that Dworkin does not canvass this possible explanation in
Law’s Empire. Indeed, his discussion appears incompatible with it. Take his
suggested alternative to the checkerboard-abortion law—namely, allowing
abortions only for rape victims. Dworkin states that this alternative would be
seen to be superior to the checkerboard statute even if one believes “that it makes
no difference whether the pregnancy is the result of rape” (183). To believe that it
makes no difference whether the pregnancy is the result of rape is to believe that
whether one has been raped is irrelevant to whether one is permitted to have an
abortion (that is, it does not provide even a pro tanto reason for permitting an
abortion). Yet Dworkin expects someone who holds that view still to prefer the
rape-abortion statute to the checkerboard-abortion statute (and he regards this
preference as reflecting an opposition to checkerboard solutions that he shares).
²² This may be an unduly narrow conception of moral relevance. For example, even if one does
not believe that foetuses have souls, one may believe that whether they have souls is relevant to the
abortion debate, since—if they did have souls—this would provide a pro tanto reason to oppose
abortion. This suggests that a consideration may also be morally relevant if it would provide a pro
tanto reason were the non-moral facts different (e.g. were foetuses to have souls). However, nothing in
this Section (Section B) turns on this point.
130 Dale Smith
that Anna must choose between the rape-abortion law and the checkerboard-
abortion law. She believes that both are based on irrelevant considerations, and so
cannot distinguish between them on this basis. However, is it not likely that Anna
will believe that the rape-abortion law is preferable to the checkerboard-abortion
law (again, assuming that both laws allow the same number of abortions)? The
former is likely to make more sense to her because she can see how someone could
come to support it (even though she believes that they are wrong to do so),
whereas she could not see how someone could come to support the latter.²⁵ This
suggests that what is distinctively objectionable about the checkerboard-abortion
law (our paradigm case of a checkerboard solution) is not that it is based on irrele-
vant considerations.
A number of objections could be offered to this argument, of which I shall
consider only one.²⁶ This objection starts by pointing out that, according to the
“irrelevant considerations” approach, something is a checkerboard solution if its
application depends on considerations that are in fact irrelevant. Which consid-
erations people believe to be irrelevant is beside the point. Therefore, it does not
matter whether Anna believes that the fact that a pregnancy is the result of rape
is morally irrelevant. What matters is whether that fact really is morally irrele-
vant. If it is, the rape-abortion law is a checkerboard solution; if it is not, the
rape-abortion law is not a checkerboard solution.
There is some truth to this objection. Under the “irrelevant considerations”
approach, what matters is whether a consideration is in fact irrelevant, not
whether it is believed to be irrelevant. However, we need to recall the structure of
Dworkin’s argument. He wants to show that integrity is a genuine political value
by showing that (inter alia) it fits our political practices. He tries to do this by
arguing that it is the fact that we value integrity that explains why we oppose
checkerboard solutions. This means that, for Dworkin’s purposes, what we
believe is pertinent. If Anna’s beliefs and practices show that she does not oppose
checkerboard solutions on the basis that their application depends on irrelevant
considerations, then this suggests that the “irrelevant considerations” approach
cannot give Dworkin what he wants. Either the “irrelevant considerations”
approach is mistaken (in which case, we must look elsewhere to discover what is
distinctively wrong with checkerboard solutions) or else Dworkin’s argu-
mentative strategy fails (because the correct explanation of what is wrong with
checkerboard solutions does not fit with the political beliefs and practices of
be a relevant consideration). However, it is doubtful whether Dworkin can accept this argument.
Of his three political values, fairness and integrity do not seem to have anything to do with excuses,
and he defines justice to be concerned with the right outcome, whereas excuses are relevant to blame-
worthiness (not to which outcome is correct). Moreover, the “irrelevant considerations” approach
would still face the further objection presented towards the end of this Section (Section B).
²⁵ I consider this as a possible explanation of what is wrong with checkerboard solutions in
Section D. ²⁶ This objection was suggested by Scott Hershovitz.
132 Dale Smith
people like Anna, since they distinguish between checkerboard solutions and
solutions based on irrelevant factors).²⁷
I am inclined to regard the first of these two possibilities as correct. If I believed
that whether a pregnancy was the result of rape is irrelevant to the permissibility of
abortion, I would still distinguish between the rape-abortion and checkerboard-
abortion laws on the basis suggested above—namely, that I can see how someone
could come to support the rape-abortion law, but I cannot see how someone could
come to support the checkerboard-abortion law.²⁸ This suggests that it is not just
Anna’s intuitions that run contrary to the “irrelevant considerations” approach.
Of course, both Anna’s and my intuitions may be mistaken, but some further
argument is required to show that this is in fact the case.
There is another counter-intuitive feature of the “irrelevant considerations”
approach. If we focus on whether a consideration is in fact irrelevant (as opposed to
whether it is believed to be irrelevant), then whether the rape-abortion law is a
checkerboard solution depends on the answer to a fairly complex moral question
(namely, whether the fact that a pregnancy is the result of rape provides a pro tanto
reason for permitting an abortion). Similarly, whether a law permitting abortions
in the first two trimesters only is a checkerboard solution depends on (inter alia)
whether personhood starts from the moment of conception and whether this
means that the age of the foetus is morally irrelevant. However, no such difficult
moral question need be resolved to determine that the checkerboard-abortion law
is a checkerboard solution—it is obvious that the permissibility of abortion should
not hinge on the year in which one is born. In other words, when we look at the
only clear case of a checkerboard solution that we have yet found, we can determine
that it is a checkerboard solution without having to evaluate the correctness of any
contested moral position. This suggests that the “irrelevant considerations”
approach fails to capture what is distinctive about checkerboard solutions, since it
does require us to evaluate the correctness of contested moral positions in order to
determine whether something is a checkerboard solution.
An obvious response is that the checkerboard-abortion law is a paradigm case of
a checkerboard solution precisely because its application clearly depends on irrele-
vant considerations. Whether other laws amount to checkerboard solutions will
be less clear, because it will be less clear whether the considerations on which their
application depends are irrelevant. However, to downplay the fact that we do not
have to evaluate the correctness of any contested moral position to determine that
whether a woman is born in an even-numbered year is morally irrelevant is to
overlook one of the most distinctive features of the checkerboard-abortion statute
(see Section D). To provide an account of what is distinctively wrong with such a
statute, we need to look beyond the question of whether its application depends
on an irrelevant consideration.
C. Coherence in Principle
A third possibility is that checkerboard solutions are undesirable because they lack
“coherence in principle”. Dworkin considers coherence in principle to be a
desideratum both of single rules and of sets of rules. However, the problem with
checkerboard solutions cannot be that they are inconsistent in principle with
other legal rules, since they are supposed to be objectionable in their own right,
without any need to consider other aspects of the legal system. Indeed, Dworkin
explicitly treats incoherence in principle between legal rules as a way of flouting
integrity that is separate from that inherent in checkerboard solutions (184).
Thus, I shall focus upon coherence in principle within a single rule.²⁹
Dworkin claims that legal decision-making should be a matter of principle, not
of political accommodation.³⁰ In other words, legal decisions must be defensible by
reference to a coherent set of principles. However, we have seen that (on Dworkin’s
account) checkerboard solutions can be defended by reference to (presumably
coherent) principles of fairness. Thus, if the defect in checkerboard solutions is that
they are not defensible on the basis of a coherent set of principles, it must be princi-
ples of justice that we should be considering, not principles of fairness.
With this point in mind, there is reason to ascribe to Dworkin the view that
checkerboard solutions are defective because they are not defensible by reference
to a coherent set of principles. Certainly, Dworkin believes that integrity involves
“a commitment to consistency in principle valued for its own sake” (167).
Moreover, he claims that a state that adopts a checkerboard solution lacks integrity
“because it must endorse principles to justify part of what it has done that it must
reject to justify the rest” (184). For example, the checkerboard-abortion law
endorses the principle that women should be allowed abortions at will when
explaining why women born in odd-numbered years are allowed abortions, and
then rejects that principle when determining whether women born in even-num-
bered years are allowed abortions.³¹ This suggests that Dworkin believes that
checkerboard solutions lack coherence in principle, because they both uphold and
reject certain principles of justice.
²⁹ Though coherence in principle between rules is discussed briefly infra in Part III, Section B.
³⁰ R. Dworkin, Life’s Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and
Individual Freedom 146 (1993). Dworkin is talking here about judicial decisions, but he demands
the same of legislators (at least when moral issues are at stake).
³¹ This may be what Dworkin has in mind when he says that checkerboard solutions are based
on a compromised theory of justice, as opposed to a compromise regarding which theory of justice to
use (179).
134 Dale Smith
³² For the sake of the example, I am assuming that we do not regard this further principle of justice
as correct, but rather regard it as an acceptable compromise between the principles of justice that dif-
ferent people do regard as correct.
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 135
that abortions should be prohibited only for women born in even-numbered years
is not recognizable as a principle of justice (whereas the principle that abortions
should be permitted for rape victims is recognizable as a principle of justice, even if
it turns out to be incorrect). However, this suggestion shifts the focus from
whether a solution both upholds and rejects a certain principle of justice to
whether it reflects anything recognizable as a principle of justice, and so is consid-
ered in Section D.
There is a further problem with the claim that checkerboard solutions are
defective because they lack coherence in principle. What motivates the require-
ment that legal decisions be defensible on the basis of a coherent set of princi-
ples of justice? It might seem obvious that no law should both uphold and reject
a principle of justice in the way that the checkerboard-abortion law does. Yet
(on Dworkin’s account) that law can be defended by reference to a coherent set
of principles of fairness. Is this not enough to ensure coherence in principle over-
all? Why do we also need coherence in terms of principles of justice? Have we
not seen that fairness may require us to abandon this more narrow type of
coherence, in order to ensure that everyone has an appropriate level of input
into political decision-making?³³ I shall delay consideration of this issue until
Part III, Section C.
³³ J. Waldron, The Circumstances of Integrity, 3 Legal Theory 1, 4 (1997) points out that some-
one might think it is more expressive of real integrity for a community to acknowledge that it is torn
between competing views of justice than to strive to cover up this tension by preserving coherence in
principle within the law.
136 Dale Smith
(In this context, “moral principle” must mean a principle of justice, since
Dworkin acknowledges that checkerboard solutions can be supported by recog-
nizable principles of fairness.)
This suggestion can be illustrated by reference to the rape-abortion law. I
suggested in Section B that some people may regard the fact that a pregnancy is
the result of rape as morally irrelevant, in the sense that it does not provide even a
pro tanto reason for having an abortion. Nevertheless, such a person could regard
the rape-abortion law as upholding a principle that is recognizably moral in
nature. In other words, she could view her opponents as putting forward a
genuinely moral position (albeit an incorrect one). Moreover, she could distin-
guish on this basis between the rape-abortion law and the checkerboard-abortion
law, since the latter cannot be seen to uphold a principle that is recognizably moral
in nature. Whether or not she accepts that principle herself, she can recognize that
the rape-abortion law upholds a moral principle, whereas the same is not true of
an abortion law based on the year in which the pregnant woman is born. The
latter turns on a factor that she cannot consider to be a moral consideration even
in the extended sense in which she can recognize the fact that a pregnancy is the
result of rape to be a moral consideration whilst regarding it as not providing even
a pro tanto reason for having an abortion. This suggests that—whether or not we
agree that it is irrelevant that a pregnancy is the result of rape—we can, at least in
principle, distinguish checkerboard solutions from principles that may be incor-
rect or based on morally irrelevant considerations but that are still recognizably
moral in nature.
This reading of Dworkin is not without textual support. For example, he states
that some compromises do not violate integrity “because they reflect principles of
justice we recognize though we do not ourselves endorse them” (436, n.8). He
gives the example of a reduction in the list of capital crimes on the basis of views
about moral culpability (or some other standard generally respected in the crimi-
nal law), as opposed to allowing criminals convicted of a capital offence to escape
death by drawing straws.³⁴ Similarly, when introducing the ideal of integrity,
Dworkin states that we assume “that we can recognize other people’s acts as
expressing a conception of justice or fairness . . . even when we do not endorse
that conception ourselves” (166). We would need to make that assumption in this
context only if integrity forbids only those actions that do not express a
(correct or mistaken) conception of justice or fairness.
Of course, this notion of a standard that is not recognizable as a principle of jus-
tice (or of a position that cannot be regarded as a genuinely moral position) is
vague. One could try to give it more analytical rigour by suggesting that the
question is whether, as a conceptual matter, a consideration can be regarded as
³⁴ Viewed in isolation, this example could be regarded as supporting either the current approach
or the “irrelevant considerations” approach. However, we saw in Section B that the latter represents
an implausible interpretation of Dworkin’s discussion of checkerboard solutions.
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 137
moral in nature.³⁵ The principle underlying the rape-abortion law falls within the
concept of morality, since it holds that the permissibility of abortion depends on a
consideration (that a pregnancy was the result of rape) that can be treated as
morally relevant by someone who is not conceptually mistaken (though she may
be morally mistaken). The same is not true of conclusions drawn from the fact
that a pregnant woman was born in an even-numbered year.³⁶ However, this can
advance matters only to the extent that we have a clear understanding of what
constraints are imposed by the concept of morality (or, in other words, of what
can count as a moral reason, consideration or principle). This is itself a controver-
sial issue.³⁷
Be that as it may, there are other problems with this interpretation of Dworkin’s
position. Why must political compromises be based on recognizable principles of
justice? We have seen that checkerboard solutions may be based on recognizable
principles of fairness (giving everyone an input into the content of the law that is
proportionate to the support they can muster within society), and why is this not
enough to make a compromise recognizably moral in nature? Why should we
privilege justice over fairness in the way that (this interpretation of ) Dworkin
requires?
One might seek to be conciliatory at this point, and suggest that whether a
political compromise reflects recognizable principles of justice is one relevant
consideration, though whether it reflects recognizable principles of fairness is
also relevant. However, Dworkin must show more than that the former is a
relevant consideration, since he claims that integrity (on this interpretation, the
requirement that laws reflect recognizable principles of justice) should “charac-
teristically” prevail over other values. He therefore needs to show that our pursuit
³⁵ On this view, for something to be a “recognizable principle of justice”, it is not enough that one
believes that it is a principle of justice. Instead, what counts is whether it in fact satisfies the conceptual
requirements for being a principle of justice.
³⁶ The difference between the “irrelevant considerations” approach and the present approach
could then be viewed as follows. The “irrelevant considerations” approach requires us to identify the
correct conception of justice, since it asks whether a factor is morally relevant. Determining whether a
factor is morally relevant requires us to determine what pro tanto moral reasons exist, which depends
upon which conception of justice is correct. The present approach, on the other hand, requires us to
consider only the concept of justice, since it asks whether a principle satisfies the conceptual con-
straints on something being a moral principle (or, more specifically, a principle of justice). It does not
matter whether that principle is valid under the correct conception of justice, provided it falls within
the concept of justice. See R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 134–135 (1977) regarding the
distinction Dworkin draws between concepts and conceptions.
³⁷ E.g., R. Hare, Sorting out Ethics (1997) claims that a strong universalizability condition is
part of the very concept of morality, whereas J. Raz, Value, Respect, and Attachment 58–59
(2001) suggests that any such condition is the result of substantive moral reasoning. This means
that—if the present approach is correct—a statute permitting abortion only for white women is a
checkerboard solution on the former view, but not on the latter. However, presumably both views
would regard the checkerboard-abortion law, along with a law that allowed abortions only for women
who are more than 160 cm tall, as checkerboard solutions, since substantive moral reasoning is not
needed to recognize that these factors are morally irrelevant (in the way that it is arguably needed to
recognize that racial characteristics are morally irrelevant).
138 Dale Smith
⁴⁰ It also differs, in the same way, from Dworkin’s other example of a checkerboard statute men-
tioned in Part I. Legislation that imposes no-fault liability upon car, but not washing machine, manu-
facturers treats victims of defective products differently depending on the sort of product that injured
them.
⁴¹ Admittedly, there is some controversy about how this metaphor should be interpreted. For a
somewhat different interpretation, see Waldron, supra note 33, 19–21.
140 Dale Smith
be justified by any correct principle of justice) and so should be rejected for that
reason.⁴²
Further support for this interpretation can be gleaned from Dworkin’s state-
ment, already noted, that checkerboard solutions involve a single principle, which
is affirmed for one group and denied for another, and it is this which we denounce
(436, n.7). He later states explicitly that any defect in checkerboard solutions
“must lie in their distinctive feature, that they treat people differently when no
principle can justify the distinction” (180).
In addition to fitting well with much of what Dworkin says about checker-
board solutions, this interpretation helps explain why the checkerboard-abortion
statute is an internal compromise (because it treats people differently without
any basis in justice) but the rock-worshipping law discussed in Section D is not
(because it treats everyone the same). It may also help to explain why checker-
board solutions are undesirable despite being supported by considerations of
fairness. It could be argued that fairness alone cannot justify treating people
differently where this is unsupported by any correct principle of justice. On this
view, whatever the arguments in favour of giving people equal input into their
community’s law-making, this cannot justify the difference in treatment
inherent in checkerboard solutions. This line of thought is pursued in Part III.
However, the fact that checkerboard solutions uphold rights or benefits for
some people but not others is insufficient to distinguish them from many other
legal decisions. For example, the rape-abortion law permits victims of rape to have
an abortion but precludes other women from having one, and so treats these two
groups differently. This by itself is insufficient to render the rape-abortion law
problematic, let alone to turn it into a checkerboard solution. Even more clear-cut
would be a constitutional provision that confers a right to freedom of association
on everyone except for criminals who are imprisoned pursuant to constitutionally
valid laws. Such a provision clearly upholds a right for some people that it denies
to others, yet is not a checkerboard solution.
Perhaps the distinctive feature of checkerboard solutions resides in the fact that
the differential treatment they require is not justified by correct principles of
justice. However, this borders on saying that a checkerboard solution is a wrong
solution (at least as seen from the viewpoint of justice), since any law that
unjustly differentiated between people would be a checkerboard solution. This
would fail adequately to distinguish checkerboard solutions from any other
decision that produces an unjust outcome (including the rape-abortion law, if
whether a pregnant woman has been raped should not be determinative of whether
abortion is permissible). There is supposed to be something especially wrong
about checkerboard solutions, which distinguishes them from decisions that are
⁴² This has led some people to suggest that “integrity” is simply Dworkin’s name for a type of
equality—namely, the equality manifested by applying the same legal principles to X that one has
applied to Y: e.g. L. Alexander & K. Kress, Against Legal Principles, 82 Iowa L. Rev. 739, 755 (1997).
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 141
wrong merely because they draw distinctions that are based on incorrect princi-
ples of justice.
One alternative⁴³ is to ask whether the differential treatment required by a law
could be justified by reference to anything recognizable as a principle of justice,
rather than asking whether it can be justified by reference to a correct principle of
justice. This would combine the present interpretation (with its focus on differen-
tial treatment) with the interpretation considered in Section D (which concen-
trated on whether the decision could be justified by reference to a recognizable
principle of justice). As it suggests that there is more than one thing wrong with
checkerboard solutions, I shall consider this possibility separately in the next
section.
F. A Multitude of Sins?
So far, I have proceeded on the assumption that there is only one thing wrong
with checkerboard solutions, and have sought to isolate that single flaw. Having
failed to do so, I must now consider whether the reason that we reject internal
compromises is because they possess several flaws. I shall pursue only what I con-
sider to be the most promising line of thought in this regard—that a checker-
board solution both treats people differently in a way that is unjust and cannot be
justified by reference to anything recognizable as a principle of justice.
The first advantage of this suggestion is that it recognizes that the fact that a law
unjustifiably upholds a right or benefit for some people but not others is a neces-
sary, but not sufficient, condition for something to be a checkerboard solution. As
a result, this interpretation provides a basis for distinguishing between the
checkerboard-abortion and rape-abortion laws. Both treat people differently, but
the latter does so on the basis of a recognizable (though perhaps incorrect) princi-
ple of justice whereas the former does not. Secondly, this suggestion enables us to
differentiate checkerboard solutions from laws (such as the rock-worshipping
statute discussed in Section D) that are not based on recognizable principles of
justice but do not treat people differently, since we have now built into our defini-
tion of checkerboard solutions a requirement of differential treatment.
Again, there is some textual support for this interpretation. Dworkin contrasts
the rape-abortion statute with the checkerboard-abortion statute in the following
terms:
You [i.e. an opponent of abortion] see the first of these statutes as a solution that gives
effect to two recognizable principles of justice, ordered in a certain way, even though you
reject one of the principles. You cannot treat the second that way; it simply affirms for
some people a principle it denies to others. (183, footnote omitted)
⁴³ Another alternative sometimes hinted at in Law’s Empire is that we should ask whether the
differential treatment can be justified by any principle of justice that is consistent with the principles
underlying other legal decisions. However, we saw in Section C that checkerboard solutions are
meant to be problematic in their own right, not only when considered alongside other legal rules.
142 Dale Smith
We see here both limbs of the current suggestion. While Dworkin does not
explicitly state that both are necessary, the quotation is meant to represent the
view of someone who shares Dworkin’s intuitions regarding checkerboard
solutions.
I believe this to be the most promising interpretation of Dworkin’s discussion
of checkerboard solutions. Not only does it bring together (in a coherent fashion)
many of Dworkin’s comments about checkerboard solutions, but it also suggests
that there is something distinctively wrong with internal compromises (something
that previous interpretations of Dworkin’s position were unable to do). Moreover,
it can explain our intuitive dislike of checkerboard solutions, since treating people
differently in a way that cannot be defended by anything recognizable as a princi-
ple of justice appears intuitively objectionable.
solution, the pro tanto reason to reject such solutions should characteristically
prevail when reaching an all-things-considered judgment about what to do. In
this section, I consider whether Dworkin succeeds in establishing the truth of this
further claim.
Dworkin’s discussion of checkerboard solutions is meant to show only that the
ideal of integrity fits with our political beliefs and practices (because it explains
why we oppose internal compromises). His argument that integrity is indeed
valuable (and should characteristically trump justice in cases of conflict) comes
later in Law’s Empire. Let us now consider that argument.
Dworkin claims that integrity has a number of benefits, but he concentrates
primarily on its implications for political obligation. His argument that
integrity is necessary for political obligations to arise is lengthy and subtle, and
I can provide only a thumbnail sketch here.⁴⁴ Dworkin claims that political
obligations are a type of “associative obligation.” In other words, they are not
voluntarily incurred, but rather arise simply through one’s membership of a
political community. However, the political community must satisfy certain
criteria if political obligations are to arise. In particular, the community must
display pervasive and equal concern for all its members. Dworkin claims that
this requirement can be satisfied only if our political obligations are not
exhausted by explicit rules. If our obligations were exhausted by explicit rules,
then our political system could not display pervasive concern, because those
rules would inevitably contain gaps where we would be left to our own devices.
(In particular, when deciding what new rules to introduce, we would be free to
act in our own self-interest, without concern for other people.) However, non-
explicit obligations can be inferred from the explicit rules only if those rules are
coherent.⁴⁵ Moreover, the coherence between the society’s rules must extend to
the principles underlying those rules, since the non-explicit obligations will be
drawn largely from those principles. Therefore, coherence in principle (which
Dworkin often equates with integrity) is a necessary condition of political
obligation.
In Section C, I shall question the extent to which this explanation of why
integrity is valuable provides support for the favoured interpretation. However,
for now it is important to note that there is at least one way in which they seem to
fit together nicely. The favoured interpretation claims that there are two principles
underlying our opposition to checkerboard solutions—the principle that we
should not treat people differently in a way that is unjust, and the principle that
we should not treat people in a way that cannot be supported by any recognizable
principle of justice. Dworkin’s account of political obligations appears to support
⁴⁴ I draw particularly on Alexander & Kress, supra note 42, at 778 in offering this reconstruction
of an argument that occupies Dworkin for nearly 30 pages in Law’s Empire (195–224). I focus only
on those aspects of the argument that are relevant to my present concerns.
⁴⁵ More than mere consistency is required. E.g., one could not infer (a pervasive set of ) non-
explicit obligations from a set of three legal rules that bore no relationship to each other.
144 Dale Smith
the former principle. A society that does not respect this principle does not display
equal concern for all its members and so does not merit everyone’s allegiance.
Even if there are principles of fairness that support the differential treatment,
those who lose out under the checkerboard solution are being sacrificed to give
people an equal share of political influence, and it might be difficult to explain to
them why they should give their allegiance to such a society.
This, in turn, suggests that Dworkin is correct in claiming that integrity should
characteristically trump justice when these two values conflict. For political obli-
gations to arise, it is not necessary that political decisions always be perfectly just,
but it is necessary that such decisions display equal concern for all members of the
community, and this would appear to rule out checkerboard solutions (which
necessarily treat people differently in a way that is unsupported by any recogniz-
able principle of justice, and so fail to show equal concern for all members of the
community). Moreover, if we allowed justice to trump integrity on a regular basis,
we would no longer be able to infer non-explicit principles from the explicit rules
of our community (since those rules would lack the necessary coherence in princi-
ple). This would mean that not only would the law have ceased to show equal
concern, but it would also have ceased to show pervasive concern.
There is, however, a well-known objection to this line of reasoning. Dworkin’s
critics often argue that, where a just outcome cannot be obtained for everyone, it
is better to obtain that outcome for as many people as possible, even if this reduces
the coherence of the law and does not provide equal treatment for those who are
left out. For example, Raz suggests that “we accept the nearest approximation to
morally sound solutions that we can obtain, even though by doing so we may
reduce the coherence of the law.”⁴⁶ If this is right, we should be more willing to
accept checkerboard solutions (and other breaches of integrity) than Dworkin
suggests, where this is necessary to reduce injustice. We might still recognize a pro
tanto reason to avoid checkerboard solutions, but we would not regard that reason
as characteristically trumping considerations of justice.
However, this objection does not really engage with Dworkin’s claim that we
must not allow justice characteristically to trump integrity, or else our community
would cease to express equal and pervasive concern for all its members, and our
case for the existence of political obligations would collapse. To determine which
side in this debate is correct, it appears that we must weigh up the value of doing
justice to as many people as possible against the value of equal and pervasive con-
cern. However, rather than engaging in the difficult task of weighing up those val-
ues, I shall explore a different line of thought. I shall argue that the value of equal
and pervasive concern does not unequivocally support Dworkin’s position, and
⁴⁶ Raz, supra note 4, at 312–313. The context makes it clear that Raz endorses the view he is
ascribing to us. Similarly, Wasserstrom, supra note 17, at 267 asserts that, if he were an egalitarian in a
libertarian society, he would support legislation that made the community’s law more egalitarian,
even if this meant that the law was less coherent overall.
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 145
⁵¹ Alexander & Kress, supra note 42, at 779–780. I have changed their example slightly, to avoid a
complication they themselves note.
⁵² If it strikes one as implausible that such a law could ever be passed, imagine that there were a
number of high-profile corporate collapses blamed on the practice of nepotism in private industry,
whereas powerful lobby groups supported nepotism in the public sector.
⁵³ Alexander & Kress, supra note 42, at 780.
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 147
for political obligation. However, Dworkin must show that this is characteristically
the case. Presumably, this will depend on a number of contingent facts about the
particular legal system being considered, and Dworkin does not even begin to
show that it is true of the particular legal systems he has in mind.⁵⁴
If I am right, Dworkin has failed to show that the value of integrity deserves
the place of special prominence that he reserves for it. In particular, he has not
given us sufficient reason to believe that integrity should characteristically prevail
over justice when these two values conflict. This has several significant implica-
tions for his broader legal and political theory, of which I shall briefly mention
two. First, it threatens to undermine his directions to both legislators and judges.
Dworkin claims that legislators should, when making new law, strive to keep the
law coherent in principle. He also claims that judges should, when identifying
and enforcing the law, seek to view the law as being coherent in principle (167).
However, these directions presuppose the pre-eminence of integrity. Coherence
in principle should be the primary goal of legislators and judges only if integrity
should characteristically trump justice. The fact that Dworkin has failed to estab-
lish that integrity should characteristically prevail means that the correctness of
his direction to legislators and judges is called into question.
Secondly, Dworkin’s failure to show that integrity should characteristically
prevail over justice means that his attempt to establish the existence of political
obligations is undermined. Dworkin argues that integrity must be valuable
because it is necessary for political obligations to arise. However, we can reverse
this line of reasoning and argue that—if integrity is not as valuable as Dworkin
claims—he has failed to demonstrate the existence of political obligations.
Unless integrity should characteristically prevail over justice, we lack sufficient
reason to achieve the level of coherence among (and within) explicit legal rules
that is required for us to be able to infer non-explicit legal principles to fill in gaps
in those rules. Yet, on Dworkin’s argument, such coherence is required in order
for political obligations to arise. Therefore, Dworkin’s failure to show that
integrity should characteristically prevail over justice means that he has failed to
show that we should achieve the level of coherence among (and within) explicit
legal rules that he claims is necessary to give rise to political obligations.
⁵⁴ Earlier in this section, we saw another way in which checkerboard solutions promote equal
concern—they give everybody some input into the content of political decisions. This, too, would
have to be weighed against the way in which checkerboard solutions undermine equal concern.
148 Dale Smith
Dworkin’s broader theory. That discussion has highlighted that there is not one,
but several, principles of integrity. There are at least two factors underlying our
attitude towards checkerboard solutions—a concern about differential treat-
ment, and a concern that legal decisions should reflect recognizable principles of
justice. If Dworkin is correct in claiming that it is integrity that explains our
attitude towards internal compromises, then both of these concerns must reflect
aspects of integrity. This in itself poses no problem for Dworkin. There are
numerous (correct) principles of justice, and there is no reason why there cannot
be several (correct) principles of integrity as well. However, in addition to the
two principles that underlie our attitude towards checkerboard solutions, there is
at least one more principle of integrity that has little to do with checkerboard
solutions. This is the principle that requires coherence between the legal princi-
ples that underlie and justify different legal rules, so that they form a single,
comprehensive vision of justice. We saw that Dworkin treats this principle as
part of the ideal of integrity, and that he recognizes that violation of this principle
poses a threat to integrity that is distinct from the threat posed by checkerboard
solutions.⁵⁵ Indeed, Kress suggests that it is this principle that Dworkin most
often refers to when discussing the ideal of integrity.⁵⁶ The problem is that, in
seeking to show that the ideal of integrity fits with our political practices,
Dworkin relies almost exclusively upon his discussion of checkerboard solutions,
and this principle of integrity is not relevant to that discussion. Therefore, even if
(via his discussion of checkerboard solutions) he has established that the first two
principles of integrity fit with our political practices, he has not shown that this
third principle of integrity does so.
Dworkin does suggest that, while our legal system often breaches this prin-
ciple, we regard this as a defect (184). However, more needs to be said to show
that a central principle of integrity satisfies one of only two conditions that
Dworkin imposes upon its acceptability (namely, the dimension of fit),⁵⁷ espe-
cially as he concedes that the evidence on this point is equivocal (since our legal
system often breaches this principle). This means that Dworkin’s defence of
integrity is incomplete. He may have shown that some principles of integrity fit
our political practices, but he has not shown that all do. Nor can he assume that,
because some principles of integrity satisfy that requirement, the rest must, too.
It is unlikely that every correct principle of justice fits our political practices, and
there is no reason to assume at the outset that integrity differs in this respect.
This would not be such a problem for Dworkin if this particular principle of
integrity did not play such an important role in his jurisprudential theory. Once
we expand our focus beyond checkerboard solutions, Dworkin’s legal theory is at
least as much concerned with coherence in principle between laws as it is with
coherence in principle within laws. The fact that Dworkin fails adequately to
explain why we should accept this third principle of integrity should therefore be
of substantial concern to him.
Dworkin might seek to avoid this problem by arguing that there is in fact only
one principle of integrity (albeit one that can be violated in different ways—for
example, via checkerboard solutions or via a lack of coherence between laws). He
does claim that “the only basis we might have for opposing checkerboard
compromises . . . is the idea of integrity, that the community must respect
principles necessary to justify one part of the law in other parts as well” (210).
The requirement that the community respect principles necessary to justify one
part of the law in other parts as well provides the basis of Dworkin’s discussion of
coherence in principle between laws, and he appears to be suggesting here that it
also provides the basis for opposing checkerboard solutions. However, this
suggestion is puzzling. When seeking to achieve integrity between laws, we are
seeking to ensure that different laws cohere with each other (and that the prin-
ciples underlying those laws also cohere with each other). When seeking to erad-
icate checkerboard solutions, on the other hand, we are seeking to eliminate
individual laws that treat different people differently in a way that cannot be sup-
ported by any recognizable principle of justice. That there are two distinct sets of
principles in play here (one requiring coherence between legal rules and princi-
ples, the other requiring that an individual law not discriminate between people
in a way that cannot be supported by any recognizable principle of justice) seems
obvious. It is further supported by the argument in Part II, Section C that we
cannot explain what is wrong with checkerboard solutions on the basis that they
both uphold and reject certain principles of justice (something that may be said
of a body of laws that contains inconsistent legal rules or principles).
It may be that we cannot display equal concern for all members of our commu-
nity if we adopt principles that are not recognizable as expressing equal concern. In
a society marked by moral disagreement, we cannot necessarily expect society to
adopt our conception of equal concern, but we can at least expect it to adopt a
recognizable conception. So long as the community adopts a recognizable concep-
tion of equal concern, we can feel that we are part of a genuine community, even if
we would prefer that it adopt a different conception.⁵⁸ However, it is not the case
that only recognizable principles of justice reflect a recognizable conception of
equal concern. In particular, checkerboard solutions are (at least in some cases)
based on principles of fairness that are recognizable as expressing equal concern
(since they are designed to produce an equal distribution of political influence). It
is unclear why this is not enough—why, that is, we need principles of justice that
we can recognize as expressing equal concern. Provided each side champions
recognizable principles of justice,⁵⁹ why should it matter if a recognizable princi-
ple of fairness requires us to compromise those principles of justice in a way that
does not reflect any further, recognizable principle of justice?
It could be argued that there is some sort of category error in resolving a matter
of principle (dealing with rights or other moral issues) by reference to something
that is not recognizable as a principle of justice. Dworkin defines justice as being
concerned with achieving morally defensible outcomes, and so it is principles of
justice that must be used to resolve matters of principle. Using something that is
not recognizable as a principle of justice reveals a misunderstanding as to the type
of solution that is required for such a problem and/or a conceptual misunder-
standing of what counts as a principle of justice.
However, this explanation is of little assistance to Dworkin. The requirement
that laws should reflect recognizable principles of justice is meant to be a princi-
ple of integrity, where integrity is meant to be a political value distinct from
justice and fairness. Avoiding category errors or conceptual misunderstandings,
on the other hand, would not seem to amount to a political value at all. (The
other principle of integrity relevant to checkerboard solutions, on the other
hand, does represent a political value, since it prohibits unjust differential treat-
ment.) Moreover, even if the importance of avoiding category errors or concep-
tual misunderstandings does reflect a distinct political value of integrity, it is not
clear that such a value should characteristically trump competing considerations
of justice or fairness. Obviously, it is desirable to avoid category errors and
conceptual misunderstandings, but it is not obvious that this is characteristically
more important than avoiding or minimizing instances of injustice or unfairness.
Therefore, this explanation does not seem well suited to supporting Dworkin’s
⁵⁸ A similar argument is suggested by J. Waldron, The Rule of Law in Contemporary Liberal Theory,
2 Ratio Juris 79, 83–84 (1989).
⁵⁹ This proviso is necessary so that we can know that they are putting forward views about justice
(since principles of fairness are meant to govern disagreements about justice).
152 Dale Smith
IV. Conclusion
⁶⁰ See supra note 17, which points out that a number of commentators have tried to explain our
opposition to checkerboard solutions by reference to the values of justice or fairness, not integrity.
The Many Faces of Political Integrity 153
I.
I am not now, nor ever was, a member of the Critical Legal Studies (CLS)
movement. But I want to consider the adequacy of the answer Ronald Dworkin
gave almost twenty years ago to an objection (to his conception of law as
integrity), which he attributed to CLS though he himself referred to it in more
general terms as “internal skepticism.”¹ I want to consider the adequacy of his
response, not out of any desire to revive the intellectual fortunes of CLS and cer-
tainly not as a complaint that Professor Dworkin failed to do justice to CLS criti-
cisms during the brief lifetime of the movement. CLS was never particularly
interested in Dworkin, nor he in them.² But they had a common interest in what
I would like to call “the background elements” of a legal system—the principles
and policies that lie in back of the rules and texts that positivists emphasize.
Ronald Dworkin and Duncan Kennedy, for example, are both theorists of the
legal background. But what they say about it is very different. Dworkin thinks
recourse to the background affords the resources necessary for legal decision in
cases where the foreground law is disputed or indeterminate. Kennedy thinks the
background is so riven with contradiction as to be capable of offering spurious
support for everything and determinate support for nothing in legal reasoning.³
So I am interested in what one might think of as Dworkin’s descriptive
optimism—his view that the background elements (of a legal system like that of
the United States) are capable of bearing the weight of determinate argument
that he wants to assign to it in his theory of law.
I will argue that, in order to answer the CLS critique, a defender of law as
integrity has to place considerable emphasis on what Professor Dworkin regards as
the constructive side of his argument. Instead of saying that the legal background is
coherent, Dworkin has to say that it is capable of being made coherent at the
hands of a sufficiently resourceful interpreter. Unfortunately the response cannot
rest there. Dworkin’s constructivism might licence an ingenious and versatile
manipulation of existing legal materials: we take the parts of the (often contradic-
tory background) that we like or approve, and we use them to add some sort of
doctrinal credibility to the positions we are aiming at. But it is not clear that this
fits the justification that Dworkin furnished for his method in Law’s Empire, for
that justification requires a party to argue, not merely that there are legal materials
which he can make use of in support of his brief, but that he is using background
materials in a way that keeps faith with the network of mutual commitments that
makes us the community we are.⁴ Unless the Dworkinian advocate can make such
an argument, he has nothing with which he can resist the urgings of a pragmatist,
to the effect that we should not bother with the background material at all, once
the foreground has been shown to be indeterminate, but we should make our case
directly for whatever is likely to promote the social good. To rebut that pragmatist
position—which Dworkin acknowledges has to be rebutted to make room for his
conception of law as integrity⁵—it is not enough to show that we can make some-
thing coherent and attractive out of the legal background. The Dworkinian advo-
cate has to show that we must attempt to make something coherent and attractive
out of the legal background. And what counts as a good faith attempt has to be
responsive to the ideas lying behind that “must.” My worry is that the construc-
tivism that Dworkin appeals to, in order to evade the CLS critique, succeeds (if it
does) only at the cost of cutting loose of the idea that the community is in some
sense already committed to a coherent and principled position which the
Dworkinian lawyer has a responsibility to unearth.
So: my aim in this paper is to explore the extent to which Professor Dworkin is
put to a hard choice between the agile and discerning constructivism he needs to
respond to CLS, on the one hand, and the integrity thesis about the commitments
of the community which he invokes to justify the claim that making coherent
sense of the existing legal materials, foreground and background, is something we
are morally required to do. I think Dworkin really is confronted with a dilemma
here, and I am not sure that a way through it can be negotiated. If he hangs on to
the integrity position, he makes it harder to respond to the skepticism of CLS. But
if he weakens the integrity requirement or loosens its connection to what is to
count as an appropriate mode of legal argument, then he leaves himself defenseless
against the pragmatist position that—clever though it is—the constructivism of
Dworkinian legal argument serves no useful purpose.
II.
The key to Dworkin’s jurisprudence is and has always been a view about what law
involves besides a heap of enacted rules (constitutions, codes, and statutes).⁷
Dworkin argues that as well as the enacted rules, which we see in the foreground
of legal analysis, a working legal system also comprises background policies and
principles, either those associated with particular enactments—as when we say
the policy of the Sherman Act is to foster competition—or those that pervade the
body of the law as a whole—as when we talk about “the well established policy of
English law of imposing a more extensive liability on intentional wrongdoers than
on careless defendants,”⁸ or as when we invoke the maxim that “[n]o one shall be
permitted to profit by his own fraud.”⁹ Dworkin believes that it is appropriate to
⁶ I must say, though, that my first-year law students notice at once the connection between
Kennedy’s work in CLS and Dworkin’s jurisprudence. And they do ask me what, if anything, has
been written to refute the implicit CLS critique. (They are too young to know that analytic legal
philosophers are supposed to disdain and ignore CLS ideas.)
⁷ The Model of Rules I, in R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (revised ed., 1977).
⁸ Three Rivers District Council and Others v. Governor and Company of the Bank of England (No 3)
[2003] 2 A.C. 1 (HL), at 162.
⁹ Box v. Lanier, 112 Tenn. 393, 409, 79 S.W. 1042, 1045 (1903).
158 Jeremy Waldron
invoke these principles and policies in legal argument and indeed that it is inap-
propriate not to. Not only are they important legal resources to be put to use in
hard cases where the foreground law is indeterminate, but they are also capable of
standing against foreground law (as the principle last-mentioned above stood
against the New York state legislation relating to wills in Riggs v. Palmer).¹⁰ Indeed
a case may be made that background principles and policies have to be assumed in
order to explain why the foreground law has the force it does.¹¹ Certainly any
jurisprudence that neglects these background elements is inadequate.
There is a lot in Professor Dworkin’s account of the legal background that I
do not want to dispute. In various places, he distinguishes between policies and
principles, as different types of background element: he associates “policy” with
social goals and “principle” with norms or reasons that command a particular
distribution of benefits, freedoms, and responsibilities.¹² I have no quarrel with
that, nor with the arguments that Dworkin rests on that distinction. I accept
Dworkin’s view that background principles (in the narrower sense) are capable
of sustaining claims of right.¹³ I also see little to quarrel with in what he says
about the logical character of the contribution that principles and policies make
to legal argument: he talks of the dimension of “weight,” which distinguishes
their contribution from the contribution made by rules.¹⁴ Finally, I have no
quarrel with what Professor Dworkin says about the kind of presence that prin-
ciples and policies have in a legal system. He argues—convincingly in my
view—that their status as law “lies not in a particular decision of some legisla-
ture or court, but in a sense of appropriateness developed in the profession and
the public over time.”¹⁵ (I think, too, that he is right to point up the difficulty
this poses for H.L.A. Hart’s concept of the rule of recognition.) None of these
matters is in dispute between Dworkin and the Crits. In fact, although CLS is
certainly less optimistic than Professor Dworkin is about the contribution that
these background elements can make to determinate legal reasoning, their criti-
cisms nevertheless presuppose that the legal background is at least as important
for jurisprudence as Dworkin claims it is. If anything they are less sympathetic
¹⁶ See, e.g. P. Gabel, Book Review of Taking Rights Seriously, 91 Harv. L. Rev. 302, 303–311
(1977).
¹⁷ This drew some of Dworkin’s early critics to the possibility that discrete principles may be “rec-
ognized,” within a positivist framework: see J. Raz, Legal Principles and the Limits of Law, 81 Yale L.J.
823, 843 ff. (1972). See Dworkin’s response in Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 7, at 68–71.
160 Jeremy Waldron
case with which we are primarily concerned. We state the principle so that its appli-
cation to the case at hand is patent, rather than a matter of further interpretation.
This suggests that the distinction between steps (1) and (2) is somewhat mislead-
ing, and that we might do better to think more directly about the relation between
the legal background and the instant case.
And that is the model suggested in some parts of Law’s Empire. The idea there is
that in any given case, a judgment for the plaintiff, say, is to be defended by show-
ing that it coheres better with existing legal materials than a judgment for the
defendant would. “Coheres better with” is understood as what Professor Dworkin
calls a post-interpretive claim. Counsel for the plaintiff offers a justificatory theory
which he says makes sense of all or most of the existing legal materials—prior
decisions, established doctrine, legislation, and so on—and he shows that that
theory would also justify a decision in favor of his client.¹⁸ The defendant offers a
contrary case, and counsel for the plaintiff will argue that the theory offered by the
defense is either less attractive in itself than the one that he has presented or covers
less of the existing materials than his does, or both. Of course, it is unlikely that
either of the theories on offer will stand in a justificatory relation to all the existing
legal materials. Some materials may be simply irrelevant—too far from the issues
in question in terms of the concerns they might be thought to embody, even
under the most abstract characterization. And some may have to be treated as out-
liers, relevant but incapable of being reconciled with the theory being put for-
ward. Also, it is unlikely that either theory—plaintiff ’s or defendant’s—will
amount to (what anyone regards as) a perfect theory of justice. Even allowing for
outliers, both theories will have to accommodate decisions (precedents, enact-
ments) that their proponents might not support if they were setting out their
favored account of justice on a blank slate. Still, plaintiff will argue that the theory
the defendant invokes to make the existing law look coherent is further from an
ideal theory of justice than the theory he (the plaintiff ) invokes, and defendant
will return the compliment. So they will argue back and forth on this dimension
of justice as well as on the dimension of how much of the legal record their rival
theories cover.
When we put the matter in this way, the distinction between background and
foreground elements in a legal system—between principles and rules—is seen as a
sort of façon de parler. What the existing law really amounts to is nothing more than
a mass of decisions—by constitution framers, by legislators, and by thousands of
earlier judges. Relying on background elements in current legal argument is not
really a matter of introducing a different set of provisions, viz. legal principles as
opposed to legal rules. It is rather a particular way of working with that existing mass
of decisions, though it may also involve self-conscious reference to the recorded
¹⁸ I shall leave out of account issues about the compartmentalization of law—see Dworkin,
Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 250–254—since these do not really affect the criticisms I shall be con-
sidering. Everything I say can be qualified with reference to “local priority” or not, as the reader
wishes.
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 161
efforts of previous decision-makers (earlier judges, for example), to work with the
mass of previous decisions that confronted them in just the same sort of way.¹⁹
So there are these two ways of characterizing Dworkin’s approach: (i) his earlier
characterization in terms of norms called principles, i.e. norms that were comprised
in the law just like rules—only in the background of the law rather than in the fore-
ground; and (ii) his later approach which talked of rival theories put forward by
those who were working with the existing law to justify a current decision. I don’t
really think they are different, or that any difference between the two really matters.
A principle (or a policy) is nothing much more than a theory (or an element of a
theory) about what makes sense of the existing law, expressed directly in normative
terms.²⁰ We can say, in the voice of the theorist (or the current advocate) that the
best interpretation of the existing law—the theory that covers most of it and makes
it look good—is that it does not permit people to profit from their own fraud. Or
we can “point to” or “cite” a principle—“No one is to profit from his own fraud”—
more or less conscious of the fact that this in effect is something we read into the
law when we commit ourselves to the theory just mentioned. The latter character-
ization will seem particularly appropriate, when the mass of materials we are con-
fronting includes holdings by other judges which interpret the materials that
confronted them in just the way that we interpret the materials that confront us:
those holdings will enable us to point to something like “authority” for the princi-
ples we are relying on.²¹ The alternative characterization will be more useful, how-
ever, in cases where we have no such authority, but are striking out on a new
interpretive path, because we have a theory which we think better explains the
existing law (and generates a result for our client) than previous efforts at interpre-
tation do. Dworkin seems happy to move back and forth between these models in
Law’s Empire. Sometimes he says—in line with characterization (ii)—that a judge
“must choose between eligible interpretations [theories] by asking which shows the
community’s structure of institutions and decisions—its public standards as a
whole—in a better light.”²² And sometimes he says—in line with characterization
(i)—that his method “asks judges to assume . . . that law is structured by a coherent
set of principles.”²³ As I say, I don’t think anything much turns on this distinc-
tion;²⁴ I mention it only in order to make it clear that I think the two amount more
or less to the same thing, and that the critical points I am going to develop can be
applied to Professor Dworkin’s jurisprudence in both its phases.
¹⁹ This last point turns out to be quite important; see infra Section VI, text accompanying notes
56–58.
²⁰ Thus Dworkin answers the question of what principles the law contains by saying that it con-
tains those principles which belong to the soundest theory of the settled (foreground) law. See
Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 7, at 340 and Altman, supra, note 2, at 213.
²¹ . . . just as I pointed to “authority” for the various principles I cited, supra in notes 8, 9, and 12.
²² Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 256. ²³ Id. at 243.
²⁴ These two ways of approaching the matter are also noted by A. Hunt, Law’s Empire or Legal
Imperialism, in Reading Dworkin Critically 9, 36–37 (A. Hunt ed., 1992). Hunt thinks the oscil-
lation between them matters much more than I do.
162 Jeremy Waldron
III.
Much of the CLS critique of Dworkin’s work is superficial:²⁵ for example, CLS
scholars charge that Dworkin’s jurisprudence is “elitist,” that he is insufficiently
concerned with “the deprived and disadvantaged in society,” that he is in denial
about the connection between law and politics, that his approach to justice is
too abstract, or that he “exhibits a profound antipathy for common consciousness
among the citizens.”²⁶ Dworkin himself, however, has identified a line of
CLS argument that poses a considerable threat to his enterprise.
The threat presents itself as follows. The law we confront in a modern democ-
racy is not the work of a single author. We do not live in a one party state, nor do we
even live in a unitary state. Law-makers of various persuasions coexist at various
levels or in the various tributaries of our legal system, and contribute to the growth
of the law from their diverse moral and political perspectives. Moreover, we live in a
society whose law is the repository of its checkered political history. When one
party succeeds another in electoral competition, it does not attempt to wipe the
legal slate clean and begin all over again; instead the latest generation of statesmen
work incrementally to make such modest changes in the law as their priorities dic-
tate and their political circumstances permit, leaving the remainder—the work of
the predecessors—to coexist comfortably or uncomfortably with whatever changes
they have managed to make.²⁷ The law in fact is a patchwork of provisions, the
work of a multitude of authors living and dead, with diverse and conflicting politi-
cal agendas, and diverse and conflicting commitments of principle.
In the midst of this patchwork—in the midst of this mess, we might say—
Dworkin’s lawyer is supposed to be able to find sufficient coherence to assert cred-
ibly that the law is pervaded by principles which favor his client’s case and to argue
credibly against any similar but opposing claim made on behalf of his opponent.
But why should we assume that this is possible? As Dworkin acknowledges, noth-
ing in the way the law was produced guarantees that the lawyer or the judge will
succeed in finding a coherent interpretation of it.²⁸ Or if he can find a coherent
interpretation of the patchwork, nothing in the way that the law was produced
guarantees that his success precludes similar success for his opponent: nothing
guarantees that the law has a shape amenable to a unique coherent justification of
principle.²⁹ Without that guarantee, or at any rate without a reasonable prospect
wrested away from their liberal opponents. All that is there, waiting in the law for
the rival parties to come along and raid in their latest forays as litigators.
Duncan Kennedy offers the tightest version of this view.³³ He believes the con-
flicting tendencies in the law can be resolved into two opposed visions of the indi-
vidual and society—an individualist vision and an altruist vision—and that these
two visions are represented haphazardly in the law that confronts us as the high-
water marks of the ascendancy in law-making of first one tendency and then of the
other tendency.³⁴ Hence, what is or appears to be at stake for a given individual
engaged in litigation will usually present itself as one or other of these tendencies,
and Professor Kennedy’s position is that the body of law that any litigation draws
upon, and that the parties look to for support for their rival positions, is also riven
with the contradictory appearance of both positions. From the advocates’ point of
view, the result is an uncomfortable awareness that there is enough in the law for
his opponent to make an argument of principle every bit as convincing (or as
unconvincing) as his own. And from the judge’s point of view, there is the sense
that his decision might go either way: the judge may be predisposed to approach a
case in the individualist mode, but may find himself suddenly, as Kennedy puts it,
“shifting modes,”³⁵ attracted suddenly by the lines of available background argu-
ment that might sustain legal argument for the side that represents the altruistic
tendency. Either way, whether the judge shifts modes or not, or whatever the
direction in which the shift takes place, he will find no difficulty in constructing
an argument of exactly the sort, drawing on exactly the sort of elements, that
Dworkin recommends. For Kennedy is also a student of the legal background: the
only difference is that his more realistic scrutiny of it has not convinced him, as
Dworkin is convinced, that it yields to only one compelling argument of principle
in difficult cases.³⁶
Dworkin, as I said, acknowledges the importance of this objection. He calls it a
form of internal skepticism³⁷—to be distinguished from external or philosophical
³³ See Altman, supra note 2, for the view that Kennedy’s critique is the most dangerous for
Dworkin’s enterprise. As a matter of fact, Professor Dworkin barely refers to Kennedy’s article: there is
one reference, in a slightly different context, in Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 438 n.26. (Dworkin’s
other references to Kennedy in Law’s Empire are to a bibliography of CLS that Kennedy
co-authored.) Still, Dworkin does acknowledge the substance of Kennedy’s position: he says that the
story of our legal system told by CLS is a story “of two deeply antagonistic ideologies at war within the
law, one drawn, perhaps, from communitarian impulses of altruism and mutual concern and the
other from the contradictory ideas of egoism, self-sufficiency, and judgmental moralism.” Law’s
Empire, supra note 1, at 272.
³⁴ Professor Kennedy also believes that these visions are present within each of us, and are not best
understood as associated, respectively, with particular parties, classes or factions in society. See
Kennedy, Form and Substance, supra note 3, at 1774–1776; see also D. Kennedy, The Structure of
Blackstone’s Commentaries, 205 Buffalo L. Rev., 28, 211–213 (1979).
³⁵ Kennedy, Form and Substance, supra note 3, at 1776.
³⁶ See also D. Kennedy, A Critique of Adjudication (fin de siècle) 34–37 (1977).
³⁷ Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 79, 266–275. For an objection to this equation,
see P. Schlag, Missing Pieces: A Cognitive Approach to Law, 67 Texas L. Rev., 1195, 1198–1200
(1989).
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 165
skepticism about the very ideas of value and coherence, which he thinks is a dis-
traction in jurisprudence³⁸—and insists that it has to be taken seriously.³⁹ It is not
out of the question, he acknowledges, that the existing law could be so riddled
with inconsistency as to be unamenable to the sort of analysis he proposes. After
all, we know the foreground law is inconsistent, if not in its direct normative
implications,⁴⁰ then in the spirit that informs it—in the purposes, principles and
policies that must be assumed to make sense of it. The Dworkinian judge “knows
that legislative supremacy gives force to some statutes that are inconsistent in prin-
ciple with others . . . But he assumes that these contradictions are not so pervasive
and intractable . . . that his task is impossible.” The question now is: can that
assumption be defended?
IV.
Dworkin’s first pass at the objection is to deny that the extent of contradiction is as
great as the CLS scholars make it out to be. “The literature of critical legal studies
announces rather than defends these claims [about pervasive contradictions], as if
they were self-evident.”⁴¹ Pierre Schlag thinks this is just summary dismissal of
CLS criticism,⁴² but he is wrong and wrong, I suspect, for two reasons. He is
wrong, first, because Dworkin does not rest here on a flat denial. Indeed, he goes
on to mobilize other arguments, which I will consider in a moment. And Schlag is
wrong, secondly, because there may be more to the factual disagreement about the
extent of contradiction than meets the eye.
I shall return to the second point in Section VIII. But for the moment, I would
like to explore the first point, the one that does not involve Dworkin simply dis-
puting the extent of contradictions. After all, Dworkin is hardly in a position to
deny the existence of something like contradiction or incoherence in the law. On
the contrary, the background presupposition of his embrace of integrity is that the
settled law of any community has had multiple authors—framers, legislators,
judges, etc.—with quite radically differing visions of justice. (If there were no con-
flict between the various views about justice expressed in the enacted law, there
would be nothing for the Dworkinian ideal of integrity to do.)⁴³ So any attempt
to rebut internal skepticism simply by saying there are no contradictions, or by
saying that whatever contradictions there are, are low-level and unimportant,
V.
So what else does he say? Dworkin’s second response is to argue that this sort of
CLS skepticism neglects an important philosophical distinction between compet-
ing principles (such as autonomy and mutual concern) which may figure in a sin-
gle view about justice, and contradictory principles (such as equality and
inequality) which cannot possibly be combined in one coherent conception.⁴⁵
Referring to a tort law example he uses in Chapter 7 of Law’s Empire, Dworkin
says there is no contradiction in recognizing both a principle of collective solidar-
ity and a principle of individual fault-based responsibility: “on the contrary, any
moral vision would be defective if it wholly disowned either impulse. . . . No gen-
eral interpretation that denied either one would be plausible; integrity could not
be served if either were wholly disavowed.”⁴⁶ The challenge, he says, is to articu-
late a principled balance between them in the interpretive theory that we use to
justify our particular legal conclusions.
Now, what Dworkin says here is right, as far as it goes. Most moral theories, includ-
ing theories of justice, do have elements that stand in tension with one another; and it
is the mark of moral maturity not to regard this as a logical defect, but rather to see it
as an inevitable feature of our coming to terms with the plurality of values and princi-
ples.⁴⁷ But does pointing this out meet the objection? I fear it does not.
CLS scholars like Kennedy deny that the individualist and altruist elements
they discern in the legal background are merely prima facie principles or the sort of
⁴⁴ See H. L. A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 593,
614–615 (1957). Hart’s response to the Realist critique was “to emphasize that the hard core of set-
tled meaning is law in some centrally important sense and that even if there are borderlines, there
must first be lines. If this were not so the notion of rules controlling courts’ decisions would be sense-
less as some of the ‘Realists’—in their most extreme moods, and, I think, on bad grounds—claimed.”
See also H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law 136–141 (2d ed. 1994); H. L. A. Hart, American
Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream, in his collection, Essays in
Jurisprudence and Philosophy 123, 126–132 (1983).
⁴⁵ Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 269–275. ⁴⁶ Id. at 269–270.
⁴⁷ In this paper, I will not explore the tension between this view of moral pluralism and the
more holistic/hedgehog approach that Dworkin defends in other contexts. See, e.g. R. Dworkin,
Sovereign Virtue (2000).
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 167
array of views about justice, not merely a diverse array of impulses (some selfish,
some communitarian) which would later have to be organized into a single theory
of justice by the Dworkinian interpreter.⁵² It is not a case of one statute’s having
been passed by an autonomy faction and another statute’s having been enacted by
the party of mutual concern, and of its never having occurred to anyone except the
judge (now faced with the two statutes together) that a suitably complex position
could accommodate both principles.
I have not said anything so far about Kennedy’s even more skeptical claim, that
(whether we regard individualism and altruism as competing balances or as com-
peting principles to be balanced) no metaprinciple of balance can be defended as
objectively correct. Kennedy says:
[I]t is futile to imagine that moral and practical conflict will yield to analysis in terms of
higher level concepts. The meaning of contradiction at the level of abstraction is that there
is no metasystem that would, if only we could find it, key us into one mode or the other as
circumstances “required.” . . . [W]e cannot “balance” individualist and altruist values . . .
except in the tautological sense that we can, as a matter of fact, decide if we have to. The
imagery of balancing presupposes exactly the kind of more abstract unit of measurement
that the sense of contradiction excludes.⁵³
This claim is supposed to cut off an approach that the Dworkinian lawyer might
take in the face of what we have said so far. Instead of saying that he is trying to
balance conflicting tendencies whose presence in the law does not reflect earlier
attempts to balance them, the Dworkinian lawyer could say that he is purporting
to replace the existing—and admittedly contradictory—balancings embedded in
the law by individualists and altruists, with a true balance, one that would be nei-
ther individualist nor altruist, but just correct. Kennedy wants to pre-empt this by
announcing that the idea of a true balance is simply out of the question.
To the extent he considers it, I think Dworkin regards this as an expression
of external skepticism about right answers in regard to balancing, and as such
he rejects it out of hand.⁵⁴ True, it may not be possible for the Dworkinian
lawyer to demonstrate that the new balancing—with which he proposes to
supersede the contradictory balancings embedded in the law by individualists
and altruists—is objectively correct. But non-demonstrability is not the same as
falsity or futility.
I think this last part of Kennedy’s critique is properly dismissed in this
way. But whether the dismissal ultimately helps Dworkin is a question we must
postpone until after we have examined the merits—in jurisprudence—of the
constructivist approach that we are now imagining the Dworkinian lawyer
undertaking.
⁵² Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 178; see also Waldron, Law and Disagreement,
supra note 27, at 193–194. ⁵³ Kennedy, Form and Substance, supra note 3, at 1775.
⁵⁴ Cf. Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra, note 1, at 267.
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 169
VI.
that this is roughly correct,⁶⁴ and that the case for internal skepticism cannot be
merely that Dworkin has offered no algorithm for correctness in legal argument.
Still, one is inclined to say: something must count as tending to show—or
there must be something one can do which counts as attempting to show—that
the argument one is making is better than any opposing argument one can
imagine being made by an opponent in the same case, drawing constructively
upon the same array of materials. I mean something must count as that, apart from
one’s consciousness that one’s own argument can be made or that it just is the
argument one is making. This is because one is also conscious—confronted as one
is, with this mass of contradictory materials—that one’s opponent’s argument can
be made as well.
I get the impression that Professor Dworkin is sometimes prepared to say that
this is a misplaced demand, analogous to what he regards as the unhelpful demand
that for a person who believes that moral propositions are objectively true or false,
something must count as trying to show that a given moral proposition is objec-
tively correct, over and above the mere assertion and re-assertion of that proposi-
tion.⁶⁵ At other times, however, he characterizes the phenomenology differently,
in a way that suggests that someone wedded to an interpretive argument may sen-
sibly regard himself as having reasons for thinking the argument he is wedded to is
correct. The characterization I have in mind is set out, in the first instance, in
regard to interpretive claims about literature:
Someone just converted to a new reading of Paradise Lost, trembling with the excitement
of discovery, thinks his new reading is right, that it is better than the one he has abandoned,
that those yet uninitiated have missed something genuine and important, that they do not
see the poem for what it really is. He thinks he has been driven by the truth, not that he has
chosen one interpretation to wear for the day because he fancies it like a necktie. He thinks
he has genuine, good reasons for accepting his new interpretation and that others, who
cling to the older view he now thinks wrong, have genuine, good reasons to change their
minds.⁶⁶
Now, I have no doubt that sometimes legal argument may have this character:
trembling with excitement, a jurist comes up with a new interpretation of existing
doctrine, a sense of something that others have missed, and of their having good
reasons to abandon their old tired reading in favor of one’s own. Sometimes it may
feel like that (though there would still be philosophical questions about what to
infer from such phenomenology). But is this how we expect it to be for most cases?
Is this phenomenology—the trembling excitement of discovery—likely to be
characteristic of legal work in the context of materials that are as contradictory as the
⁶⁴ But note that, anyway, the right answer motif is muted in Law’s Empire. I have discussed this
further in J. Waldron, The Rule of Law as a Theater of Debate, in Dworkin and his Critics ( J. Burley
ed., 2004)
⁶⁵ See Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 81; R. Dworkin, Objectivity and Truth: You’d
Better Believe It, 25 Philosophy and Public Affairs 87 (1996).
⁶⁶ Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 77.
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 173
CLS scholars say our existing American law is? For remember: Dworkin is offering
the constructive aspect of his argument as a way of finessing the CLS claim about
contradictions. Never mind how conflicted the law is, he says, never mind how
riddled it is with contradictions; one can always come up with some sort of con-
structive argument for one’s position. So the question is—if the legal materials are
as conflicted (and are known to be as conflicted) as, say, Duncan Kennedy thinks
they are⁶⁷—would one expect the process of constructive argument that Dworkin
promotes to have the sort of phenomenological flavor of “discovery” and “good
genuine reasons” that characterizes our imagined student’s new interpretation of
Paradise Lost? Given the knowledge that anyone faced with a set of contradictions
has about the opportunities that inconsistent premises offer for a multitude of
arguments in opposite directions, I think this is most unlikely.
We are contemplating the possibility that faced with an array of legal materials
as contradiction-ridden as Kennedy and other CLS scholars take them to be, a
constructive argument interpreting the law in favor of one side or the other in liti-
gation will be able to satisfy some very modest threshold of “fit.” Crudely, it will
make sense of roughly half of the materials it considers, and its proponent will be
conscious that any remotely competent work done on behalf of the other party
will also satisfy that threshold of fit, since it makes sense of the other half of the
(conflicting) legal materials under consideration. In these circumstances, should
we expect either advocate to make his argument with a burning consciousness that
he is right about the law and his opponent wrong? Should we expect the judge,
who entertains both arguments and understands the condition of the possibility
of each of them, to be conscious of a basis for discriminating between them?
Dworkin remains remarkably upbeat, as he faces the prospect of this even
rivalry between two equally viable theories purporting to make “sense” of the same
mess of contradictory legal decisions. What he says, at least about the judge’s situ-
ation, is this:
Hard cases arise, for any judge, when his threshold test [of fit] does not discriminate
between two or more interpretations of some statute or line of cases. Then he must choose
between eligible interpretations by asking which shows the community’s structure of insti-
tutions and decisions—its public standards as a whole—in a better light from the stand-
point of political morality. His own moral and political convictions are now directly
engaged.⁶⁸
The idea is that a judge, faced with two arguments that “fit” (in this quixotic
sense) an equal quantity of the contradictory legal materials, will resolve the issue
between them by considering which is superior on the merits, that is, on grounds
of justice or other substantial values. And that will be the tie-breaker.⁶⁹
⁶⁷ Of course, they may not be. But then Dworkin is thrown back on the position we discussed at
the end of Section IV: saying (Hart-style) to the skeptics: it is not really as bad as all that.
⁶⁸ Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, at 255–256.
⁶⁹ See also Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, supra note 7, at 340–341.
174 Jeremy Waldron
To understand what this position amounts to, we need to recall that on the CLS
account the legal materials are not just contradictory in some technical sense.
They are contradictory as between the main views about justice (and other sub-
stantial values) already held by diverse factions in society, and also as between the
main values that are likely to be at stake in any piece of litigation to which it is sup-
posed that law as integrity should be applied. We need to remember, too, that this
is the hypothesis that Dworkin is supposed to be responding to, and in connec-
tion with which the passage just quoted above is supposed finally to refute the
internal skeptic’s critique.
Let me put it very schematically: suppose Kennedy is right and there are two
recognizable moral positions, Ind (for individualism) and Alt (for altruism) in the
law—contradicting one another, but spread throughout the settled law in an array
of decisions in numbered cases {Ind1, Alt2, Ind3, Alt4, Ind5, Alt6, . . . }. And now
once again, the old adversaries face off against one another in yet another case—
case 7, say. So the two sides set about constructing their arguments, following the
constructive method that Dworkin recommends to practitioners of law as
integrity. The individualist party cites a subset of the established cases {Ind1, Ind3,
Ind5} and he puts cases 2, 4, and 6 aside. He is conscious, of course, that his oppo-
nent is likely to cite an equally sized subset {Alt2, Alt4, Alt6}, putting cases 1, 3, and
5 aside. So what does the individualist party propose to clinch his argument? He
says that his argument with its support in half the case law is better than his oppo-
nent’s, because it is committed to Ind and because Ind is, as he believes, a better
moral theory than Alt. The reason that clinches the matter on his account—the
reason that is supposed to be capable of clinching the matter on Dworkin’s
account—is simply that in this conflict between two moral views that have come
to pervade the law, he has aligned himself with the better one!
I very much doubt whether Dworkin will be embarrassed by this (though I will
show shortly that he ought to be). The point of the critique implicit in my
schematic example tends to be obscured by the fact that when Dworkin says that
the judge’s “own moral and political values” are engaged in the choice among rival
theories that fit the existing legal materials equally well, we are not reminded that
those very values are likely to be implicated on one side of the contradictions that
pervade the law (on the CLS account). He sometimes writes as though the contra-
dictory legal materials—leading to the impasse of fit—are one thing, and the val-
ues the judge brings to his task are another. I don’t mean that Dworkin’s argument
rests on this misapprehension. He would probably bite the bullet and say that the
judge has no choice but to rely on his own views about justice, even when his own
views about justice are exactly the views that are represented (and contradicted) in
the diverse legal materials facing him. But the possibility is not one that he brings
to our attention. More important, he doesn’t draw to our attention the fact that
the attorneys for the parties⁷⁰ are already committed to one side or the other in
this debate; they are litigating the issue precisely because they are partisans of Ind
and Alt respectively. So the values they appeal to when they try to clinch their
argument are, in some sense, question-begging arguments. They assume the very
point at issue and they then claim that this assumption breaks the tie between
their own argument and that of their opponents!
VII.
⁷¹ Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 1, 160–162. ( I have reversed the order of the first two sen-
tences in this excerpt. That does not affect the sense.) ⁷² Id. Ch. 4.
⁷³ Id. at 186–216. ⁷⁴ Id. at 199.
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 177
which gives an attractive and coherent account of what has been done among us
already in the name of our association—both of these are ways of trying to show
what that “diffuse sense of members’ special rights and responsibilities” is. And
connecting those principles or that theory with the decision one is arguing for in a
particular case is a way of showing that parties in the case have an associative obli-
gation to abide by that decision, because they are already in a sense committed to it.
Dworkin argues that such a strategy has a huge legitimacy-advantage over the
pragmatist approach. In aiming to make society better for the future, the pragma-
tist naturally commands the support of those who accept his vision of social jus-
tice and the general good. But it is hard to see why anyone with a different or
opposed vision of social justice or the general good should accept the decisions of
a pragmatist official. Integrity, however, makes a different sort of claim—one
rooted ultimately in reciprocity. Even when we disagree with one another about
justice or the general good, we can see that some among us have been benefitted
by decisions applying principles of a certain sort, and we can appreciate the fair-
ness of allowing others to be benefitted by those principles, even when we disagree
with them, because we think that their consistent and open-ended application
across a diverse array of cases helps to establish us as a community of principle.
So: this is the case that Dworkin needs in order to make sense of modes of legal
argumentation that grapple—in this non-pragmatic way—with the obscure
implications of the set of decisions our community has already committed itself
to. Such arguments present our association with one another as a community of
principle and they use that as a basis for saying that a decision, now, that flows
from the principles we have unearthed has legitimacy even for those who would be
inclined in the abstract to oppose it. To claim this legitimacy advantage, we have
to be willing to view the existing record of our community in a certain light—“to
see and enforce it as coherent.”⁷⁵ A judge who accepts integrity must be prepared
to treat the parties who come before him in this spirit: “They are entitled, in prin-
ciple, to have their acts and affairs judged in accordance with the best view of what
the legal standards of the community required or permitted at the time they acted,
and integrity demands that these standards be seen as coherent, as the state speak-
ing with a single voice.”76 And it is in this spirit that Professor Dworkin under-
takes the enterprise which we have been discussing in Sections II through VI.
Let us return now to the internal skepticism of CLS and to the constructivism
that Dworkin uses to respond to it. The internal skeptic denies that it is possible
to view the record of a community like ours as one in which a certain set of coher-
ent principles have consistently determined legal outcomes. The record of our
community, he says, does not disclose any consistent “sense of members’ special
rights and responsibilities from or toward one another,” diffuse or otherwise. The
internal skeptic denies therefore that any resolution of an instant case can made
legitimate by showing that it flows from such a set of coherent principles. The record
of our community, he says, is one of incoherence, in which the principles necessary
to sustain some decisions are contradicted by the principles necessary to sustain
others. There is nothing, says the internal skeptic, corresponding to Dworkin’s
description of a consistent set of principles presupposed by all or most of the
existing legal materials, from which we could infer legitimate answers to the legal
questions that currently confront us. Professor Dworkin may say that “associative
obligations can be sustained among people who share a general and diffuse sense
of members’ special rights and responsibilities from or toward one another, a sense
of what sort or level of sacrifice one may be expected to make for another.”⁷⁷ But
Duncan Kennedy’s point is precisely that we are conflicted about what we owe one
another; we don’t share a single conception; we share contradictory ones, if we
share anything at all. Again, Dworkin may say that “[l]aw as integrity asks judges
to assume, so far as this is possible, that the law is structured by a coherent set of
principles . . . and it asks them to enforce these in the fresh cases that come before
them, so that each person’s situation is fair and just according to the same stan-
dards.”⁷⁸ But the skeptical case is that this is not possible, and that this instruction
simply cannot be carried out, because the existential assumption fails: law is not
structured by a coherent set of principles.
For myself, I find it difficult to see how any form of versatile constructivism can
displace or mitigate this verdict. A Dworkinian judge or lawyer might make an
attempt to establish a record that is consistent as far as it goes, in the sense of identi-
fying principles which offer a coherent explanation of some of the extant decisions.
But the internal skeptic thinks that any such attempt will be easy to discredit.
Whatever decisions it explains, it will leave an equal number of decisions unex-
plained (treated as outliers). So any such interpretation (in Dworkin’s own words)
will “show the record of the community in an irredeemably bad light, because
proposing that interpretation suggests that the community has characteristically
dishonored its own principles.”⁷⁹
Notice that this is not just a matter of there being rival theories available, and no
demonstrable way of settling the issue between them. We can accept Professor
Dworkin’s claim that “people are entitled to a coherent and principled extension
of past political decisions even when judges profoundly disagree about what this
means”⁸⁰ and his view that “consistency in principle [can] be important for its
own sake, . . . [even] when it is uncertain and controversial what consistency really
requires?”⁸¹ But those maneuvers do not save the position here. For what we face,
if the internal skeptic is correct, is not a dispute between two viable interpretations
which unfortunately cannot be settled in a demonstrable way; what we face are
two rival interpretations, each of which is discredited by the fact that it seems to
show a very considerable part of the community’s record in a very bad light.
⁷⁷ Id. at 199. ⁷⁸ Id. at 243. ⁷⁹ Id. at 257. ⁸⁰ Id. at 134. ⁸¹ Id. at 163.
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 179
VIII.
Since the end of Section IV, I have been working on the assumption that the legal
background in a society like ours is about as riddled with contrary principles as the
CLS skeptics say it is. I proceeded on this assumption in order to see whether
Professor Dworkin had anything convincing to say in response to their skepticism
apart from a flat denial of its factual premise. I think we have concluded that he
has not. The distinction between tensions and contradictions does not do the
trick and neither does the move to constructivism nor the insistence that non-
demonstrability is compatible with objectivity.
That leaves the flat denial. At the end of Section IV, I was inclined to doubt that
Dworkin wanted to rest his jurisprudence on this. It sounded flabby and uncon-
vincing, and appeared to make the whole enterprise contingent and precarious.
But maybe that was premature, and if we turn around the argument that we have
just been developing (in Section VII), we may be able to see why. I said that con-
structive interpretation by a Dworkinian advocate cannot count as a bona fide
attempt to keep faith with the commitments of his community if it is known to
the advocate that the record of the community is one of pervasive and systematic
contradiction. If the advocate knows that roughly half the decisions embody the
moral proposition that members of the community have very limited obligations
to one another and roughly half of the decisions embody the moral proposition
that members of the community have very extensive obligations to one another,
he cannot with a straight face pull out just the materials in the latter half and argue
on that basis that his opponent has a particular obligation to his client because this
is what we—the community—have always been committed to. But suppose his
knowledge of the extent and pervasiveness of the contradictions is not so clear.
After all, the illustration that we used in Section VI—an array of decisions in
numbered cases {Ind1, Alt2, Ind3, Alt4, Ind5, Alt6, . . . }—was a ludicrously over-
simplified version of the legal record that most advocates are likely to be con-
fronted with. Ludicrously over-simplified, and ludicrously over-clarified: the tens
of thousands of extant legal decisions that we find in the law reports and the
statute books present a much more equivocal and tangled record than this.
Confronted then with real-world legal materials, the Dworkinian advocate will
have in the back of his mind the possibility that he will not be able to make a
determinate case—or, as I emphasized in Section VI, the possibility that his
opponent may be able to make a case as determinate as the one that he makes—but
he may think it worth trying to see whether he can do any better, for integrity, than
that. If it seems to him that the prospect of success here is not out of the question,
then there is no reason to say—as I said about the overly simple case—that his
attempt just makes a mockery of integrity.
So the factual disagreement between Dworkin and the skeptics may come
down to this: Are the contradictions so clear and so pervasive that it is evidently
not worth trying to see whether a particular set of principles (or a particular inter-
pretation) fits the existing law? “Not worth trying” is the key predicate in this
formulation. It does not mean and it should not be taken to mean that there is no
legal argument that we can come up with. If we are prepared to pick and choose, we
can always come up with something, even if or (as I said earlier on the basis of ele-
mentary propositional logic) especially if we know the materials are inconsistent.
“Not worth trying” must refer to the conditions that would make the attempt
important or worthwhile; that is, it must refer to the general idea of integrity.
It must not be out of the question that our argument or our principles fit a very
significant portion of the legal materials, and it must not be out of the question
that this is not the case for our opponent’s argument. If the constructive strategy
that organizes our attempt rests on our having to say, even implicitly, that “the
Did Dworkin Ever Answer the Crits? 181
I. Political Obligation
One of the strands woven into the complex fabric of Law’s Empire (hereinafter LE)
is an argument that there exists, under certain conditions, a general moral obligation
to obey the law. Whether or not there can ever be such an obligation is an age-old
problem in political philosophy, and Dworkin’s argument is offered, in part, as a
contribution to that particular philosophical tradition. But it is more than that,
because the argument also constitutes an integral part of Dworkin’s general theory
of law. That is why I say it is one strand of a complex fabric; for Dworkin, political
and legal philosophy are inextricably connected. For many of the philosophers
who have addressed the question of political obligation, as I shall call it, there is no
such inevitable connection. Notice, to begin, that no respectable theory of politi-
cal obligation ever claimed that a person is obligated no matter what to obey the
laws of a legal system to which he or she is subject. Every minimally plausible the-
ory sets out certain conditions under which such an obligation is said to arise, and
Dworkin’s is no exception. Many such theories have, however, regarded these con-
ditions as ones that do not figure in any essential way in the concept of law itself.
They assume that law constitutes a system of norms the existence and content of
which can be established by, say, looking to certain kinds of social facts, and then
asking whether or not a given legal system meets a set of independently specifiable
conditions; if these conditions are met, then a general obligation to obey is said to
exist. Arguments based on consent are often (although not necessarily) of that
form; they look to an independently specifiable condition that asks whether or
not everyone who is subject to a legal system has validly consented to obey its laws,
whatever they are. The argument from fair play is also of this form; it looks to an
independently specifiable set of conditions that asks, first, whether the content of
the norms of the system show it to be a mutually beneficial scheme of cooperation,
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law. Stephen Perry.
© Oxford University Press 2006. Published 2006 by Oxford University Press.
184 Stephen Perry
and, secondly, whether or not those subject to the system have “accepted” its benefits.¹
There are, as Dworkin points out, well-known problems with both arguments if
they are regarded as the basis of a general obligation to obey the law, since it is never
the case that everyone subject to any given legal system has validly consented
to obey it or has accepted, in the appropriate sense, certain benefits it happens to
provide (LE at 192–195).² My present point, however, is that these arguments
treat the philosophical problem of political obligation as for the most part inde-
pendent of the philosophical problem about the nature of law.
Dworkin’s theory, as I noted, is not like this. Before I say anything about the
specifics of his view, however, let me first say a little more about the question of
political obligation itself.³ A general obligation to obey the law exists only if every
person who is subject to a given legal system has a moral obligation to obey each
and every law of the system because it is a law of the system. In saying that one has
an obligation to obey the law because it is the law I do not mean that one’s reason
for action in doing as the law requires must be that the law requires it; for the most
part, the law is indifferent to why one complies with the law so long as one does so.
To say that one has an obligation to obey the law because it is the law means,
rather, that at least one sufficient ground or basis of the obligation is the fact that
the law exists. The law need not be the only basis of the obligation. We clearly have
independent moral obligations not to assault and murder people, for example.
However, if one has a moral obligation to obey the law then the law must be a basis
of obligation in addition to one’s independent moral obligations. Often, of
course, the law modifies (or at least purports to modify) independent moral obliga-
tions, or to make them more precise where they are indeterminate, and there
would not be much point to law if it was not capable of at least sometimes doing
this. But it will not suffice to establish a general moral obligation to obey the law
to show that the law has had some effect on one’s moral obligations or, more gen-
erally, on one’s moral situation. It is, as I said, necessary to show that one has an
obligation to obey each and every law because it is the law. This challenge must be
met not just where the law reproduces independent moral obligations, but also
where the law makes moral mistakes, for example mistakes about what justice
requires. Theories of political obligation almost always place limits on the extent
to which the law can make moral mistakes and still give rise to a general obligation
to obey the law, but it is nonetheless no easy matter to show that there is ever an
obligation to obey an unjust law. And since no legal system is ever perfectly just, a
theory of political obligation would not have shown very much if it failed to show
¹ See H. L. A. Hart, Are There any Natural Rights?, 64 Phil. Rev. 185 (1955); J. Rawls, A Theory
of Justice 301–308 (2d ed., 1999).
² See A. J. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (1979), especially
chs. 3–5.
³ In this paragraph I draw on material from my article Law and Obligation, 50 American
Journal of Jurisprudence 263 (2005). For very helpful (albeit skeptical) discussions of political
obligation, see Simmons, supra note 2; L. Green, The Authority of the State (1990), particularly
ch. 8; and J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain (1994), ch. 14.
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law 185
that the general obligation to obey is not capable of encompassing at least some
unjust laws. Dworkin’s theory acknowledges this point. A general obligation to
obey the law can, of course, be prima facie and defeasible by other moral consid-
erations; it is possible that an obligation to obey an unjust law can exist, but be
overridden by the independent obligations of justice itself. Dworkin’s theory
acknowledges this point as well.
Here it will be helpful to bring in a distinction that Dworkin draws between the
grounds and the force of law (LE at 108–113). Dworkin does not employ the fol-
lowing formulation, but we can say that the grounds of law are the truth condi-
tions of propositions of the form “It is the law (of some specified jurisdiction) that
A,” where A is a normative proposition that states that some person or group of
persons has some normative status, for example that they have an obligation,
right, permission, liability, or power. The paradigmatic case is a proposition speci-
fying an obligation, and I will continue to concentrate on that case. (The properly
generalized version of the problem of political obligation asks whether the law sys-
tematically affects persons’ normative status in all the various ways that it claims to
do; for present purposes, we can ignore this complication.) For the sake of ease of
expression I will from now on omit the reference to a specific jurisdiction,
although it should always be understood as present. Suppose the proposition “It is
the law that everyone has an obligation to do X” is true.⁴ The force of law is its
normative force, which means its moral force.⁵ The concern when we are speaking
about force, in other words, is with the truth or falsity of normative propositions
such as “Everyone has an obligation to do X” when they figure in true proposi-
tions such as “It is the law that everyone has an obligation to do X.” To say that a
legal system has general normative force is simply to say that it gives rise to a gen-
eral obligation to obey. Force, as a general concept in legal philosophy, is con-
cerned with the connection between the truth of propositions of the form “It is
the law that A” and the truth of “A.” For the reasons given in the preceding para-
graph, it will not suffice to establish that there is a general obligation to obey the
law to show that for all propositions of the form “It is the law that ——,” both “It
is the law that A” and “A” are true. One must show, in addition, that at least one
sufficient basis for the truth of “A” is the truth of “It is the law that A.” Stated more
precisely, one must show that the various facts, whether social, moral, or both,
that serve to establish the truth of “It is the law that A” also serve to establish the
truth of “A.” A theory of political obligation is a theory about the conditions that
⁴ “Everyone” can be understood as referring to all persons who are subject to the particular legal
system; it does not matter for present purposes what, exactly, that means.
⁵ It is of course true that not all normativity is moral, but Dworkin assumes that legal normativity,
if it exists at all, is a type of moral normativity. Thus legal obligations (if they exist) are moral obliga-
tions, legal permissions (if they exist) are moral permissions, and so on. In my view this assumption is
correct, but I cannot discuss the point here. I will limit myself to the observation that it is not an
assumption that is in conflict with positivism, although not all positivists accept it. Kelsen and Raz
do, but Hart does not.
186 Stephen Perry
must obtain in order for this connection to hold in a systematic way for all the
laws of a legal system.
This brings me back to the observation that Dworkin’s theory of political obliga-
tion does not treat the question of whether there is ever a general obligation to
obey the law as independent from the philosophical problem about the nature of
law. Dworkin says that a theory of law is a theory about the grounds of law, which
means that it is a theory about the truth conditions of propositions of the form “It
is the law that A.” He is not always entirely clear about whether such a theory
applies only to the law of particular jurisdictions or whether it is meant to be more
general, but I think it is ultimately clear that it is meant to be more general: a the-
ory about the grounds of law is (part of ) a theory about the nature of law under-
stood as a general kind of social phenomenon. To say that a theory of law is about
the grounds of law is very vague, but I hope the formulation will suffice for present
purposes. It is meant to cover, for example, such theoretical views as Dworkin’s
own theory of law as integrity, Hart’s theory of the rule of recognition, and various
versions of the social sources thesis. I will say something about the specifics of law
as integrity in a moment. The point to be noticed for present purposes, however, is
that the theory holds that the grounds of law depend, in part, on considerations
having to do with the (potential) force of law. Dworkin does not put the point in
the following way, but I believe the essence of his view is this: law as integrity,
which is a substantive theory about the grounds of law, presupposes the truth of a
particular theory of political obligation, and it does so in such a way that the truth
of propositions of the form “It is the law that A” depends, in part and to a limited
extent, on whether or not “A” is capable of being made true by that theory of
political obligation.⁶ This is very abstract, and I will begin to fill in the details of
the view later in this section and in section III. But the abstract formulation suf-
fices to show us that, on Dworkin’s view, the theory of political obligation does
not take the content of law as given and then ask whether or not there is a general
obligation to obey; it is, rather, an integral part of the theory of the grounds of law,
and therefore itself has an effect on the content of law. This is, as I said, a claim
that Dworkin makes about law as integrity. But earlier in Law’s Empire he makes
an even more ambitious, methodological claim, which holds, in effect, that any
general theory about the grounds of law must presuppose some theory of political
⁶ Notice that the truth of propositions of the form “It is the law that A” is said to depend in part
not on the independent truth of the normative proposition “A,” in which case we would be dealing
with a certain radical kind of natural law theory, but rather on whether or not “A” is capable of being
made true by the theory of political obligation. In other words, the truth of “It is the law that A”
partly depends on whether or not “A” is capable of being made true by the truth of “It is the law that
A.” As we shall see, Dworkin’s own theory of law as integrity makes this determination holistically, by
looking to how “A” fits into the content of the law taken as a whole. There is no vicious or unavoid-
able circularity here. It should also be emphasized that the truth of propositions of the form “It is the
law that A” is said to depend only partly on the theory of political obligation. The most important
determinant of the truth of such propositions is, of course, social practice, such as facts about what
legislatures and courts have done. This is the crucial dimension of “fit” in Dworkin’s general theory of
interpretation.
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law 187
obligation in much the same way as his own theory of law as integrity does.⁷
Dworkin summarizes the point by saying that “[a] general theory of law . . . pro-
poses a solution to a complex set of simultaneous equations” having to do with
both the grounds and the force of law (LE at 110). Different theories of law pre-
suppose different theories of political obligation (or else deny that there can be
such a theory). To determine which theory of law is correct we must, therefore, at
some point address the general question of political obligation, and this necessar-
ily takes us deep into issues of substantive political morality. This is, I believe, the
nerve of Dworkin’s general theory of interpretation, understood as a methodology
for doing philosophy of law.
I cannot discuss the general theory of interpretation here, except to make the
following brief observations. Although the truth conditions of propositions like
“It is the law that A” are affected by moral considerations having to do with the
capacity of the law to obligate us, they also depend crucially and unavoidably on
social facts, and in particular on facts about what legislatures and courts have
done. Given that social practice is, necessarily, the starting point of interpretation,
I do not think that Dworkin should be understood as saying that propositions of
the form “It is the law that A” can never be true unless some theory of political
obligation is true (although he is clearly more optimistic on this latter score than
most other contemporary theorists). What I believe he is saying, rather, is that the
practice of law with which we are familiar presupposes that there is a true theory of
political obligation. The practice is built on the assumption that certain kinds of
social facts serve as a systematic basis or ground for obligations. But this presupposi-
tion might be mistaken. It is possible that, as a general moral matter, the truth of a
proposition of the form “It is the law that A” can never be a sufficient basis for the
truth of “A”—i.e., the truth of such a proposition can never be a sufficient basis
for the existence of an obligation—in which case law as a general kind of social
practice would not make sense; complete skepticism about it would be justified. It
is also possible that, whether or not a general theory of political obligation is true,
a particular legal system is so unjust or evil that, within that system, the truth of a
proposition of the form “It is the law that A” is never, or almost never, a sufficient
ground for the truth of “A;” skepticism about the particular legal system would
then be justified. In both of these cases, Dworkin need not and should not deny
that propositions of the form “It is the law that A” could still be true just by virtue
of facts about social practice. In making this acknowledgment, however, we would
also have to acknowledge that, in the first case, the general practice was by its own
lights a radically defective one, and, in the second case, that we were dealing with a
degenerate instance of a legal system. (Cf. LE at 101–108.)
There is one more preliminary matter that needs to be mentioned before we
consider the specifics of Dworkin’s substantive views about political obligation.
⁷ “In much the same way” is deliberately vague. It is beyond the scope of this paper to explore
Dworkin’s general methodological claims about legal philosophy in any detail.
188 Stephen Perry
Associative obligations are, very roughly, obligations that arise in connection with
certain limited human associations, like friendships and families. Such obligations
are, as Dworkin notes, special, which means that they are owed only to certain
persons and not universally. Are all special obligations also associative? This is not
a question that can be definitively answered before we have in hand an analysis of
associative obligations, but as an intuitive matter there does not seem to be any
good reason to think that they are. Suppose there is a general moral duty of easy
rescue, meaning a duty to assist another person who is in serious danger if one can
do so at no great cost to oneself. If you fall into a raging river and I am in a position
to throw you a life ring, then it is quite plausible to think that the duty I have in
those circumstances is a special one; I owe a duty to you that I do not owe to other
people. No doubt there is some formal sense in which the two of us are in associ-
ation with one another, but this does not look like what people typically have in
mind in speaking of associative obligations. Or think of the obligations that arise
190 Stephen Perry
Dworkin summarizes the four conditions in the following way: “The responsibil-
ities a true community deploys are special and individualized and display a perv-
asive mutual concern that fits a plausible conception of equal concern” (201). He
adds that “[t]he concern [these conditions] require is an interpretive property of
the group’s practices of asserting and acknowledging responsibilities—these must
be practices that people with the right level of concern would adopt—not a psy-
chological property of some fixed number of the actual members” (LE at 201).
There is much about this analysis that rings true. All four conditions appear to
hold for friendship, for example, which is surely a paradigm of a type of human
relationship that gives rise to associative obligations. I have some doubts, however,
about whether the same can be said of every associative obligation, or at least every
example of an associative obligation that Dworkin offers us. Clearly, as already
noted, the first condition is a necessary one; associative obligations are special, in
the sense that they are owed only to certain persons. The third condition, that
associative obligations express a general concern for the other person or persons
with whom one is associated, is probably a necessary one as well. But are all asso-
ciative obligations personal, in the sense defined by Dworkin’s second condition?
Certainly the obligations that exist in the paradigm cases of friendship and family
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law 191
are personal in this sense. Recall, however, that Dworkin wishes to show that
political obligation is a type of associative obligation. If a general political obliga-
tion ever exists, it is far from clear that it is personal. In form, at least, it is not. A
general obligation to obey the law is usually thought to be owed, if to anyone, to
the community or state itself rather than to one’s fellow citizens considered one by
one. If the obligation is owed to the community it must of course be true that the
community is, or is capable of being treated as, a moral agent in some appropriate
sense, but this is far from being an obstacle for Dworkin; he insists that a proper
understanding of political and legal practice in fact requires moral personification
of the community. When it comes time to argue that the model of principle,
which is Dworkin’s preferred model of political community, meets the four stated
conditions, he writes with respect to the second condition that the model makes
the responsibilities of the relevant community “fully personal” because “it com-
mands that no one be left out, that we are all in politics for better or worse, that no
one may be sacrificed, like wounded left on the battlefield, to the crusade for
justice overall” (LE at 213). But this is not the sense of the second condition as
Dworkin originally defined it. He is not here arguing that the responsibilities in
question “run directly from each member to each other member.” The idea that
the model of principle “commands that no one be left out” sounds, rather, like a
restatement of the fourth condition, which holds that the concern expressed by
the responsibilities of an associative relationship must be an equal concern.
Turning directly to that fourth condition, what does it mean to say that the con-
cern expressed by the responsibilities of an associative relationship must be an equal
concern? Consider friendship. In this context the condition presumably means
that the obligations that two friends reciprocally owe to one another must express a
more or less equal level of concern. This is what Dworkin seems to have in mind
when he says that friends ought to have “roughly the same concern” for one another
even if they do not share exactly the same understanding of the responsibilities of
friendship (LE at 199). In the family context, however, the equality condition seems
to mean something different. Dworkin discusses the example of a culture that gives
parents the power to choose spouses for their daughters but not for their sons. The
culture accepts “in good faith” the equality of the sexes but thinks, mistakenly, that
equality of concern requires a paternalism for daughters that it does not require for
sons. Dworkin argues that, despite this moral mistake, it is possible that daughters
in this culture owe their parents a genuine obligation of obedience, although it is
also possible that the obligation might ultimately be overridden by other moral
considerations (LE at 204–205). I am not at present concerned with the question
of whether or not Dworkin is correct in making this claim. I mean only to point
out that the notion of “equal concern” must in this context have a quite different
sense from the one it has in the context of friendship. Here, it seems to mean some-
thing like the following: the moral powers that one holds over others within an
associative relationship may only be exercised in a way that manifests equal concern
for all those over whom the powers are held. Dworkin claims, controversially, that
192 Stephen Perry
children can come under an obligation to obey their parents even if parental power
is not so exercised, so long as it is exercised in accordance with a conception of equal
concern that is plausible and sincerely held. Whether or not this claim is true,
“equal concern” does not here refer, as it does in the case of friendship, to an equal
level of reciprocal concern that the members of an associative relationship owe to
one another. To make this clear, imagine the case of a single parent raising a single
child. The parent has an obligation to care for the child, and associated with this
obligation is a power to command obedience. The child has an obligation to do
as the parent requires. These two obligations—the obligation on the part of the
parent to care for the child, and the obligation on the part of the child to obey the
parent—are not reciprocal obligations like those that hold between two friends.
Both obligations are most plausibly understood as being grounded in the wellbeing
of the child alone. It is of course true that the child may eventually come under an
obligation to care for the parent in the latter’s old age, but this is not an obligation
that is reciprocal to the parent’s obligation to care for the child when the child is
young. This is not because the two obligations cannot exist at the same time. It is
because neither obligation is conditioned on the existence—past, present or
future—of the other. The parent of a child with a fatal illness has no less a duty to
care for the child—and arguably has a greater one—than the parent of a child with
a normal life expectancy, and a person close to adulthood who is adopted or
becomes a step-child may still come under an obligation to care for his or her new
parent in old age.
The main point I was concerned to establish in the last paragraph is that there
does not seem to be a single conception of equal concern that informs even the
paradigmatic associative relationships of family and friendship. The equality of con-
cern that must hold between friends, which is a form of reciprocity, need not hold
between parent and child. (Relations between siblings is a more complicated case,
which I do not discuss here.) Nor does there seem to be, in the case of friendship, an
analogue to the obligation to exercise parental powers over a number of different
children so as to manifest equal concern for each. (We do not, for example, owe the
same level of concern to all our different friends, and that is true even within a
group of mutual friends; the appropriate level of concern varies with the closeness
of the particular friendship.) It does not help to say that there is a more abstract
conception of equality underlying the specific conceptions that inform friendship
and family, because at a sufficiently abstract level all moral principles, and not just
those that underpin associative obligations, are, in Dworkin’s phrase, “conceptually
egalitarian.” None of this calls into question the obligatoriness of true associative
obligations, but it suggests, particularly when considered with the point made earl-
ier that some associative obligations might not be personal in character, that the
attempt to find a comprehensive set of attributes that hold for all associative rela-
tionships is unlikely to succeed. The problem is compounded when one considers
the many kinds of social practice that Dworkin regards as being, at least potentially,
associative in character: in addition to family, friendship, and political community,
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law 193
⁹ I take it that the existence of the interpretive attitude is a psychological or sociological matter. If
it were not, there would a danger that the term “interpretive” would simply be a label applied to prac-
tices that might, for whatever reason, be capable of being a source of obligation. The general account
of interpretation would lose its distinctiveness.
¹⁰ D. Réaume, Is Integrity a Virtue? Dworkin’s Theory of Legal Obligation 39 U. of Tor. L.J. 380,
402 (1989).
194 Stephen Perry
According to Dworkin’s critique, the fact that a group treats certain of its practices
as obligatory cannot, in and of itself, make them obligatory; something more in
the way of normative argument is required.¹¹ As it stands Réaume’s objection
skips too quickly over a crucial point, which is that the four conditions are
expressly stated by Dworkin to be interpretive properties of a group’s practices
rather than “psychological propert[ies] of some fixed number of actual members”
(LE at 201).¹² The third condition, for example, requires that these practices be
ones that “people with the right level of concern would adopt” rather than ones in
which some minimum proportion of members actually manifest concern for their
fellows (LE at 201).¹³ The four conditions together are meant to be an interpreta-
tion of what Dworkin takes to be a general practice of associative obligation, and
interpretations always have a dimension of justification or value. Dworkin’s
analysis thus cannot be regarded as a mere variant of Hart’s practice theory. That
having been said, however, we still run up against the question mentioned in the
previous paragraph of whether or not there is, in fact, a general interpretive prac-
tice of associative obligation. We also run up against the related problem of what
the value associated with such a practice might be. Although Dworkin is not
entirely clear about this point, he seems simply to invoke a single general value of
community or fraternity. But just as it is not clear that there is, in fact, a general
interpretive practice of associative obligation, it is similarly not clear that there is a
single value that can be regarded as accompanying such diverse forms of human
association as friendship, political community, union membership, and so on. If I
am right that the four conditions fail to capture common features of even the
paradigmatic instances of associative obligation, then we have at least some reason
to doubt the existence of both a general practice and a single value that underlies
every instance of such a practice.
In the preceding discussion I have tried to raise some doubts about Dworkin’s
analysis of associative relationships, but I have not called into question his basic
strategy for showing that a general moral obligation to obey the law can exist. He
begins, it will be recalled, with the premise that certain limited forms of human
association are generally and plausibly regarded as giving rise to obligations, and
then argues that political communities are associations of that same kind and
therefore they, too, are capable of giving rise to obligations. I believe this strategy is
a promising one, but if we are to give effect to it we must characterize associative
obligations in a somewhat different way from Dworkin’s analysis based on the
four conditions. (As I will suggest later, the appropriate characterization turns out
to be an important, if perhaps implicit, strand in Dworkin’s own discussion of
associative obligations.) My approach will be to focus, in the first instance, on the
paradigm associative relationship of friendship. Why do friends have obligations
towards one another? It seems almost misplaced to ask this question, and it is
tempting to answer it by saying that friends have obligations because that’s part of
what friendship is. So far as it goes this answer is completely correct, but it must be
understood as part of a deeper truth. As Aristotle and many others since have
observed, friendship has intrinsic value. It may also have instrumental value, of
course, but if a relationship between two persons was not intrinsically valuable—
and if its intrinsic value did not dominate its instrumental value for each of
them—then it would not be friendship. It is partly constitutive of friendship
that friends hold certain characteristic attitudes towards one another, the most
important of which are affection and respect. But the obligations of friendship—
primarily duties of loyalty and mutual assistance—are themselves partly constitutive
of the relationship.¹⁴ The attitudes, obviously, evolve over time, and the potential
friends must each make choices that permit the friendship to develop. At a certain
point, however, they just become friends, and the duties exist. This is not a matter
of exercising a power of promise or consent. As Dworkin says, it would be perverse
to describe friendship as a matter of assuming obligations; the shared history by
virtue of which friends come to owe obligations is, on the contrary, “a history of
events that attract obligations” (LE at 197). This seems exactly right. But the reason
this happens is that the relationship of friendship, constituted in part by certain
mutual duties, is intrinsically valuable. It might be objected that this is moral
bootstrapping. Doesn’t it amount to saying that the duties exist because it is
good that they exist? Yes, it does. But this kind of bootstrapping is pervasive
and unavoidable in morality. Duties are justified either instrumentally or non-
instrumentally, but in both cases the existence of the duty turns on its relationship
to value. Instrumental duties exist because they promote or contribute to the
creation of independently valuable states of affairs, or are likely to do so. Non-
instrumental duties exist because they are valuable in themselves, or partly con-
stitutive of a relationship that is valuable in itself. In each case, it is part of the
argument for the existence of the duty that it is good that it exist.
Dworkin is of course aware of the relationship between duty and value. One of
the two dimensions of interpretation is success in justifying a normative practice—
the other is success in fitting the practice—and justifications cannot help but
invoke value. There is an interesting question about the relationship between asso-
ciative obligations and interpretive practices in general. Dworkin clearly expresses
the view in Law’s Empire that all associative relationships are either interpretive
practices themselves or are formed within broader interpretive practices, but does
he also think that all interpretive practices are (potential) associative relationships?
It is not entirely clear. Whatever Dworkin’s view on this question might have been
at the time that he wrote Law’s Empire, I wish to suggest that associative relation-
ships are a narrower category than interpretive practices generally.¹⁵ Taking friend-
ship as a paradigm, the suggestion is that we can identify a distinctive type of
obligation that arises because it is partly constitutive of some form of limited
human relationship that possesses intrinsic value. The further suggestion is that
Dworkin’s strategy for establishing the possibility of political obligation requires
one to argue that genuine political community—the term is Dworkin’s (LE at
211)—is an intrinsically valuable form of human association. Properly under-
stood, I believe that this is exactly Dworkin’s argument. Before defending that con-
clusion, however, let me say a bit more about associative obligations in general.
Notice, to begin, that this account of associative obligations does not presup-
pose a general interpretive practice of associative obligation, although it is consis-
tent with the existence of such a practice. The account is, in the first instance,
simply a first-order moral claim about the way in which certain kinds of human
relationships may give rise to obligations. Whether or not there is a general inter-
pretive practice of associative obligation is not, therefore, a question that needs to
be answered definitively for present purposes. I earlier argued that the four condi-
tions that Dworkin advances as characteristic of such a general practice are not
found together in every associative relationship. But it is important to emphasize
that those conditions are nonetheless likely to figure prominently in most such
relationships, although no doubt in different ways and configurations. A further,
related point to notice about the account I have offered is that just as it does not
require that there be a general interpretive practice of associative obligation, nei-
ther does it require that there be a single intrinsic value that all such obligations
share. The claim is simply that we can identify certain kinds of obligations that are
in an important sense similar to one another, for the reason that they are partly
constitutive of relationships that are intrinsically valuable. The account is consist-
ent with the idea that a single value underlies all associative obligations, but it is
¹⁵ It is also at least conceivable that associative relationships need not necessarily be, or be formed
within the context of, interpretive practices in Dworkin’s strong sense. For example, is it only possible
for two persons to be friends within a broader interpretive practice of friendship? It is almost imposs-
ible to imagine a human world in which most persons did not have ties of respect and affection with
others, but the interpretive attitude requires a certain self-consciousness about the general practice of
friendship, and, in particular, about what is taken to be its point or value, that might nonetheless be
absent from a particular culture. It is at least arguable that so long as individuals hold the appropriate
attitudes towards one another an intrinsically valuable relationship, together with its associated
duties, comes into being, regardless of whether these or any other persons hold views about the point
or value of friendship. I will not, however, pursue this line of thought further here.
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law 197
probably more plausible to think that we are dealing with a plurality of values; the
intrinsic value of friendship would thus be different from the intrinsic value of
family, and different again from the intrinsic value, if any, of political community.
As has already been noted, it follows from the account of associative obligation
I have offered—that these are obligations that are partly constitutive of some
intrinsically valuable form of human relationship—that not all interpretive prac-
tices are, either in fact or potentially, associative relationships. There is nothing in
Dworkin’s general account of interpretation that rules out the possibility that the
value or point of some interpretive practices is instrumental, just as nothing rules
out the possibility that the value of some is non-instrumental. If the general char-
acterization is right, moreover, then Dworkin casts the net of associative obliga-
tion too widely: it seems unlikely, for example, that either union membership or
academic colleagueship is an intrinsically valuable form of human relationship.
This general account of associative obligation also makes clear that not all special
obligations are associative. Earlier I pointed to the example of a general duty of easy
rescue that is capable of generating special duties owed to particular individuals.
Although I shall not argue the point here, it seems plausible to think that both the
general and the special duties are justifiable solely on instrumental, consequentialist
grounds. The special duty is thus not an associative one. What about special obli-
gations that arise from the exercise of powers of promise and consent? This is an
interesting case. The power to promise is a power deliberately to place oneself
under new obligations to others, and the power to consent is, roughly, a power
deliberately or knowingly to change one’s normative situation in a broader sense.
(In addition to consenting to assume an obligation, one can, for example, consent
to waive one’s rights.) It would be very implausible to think that every relationship
that arises from the exercise of such powers is one of intrinsic value—consider
commercial contracts, for example—although their exercise can clearly contribute
to, or deepen, relationships that have such value independently; the best example is
probably the vows of marriage. If the relationships are not intrinsically valuable then
neither are the special obligations that constitute them; these obligations are not,
or at least are not necessarily, associative obligations. Even if this is true, however,
it is quite possible that the powers themselves are intrinsically valuable. Joseph
Raz, for example, has argued very persuasively that an important justification for
such powers, although not the only one, lies in the intrinsic value of being able to
create special bonds with others and, more generally, being able to fashion the
shape of one’s own moral world.¹⁶ (Notice that this is another example of the kind
of bootstrapping that I said earlier was unavoidable in morality; these powers exist
because it is good that they do so.) If this is correct then there is an important
affinity between assumed obligations and associative obligations, even though the
former are not necessarily instances of the latter.
¹⁶ J. Raz, Promises and Obligations, in Law, Morality, and Society: Essays in Honour of
H. L. A. Hart 210, 226–228 (P. M. S. Hacker and J. Raz., eds, 1977); J. Raz, The Morality of
Freedom 86–87 (1986).
198 Stephen Perry
appropriately similar fashion: litigants can be assured, for example, that their case
will be handled in accordance with the same general principles whether they end
up in courtroom A or in courtroom B. In that sense government will, in
Dworkin’s phrase, “be speaking with one voice.” But equality in this sense is con-
sistent with great substantive inequality: members of one race, for example, might
consistently be treated very differently from members of another race, even
though any given individual would be treated exactly the same way in courtroom
A as he or she would have been treated in courtroom B. Integrity is connected to
substantive equality because it requires not just that the state act in accordance
with a single set of logically consistent standards, but that it act in accordance with
a single conception of justice. In Dworkin’s words, the government must “extend
to everyone the substantive standards of justice or fairness it uses for some.” This is
a tricky matter, because integrity is distinct from justice and hence does not
require that citizens be treated as justice in fact requires. Dworkin is assuming, I
believe, that while true justice necessarily entails equality of concern, equality of
concern does not necessarily entail true justice. This is a strong assumption, but it
has a great deal of plausibility. Dworkin at times speaks somewhat loosely of
integrity as requiring a plausible or coherent conception of equal concern (LE at
213). I think the better way to put the point, however, is to say that integrity
requires actual equal concern, which will take the form of a plausible or coherent
(but perhaps false) conception of justice. Integrity, in other words, is not just a
matter of sincerity or plausibility or coherence, but has genuine moral content.
That content is provided by the concept of equal concern, which occupies a moral
middle ground between simple consistency on the one hand, and true justice, on
the other. At any rate this will be my working assumption for present purposes.
When a legal system has integrity, Dworkin suggests, a “bare” political
community is transformed into a “genuine” political community, and its mem-
bers come under a general obligation to obey the law. Integrity, I have suggested,
is a matter of true equal concern. Equal concern is, in turn, the bridge between
Dworkin’s general analysis of associative obligations and his particular argument
for political obligation. While I have argued in the preceding section that
Dworkin’s general analysis, based on the four conditions, cannot be expected to
apply to associative obligations across the board, it is nonetheless very plausible
to think that the idea of equal concern would play a central role in justifying an
associative political obligation. The concern in question would be expressed by
the state, through its laws and governing actions, towards all its citizens. The
state is not, of course, a real person, from which two points immediately follow.
First, equal concern cannot in this context be a psychological matter; in the case
of political obligation, it must be an interpretive property (LE at 201). Secondly,
as Dworkin explicitly recognizes, the account requires that the state be morally
personified (LE at 167–175). (Recall that it is because political obligation runs
between the state and its citizens, rather than between citizens individually,
that political obligation cannot be personal in the sense defined by Dworkin.)
200 Stephen Perry
Why, then, might integrity make a moral difference of the kind to which
Dworkin points? The reason, I wish to suggest, is that when integrity is present,
the relationship between each individual citizen and the state—the state being
understood as an abstract moral personification of the general political
community—becomes, according to Dworkin’s argument, one that is intrinsi-
cally valuable. He writes that “a political society that accepts integrity as a politi-
cal virtue thereby becomes a special form of community, special in a way that
promotes its moral authority to assume and deploy a monopoly of coercive force”
(LE at 188). Dworkin goes on to describe other justifications for integrity that
are purely instrumental, such as the fact that it provides protection against
partiality, deceit, and corruption. The distinction between the two types of
justification suggests that he regards genuine political community as special
precisely because it has non-instrumental value. But whether or not I am correct
in attributing such a specific view to him, I believe that this idea is the basis of
the most compelling philosophical understanding of his argument for political
obligation.
In order to defend that claim, however, this interpretation of the argument
must be spelled out in greater detail. Why might it be thought that political com-
munity, even when it meets certain conditions pertaining to equal concern, could
be intrinsically valuable? It may well be the case that simply belonging to or iden-
tifying with certain kinds of communities is an intrinsic good for individuals. But
the good of belonging or identification seems unlikely to be enough to support an
obligation to obey. There are, after all, many kinds of communities other than
political ones—for example, ethnic, national, or religious communities—that
seem just as likely to provide such a good, and yet it is far from clear that this fact
can serve as the basis of an obligation to obey the relevant community’s norms.¹⁷
(This is not to deny that there might be other reasons to obey.) The claim must
therefore be, I think, that political community is a unique good, and one which is
¹⁷ Joseph Raz has argued that the law can have intrinsic value because it is one kind of standard of
conduct that a community can have, and “our perception of ourselves, of who we are, depends among
other things on our ability to identify with communities we live in, on our ability to belong to these
communities in the full sense of the word.” J. Raz, On the Nature of Law, 82 Archiv für Rechts
und Sozialphilosophie 1, 10 (1996). (Notice that he does not claim that political community is
unique in this regard.) But Raz also thinks that there is a voluntary aspect to identification and
belonging: “Identification with a community depends on our ability and willingness to accept the
standards which these communities endorse as our own. This ability . . . depends [among other
things] on one’s moral judgement giving basic approval to those standards.” Id. at 12. Elsewhere he
has similarly argued that respect for law, which is an attitude expressing identification with one’s
political community, can ground an obligation to obey that is, like the obligations of friendship,
“semi-voluntary”: “Such an attitude, if directed to a community which deserves it, is intrinsically
valuable. It is not, however, obligatory. One does not have a moral duty to feel a sense of belonging in
a community.” Raz, supra note 3, at 338. The attitude of respect for law is, in Raz’s view, not consent-
based but nonetheless semi-voluntary because, like friendship, it grows and develops over time. There
are obvious affinities between this view and Dworkin’s understanding of political obligation. But
Dworkin does not think that there is a voluntary or semi-voluntary aspect to political obligation, and
that is why he must make the stronger assumption about the value of political community that is
identified in the text.
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law 201
¹⁸ Leslie Green raises a related question when he argues that “integrity [in individuals] creates no
duty to obey those who display the virtue,”and this does not change in the case of a personified com-
munity. L. Green, Associative Obligations and the State, in Law and the Community: The End of
Individualism? 93, 106 (A. Hutchinson and L. Green, eds., 1989). Green’s argument is much more
plausible if one assumes, as he at least implicitly does, that integrity cannot confer intrinsic value on a
political community. The analogy with integrity in an individual, which Dworkin himself makes, is
in fact quite misleading: the integrity of an individual cannot be a source of value for others in the way
that the integrity of a political community can, at least conceivably, make that community intrins-
ically valuable for its citizens. If I am right that the essence of integrity in the political context is a con-
cept of equal concern, then there is no analogue with the virtue of integrity in individuals; integrity in
the former sense is a creature of political morality alone. However, even if it is true that political
integrity can be a source of value in the way that I have suggested, it does not automatically follow
that citizens have a general moral obligation to obey the law.
202 Stephen Perry
exist in various ways; there is, for example, a clear sense in which a norm exists
simply because the members of a legislature enacted a law. But the argument for
political obligation that I am attempting to explicate holds that the relationship
between a political community and its citizens is, under certain conditions, intrin-
sically valuable. It seems to me to be implausible in the extreme to think that this
relationship could be morally valuable in that way unless the norms that are par-
tially constitutive of the relationship existed not just in a social or conventional
sense, but in the stronger sense of having the normative force that they purport to
have. They must, in other words, be valid norms, which in this context means
morally valid norms,¹⁹ and the obligations they purport to impose must be real
obligations. This is moral bootstrapping, but bootstrapping is no more problem-
atic here than it is in the case of friendship. Legal norms (and their attendant
obligations) are partially constitutive of the relationship between the state and
the citizen in exactly the same way that the obligations of friendship are partially
constitutive of friendship. It is in this claim, I believe, that the true power of
Dworkin’s argument’s for political obligation resides. Given the non-instrumental
nature of the argument, there is no basis for picking and choosing among laws
in the way that attempted instrumental justifications of a general obligation to
obey almost invariably permit.²⁰ It seems to me that not even non-instrumental
considerations of a different kind, such as considerations of justice, can negate the
obligation, in the sense of justifying the conclusion that it does not exist. (They can
defeat or override the obligation, as I will discuss further below, but that is quite
a different matter.) We are assuming, it should be recalled, that the state treats
all of its citizens with equal concern—since otherwise the law would not have
integrity—and we are also assuming that equal concern is a concept that has genu-
ine moral content. If the argument up to this point is correct, then equal concern is
the only moral property that the law must have if political community is to have
intrinsic value. Political community could not have such value unless the norms
that constitute it are morally valid and hence binding. No other moral considera-
tions are relevant to the existence of the obligation, although they may defeat or
override it.
The point that other moral considerations may defeat or override the general
obligation to obey the law is an absolutely crucial one, since otherwise the conclu-
sion that such an obligation exists will be unacceptable on its face. The point is not,
in fact, a controversial one; almost every contemporary theorist who discusses this
issue assumes that if there is a general obligation to obey the law, which most deny, it
is only prima facie in character. It is perhaps less obvious that the obligation, if it
exists, need not be particularly strong. It is completely consistent with the argument
of the preceding paragraph that the obligation is routinely overridden by considera-
tions of justice, or even by instrumental considerations. A related point is that a gen-
eral obligation to obey the law need not, by itself, be strong enough to justify the use
of coercion by the state. As was noted in section I, Dworkin is careful to note that
while obligation is close to a necessary condition for coercion, it is not by itself
sufficient (LE at 191). It should be borne in mind in this regard that not all laws are
enforceable by coercive means, or even enforceable in any legal sense at all; the laws
that govern the relations among different branches of government are only the most
obvious example. It is, again, completely consistent with the argument of the
preceding paragraph that even if there is a general obligation to obey, the coercive
enforcement of any given law can only be justified by reference to instrumental con-
siderations, such as deterrence, or different non-instrumental considerations, such
as retribution. Finally, the claim that there is a general non-instrumental obligation
to obey the law is completely consistent with the possibility that the obligation to
obey many individual laws can also be justified on instrumental grounds, such as the
need for coordination. As was remarked in section II, there is no reason why an
obligation cannot be justified both instrumentally and non-instrumentally.
There is one aspect of Dworkin’s discussion of integrity that I have not
mentioned up to this point, which is captured by the following passage:
Members of a society of principle accept that their political rights and duties are not
exhausted by the particular decisions their political institutions have reached, but depend,
more generally, on the scheme of principles those decisions presuppose and endorse. So
each member accepts that others have rights and that he has duties flowing from that
scheme, even though these have never been formally identified or declared. (LE at 211)
Elsewhere Dworkin goes beyond this claim, arguing that integrity may in fact
require the rejection of certain past political decisions as mistakes; despite
appearances, those decisions never contributed to the content of the law. The
general point that the content of the law may extend beyond past political deci-
sions, or to some extent depart from them altogether, flows from the role that
interpretation plays in Dworkin’s substantive theory of the grounds of law;²¹ it is
a consequence of the claim that there is a tradeoff between fit and justification,
which are the two dimensions of interpretation, rather than a lexical ordering. It
is because interpretation figures in this way in Dworkin’s substantive theory that
considerations of force can have an effect on the grounds of law. As was noted in
section I, within Dworkin’s substantive theory the truth of “It is the law that A”
depends, in part, on whether or not the normative proposition “A” is capable of
being made true by the truth of “It is the law that A.” The theory makes this
determination holistically, by looking to how “A” fits into the content of the law
taken as a whole.²² The upshot of all this is the following. The answer to the
²¹ Interpretation plays a separate but related role in Dworkin’s arguments about methodology in
legal philosophy. See the brief discussion of this issue in section I above. ²² See supra note 6.
204 Stephen Perry
question of whether or not there is a general obligation to obey the law of a par-
ticular legal system depends on whether or not the content of the law, considered
as a whole, has integrity, while the question of what is the content of the law
depends, in part, on whether or not law understood as having this content rather
than that would have integrity (and hence would give rise to a general obligation
to obey). This is complicated but not circular, or at least not viciously so. The
only comment that I will make here on the interpretive aspect of Dworkin’s the-
ory of the grounds of law is that, while it fits naturally with the claim that the
existence of political obligation depends on whether or not the law has integrity,
it is logically independent of that claim. One could make the claim that political
obligation depends on integrity even if one thought that the content of law was
determined solely by social facts. One could make the claim, in other words, as a
matter of pure political philosophy, and hence even if one held views about the
relationship between political and legal philosophy that were quite different
from Dworkin’s own.
Dworkin’s argument that there is a general obligation to obey the law is, at least
in the version I have presented here, obviously controversial. It depends on a num-
ber of strong assumptions. One is the claim that the concept of equal concern has
independent moral content; another is the claim that political community can
have intrinsic value; and yet another is the claim that political community is a
unique good which is necessary for human beings to live complete or completely
fulfilled lives. Any of these assumptions might be wrong. It is also possible that
even if the argument is correct, it does not establish very much of interest because
the conditions it requires will rarely, if ever, be met: it may be, for example, that
the moral property of equal concern cannot be comprehensively attributed to any
existing legal system any more than true justice can. The argument seems to me to
be an important one even so, if only because there is no plausible route other than
a non-instrumentalist one for establishing the existence of a general obligation to
obey the law. Enthusiasts of a predominantly instrumental approach to the value
of law have, for the most part, embraced the conclusion that there can be no
purely instrumental argument for the existence of such an obligation,²³ and in
this I think they are right. They believe that a general obligation to obey the law is
a fiction, and in any event could not have any moral significance; whatever the law
achieves that is of moral value, they argue, it does so whether there is such an
obligation or not. The instrumentalists may be correct. But perhaps it is not
entirely irrelevant that so many judges, legislators and ordinary citizens believe
²³ See supra note 20. John Finnis offers an argument for a general obligation to obey the law that is,
I believe, best regarded as combining both instrumental and non-instrumental aspects. See, e.g.
Finnis, The Authority of Law in the Predicament of Contemporary Social Theory, 1 Notre Dame J. of
L. Ethics, & Pub. Pol. 115 (1984). Finnis’s theory of political obligation is quite different from
Dworkin’s, in ways that it is not possible to elaborate here. I discuss the details of Finnis’s view at some
length in Perry, Law and Obligation, supra note 3.
Associative Obligations and the Obligation to Obey the Law 205
that they really do have an obligation to obey the law. If the instrumentalists were
right, wouldn’t the news have filtered down by now? Perhaps the tenacity of the
belief in an obligation to obey the law should give them, and the rest of us, some
pause. One of the many merits of Dworkin’s argument is that it gives us a way of
thinking about the matter that helps to illuminate why that belief is as tenacious
as it is.
9
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire
John Gardner*
I
Does law have a purpose or point? Surely it does. The trickier questions are these:
Does law have a unifying purpose or point? Does law have a distinctive purpose or
point? Many think that, inasmuch as law has a unifying purpose—such as “the
guidance of conduct”—it is not a distinctive purpose. It is a purpose shared by
many things that are not law. And inasmuch as law has more distinctive pur-
poses—such as “being the final public arbiter of disputes” or “monopolizing the
use of force”—they are not unifying. Each such purpose is the purpose of some
law but not of all law. H.L.A. Hart’s book The Concept of Law is perhaps the best-
known defence of this conjunction of views.¹ Although he accepts that the law has
purposes, Hart advances a non-purposive (and more broadly non-functional)²
account of what legal norms have in common that distinguishes them from other
norms.
Ronald Dworkin belongs to a long tradition of writers who hold, by contrast,
that law has some purpose that is both unifying and distinctive. His book Law’s
Empire is an unusual contribution to this tradition in that it stands for the view
that law must have a unifying-and-distinctive purpose, but it does not commit
* Some of this paper reworks fragments of an earlier and more ambitious (but unpublished) paper
co-authored with Elisa Holmes. Thanks to Elisa for, inter alia, helping to disentangle the two differ-
ent projects that got tangled up in the earlier paper. Thanks to Jules Coleman, Scott Hershovitz and
Maris Köpcke-Tinturé for demonstrating the need to do so. And thanks to all these people for their
many other helpful suggestions, not all of which, alas, have found their way into this final text.
¹ H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (1961). On some of law’s distinctive but non-unifying
purposes, see id. at 38–41. On some of law’s unifying but non-distinctive purposes, see id. at
189–195. See also Hart’s postscript to the second edition of The Concept of Law (2d ed., 1994), at
248–249. (Subsequent references are to the first edition unless otherwise indicated.)
² Not only is law not distinguished by its purposes; it is also not distinguished by its achievements.
For Hart, as for Kelsen, neither intended nor actual effects set legal systems apart from other norm-
ative systems. As Green summarizes the Hart-Kelsen view, law is “a modal kind and not a functional
kind.” L. Green, The Concept of Law Revisited, 94 Mich. L. Rev. 1687, 1711 (1996).
itself to a final view on what this purpose is.³ In Chapter 3 of Law’s Empire,
Dworkin provisionally attributes a purpose to law in order to “organize[ ] further
argument about law’s character.”⁴ Even if he has this purpose wrong, he argues,
some unifying-and-distinctive purpose for law must be relied upon if arguments
about the nature of law are to get off the ground. We need “a statement of the
central concept of [our] institution that will allow [us] to see our arguments . . . as
arguments over rival conceptions of that concept.”⁵ To furnish such a “conceptual
statement”⁶ in the case of law, he says, we must find “the most abstract and funda-
mental point of legal practice.”⁷ For law is an “interpretive enterprise”⁸ and this
means that those who are interested in finding out what (else) is true about law
have to begin by taking an “interpretive attitude” to their subject. This in turn
means starting from the assumption that law “has some point” that sets it apart
and brings it together as the particular interpretive enterprise that it is.⁹
Here Dworkin’s argument proceeds transcendentally. Unlike many before him,
he does not try to show that law must have a unifying-and-distinctive purpose by
showing what unifying-and-distinctive purpose law has. Rather, he tries to show
that law must have a unifying-and-distinctive purpose by showing that we cannot
make sense of law without assuming one. The question of which unifying and dis-
tinctive purpose law has can be settled later. Meanwhile we can make do with a
provisional proposal that is pencilled in for the sake of argument.
So what purpose does Dworkin provisionally attribute to law for the sake of
argument? The following purpose, he says, is “sufficiently abstract and uncontro-
versial” to do the job:
Our discussions of law by and large assume, I suggest, that the most abstract and funda-
mental point of legal practice is to guide and constrain the power of government in the fol-
lowing way. Law insists that force [ ⫽ coercion] not be used or withheld . . . except as
licensed or required by individual rights and responsibilities flowing from past political
decisions about when collective force is justified.¹⁰
Dworkin’s Suggested Purpose, or DSP as I will call it for short, is complex and
intriguing. But is it plausible? I think not. At any rate, it is far from uncontrover-
sial. As many have pointed out, a legal system might still exist, and if it did would
still have a purpose or point, in a society of angels. Since the ex hypothesi perfect
population of such a society will be guided by the ex hypothesi perfect laws and
policies of their ex hypothesi perfect government, coercion by that government will
not be needed, and will not be used, to get them to fall into line with law. Nor,
therefore, will law be called upon to regulate government coercion. Yet there will
³ R. M. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986) [hereinafter “LE”]. ⁴ LE, 93. ⁵ LE, 92.
⁶ LE, 92.
⁷ LE, 93. For present purposes I assume that nothing turns, for Dworkin, on the distinction
between “law” and “legal practice.” ⁸ LE, 90.
⁹ LE, 47.
¹⁰ LE, 93. The square-bracketed insertion reflects what Dworkin says a few lines later, and is added
here to reduce the volume of quotation.
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 209
still be co-ordination problems to which angelic law may provide the best solu-
tions (what side of the road to drive angelic vehicles on, what frequencies to allo-
cate to angelic cellphones, etc.). So angelic law may still exist and, if it does, it will
still have a purpose—even though there is no coercion by angelic governments for
it to “guide and constrain.”¹¹
There are several things one can learn from this exotic thought-experiment.
The most important lesson is this: That the licensing of government coercion in
ordinary human legal systems, even when successful, is a consequence of a deeper
failure. As Hart captures the point, the resort to legal coercion is a “pis aller,” a
“secondary provision[ ] for a breakdown in case the primary intended peremptory
reasons are not accepted as such.”¹² Whatever other purposes law may have, it
clearly has the purpose of providing law-subjects, including the government, with
normative guidance; that is to say, of subjecting their conduct to the governance
of norms. If only law were fully to succeed in this purpose, if only all law-subjects
were to use legal norms as they are supposed to be used, by being guided by them
qua norms, there would be no need, and no case, for the government to coerce
people into conformity with those same norms. So there would be no need for law
to regulate government coercion. If that much is true, then DSP, even if it is a dis-
tinctively legal purpose, is not a unifying one. It is a purpose of law only on those
occasions when law has failed to achieve its more unifying (albeit less distinctive)
purpose of providing normative guidance for use by its subjects.
II
Although I have just made my own sympathies clear, my interest here is not in
developing this critique of DSP.¹³ I am interested, rather, in an aspect of DSP that
the critique, as it stands, leaves unchallenged. Possibly law’s purpose, even in a
society of angels, is not merely to provide its subjects (including the government)
with normative guidance. Possibly law’s purpose, more specifically, is to provide
its subjects with justified normative guidance. This view has been defended at
length by John Finnis in Natural Law and Natural Rights. To Finnis, the “society of
angels” thought-experiment¹⁴ tends to suggest, not that law lacks a unifying-and-
distinctive purpose, but that law has a unifying-and-distinctive purpose quite
¹¹ Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics 1179b30–1180b28; Hart, The Concept of Law, supra
note 1, at 195; J. Raz, Practical Reason and Norms 159 (1975); J. Finnis, Natural Law and
Natural Rights 266–267 (1980).
¹² Hart, Commands and Authoritative Legal Reasons in his Essays on Bentham 254 (1982).
¹³ One way to attempt a rescue of DSP might be to argue, with Kelsen, that there are no legal
norms except those that regulate the coercive conduct of state officials. In Kelsen’s words: “Law is the
primary norm which stipulates the sanction.” See General Theory of Law and State 63 (1949).
This view of Kelsen’s has not, however, survived Hart’s critique of it in The Concept of Law, supra
note 1, at 35–41.
¹⁴ Or “world of saints”, as Finnis prefers: Natural Law and Natural Rights, supra note 11,
at 269.
210 John Gardner
different from DSP. The purpose is that of providing co-ordination of conduct for
the common good.¹⁵ This purpose is in two respects more distinctive than that of
merely providing normative guidance to law-subjects. In the first place, according
to Finnis, law aims to provide normative guidance to law-subjects that works in a
distinctive way, namely by co-ordinating their conduct. In the second place, law
aims to provide normative guidance that lives up to a certain standard: it aims to
serve the common good. This second specification is the one that we are concerned
with here. It entails an important feature that Finnis’s suggested purpose shares
with Dworkin’s. For Finnis and Dworkin alike, law aims to guide its subjects prop-
erly, soundly, upstandingly, well. Law aims to be justified in the guidance that it
gives to those whom it aims to guide, such that what they do, when they are guided
by the law and make no mistakes about the law, will itself be justified.
One should be careful not to trivialize this thesis. In all norm-governed pur-
suits, questions of justification arise that are, so to speak, internal to the pursuit.
They are simply questions of whether the norms are being adhered to. In a game
of Monopoly, for example, I land on “Chance” and draw the “Go Directly to
Jail” card. The “banker” refuses to pay me the “salary” I ususally get for passing
“Go.” Is this refusal justified? The answer depends on the rules of Monopoly.
Barring exceptional circumstances (e.g. we are playing for the last space in the
lifeboat, or the “banker” is a cheat), the act of denying me the “salary” has no
significance outside the game, and there is no relevant extra-ludic standard of
assessment. In law, we are sometimes temporarily interested in justification con-
ceived in this purely internal way. On some occasions and for some purposes, we
merely want to know whether what we are doing is justified by the legal system’s
own rules, however quirky and technical. We want to know, for example, what
deadline the law sets for serving a notice to quit following a breach of lease,
because we want to know what the legal consequences will be of our postponing
service of the notice until after rent negotiations are complete. This is a superfi-
cially game-like question. As a lawyer, one may sometimes be tempted to think
of it on the model of Monopoly. But law, as Finnis rightly emphasizes, is not a
game.¹⁶ Everything done by law affects someone, or potentially affects some-
one, in a morally significant way. Thus a question of legal justification always
invites, and never eclipses, a further question of justification. The law sets, let us
suppose, a 14-day deadline for serving a notice to quit following breach of a
lease. But in one’s relations with one’s tenants, should one use this legal deadline
rather than some other? This is not a question about what is justified under the
legal norm. Ex hypothesi, a deadline of 14 days from breach of lease is justified
under the legal norm. Rather, it is a further question about whether one is
morally justified in relying on the legal norm as a justification for one’s action.
Law, on the view I am associating with Dworkin and Finnis, aims to live up to
¹⁵ Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, supra note 11, e.g. at 334–336.
¹⁶ Id. at 305.
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 211
this standard: to be something that its users are morally justified in using. In
Finnis’s terms, law can be “fully understood only by understanding [its] point,
that is to say [its] objective,”¹⁷ which is to make a distinctive kind of contribu-
tion to “practical reasonableness” (this expression being substituted only
because “the term ‘moral’ is of somewhat uncertain connotation”).¹⁸
No doubt Dworkin would resist this (Finnis-influenced)¹⁹ conceptualization
of the contrast between law and game-playing. Dworkin treats the moral ques-
tions inevitably raised by law as bearing (mainly) on the correct interpretation of
legal norms, not (or not mainly) on the propriety of their use once correctly
interpreted.²⁰ This is the second component of the “interpretive attitude” that
law calls for as an “interpretive enterprise.” Law not only “has a point”; law’s
content—what the law of any given jurisdiction says on any given question—is
also “sensitive to its point.”²¹ Thus, for Dworkin, what one is morally justified in
doing in one’s relations with one’s tenants affects (mainly) whether the law
should be understood as setting a 14-day deadline in the first place, not (or not
mainly) whether one is justified in using the legal deadline once the law is so
understood. It follows that in the legal domain, according to Dworkin, there is
normally no such thing as justification “internal to the pursuit” where this
implies leaving the question of moral justification open in determining what the
applicable legal norms are.
I will return to this issue later. For the time being, we need only note that
Dworkin’s famous view about the determination of legal content (the second
component of his “interpretive attitude”) does not drive any wedge between him
and Finnis on the question of law’s purpose or point (the first component). Finnis
and Dworkin alike suggest that law has a justificatory purpose. Moreover, for both
of them it is a morally justificatory purpose. Theirs is not the easy-to-accept thesis
that law is a normative pursuit and hence cannot but provide standards of justi-
fication of some kind. Theirs is the more substantial and contentious thesis that
law aims to provide standards of moral justification, and hence to be morally justi-
fied in the norms it provides. This thesis leaves open whether the aim in question
is to be served by interpreting laws morally, or by not following immoral laws, or
perhaps sometimes by interpreting laws morally and sometimes by not following
immoral laws. This disagreement can be bracketed for now. Our interest for the
time being is only in the Finnis-Dworkin “plateau”²² of agreement, which seems
to extend to the following thesis, if no further:
(␣) Law aims to be morally justified.
In formulating (␣) I have chosen “aims” rather than “has the purpose” or “has the
aim,” not only to save words, but also to avoid giving the impression that,
for either Finnis or Dworkin, (␣) fully captures law’s unifying-and-distinctive
purpose. For both of them (␣) captures no more than one (unifying but not
distinctive) aspect of law’s unifying-and-distinctive purpose.²³
III
Is Dworkin committed to (␣)? (␣) is entailed by DSP, which is Dworkin’s own “con-
ceptual statement” about law. But recall that DSP is only mooted provisionally by
Dworkin, as a working assumption to help us “organize[ ] further argument about
law’s character.” Does (␣) represent an equally provisional aspect of Dworkin’s
thought? Does he align himself with (␣) only for the sake of argument? Or would
(␣) also be entailed by every other suggested unifying-and-distinctive purpose for
law that Dworkin would be prepared to entertain as an alternative to DSP?
There is much in Law’s Empire to suggest that the answer is yes. Chapters four
to seven of the book are devoted to exploring the question: Which moral ideal is
the proper moral ideal for law (through its practitioners and officials) to aim at?
Dworkin famously answers: “integrity.”²⁴ His defence of this answer is conducted
on the footing that, while the choice of integrity as the proper moral ideal to be
aimed at is not itself conceptually determined—“law as integrity” is but one pos-
sible “conception” of law—nevertheless, it is part of the concept of law that law
aims at some moral ideal. Since it is (in turn) part of the concept of a moral ideal
that whatever aims at a moral ideal aims to be, at the very least, morally justified, it
seems that, for Dworkin, any acceptable conception of law is one that paints law
as aiming to be, at the very least, morally justified. So, in these subsequent chap-
ters of Law’s Empire, (␣) seems to be endorsed by Dworkin and not just mooted
for the sake of argument.
Yet there are also conspicuous themes in Dworkin’s work that seem to militate
against his endorsing (␣). In the following three sections I will consider three of
these themes.
IV
²³ This opens up the possibility that thesis (␣) is also endorsed by Hart in The Concept of Law,
supra note 1, at 186–188. But Hart keeps his options open on this point, and in the postscript to the
second edition of The Concept of Law, supra note 1, at 248–249, he explicitly disclaims any attach-
ment to (␣). Law is not a game, but the difference, for Hart, does not lie in law’s aim. It lies, inter alia,
in law’s claim. See Section IV below on aims and claims.
²⁴ LE, 244. Hercules, the ideal judge “follows law as integrity.”
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 213
This type of personification is often used in philosophy as a shorthand way of stating the
meaning or content of a class of propositions. A philosopher might say, for example, that
morality claims to impose categorical requirements, or that physics claims to reveal the
deep structure of the physical universe. He means that no proposition is a true proposition
of morality unless it accurately reports categorical (rather than only hypothetical) require-
ments or that no proposition is a true proposition of physics unless it correctly reports
physical structure. If we read Raz’s personification in this familiar way, we take him to
mean that no proposition of law is true unless it successfully reports an exercise of legit-
imate authority. But that would imply not that morality cannot be a test for law, as Raz
claims, but that it must be a test for law because, as he recognizes, no exercise of authority is
legitimate “if the moral or normative conditions for one’s directives being authoritative are
absent.”
It is difficult to find a sensible alternative reading of Raz’s personification. He sometimes
suggests that when he says “law” claims legitimate authority he means that legal officials
claim that authority; legal officials do this when they insist that they have a “right” to
impose obligations on citizens and that these citizens “owe them allegiance” and “ought to
obey the law.” It is one thing to suppose that legal officials often make such claims; it is
quite another to suppose that unless they make such claims, there is necessarily no law. In
fact many officials do not. Oliver Wendell Holmes, for example, thought the very idea of
moral obligation a confusion. He did not suppose that legal enactments replace the ordin-
ary reasons people have for acting with some overriding obligation-imposing directive, but
rather that these enactments add new reasons to ordinary ones by making the cost of acting
in certain ways more expensive. Whether a community has law does not depend on how
many of its legal officials share Holmes’ views. So we cannot make sense of Raz’s crucial
personification by supposing it to refer to the actual beliefs or attitudes of officials.²⁵
If sound, these criticisms tell against an important thesis that Raz implicitly
defends as a rival to (␣). This rival thesis is entailed by the thesis that law claims
legitimate authority. It says:
() Law claims to be morally justified.
Dworkin’s criticisms of Raz on authority tell against () because () can be true
only if law is the kind of thing that can make claims, and in the quoted passage
Dworkin denies that law is that kind of thing. But should he deny it?
One may readily agree with Dworkin, as Raz does, that it takes a human being
to make a claim. Raz makes tolerably clear that, for these purposes, the relevant
human beings are legal officials.²⁶ Legal officials, he argues, are those who make
the claim mentioned in (). Yet at the same time Raz’s attribution of the claim to
law itself is not elliptical. It is not shorthand for “legal officials claim that law is
morally justified.” That is because legal officials, according to Raz, make the claim
mentioned in () on law’s behalf. And that in turn is because it is part of the con-
cept of a legal official that, when someone acts as a legal official, she acts on law’s
behalf. So if () is sound, then someone who does not claim moral justification for
²⁵ Dworkin, Thirty Years On, 115 Harv. L. Rev. 1655, 1666–1667 (2002).
²⁶ J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain 215–216 (paperback ed., 1995).
214 John Gardner
what she does is not, in doing it, acting as a legal official, for (in failing to make the
claim that law necessarily makes) she is no longer acting on behalf of the law. That
is the most important pay-off of (), and it holds only if the claim in () is under-
stood (non-elliptically) to be law’s own claim, and not merely the claim of some
human beings.²⁷ It takes a human being to make a claim but it does not follow
that human beings are the only things that make claims. Law makes claims
through human beings acting on its behalf.
These remarks about () matter for present purposes because they apply,
mutatis mutandis, to (␣) as well. True, law cannot make any claims except through
human beings acting on its behalf, i.e. legal officials. But by the same token law
cannot have any aims except through human beings acting on its behalf. For (␣) to
be non-elliptically true, there must equally be human beings who, on law’s behalf,
aim at the law’s being morally justified, and who are acting on law’s behalf (i.e.
count as legal officials) only if they aim at the law’s being morally justified.
Inasmuch as () is offered by Raz as a rival to (␣), there must obviously be some
objections to () that are not objections to (␣). But Dworkin’s way of rejecting (),
in the passage just quoted, would also commit him to rejecting (␣). Consider what it
means to make a claim to moral justification. Minimally, it means acting with the
aim that one be taken to be morally justified. Legal officials—those acting on behalf
of the law—make a claim to moral justification only if they aim that the law should
be taken to be morally justified by those law-subjects to whom it is addressed. This in
turn means that they aim either that law be morally justified or that it be mistaken for
something that is morally justified. It is the second possibility—the possibility of a
pretence or masquerade on the part of law and legal officials—that distinguishes ()
from (␣). Some things that would not count as law according to (␣)—because they
do not aim to be morally justified—still count as law according to ()—because they
masquerade as having that aim. Raz is careful to point out that, as compared with law
that lives up to the standard enunciated in (␣), law that merely masquerades as doing
so is a less central case of law.²⁸ Just as the central case or paradigm of anything that
has an aim is (ceteris paribus) the case in which it succeeds at that aim, so the central
case or paradigm of anything that makes a claim is (ceteris paribus) the case in which
it makes that claim sincerely. So the central case of law, according to Raz’s criterion
(), is the case of law that is morally justified. Relative to morally justified law, law
that merely aims to be morally justified but does not succeed in that aim is a less cen-
tral case of law. And relative to law that aims to be morally justified (whether or not it
succeeds in that aim), law that merely pretends to have that aim but does not really
have it is in turn a less central case of law. It is a highly deviant case of law. Yet the
claim that is present in the deviant case is also present in the central case. That is one
of the features that, for Raz, brings them all together as cases of law. Although there
may be law that does not have the aim mentioned in (␣), there is no possible law that
does not make the claim mentioned in ().
²⁷ Cf. P. Soper, Law’s Normative Claims in The Autonomy of Law (R. P. George ed., 1996).
²⁸ Ethics in the Public Domain, supra note 26, at 270.
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 215
Perhaps more importantly, Law’s Empire itself gives us reason to doubt whether
Dworkin accepts, or could accept, (␣). Consider Dworkin’s statement of the first
assumption made by those who take the “interpretive attitude” to law. They
²⁹ O. W. Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harvard Law Review 457, 461–462 (1897).
³⁰ Contrast LE, 172–175, where Dworkin seems to suggest that the law has a moral voice in which
officials, acting as officials, cannot but speak.
216 John Gardner
assume, he says, “that the practice [of law] does not simply exist but has value, that
it serves some interest or purpose or enforces some principle—in short that it has
some point—that can be stated independently of just describing the rules that
make up the practice.”³¹ There is some equivocation in this remark. To adopt the
interpretive attitude, says Dworkin, we need to assume that law serves a purpose.
Does this mean that law has a purpose? Or does it mean that law achieves that pur-
pose? The two claims are not, as they stand, incompatible. Many things have a
purpose that they also achieve. But the two claims are incompatible as soon as they
are understood as “conceptual statements” about law. That is because purposive
agency is agency that leaves open the logical possibility of failure. If it is impossible
to classify the actions of a certain agent into the categories “failure” and “success”
(because failure is conceptually ruled out) then that agent is not a purposive agent.
It does not have any purposes. And if a certain action cannot be classified as a fail-
ure or success (because failure is conceptually ruled out) then that action is not an
action with a purpose. And if a certain action cannot be classified as a failure or
success in its possession of a certain property (because failure to possess that prop-
erty is conceptually ruled out) then having that property cannot figure among the
purposes of that action. Accordingly, if law is such that whatever it does is morally
justified—if its being morally justified is part of what it means for it to count as
law—then it cannot at the same time aim at (have among its purposes that of )
being morally justified.
In short, thesis (␣) cannot possibly be true if the following rival thesis about law
is true:
() Law is morally justified.
If Dworkin accepts () then he cannot accept (␣).³² Moreover, he cannot accept
any “conceptual statement” for law of which (␣) is an implication. So he must also
abandon DSP, the unifying-and-distinctive purpose that he provisionally attaches
to law in Chapter 3 of Law’s Empire. Since by () there is no logical space for law to
fail in the moral justification of state coercion—since law’s own moral justification
in doing whatever it does is conceptually secure—morally justifying state coercion
cannot be an aim or purpose of law. It can of course be an aim or purpose of some
people writing about law, such as Dworkin himself. Such law-favourers may aim
to morally justify (all) law in order to support the case for (). My point is only
that law itself (acting through its officials) cannot aim to be morally justified if ()
is true, whereas law itself (acting through its officials) cannot but aim to be morally
justified if (␣) is true.
Does Dworkin accept (), and hence eschew (␣)? Some other passages in Law’s
Empire maintain the same equivocation between () and (␣) that afflicts
³¹ LE, 47.
³² Contrast J. Dickson, Evaluation and Legal Theory 106 (2001). Dickson allows Dworkin to
endorse both (␣) and () together, and seems to see them as natural bedfellows.
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 217
VI
Yet the problem of reconciling (␣) with other themes of Law’s Empire is not yet
over. Consider now Dworkin’s statement of the second assumption made by those
who take the “interpretive attitude” to law. They assume, he says, “that the
requirements of [law]—the behavior it calls for or judgments it warrants—are not
³³ LE, 103–104.
218 John Gardner
necessarily or exclusively what they have always been taken to be but are instead
sensitive to its point, so that the strict rules must be understood or applied or
extended or modified or qualified or limited by that point.”³⁴ Here we find traces
of the same equivocation between (␣) and () that ran through Dworkin’s state-
ment of the first assumption, quoted above. If () is true then the law’s “require-
ments,” the “strict rules,” are already morally justified and officials need not alter
them to make them so. If (␣) is true, on the other hand, then there may be
“requirements” or “strict rules” of law that are not already morally justified, in
which case legal officials, acting on behalf of the law, have the (␣)-given aim of
transforming them into morally justified requirements or rules. The words
“extended or modified or qualified or limited” plainly support the second reading
of the passage, and hence tend to confirm Dworkin’s allegiance to (␣) over ().
Legal officials have the (␣)-given aim of taking morally unjustified legal norms
(“strict rules”) and changing them (by extension, modification, qualification or
limitation) into morally justified legal norms. So there can be morally unjustified
legal norms that call for legal officials to change them with the (␣)-given aim of
making them morally justified. () is false because (␣) is true.
The words “understood or applied,” on the other hand, can be read consistently
with either (␣) or (). Understanding and applying legal norms might be oper-
ations that legal officials perform upon legal norms with the aim of improving
them, i.e. with the aim of transfoming them into morally justified norms on the
occasions when they are not morally justified as they stand. On this reading of
“understood or applied,” () remains false, for there can be morally unjustified as
well as morally justified legal norms. Yet one may also read the words “understood
or applied” consistently with (), and hence inconsistently with (␣). No legal
norm is morally unjustified, and therefore no legal official can possibly have the
aim of changing a legal norm from a morally unjustified one to a morally justified
one. The challenge for legal officials under the heading of “understanding and
applying” the “strict rules” is only to bring out what is already in these rules, i.e. to
understand each legal norm as the morally justified norm that it already is, and to
apply it accordingly.
Dworkin’s account of how judges should go about understanding and applying
the law—namely, by “constructively interpreting” it—is usually read in the latter
way, as an account according to which the law already means what it should mean
(i.e. what it would mean if it were morally justified) and hence only needs to have
its meaning brought out, not altered, by judges. This is what I referred to above as
“Dworkin’s famous view about the determination of legal content.” But on closer
inspection Dworkin’s official characterization of “constructive interpretation” in
Chapter 2 of Law’s Empire leans very strongly in the opposite direction:
Roughly, constructive interpretation is a matter of imposing purpose on an object . . . in
order to make of it the best possible example of the form or genre to which it is taken to
³⁴ LE, 47.
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 219
belong. It does not follow, even from that rough account, that an interpreter can make of
[the object] anything he would have wanted it to be, that a citizen of courtesy who is
enthralled by equality, for example, can in good faith claim that courtesy actually requires
the sharing of wealth. For the history and shape of a[n] . . . object constrains the available
interpretations of it . . . . Creative intepretation, on the constructive view, is a matter of
interaction between purpose and object.³⁵
This passage has an odd start, when set against other passages in the same chapter.
Dworkin suggests that a purpose needs to be imposed on an object by a construct-
ive interpreter. If this were true it would compete with the thought that law has a
purpose. Perhaps Dworkin only means that the interpreter has to work out what
the purpose in question is? Or perhaps Dworkin means that, given that law has
among its purposes that of being morally justified, the interpreter still needs to do
the work of adjudicating between various different moral ideals for law (“concep-
tions”) to decide which particular laws would be morally justified ones and why?
Either way, the word “impose” seems ill-suited to capture how the interpreter is
supposed to relate to his or her object.
That constructive interpreters “impose” purpose on the object before them
seems, then, to be an infelicity in Dworkin’s formulation.³⁶ That constructive
interpreters thereby “make [something] of ” the object before them seems, how-
ever, to be an accurate statement of what Dworkin has in mind. There is always
an object of interpretation and the aim of the constructive interpreter is to
improve it, transform it into a better object of the same kind. In legal contexts,
thanks to the truth of (␣), that means a morally better object, a legal norm that
comes closer to conforming to the proper moral ideal for law, whatever that
ideal may be. In the process, there must of course be some preservation of some
aspects of the norm one started with. If there is nothing at all left of that norm
then what one did to it cannot count as interpreting it. But there must also be
some improvement. If one did not improve the norm one started with, one’s
interpretation of it was not constructive.
That seems to be the sense in which, according to Dworkin, constructive inter-
pretation is a matter of “interaction between purpose and object.” There is some
continuity in the object but there is also some improvement, some gravitation
towards the ideal that properly pertains to an object of that type. The key
Dworkinian contrast seems to be that between constructive interpreters, who aim
to give the same object a new and better meaning, and what Raz has called “con-
serving” interpreters, who aim to retrieve some meaning that the object already
has or has had.³⁷ Both differ from non-interpreting improvers—Dworkin calls
them “pragmatists”—who are simply inclined to replace the object outright with a
new and better one.
³⁵ LE, 52.
³⁶ See also J. Finnis, On Reason and Authority in Law’s Empire, 6 Law and Philosophy 357,
359–360 (1987).
³⁷ J. Raz, Interpretation without Retrieval in Law and Interpretation (A. Marmor ed., 1996).
220 John Gardner
If this reading is correct, then “understanding” and “applying” the law, when
tackled constructively, are also ways of “extending or modifying or qualifying or
limiting” the law. The law is not left as it was by the interpreting judge. This con-
clusion is crucial to the success of Law’s Empire if it is to be read as a defence and
explication of (␣). Throughout the book, Dworkin uses the situation of judges to
illustrate the force of (␣). But if judges are to have the aim, on behalf of the law,
that law be morally justified, there must be possible morally unjustified legal
norms for them to have and pursue this aim in respect of—morally unjustified
legal norms that they can render morally justified by their improving interpret-
ative interventions.³⁸
The most striking implication of this, if true, is that the Dworkin of Law’s
Empire has no significant axe to grind with the legal positivist tradition. In order
to continue grinding this axe, the Dworkin of Law’s Empire turns legal positivists
into advocates for “conserving” interpretations of legal norms. He thereby creates
an issue between himself and legal positivism, namely the issue of constructive
versus conserving interpretation. But none of the major recent writers commonly
thought of as legal positivists (Kelsen, Hart, Raz, Coleman) shows any predilec-
tion for conserving interpretations of legal norms.³⁹ The thing they all agree on,
what unites them as legal positivists, is that the law is made by legal officials, such
that if one wants to know what the law says on a given subject in a given jurisdic-
tion one needs to investigate what those officials did or said, not what they ought
to have done or said. The law is made up exclusively of norms that have been
announced, practised, invoked, enforced, or otherwise engaged with by human
beings acting on law’s behalf. We can represent this thesis as:
(␦) In any legal system, the law is made up of norms which are part of the law
only because some legal official engaged with them, and such an agent is
a legal official only because, by engaging with norms in certain ways, he
or she can make them part of the law.⁴⁰
³⁸ Cf. Nicos Stavropoulos’s claim that Dworkin “need not accept that any legal norms or rules are
individuated non-interpretively”: Interpretivist Theories of Law, Stanford Encyclopaedia of
Philosophy, ⬍http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/law-interpretivist/⬎. What does Stavropoulos mean?
Perhaps all he means is that each new constructive interpreter comes to the norm as already shaped
by some previous constructive interpretation of it. This is false (someone has to be the first judge
to read the first constitution, the first statute, etc). But even if it were true it would be trivial. Relative
to each act of interpretation there would still surely be a pre-interpretive norm, viz. one that was out-
put by a previous interpreter. Dworkin must accept that these pre-interpretive norms exist, or else an
act of constructive interpretation has norms neither as inputs nor as outputs, and so is in no sense
normative.
³⁹ Furthermore, Hart and Raz explicitly renounce any such predilection: see Hart, The
Concept of Law, supra note 1, at 200–202; Raz, Why Interpret?, 9 Ratio Juris 349, 360–363
(1996).
⁴⁰ For a perhaps more familiar formulation of (␦), see J. Gardner, Legal Positivism: 51⁄2; Myths, 46
American Journal of Jurisprudence 199 (2001).
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 221
⁴¹ LE, 7. Strictly speaking, the words “in no way” make this view slightly more restrictive than (␦).
Some who endorse (␦), including Hart, understand it to be compatible with there being moral tests of
legal validity if (but only if ) those moral tests have been engaged with (announced, used, etc.) by legal
officials: see Hart, The Concept of Law, supra note 1, at 70–71. Elsewhere on the same page
Dworkin places a different restriction on the “plain fact” view. He formulates it as the view that “the
law is only a matter of what legal institutions have decided in the past . . . So questions of law can
always be answered by looking in the books where the records are kept.” Such a view may have been
held by Austin and maybe even Bentham but it is rejected by Kelsen, Hart, Raz and Coleman, all of
whom recognize the using of a norm, as well as the announcing of it, as a possible way of engaging
with it so as to make it into law. I am assuming that Dworkin means the “plain fact” view to be one
that could be taken by Kelsen, Hart, Raz and Coleman—in other words, that, in spite of his ambiguities,
he means it to correspond to (␦).
⁴² A point that is accepted and emphasized by Finnis. See Natural Law and Natural Rights,
supra note 11, at 232; also The Truth in Legal Positivism in The Autonomy of Law, supra note 27.
⁴³ See supra text accompanying note 25.
222 John Gardner
must be human beings who do those things on behalf of law. (␣) emphasizes that
legal norms are made (and modified) by people, for by (␣) legal norms are made
(and modified) with a certain aim, viz. that they be morally justified. If there are
any legal norms that are not made (or modified) by human beings then they can-
not have that or any other aim, so they would count as counterexamples to (␣). So
if Law’s Empire is a defence of (␣), it should also be read as a defence, albeit a back-
handed defence, of thesis (␦), which is the thesis that unites members of the legal
positivist tradition.
Of course the converse does not hold. One may be a legal positivist—a (␦)-
endorser—who does not endorse (␣). Raz is an example. As we saw, he endorses
() over (␣). The difference, recall, is that () allows for legal officials who only
pretend to aim that the law be morally justified: on law’s behalf they make the
claim to be morally justified but do not really have the aim. () makes conceptual
space for such pretence, so that Nazi law is law, and Nazi officials are legal offi-
cials, even if many of them are only pretending to aim at moral justification. Of
course, while it makes logical space for it, () does not make any moral space for
such pretence. () is a thesis about law, not a thesis about the moral duties of
legal officials. Morally, as Raz says, judges should aim that the law they make or
modify be morally justified.⁴⁴ That they should have this aim does not entail
that, whenever they speak on behalf of the law, they do have this aim. It does not
entail that (␣) rather than () is true, any more than it entails the opposite. It is
an independent problem. Nevertheless it is a problem that one confronts only if
one endorses (␣) or () rather than (). For if () is true then there is no logical
space for judges to act with the aim that the law they make or modify be morally
justified. For all the law they engage with is morally justified already, and their
only job is to bring this fact out.
VII
⁴⁴ Sometimes, on Raz’s view, this moral imperative should carry judges beyond interpreting
the law to make it morally better. Sometimes they should effect moral improvements to the law in
ways that are more radical than mere interpretation would allow. They should sometimes decline to
follow the law. See, among many discussions spread across Raz’s work, The Authority of Law
(1979), ch. 10; Ethics in the Public Domain, supra note 26, ch. 14, and Incorporation by Law, 10
Legal Theory 1 (2004).
Law’s Aims in Law’s Empire 223
⁴⁵ Robert Alexy has devoted much energy to showing that (), which he calls “law’s claim to moral
correctness” is incompatible with legal positivism. But this is only because he holds legal positivism to
the thesis that there is no necessary connection between law and morality. Thesis ( ) is clearly incon-
sistent with this, since it states a necessary connection between law and morality.
⁴⁶ A more common position is that the positivity of legal norms—the fact that they are made by
people—automatically lends some redeeming value to legal norms even when they are (otherwise)
morally abhorrent. I also find this position unattractive. In my view there can be immoral laws that
have absolutely no morally redeeming features.
10
How Facts Make Law
Mark Greenberg*
I. Introduction
Nearly all philosophers of law agree that non-normative, non-evaluative, contin-
gent facts—descriptive facts, for short—are among the determinants of the content
of the law. In particular, ordinary empirical facts about the behavior and mental
states of people such as legislators, judges, other government officials, and voters
play a part in determining that content. It is highly controversial, however, whether
the relevant descriptive facts, which we can call law-determining practices, or law
practices (or simply practices) for short,¹ are the only determinants of legal content,
or whether legal content also depends on normative or evaluative facts—value
facts,² for short. In fact, a central—perhaps the central—debate in the philosophy
of law is a debate over whether value facts are among the determinants of the
content of the law (though the debate is not usually characterized in this way).
A central claim of legal positivism is that the content of the law depends only on
social facts, understood as a proper subset of descriptive facts. As Joseph Raz says,
“H. L. A. Hart is heir and torch-bearer of a great tradition in the philosophy of law
which . . . regards the existence and content of the law as a matter of social fact
* This chapter was originally published as How Facts Make Law, 10 Legal Theory 157 (2004). It is
reprinted here with permission from Cambridge University Press. For helpful comments on ancient
and recent predecessors of this chapter, I am very grateful to Larry Alexander, Andrea Ashworth, Ruth
Chang, Jules Coleman, Martin Davies, Ronald Dworkin, Gil Harman, Scott Hershovitz, Kinch
Hoekstra, Harry Litman, Tim Macht, Tom Nagel, Ram Neta, Jim Pryor, Stephen Perry, Joseph Raz,
Gideon Rosen, Scott Shapiro, Seana Shiffrin, Ori Simchen, Martin Stone, Enrique Villanueva, and
two anonymous referees for Legal Theory. Special thanks to Susan Hurley and Nicos Stavropoulos for
many valuable discussions. I would also like to thank audiences at the University of Pennsylvania,
New York University, UCLA, Yale University, the 2002 Annual Analytic Legal Philosophy
Conference, and the 2003 International Congress in Mexico City, where versions of this material
were presented. Finally, I owe a great debt to the work of Ronald Dworkin.
¹ For the moment, I will be vague about the nature of law practices. For more precision, see
Section II.B below. ² For some explanation of what I mean by “value facts,” see infra note 22 .
whose connection with moral or any other values is contingent and precarious.”³
In contemporary philosophy of law, there are two distinct ways of developing this
tradition: hard and soft positivism. Hard positivism denies that value facts may
play any role in determining legal content.⁴ Soft positivism allows that the rele-
vant social facts may make value facts relevant in a secondary way. For example,
the fact that a legislature uses a moral term—“equality,” say—in a statute may
have the effect of incorporating moral facts—about equality, in this case—into
the law.⁵ On this soft positivist view, however, it is still the social facts that make
the value facts relevant, and the social facts need not incorporate value facts into
the law. Hence according to both hard and soft positivism, it is possible for social
facts alone to determine what the law is, and even when they make value facts
relevant, social facts do the fundamental work in making the law what it is—work
that is explanatorily prior to the role of value facts. To put things metaphorically,
hard positivism and soft positivism hold that there could still be law if God
destroyed all value facts.
Ronald Dworkin is the foremost contemporary advocate of an antipositivist posi-
tion. According to Dworkin, a legal proposition is true in a given legal system if it is
entailed by the set of principles that best justify the practices of the legal system.⁶
Since the notion of justification on which Dworkin relies is a normative notion, a
consequence of Dworkin’s view is that the content of the law depends on value facts.
Understanding and resolving the debate between positivists and antipositivists
requires understanding the nature of the relevant determination relation—the
relation between determinants of legal content and legal content. The debate, as
noted, concerns whether law practices are the sole determinants of legal content.
It is difficult to see how one can systematically address the question of whether
A facts are the sole determinants of B facts without understanding what kind of
determination is at stake. But the positivist/antipositivist debate has so far been
conducted with almost no attention to this crucial issue.
A preliminary point is that the determination relation with which we are con-
cerned is primarily a metaphysical, or constitutive, one, and only secondarily an
epistemic one: the law-determining practices make the content of the law what it is.
To put it another way, facts about the content of the law (“legal-content facts”)
obtain in virtue of the law-determining practices. It is only because of this underlying
metaphysical relation that we ascertain what the law is by consulting those practices.
A second preliminary point, which should be uncontroversial, is that no legal-
content facts are metaphysically basic or ultimate facts about the universe, facts for
which there is nothing to say about what makes them the case. Legal-content facts,
like facts about the meaning of words or facts about international exchange rates
³ J. Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain 210 (1994). Raz also puts the point epistemically: the
content of the law “can be identified by reference to social facts alone, without resort to any evaluative
argument.” Id. at 211.
⁴ See, e.g., Raz, supra note 3, at ch. 10; J. Raz, The Authority of Law ch. 3 (1979).
⁵ See, e.g., J. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, 11 J. Legal Stud. 139 (1982); H. L. A. Hart,
Postscript, in The Concept of Law (2d ed., 1997). ⁶ See R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986).
How Facts Make Law 227
(for example that, at a particular time, a U.K. pound is worth 1.45 U.S. dollars),
hold in virtue of more basic facts. The important implication for present purposes
is that the full story of how the determinants of legal content make the law what it
is cannot take any legal content as given. It will not be adequate, for example, to
hold that law practices plus some very basic legal-content facts (for example, legal
propositions concerning the relevance of law practices to the content of the law)
together make the law what it is, for such an account fails to explain what it is in
virtue of which the very basic legal-content facts obtain.
Descriptive facts about what people said and did (and thought) in the past are
among the more basic facts that determine the content of the law. I claim that the
content of the law depends not just on descriptive facts but on value facts as well.
Given the plausible assumption that fundamental⁷ value facts are necessary rather
than contingent, there is, however, a difficulty about expressing my claim in terms
of counterfactual theses or theses about metaphysical determination. Even if the
value facts are relevant to the content of the law, it is still true that the content of
the law could not be different from what it is without the descriptive facts being
different (since it is impossible for the value facts, being necessary, to be different
from what they are). Necessary truths cannot be a non-redundant element of a
supervenience base. Hence both positivists and antipositivists can agree that
descriptive facts alone metaphysically determine the content of the law.⁸
In order to express the sense in which the content of the law is claimed to
depend on value facts, we therefore need to employ a notion different from and
richer than metaphysical determination. We can say that the full metaphysical
explanation of the content of the law (of why certain legal propositions are true)
must appeal to value facts. I earlier put the point metaphorically by saying that if
God destroyed the value facts, the law would have no content. The epistemic
corollary is that working out what the law is will require reasoning about value.
As we will see, a full account of what it is in virtue of which legal-content facts
obtain has to do more than describe the more basic facts that are the metaphysical
determinants of legal content. The relevant determination relation is not bare
⁷ The point of the qualification “fundamental” is to distinguish basic or pure value facts—that,
say, harm is a relevant moral consideration—from applied or mixed value facts—that returning the
gun to John tomorrow would be wrong. The fundamental value facts are plausibly metaphysically
necessary, while the applied value facts obviously depend on contingent descriptive facts as well as on
fundamental value facts. This qualification does not affect the point in the text, since the contingent
facts are encompassed in the supervenience base of descriptive facts. That is, if the fundamental value
facts supervene on the descriptive facts, the applied value facts will do so as well.
⁸ The term “metaphysical determination” is typically used in a way that implies nothing about the
order of explanation or about relative ontological basicness. In this sense, that the A facts metaphys-
ically determine the B facts does not imply that the B facts obtain in virtue of the obtaining of the A
facts. Positivists and antipositivists can agree not only that descriptive facts alone metaphysically
determine the content of the law but also that the obtaining of the relevant descriptive facts is part of
the explanation of the obtaining of legal-content facts. In this paper, we will be concerned only with
cases in which the putative determinants are more basic than and part of the explanation of the deter-
mined facts. For convenience, I will therefore say that the A facts metaphysically determine the B facts
only when the B facts obtain at least in part in virtue of the obtaining of the A facts.
228 Mark Greenberg
metaphysical determination. (As we have just seen, if that were the relevant relation,
there would be no debate between the positivists and the antipositivists. Positivists
would win the debate trivially, since the descriptive facts alone fix the content of the
law.) I argue for a particular understanding of the metaphysical relation (between
the determinants and the legal content that they determine), which I call rational
determination. Rational determination, in contrast to bare metaphysical determin-
ation, is necessarily reason-based (in a sense that I elaborate in Section II.B).
A quick way to grasp the basic idea is to consider the case of esthetic facts.
Descriptive facts metaphysically determine esthetic facts. A painting is elegant in
virtue of facts about the distribution of color over the surface (and the like). But
arguably there need not be reasons that explain why the relevant descriptive facts
make the painting elegant. We may be able to discover which descriptive facts make
paintings elegant (and even the underlying psychological mechanisms), but even if
we do, those facts need not provide substantive aesthetic reasons why the painting
is elegant (as opposed to causal explanations of our reactions). On this view, it may
just be a brute fact that a certain configuration of paint on a surface constitutes or
realizes a painting with certain esthetic properties. (As noted below, facts about
humor provide an even clearer example.) In contrast, if it is not in principle intelli-
gible why the determinants of legal content—the relevant descriptive facts—make
the law have certain content, then it does not have that content.
Rational determination is an interesting and unusual metaphysical relation
because it involves the notion of a reason, which may well be best understood as
an epistemic notion. If so, we have an epistemic notion playing a role in a meta-
physical relation. (Donald Davidson’s view of the relation between the determi-
nants of mental content and mental content is plausibly another example of this
general phenomenon.)⁹ For this reason, I believe that the rational-determination
relation is of independent philosophical interest.
My main goal in this chapter, however, is to show that, given the nature of the
relevant kind of determination, law practices—understood as descriptive facts
about what people have said and done—cannot themselves determine the content
of the law. Value facts are needed to determine the legal relevance of different
aspects of law practices. I therefore defend an antipositivist position, one that is
roughly in the neighborhood of Dworkin’s, on the basis of very general philosoph-
ical considerations unlike those on which Dworkin himself relies.¹⁰
We have two domains of facts: a higher-level legal domain and a lower-level
descriptive domain. It is, I claim, a general truth that a domain of descriptive facts can
rationally determine facts in a dependent, higher-level domain only in combination
with truths about which aspects of the descriptive, lower-level facts are relevant to the
higher-level domain and what their relevance is. Without the standards provided by
such truths, it is indeterminate which candidate facts in the higher-level domain
are most supported by the lower-level facts. There is a further question about the
source or nature of the needed truths (about the relevance of the descriptive facts to
the higher-level domain). In the legal case, these truths are, I will suggest, truths about
value.
The basic argument is general enough to apply to any realm in which a body of
descriptive facts is supposed to make it the case by rational determination that facts
in a certain domain obtain. For example, if the relation between social practices,
understood purely descriptively, and social rules is rational determination, the
argument implies that social practices cannot themselves determine the content of
social rules. (At that point, we reach the further question of the source of the
truths needed in the case of social rules; the answer may differ from that in the
legal case.) Hence the argument is of interest well beyond the philosophy of law.
In this chapter, I will largely confine the discussion to the legal case.
In Section II, I clarify the premises of the argument and explain that they
should not be controversial. In Section III, I examine why there is a problem of
how legal content is determined. The content of the law is not simply the mean-
ings of the words (and the contents of the mental states) that are uttered in the
course of law practices. Something must determine which elements of law prac-
tices are relevant and how they combine to determine the content of the law. Next,
in Section IV, I argue that law practices themselves cannot determine how they
contribute to the content of the law. In Section V, I consider and respond to three
related objections. Finally, in Section VI, I examine what the argument has estab-
lished about the relation between law and value.¹¹
In this section, I set out the two premises of the argument and make a number of
clarifications. The second premise will require a great deal more discussion than the
first. I take both premises to be relatively uncontroversial in many contemporary legal
systems, including those of, for example, the United States and the United Kingdom.
In general, then, law practices consist of ordinary empirical facts about what
people thought, said, and did in various circumstances.¹⁵ For example, law prac-
tices potentially include the facts that, in a particular historical context, a legisla-
tive committee issued a certain report, various speeches were made in a legislative
debate, a bill that would have repealed a statute failed to pass, a concurring judge
issued a certain opinion, and an executive official announced a particular view of a
statute.¹⁶ Once I have clarified the claim that law practices partially determine the
content of the law, I will be able to say something more precise about what counts
as a law practice.
When L says that law practices determine (in part) the content of the law, what
sense of “determine” is involved? As noted above, a preliminary point is that L’s
claim is constitutive or metaphysical, not epistemic. That is, it is not a claim that
we use law practices to ascertain what the content of the law is, but that such prac-
tices make it the case that the content of the law is what it is.
I maintain that the relevant kind of determination is not bare metaphysical
determination but what we can call rational determination. The A facts rationally
determine the B facts just in case the A facts metaphysically determine the B facts
and the obtaining of the A facts makes intelligible or rationally explains the
B facts’ obtaining. Thus, L is the conjunction of two doctrines, a metaphysical-
determination doctrine and a rational-relation doctrine. Let me elaborate.
I will make the (uncontroversial, I hope) assumption that there are facts that
(1) are ontologically more basic than facts about legal content and (2) metaphysically
determine that the content of the law is what it is. The metaphysical-determination
doctrine is that these more basic facts that determine the content of the law non-
redundantly include law practices.
Metaphysical determination can be brute. If the A facts are more basic facts that
metaphysically determine the B facts, there is a sense in which the A facts explain
the B facts, for the A facts are more basic facts, the obtaining of which entails that
the B facts obtain. But there need be no explanation of why the obtaining of par-
ticular A facts has the consequence that it does for the B facts. To dramatize the
point, even a perfectly rational being may not be able to see why it is that particu-
lar A facts make particular B facts obtain.
The metaphysical-determination doctrine is not enough to capture our
ordinary understanding (which L attempts to articulate) of the nature of the
¹⁵ Hypothetical decisions arguably play a significant role in determining the content of the law,
but for purposes of this paper they will largely be ignored. Susan Hurley characterizes hypothetical
decisions as hypothetical cases that have a settled resolution. See S. L. Hurley, Coherence, Hypothetical
Cases, and Precedent, 10 Oxford J. Legal Stud. 221 (1990). Another possibility is to include any
hypothetical case that has a determinate right answer, even if there is disagreement on its resolution.
There would be disagreement about which hypothetical cases had determinate right answers and
therefore about which were determinants of legal content.
¹⁶ Nothing turns on how we individuate practices, at least in the first instance. E.g. a legislative
committee’s issuance of a report could be considered part of the circumstances in which a majority of
the legislature voted for a statute or could be considered a separate practice. Once the roles of differ-
ent elements of law practices are determined, there may be a basis for individuation.
232 Mark Greenberg
determination relation between the law practices and the content of the law. We
also need the rational-relation doctrine, which holds that the relation between the
determinants of legal content and legal content is reason-based. In the relevant
sense, a reason is a consideration that makes the relevant explanandum intelli-
gible.¹⁷ Here is one way to put the point. There are indefinitely many possible
mappings, from complete sets of law practices to legal content (to complete sets of
legal propositions). As far as the metaphysical-determination doctrine goes, it
could simply be arbitrary which mapping is the legally correct one. In other
words, the connection between a difference in the practices and a consequent dif-
ference in the content of the law could be brute. For example, it is consistent with
the truth of the metaphysical-determination doctrine that, say, the deletion of one
seemingly unimportant word in one subclause of one minor administrative regu-
lation would result in the elimination of all legal content in the United States—in
there being no true legal propositions in the U.S. legal system (though there is no
explanation of why it would do so). By contrast, according to the rational-relation
doctrine, the correct mapping must be such that there are reasons why law practices
have the consequences they do for the content of the law.
To put it metaphorically, the relation between the law practices and the content
of the law must be transparent.¹⁸ (For the relation to be opaque would be for it to
be the case that any change in law practices could have, so far as we could tell, any
effect on the content of the law. The effects on the content of the law could be
unfathomable and unpredictable, even if fully determinate.)
It bears emphasis that what must be rationally intelligible is not the content of
the law but the relation between, on the one hand, determinants of legal content
and, on the other, legal content. L holds not that the content of the law must be
rational or reasonable but that it must be intelligible that the determinants of legal
content make the content of the law what it is. For example, there must be a rea-
son that deleting a particular word from a statutory text would have the impact on
the law that it would in fact have.¹⁹
¹⁷ I will not attempt to spell out the relevant notion of a reason more fully here. One possibility is
that the best way to do so is in terms of idealized human reasoning ability. For example, the idea
might be that practices yield a legal proposition if and only if an ideal reasoner would see that they do.
The notion of a reason would hence be an epistemic notion. In that case, L would imply that the
metaphysics of law involves an epistemic notion; that is, what the law is would depend in part on
what an ideal human reasoner would find intelligible.
¹⁸ A useful comparison can be made to certain well-known positions in the philosophy of mind.
Donald Davidson’s radical interpretation approach to mental and linguistic content presupposes that
behavior determines the contents of mental states and the meaning of linguistic expressions in a way
that must be intelligible or transparent. D. Davidson, Radical Interpretation, in Inquiries into
Truth and Interpretation (1984); and D. Davidson, Belief and the Basis of Meaning, in Inquiries
into Truth and Interpretation (1984). Similarly, Saul Kripke’s “Kripkenstein” discussion presup-
poses that we must be able to “read off ” the contents of mental states from the determinants of con-
tent. S. Kripke, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language 24, 29 (1982). See infra note 25.
¹⁹ At this point in the text, I have deleted a paragraph that appeared in the original publication of
this chapter. I have also made a few changes in the next few paragraphs.
How Facts Make Law 233
²⁰ At a later stage of analysis, we might find that there are restrictions on what kind of reasons the
determinants of legal content must provide. For example, it might turn out that legal systems have
functions and that in order for a legal system to perform its functions properly, the determinants of
legal content must provide reasons for action. See infra the last paragraph of Section VI.A. L does not
presuppose any such restrictions, however.
234 Mark Greenberg
be the determinants of legal content, not part of the legal content that is to be
determined.
Suppose an objector maintained that the law practices that determine legal
content are themselves laden with legal content. It is certainly natural to use the
term “law practices” in this way. After all, the fact that the legislature passed a bill
is legal-content laden: it presupposes legal-content facts about what counts as a
legislature and a bill. Since legal-content facts are not basic, however, there must
be non-legal-content facts that constitute the legal-content-laden practices. At
this point, we will have to appeal to descriptive facts about what people thought,
said, and did—the facts that I am calling “law practices.” For example, the fact
that a legislature did such and such must hold in virtue of complex descriptive
facts about people’s behavior and perhaps also value facts. (If, in order to account
for legal-content-laden practices, we have to appeal not merely to descriptive facts
but also to value facts, so much the worse for the positivist thesis that the content
of the law depends only on descriptive facts.) The convenience of talking as if law
practices consisted in legal-content-laden facts about the behavior of legislatures,
courts, and so on should not obscure the fact that there must be more basic facts in
virtue of which the legal-content facts obtain. To build legal-content facts into law
practices would beg the question at the heart of this paper—the question of the
necessary conditions for law practices to determine the content of the law. (For
ease of exposition, I will continue to use legal-content-laden characterizations of
the law practices, but the law practices should, strictly speaking, be understood to
be the underlying descriptive facts in virtue of which the relevant legal-content
facts obtain.)
It is uncontroversial that certain kinds of facts are among the supervenience base
for legal content: roughly speaking, facts about what constitutional assemblies,
legislatures, courts, and administrative agencies did in the past. Of course, as just
noted, such characterizations are legal-content laden and are therefore shorthand
for non-legal-content characterizations of the law practices. (I do not mean, of
course, that it is uncontroversial exactly which facts of these kinds are relevant; I’ll
return to this point shortly.) There are at least two kinds of controversy, however,
about the determinants of legal content.
First, it is controversial whether value facts are among the determinants of
content. The reason for the second exclusion—the exclusion of value facts—is
that this paper tries to argue from the uncontroversial claim that law practices are
determinants of the content of the law to the conclusion that value facts must play
a role in determining the content of the law. If law practices were taken to be
value-laden, it would no longer be uncontroversial that they are determinants of
legal content. (On the other hand, even those theorists who think that value facts
are needed to determine the content of the law can accept that descriptive facts
also play a role.) Moreover, unless we separate the descriptive facts from the value
facts, we cannot evaluate whether the descriptive facts can themselves determine
the content of the law. In sum, by understanding law practices to exclude value
236 Mark Greenberg
facts, I ensure that L is uncontroversial and I prepare the way for my argument
that descriptive facts alone cannot determine the content of the law.
The second kind of controversy about the determinants of legal content is con-
troversy over precisely which descriptive facts are determinants. I have mentioned
some paradigmatic determinants of legal content. But there are other kinds of
descriptive facts—for example, facts about customs, about people’s moral beliefs,
about political history, and about law practices in other countries—that are
arguably among the determinants of legal content. Also, somewhat differently, it
is controversial which facts about judicial, legislative, or executive behavior are rel-
evant. There can be debate, for example, about the relevance of legislative history,
intentions of legislators and of drafters of statutes, legislative findings, judicial
obiter dicta, and executive interpretations of statutes. I propose to deal with this
second kind of controversy by leaving our understanding of law practices open
and non-restrictive.
There are several reasons for this approach. First, my argument is that prac-
tices, understood as composed of descriptive facts, cannot themselves determine
the content of the law. If I begin with a restrictive understanding of practices, my
argument will be open to the reply that I failed to include some of the relevant
facts. For this reason, I want to be liberal about which descriptive facts are part of
law practices. Secondly, my argument will not depend on exactly which descrip-
tive facts make up law practices. Rather, I will make a general argument that
descriptive facts—in particular, facts about what people have done and said and
thought—cannot by themselves determine the content of the law. Therefore it
will not matter precisely which such facts are included in law practices. Thirdly,
my view is ultimately that the question of which facts are part of law practices—
like the question of how different aspects of law practices contribute to the con-
tent of the law—is dependent on value facts. (Indeed, I will often treat the two
questions together as different aspects of the general question of the way in
which law practices determine the content of the law.) As we will see, that we
cannot in an uncontroversial way specify which are law practices and which are
not is one consideration in support of my argument for the necessary role of
value. All we need to begin with is some rough idea of law practices, which can
be overinclusive.
In sum, let law practices include, in addition to constitutions, statutes, and
judicial and administrative decisions, any other non-legal-content descriptive
facts that turn out to play a role in determining the content of the law.²³ Which
facts these are and what role they play are controversial, so we can begin with a
rough and inclusive understanding of law practices. One aspect of figuring out
how law practices contribute to the content of the law will be figuring out which
²³ This proviso does not make L the tautological claim that the determinants of legal content
determine legal content. L says that constitutions, statutes, judicial decisions, and so on are (non-
redundantly) among the determinants of content.
How Facts Make Law 237
facts make a contribution and which do not. But there is no reason to expect a
clean line between law practices and other facts.²⁴
The exclusion of value facts should not be taken to suggest that law practices are
to be understood in solely physical or behavioral terms. To the contrary, as I explain
in the next section, I take for granted the mental and linguistic contents involved
in law practices. In other words, law practices include the facts about what the
actors believe, intend, and so on and about what their words mean.
²⁴ One natural understanding of “law practices” is more restrictive than the way I use the term.
According to this understanding, law practices are limited to (facts about) what legal institutions and
officials do in their official capacities. If we used the term “law practices” in this natural way, we would
need, in addition to the category of law practices, a category of other descriptive facts that play a role
in determining the content of the law.
238 Mark Greenberg
that the law practices do not provide reasons supporting certain legal propositions
over others, the law is indeterminate.)
I will not attempt to defend the rational-relation doctrine fully here but will
mention a few considerations. Suppose the A facts metaphysically determine
the B facts, but the relation between the A facts and the B facts is opaque. In that
case, how could we know about the B facts? One possibility is that we have
access to the B facts independently of our knowledge of the A facts. An example
might be the relation between the microphysical facts about someone’s brain
and the facts about that person’s conscious experience. Suppose that the micro-
physical facts metaphysically determine the facts about the person’s conscious
experience but that the relation is opaque. The opaqueness of the relation does
not affect the person’s ability to know the facts about his conscious experience,
because we do not in general learn about our conscious experience by working it
out from the microphysical facts. (Moreover, since we have independent know-
ledge of conscious experience, we might be able to discover correlations between
microphysical facts and conscious experience even if those correlations were not
intelligible even in principle.) To take a different kind of example, the micro-
physical facts may metaphysically determine the facts about the weather, and
the relation may be opaque, but again, we do not learn about the weather by
working it out from the microphysical facts.
A second possibility is that we do work out the B facts from the A facts but
that we have a nonrational, perhaps hardwired, capacity to do so. For example,
it is plausible that the facts about what was said and done (on a particular occa-
sion, say) determine whether what was said and done was funny (and to what
degree and in what way). And we do work out whether an incident was funny
from the facts about what was done and said. It is plausible, however, that the
relation between what was said and done and its funniness is not necessarily
transparent to all rational creatures; our ability to know what is funny may
depend on species-specific tendencies; that is, there may not be reasons that
make the humor facts intelligible; it may just be a brute fact that humans find
certain things funny.²⁵
Law seems different from both of these kinds of cases. First, our only access to
the content of the law is through law practices. It is not as if we can find out what
the law is directly or through some other route. And the whole enterprise of law-
making is premised on the assumption that the behavior of legislators, judges, and
²⁵ Compare the issue of how facts about our use of words determine their meaning. Natural
languages are a biological creation. Although many philosophers have thought differently (see
supra note 18), we cannot take for granted that the correct mapping from the use of words to their
meaning will be based on reasons. How, it may be objected, would we then be able to work out
from their use of words what others mean? The answer may simply be that we have a species-
specific, hardwired mechanism that rules out many incorrect mappings that are not ruled out by
reasons. In that case, an intelligent creature without that mechanism would not be able to work out
what words mean.
How Facts Make Law 239
other law-makers will have understandable and predictable consequences for the
content of the law.
Secondly, we are able to work out what the law is and predict the effect on the
law of changes in law practices through reasons, not through some non-rational
human tendency to have correct law reactions to law practices.
When lawyers, judges, and law professors work out what the law is, they give
reasons for their conclusions. Indeed, if we find that we cannot articulate reasons
that justify a provisional judgment about what the law is in light of law practices,
we reject the judgment. By contrast, it is notoriously difficult to explain why
something is or is not funny, and we do not generally hold our judgments about
humor responsible to our ability to articulate reasons for them. A related point is
that we believe that we could teach any intelligent creature that is sensitive to reasons
how to work out what the law is.
It might be objected that although the epistemology of law is reason-based, the
metaphysics might not be. It is difficult to see how such an objection could be
developed. For present purposes, I will simply point out that when legal practi-
tioners give reasons for their conclusions about what the law is, they believe that
they are not merely citing evidence that is contingently connected to the content
of the law; rather, they believe that they are giving the reasons that make the law
what it is. The point is not that lawyers believe themselves to be infallible. Rather,
they believe that when they get things right, the reasons they discover are not
merely reasons for believing that the content of the law is a particular way, but the
reasons that make the content of the law what it is. Although they would never put
it this way, lawyers take for granted that the epistemology of law tracks its meta-
physics. And the epistemology of law is plainly reason-based.
Legal theorists generally take for granted some version of the claim that the
relation between law practices and the content of the law is reason-based. An
example is H.L.A. Hart’s argument that the vagueness and open texture of legal
language have the consequence that the law is indeterminate.²⁶ If bare metaphysical
determination were all that was at issue—if it were not the case that the relation
between practice and content were necessarily intelligible—the vagueness of
language would in no way support the claim that law was indeterminate. Similarly,
when legal realists or Critical Legal Studies theorists argue that the existence of
conflicting pronouncements or doctrines in law practices results in underdetermin-
ation of the law, their arguments would be beside the point if what was at stake
were not rational determination.²⁷
In general, the large body of legal theory that has explored the question of
whether law practices are capable of rendering the law determinate (and if so, how
determinate) presupposes that law practices determine the content of the law in a
reason-based way. If the relation between law practices and the content of the law
could be opaque, any set of law practices would be capable, as far as we would be
able to judge, of determining any set of legal propositions. (As long as there are as
many possible sets of law practices as there are possible sets of legal propositions,
there is no barrier to the content of the law’s being fixed by the practices, and we
would have no warrant to rely on our assessment of other putative prerequisites
for practices to determine the content of the law.) In sum, the doctrine that law
practices rationally determine the content of the law captures a basic conviction
about the law that is shared by law-makers, lawyers, and legal theorists and is
supported by the epistemology of law.
Why does it matter to my argument that the relation between law practices and
the content of the law is reason-based? This paper explores the necessary conditions
for law practices’ making the content of the law what it is. The central argument is
that descriptive facts cannot determine their own rational significance—what reasons
they provide. The argument therefore depends on the claim that the descriptive
facts determine the content of the law in a reason-based way. It turns out that value
facts are needed to make it intelligible that law practices support certain legal
propositions over others.²⁸
²⁸ Suppose that the relation between law practices and the content of the law were necessarily
intelligible only in a way that depends on some human-specific tendency. As long as practices must
provide considerations that are intelligible (even if only to humans), a version of my argument should
still go through.
How Facts Make Law 241
²⁹ There is no practical problem with taking these matters for granted and proceeding without
a solution to basic problems concerning how linguistic and mental content are possible. These
problems do not concern difficulties we encounter in practice in attributing linguistic and mental
content; the difficulty is in saying what it is in virtue of which a linguistic expression or mental
state has its content.
242 Mark Greenberg
determine legal content; or one might think that the only problem was how to
combine or amalgamate a large number of rules or propositions.
Although it would beg the question to take legal propositions for granted, we
do have the propositions that are the content of the utterances and mental states of
participants in law practices. What is wrong with the idea that those propositions
constitute legal content, so that law practices, once they are understood to include
facts about mental and linguistic content, automatically have legal content?
I will begin with the least serious problems—those concerning the attribution
of non-legal content. Although we are normally able to attribute attitudes to peo-
ple based on what they say and do and to attribute standard meanings to a large
number of sentences of a language we speak, there are difficulties in attributing
non-legal content to aspects of a putative law practice. Here are a few examples.
First, when I say that we can take for granted mental and linguistic content,
I mean that we need not ignore the mental and linguistic content that is available.
We should not, however, assume that all of the contents of the mental states of all
of the people involved in law practices are available. That would obviously be
false. In general, what is available in the standard reports of law practices is not
sufficient to attribute much in the way of attitudes to the people who actually per-
formed the actions and made the utterances; the fact that a particular legislator
voted for a bill or a certain judge signed an opinion is not in general sufficient to
attribute beliefs, intentions, hopes, and so on, to her. Moreover, the law restricts
what evidence of the intentions and beliefs of legislators and judges is acceptable to
determine the content of the law. Even when the intentions of a legislator or judge
are relevant to the content of the law, it is not the case that, say, her private letters
or diary may be a source of that intention. Something must determine which evi-
dence of legally relevant attitudes is legally acceptable.
Secondly, though many sentences of natural languages have standard meanings,
it is notorious that this is not true of some of the sentences uttered by those
engaged in making law practices. The point here is not that in legal contexts lin-
guistic expressions often have specialized meanings that are not straightforwardly
connected to their ordinary meanings. Rather, some of the contorted sentences in
the law books have no standard meaning in a natural language.
Thirdly, even when sentences taken alone have standard meanings, collections
of those sentences may fail to do so. In other words, the property of having a stand-
ard meaning (on a notion of standard meaning appropriate for present purposes)
is not closed under conjunction (for example, because context may introduce
ambiguity into an otherwise unambiguous sentence).
Setting aside these problems with ascertaining non-legal content, we can turn
to the more important question of the bearing of non-legal content on legal con-
tent. One problem is that the non-legal content of some elements of law practices
has, or arguably has, little or nothing to do with the legal content determined by
those practices. Consider sentences in statutory preambles, sentences in presiden-
tial speeches at bill-signing ceremonies, and sentences in judicial opinions that are
How Facts Make Law 243
not necessary to the resolution of the issue before the court. Another example is
the actual but unexpressed hopes of the members of the legislature as to how the
courts would interpret a statute. Countless sentences are written and spoken at
different stages of law-practice making by people with myriad attitudes.³⁰
Something must determine which sentences’ and attitudes’ contents are relevant.
Another problem is that the contribution of a particular law practice to the
content of the law may not be the meaning of any text or the content of any per-
son’s mental state. The actual attitudes of appellate judges may be irrelevant;
instead the relevant question may be what a hypothetical reasonable person would
have intended by the words uttered by the judges or what would be the best, or the
narrowest, explanation of the result reached. Another possibility is that aspects of
law practices that contribute to non-legal content in one way contribute to legal
content in an entirely different way; facts about what was said and done may have
peculiarly legal significance. An obvious example is that common words such as
“malice” and “fault” are often used in legal discourse in a technical sense. To take a
more subtle instance, when a panel of several judges is badly split, it can be a com-
plex and tricky matter to ascertain the relevance to legal content of the meanings
of the words of the different judicial opinions.
Similarly, facts about the circumstances in which sayings and doings occurred
that have little to do with the non-legal content of the people’s attitudes and words
may significantly affect the content of the law. For example, in a judicial decision,
the fact that an issue is not in controversy arguably prevents the court’s statements
on that issue from making any contribution to the content of the law.
Even when the content of sentences and mental states is relevant to the content
of the law, there can be no mechanical derivation of the content of the law. For
example, how are conflicting contents to be combined? In general, there remains
the problem of how the non-legal contents associated with different law practices
interact with each other (and with other relevant aspects of law practices) to deter-
mine the content of the law.
We have surveyed a number of reasons why non-legal content—the meanings of
sentences and contents of mental states—does not simply constitute legal content.
But this way of thinking about the problem will have an artificial quality for those
familiar with legal reasoning. The idea that the non-legal content of law practices
constitutes their legal content presupposes roughly the following picture. Associated
with each law practice is a text (and perhaps some mental states). Once we have the
meanings of the texts and the contents of the mental states, each law practice will be
associated with a proposition or set of propositions. Ascertaining the law on a
³⁰ In the case of a judicial decision, for example, the possibly relevant sentences include sentences
uttered by the parties to the controversy, by lawyers, and by judges to lawyers and other judges. They
include sentences written by judges in orders and judicial opinions. Judicial opinions alone include a
large number and variety of sentences: they state facts, give reasons, summarize, make general claims
about the content of the law, state holdings; moreover, there are concurring and dissenting as well as
majority opinions.
244 Mark Greenberg
particular issue is just a matter of looking up the propositions that are applicable to
the issue. Even if this picture were accurate, we have discussed a number of reasons
why non-legal content would not automatically yield legal content. But the problem
is worse than these reasons would indicate. As I will now suggest, the whole picture
is wrongheaded. Law practices do not determine the content of the law by con-
tributing propositions which then get amalgamated.
Here is the real problem of legal content. There are many different law practices
with many different aspects or elements. There is an initial question of which facts
are parts of law practices and which are not. Are preambles of bills, legislative
findings, legislative committee reports, dissenting opinions, unpublished judicial
decisions, customs, the Federalist Papers, and so on to be included in law practices?
In my view, this question is really just part of a second question: Which aspects
of, for example, judicial or legislative practices are relevant to the content of the
law? Just to suggest the dimensions of the problem, here are some candidates for
the relevant elements or aspects of practices. With respect to a judicial decision: the
facts of the case, the judgment rendered, the words used by the court in the
majority opinion, the reasons given for the outcome, the judges’ beliefs, the judges’
identities, the level and jurisdiction of the court; with respect to a legislative action:
the words of the statute, the legislature’s actual intention (if there is such a thing),
the purposes that the words of the statute could reasonably be intended to imple-
ment, statements by the person who drafted the statute, speeches made during the
legislative debate preceding passage, the circumstances in which the legislature
acted, subsequent decisions not to repeal the statute.
Fourthly, once we know which elements of practices are relevant, the problem
of determining the content of the law is not simply a problem of adding or amal-
gamating the various relevant aspects of practices. One obvious point is that
some elements of practices are far more important than others, and elements of
practices matter in different ways. But more fundamentally, as anyone familiar
with legal reasoning knows, the content of the law is not determined by any kind
of summing procedure, however complicated. For example, judicial decisions,
constitutional provisions, and legislative history can affect what contribution
a statute makes. It is not that those practices contribute propositions that are
conjoined to a proposition contributed by the statute. The statute’s correct inter-
pretation may be determined by a potential conflict with a constitutional provision
or by the outcome of cases in which courts have interpreted the same or related
statutes.
To take a different kind of example, constitutional provisions, statutes, and
judicial decisions can have an impact on the contribution of judicial and adminis-
trative decisions to the content of the law by affecting our understanding of the
proper role of courts and administrative agencies. Or, differently, statutes can have
an impact on what judicial decisions mean by making clear what the legislature
cares about, thus affecting which differences between cases matter and conse-
quently whether past precedents control the present issue. A final example is that
How Facts Make Law 245
the principle that a series of cases stands for is not the conjunction of the proposi-
tions announced in each case.
It is safe to conclude that the law does not automatically acquire content
when actions, utterances, and sentences involved in law practices are attributed
content. It is a mistake even to think that the issue is how to convert non-legal
content into legal content. We need to reject the simplistic picture in which
each law practice contributes to the content of the law a discrete proposition (or
set of propositions), which is the result of converting the non-legal content of
sentences and mental states into legal content. The bearing of non-legal content
on the content of the law is not mechanical. Once we root out any idea of a
mechanical conversion of non-legal content to legal content, it is clear that
something must determine which aspects of law practices are relevant to the
content of the law and what role those relevant aspects play in contributing to
the content of the law.
content of the law unless the president signs them, and that precedents of higher
courts are binding on lower courts in the same jurisdiction.
The content of the law cannot itself determine which model is correct, however,
for the content of the law depends on which model is correct. If, for example,
statutes contributed to the law only the plain meaning of their words, the content of
the law would be different from what it would be if the legislators’ intentions made a
difference. Obviously, which legal propositions are true depends on which model is
correct. But as we have just seen, which model is correct depends in part on the legal
propositions. The content of the law and the correct model are thus interdependent.
This interdependence threatens to bring indeterminacy. Consider the law prac-
tices of a particular legal system at a particular time and ask what the content of
the law is. Suppose that if candidate model A were legally correct, a certain set of
legal propositions would be true, according to which model A would be correct.
And if candidate model B were correct, a different set of legal propositions would
be true, according to which model B would be correct. And so on. Without some
other standard, each mutually supporting pair of models and set of legal proposi-
tions is no more favored than any other pair.³²
Can law practices determine which model is correct? The prima facie problem
is that we cannot appeal to practices to determine which model is correct because
which model a set of practices supports itself depends on which model is correct.
But let us consider the matter in more depth. If practices are to determine which
model is correct, there are two possibilities.
First, a privileged foundational practice (or set of foundational practices) could
determine the role of other practices. This possibility encounters the problem of
how practices themselves can determine which practices are foundational. For
example, the fact that a judicial opinion states that only the rationale necessary to
the decision of a case is contributed to the content of the law cannot determine
that that is a correct account of the contribution of judicial decisions to the con-
tent of the law. Something must determine that the judicial opinion in question is
relevant and trumps other conflicting practices. A putatively foundational prac-
tice cannot non-question-beggingly provide the reason that it is foundational.
³² This note registers a rather technical qualification and can be skipped without losing the
main thread of the argument. A candidate model, given the law practices, may yield a set of legal
propositions that lends support to a different, inconsistent model. To the extent that this is the
case, we can say that the model is not in equilibrium (relative to the law practices). Models that are
in equilibrium (or are closer to it) are plausibly favored, other things being equal, over those that
are not (or are further from it). There is no reason to expect, however, that there will typically be only
one model that is closer to equilibrium than any other model. In fact, indefinitely many models are
guaranteed to be in perfect equilibrium (yet yield different sets of legal propositions). For example,
any model that includes a rule that practices (and thus the true legal propositions) have no bearing
on which model is correct is necessarily in perfect equilibrium. Without some independent stand-
ard for what models are eligible, there is no way to rule out such models. Hence the varying degree
to which different candidate models are in equilibrium does not ensure a unique correct model and
determinate legal content. See also the discussion of a coherentist solution in the text below.
248 Mark Greenberg
³³ See M. Greenberg & H. Litman, The Meaning of Original Meaning, 86 Geo L.J. 569, 614–617
(1998).
³⁴ See S. L. Hurley, Natural Reasons 26, 84–88 (1989). Hurley credits Ramsey’s and
Davidson’s uses of arguments with similar import. See, e.g. D. Davidson, The Structure and Content of
Truth, 87 J. Phil. 279, 317–320 (1990).
How Facts Make Law 249
from the practices because the standards are a prerequisite for interpreting the
practices.
It may be helpful to notice that the problem has a structure similar to that of
two famous philosophical puzzles: Nelson Goodman’s problem about green and
grue, and Saul Kripke’s problem about plus and quus.³⁵ In order for there to be
legal requirements, it must be possible for someone to make a mistake in attribut-
ing a legal requirement (if just any attribution of a legal requirement is correct, the
law requires that P and that not P and so does not require anything). One makes a
mistake when one attributes a legal requirement that is not the one the law prac-
tices yield when interpreted in accordance with the correct model. For any can-
didate legal requirement, however, there is always a non-standard or “bent” model
that yields that requirement. It is therefore open to an interpreter charged with a
mistake to claim that in attributing the legal requirement in question, she has not
made a mistake in applying one model but is applying a different model.
The proponent of the coherence solution will respond that law practices them-
selves support certain models. For example, in appealing to practices to decide
cases, courts have developed well-established ways of understanding the relevance
of those practices to legal content. The problem is that there will always be bent
models according to which the judicial decisions (and other practices) support the
bent models rather than the purportedly well-established ones. This kind of point
shows that there must be factors, not themselves derived from the practices, that
favor some models over others.
Here is an example.³⁶ Suppose that on February 1, 2005, a judge in a state court
in the United States must decide whether a woman has a federal constitutional
right not to be prevented from obtaining an abortion. Imagine that the judge
holds that the woman does not have such a right. It seems that the judge has mis-
read Roe v. Wade,³⁷ the seminal decision of the United States Supreme Court. The
judge claims, however, that according to the correct model of how judicial decisions
contribute to legal content, when constitutional rights of individuals are at stake
and strong considerations of justice support the claims of both sides, such deci-
sions should be understood as establishing a form of “checkerboard” solution.
According to such a solution, whether a person has the right in question depends
on whether the person is born on an odd- or even-numbered day.³⁸ Since Jane Roe
was born on an odd-numbered day (let us assume), Roe v. Wade’s contribution to
content is that only women born on odd-numbered days have a constitutional
right to an abortion.
³⁵ See N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast 72–81 (3d ed., 1973); S. Kripke,
Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language 7–32 (1982). These puzzles involve concepts that
seem bizarre and gerrymandered. One challenge is to determine what it is that rules such concepts
out (at least in particular contexts), for if they are not ruled out, unacceptable results follow.
³⁶ The example borrows from Dworkin’s discussion of a “checkerboard” solution to the abortion
controversy. See Dworkin, supra note 6, at 178–186. Dworkin cannot be held responsible, however,
for my example. ³⁷ Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
³⁸ See Dworkin, supra note 6, at 178–179.
250 Mark Greenberg
Before discussing the example, it must be emphasized that the point is not that
the judge’s position should be taken seriously; on the contrary, the example
depends on the fact that the judge’s position is plainly a non-starter. Since it is evi-
dent that the position cannot be taken seriously, there must be factors that rule out
models like the one in the example. The example makes the point that these fac-
tors must be independent of practices. Since the unacceptable positions that we
want to exclude purport to determine what practices mean, the factors that
exclude these positions cannot be based on practices. Moreover, there is no way to
rule out such positions on a purely logical level, since, as will become evident, it is
easy to construct self-supporting, logically consistent systems of such positions.
The claim is, then, that our unwillingness to take the judge’s position seriously
suggests that we must be depending on tacit assumptions independent of law
practices in determining which models are acceptable. Let us look at the example
to see why practices themselves cannot exclude the judge’s model.
The first objection to the judge’s position may be that the Supreme Court in
Roe v. Wade said nothing about the abortion right’s depending on birth dates. The
judge replies that according to the correct model, the reasons that judges give in
their opinions make no or little contribution to the content of the law. A second
objection may move to a different level: the practices of the legal system do not
support the judge’s model. Judicial decisions, for example, do not interpret the
contributions made by other decisions in such a checkerboard fashion, nor do
they ignore the reasons judges give. The judge, however, claims that according to
his model, judicial decisions have all along been using a bent model, according to
which the reasons judges give are significant until February 1, 2005, but not after-
wards. Similarly, the model specifies no checkerboard contributions to content
until that date, then requires them afterwards. All of the judicial decisions so far
are logically consistent with the hypothesis that they are using the bent model.
Obviously a third-level objection—that the practices do not support models that
give dates this sort of significance—can be met with the same sort of response.
In another version of the example, the judge might claim that according to
the correct model, in all cases involving the right to abortion, a Supreme Court
decision’s relevance to content ends, without further action by the Court, as soon
as a majority of the current Supreme Court believes that the decision was wrongly
decided. Since the judge believes that that is now the situation with regard to Roe
v. Wade, he claims that Roe v. Wade no longer has any bearing on the content of the
law. If it is objected that the judge’s position is not an accurate account of how
judicial decisions interpret past judicial decisions, the judge will claim that judi-
cial decisions have been following his model all along. Since (let us suppose) it
has never been the case before that a majority of the Supreme Court has disagreed
with a past Supreme Court decision on the right to abortion, the evidence of past
decisions supports the judge’s model, which treats only abortion rights cases
idiosyncratically, as strongly as a more conventional one.
How Facts Make Law 251
The point should be obvious by now: these sorts of unacceptable models are
unacceptable because there are standards independent of practices that determine
that some sorts of factors are irrelevant to the contributions made by practices to
legal content. The practices themselves cannot be the source of the standards for
which models are permissible.
In this section, I have argued that practices themselves cannot determine how
practices contribute to the content of the law. Although I will not discuss the point
here, it is worth noting that my argument is not limited to the law. For example, the
argument shows that without standards independent of the practices, no set of
practices can rationally determine rules. What rules a set of practices rationally
determines will depend on what aspects of the practices are relevant and how those
aspects are relevant. And the practices cannot themselves resolve those issues.
Similarly, my argument does not depend on the complexities of contemporary
legal systems. My point therefore holds even for extremely simple cases. Even if
there were only one law-maker who uttered only simple sentences, and even if it
were taken for granted that the law-maker’s practices were legally relevant, the pre-
cise relevance of those practices would still depend on factors independent of the
practices. For example, there would still be an issue of whether the relevant aspect
of the practices was the meaning of the words uttered, as opposed to, say, the law-
maker’s intentions or the narrowest rationale necessary to justify the outcome of
the law-maker’s decisions.
V. Objections
I want now to consider three closely related objections. First, it may be objected to
that in practice there is often no difficulty in knowing which aspects of a practice
are relevant or which facts provide reasons. Bent models are not serious candi-
dates. Secondly, it may be objected to that practitioners’ beliefs (or other attitudes)
about value questions, not value facts, solve the problem of determining how
practices contribute to the content of the law. Thirdly, it may be said that in limit-
ing law practices to descriptive facts, I have relied on too thin a conception of law
practices. Properly understood, law practices can themselves determine the con-
tent of the law.
I replied to a version of the first objection in discussing the example of the abor-
tion-rights decision, but I will make the point in more general terms here. As I
have emphasized, the question of the necessary conditions for law practices to
determine the content of the law is a metaphysical, not an epistemic, question.
The problems that I have raised concerning how law practices determine the con-
tent of the law are not practical problems that legal interpreters encounter in try-
ing to discover what the law requires. Hence it is no objection to my argument
that legal interpreters do not encounter such problems.
252 Mark Greenberg
I have argued that there is a gap between law practices and the content of the
law that can be bridged only by substantive factors independent of practices. If
legal practitioners have no difficulty in crossing this gap—for example, in elimin-
ating bent models from consideration—that must be because they take the neces-
sary factors for granted. With respect to the example of the abortion-rights
decision, I argued that practices themselves cannot rule out the judge’s bent
models. Therefore our unwillingness to take the judge’s position seriously is evid-
ence that we are relying on tacit assumptions about what models are acceptable.
The lack of difficulty in practice suggests not that substantive constraints are not
needed but that they are assumed.
This point leads naturally to the second objection, which holds that it is the
assumptions or beliefs of participants in the practice that solve the problem of
how practices determine the content of the law. For example, it might be that a
consensus or shared understanding among judges or legal officials determines the
relevance of practices to the content of the law. Beliefs about value, not value facts,
do the necessary work.
As an epistemic matter, of course, we rely on our beliefs about value to ascertain
what the law is. But that is exactly what we would expect if the content of the law
depended on value facts. After all, in working out the truth in any domain, we
must depend on our beliefs. That we do so in a given domain in no way suggests
that the truth in that domain depends on our beliefs. Notice, moreover, that if the
content of the law depended on beliefs about value, then in order to work out
what the law was, we would have to rely on our beliefs about our beliefs about
value. For example, we might ask not whether democratic values favor intention-
alist theories of statutory interpretation, but whether there is a consensus among
judges that democratic values do so.
The most important point is that facts about what participants believe (under-
stand, intend, and so on) could not do the necessary work because such facts are
just more descriptive facts in the same position as the rest of the law practices. As
with the facts about the behavior of law-makers, we can ask whether facts about
participants’ beliefs are relevant to the content of the law, and if so, in what way.
Since the content of the law is rationally determined, the answers to these ques-
tions must be provided by reasons. As I have argued, the law practices, including
facts about participants’ beliefs, cannot determine their own relevance.
More generally, the same kind of argument explains why the questions of value
on which the content of the law depends must be resolved by substantive stand-
ards rather than by value-neutral procedures. In general, there are procedural ways
to resolve value questions—flipping a coin and voting are examples. Such pro-
cedures are in the same position as other law practices, however. There have to be
reasons that determine that a given procedure is the relevant one and what the
significance of the procedure is to the content of the law.
The third objection claims that the additional substantive factors are part of law
practices themselves. I have already addressed the suggestion that the law prac-
tices, conceived as facts about behavior and mental states, determine their own
How Facts Make Law 253
A. Value Facts?
In order for practices to yield determinate legal requirements, it has to be the case
that there are truths about which models are better than others independently of
how much the models are supported by law practices. Since practices must ration-
ally determine the content of the law, truths about which models are better than
others cannot simply be brute; there have to be reasons that favor some models
over others.
We have seen that law practices cannot determine their own contribution to the
content of the law. By contrast, value facts are well suited to determining the rele-
vance of law practices, for value facts include facts about the relevance of descriptive
facts. For example, that democracy supports an intentionalist model of statutes is, if
true, a value fact. What about the relevance of the value facts themselves? At least in
the case of the all-things-considered truth about the relevant values, its relevance
is intelligible without further reasons. If the all-things-considered truth about the
relevant considerations supports a certain model of the law practices, there can be no
serious question of whether that truth is itself relevant, or in what way. The signifi-
cance for the law of the fact that a certain model is all-things-considered better than
others is simply the fact that that model is better than others.
It might be suggested that an appeal to conceptual truth offers a way to avoid
the conclusion that the content of the law depends on value facts. The idea would
be that the concept of law (or some other legal concept), rather than substantive
value facts, determines that some models are better than others. As noted above,
conceptual truth is the kind of consideration that could provide reasons of the
necessary sort. The question is whether conceptual truth does so in the case of law.
My response begins with two points about what notion of conceptual truth this
kind of suggestion can rely on. According to what we can call a superficialist notion,
conceptual truths are truths about the use of concept-words, truths that are tacitly
known by all competent users of those words or are settled by community con-
sensus about the use of the words. Given such a notion of conceptual truth, we
should reject the idea that there are conceptual truths that can do the necessary
work. Ronald Dworkin famously argued that disputes about the grounds of law are
substantive debates, not trivial quarrels over the use of words.³⁹ Positivists have
generally responded by denying that they hold the kind of view Dworkin was
attacking. Thus, both sides agree that questions about which models are better than
others are not merely verbal questions that can be settled by appeal to consensus
criteria for the use of words. And both sides are correct on this point.
When, for example, Justices of the Supreme Court debate whether legislative
history is relevant to the content of the law, the dispute cannot be settled by appeal
to agreed-on criteria for the use of words. A lawyer or judge who challenges
well-established models is not ipso facto mistaken. For example, a lawyer could
advance a novel theory according to which New Jersey statutes make no contribu-
tion to the content of the law (on the ground, say, that there is a constitutional
flaw in New Jersey’s legislative process). The claim would not be straightforwardly
wrong merely because it goes against the consensus model, though it is likely mis-
taken on substantive grounds.
Secondly, we have seen that the practices of participants in the legal system can-
not be the source of the standards that support some models over others. It follows
that if conceptual truth is to be the source of the standards, conceptual truth must
not be determined by the practices of participants in the legal system; it must
depend on factors independent of our law practices.
The consequence of these two points is that if conceptual truth is to provide
the needed standards, it would have to be conceptual truth of a kind that is not
determined by consensus about the use of words and is not determined by our
law practices. I am sympathetic to such a notion of conceptual truth. Given
such a notion, however, it is not clear that an appeal to conceptual truth is a way
of avoiding the need for substantive value facts. Instead, the conceptual truths
in question may include or depend on value facts, for example, facts about fair-
ness or democracy. At this point, the burden surely rests on a proponent of the
conceptual-truth suggestion to offer a position that avoids the two problems
that I have just described without collapsing into a dependence on substantive
value facts.
A different kind of appeal to conceptual truth is possible. It could be argued not
that there are conceptual truths about which models are better than others, but
that conceptual truth determines that such issues are determined by a specific
internal legal value. This appeal to conceptual truth does not attempt to avoid the
need for value facts; it attempts to explain those value facts as internal to the law.
I will turn now to the nature of legal value facts. It is worth noting, however, that
an appeal to conceptual truth as the source of internal value facts will encounter the
same challenge as the appeal to conceptual truth to avoid the need for value facts.
Such an appeal requires an account of conceptual truth according to which truths
about the concept of law are independent of our law practices yet also independ-
ent of genuine value facts.
I have argued that the content of the law depends on substantive value facts.
What is the nature of those value facts? The most straightforward possibility is
that, other things being equal,⁴⁰ models are better to the extent that they are
favored by the all-things-considered truth about the applicable considerations—
the Truth, for short. In other words, the legally correct standard or value is simply
the truth about value. On this view, there is no special legal standard or value. For
example, the bearing of legislative history on the content of the law depends on
⁴⁰ “Other things being equal” because practices also play a role in determining which models are
better than others. See infra Section VI.B.
256 Mark Greenberg
content. Therefore something other than law practices would have to determine
the internal value standard—to make it the case that this standard was the relevant
one for the law (or for the particular legal system). It is difficult to see what that
could be other than the relevant considerations—the Truth. If we appeal to the
Truth, however, we have returned to the first or second possibility.
Any account of internal value facts thus faces a challenge of steering between
the law practices on the one hand and the Truth on the other. I have already
described the way in which an attempt to ground internal legal facts in concep-
tual truth faces this challenge. But the challenge confronts any account of
internal value facts. For example, suppose a theorist appeals to the function of
law or legal systems to ground internal value facts. On the one hand, as we saw
with conceptual truth, if the law’s function is going to provide the value facts
necessary for practices to determine the content of the law, that function must
be determined by something independent of the law practices. On the other
hand, if the law’s function is determined by the all-things-considered truth
about the relevant factors, an appeal to function is not a way of avoiding an
appeal to genuine value facts. Until we have an account of internal value facts
that meets the challenge, it is difficult to evaluate the potential of an appeal to
internal value facts.
An internal-value view faces a more substantive challenge as well. Internal
value facts would have to have appropriate consequences for the nature of law.
In a normal or properly functioning legal system, the content of the law pro-
vides reasons for action of certain kinds for certain agents. Whether the content
of the law can provide such reasons may depend on the nature and source of the
legal value facts. For example, it is plausible that for a legal system to be func-
tioning properly, the content of the law must provide genuine reasons for action
for judges. An internal-value theorist must explain how legal content deter-
mined exclusively by law practices and internal value facts can provide genuine,
as opposed to merely internal, reasons for action. More generally, we can investi-
gate the nature of legal value facts by asking what role such facts must play in a
theory of law.
I will make two clarifications about the role of X and then consider the implica-
tions for the relation between law and value. The first point is that X only helps to
determine which models are correct. X’s favoring model A over model B is neither
necessary nor sufficient for A to win out over B. As we saw in Section IV, practices
play a role in determining which model is better. Hence the model that is best all
things considered may not be the same as the model that is ranked highest by X
alone. (For simplicity I sometimes omit this qualification.)
In Section IV we discussed the interdependence between models and legal con-
tent. We saw that if we hold law practices constant, different candidate models
yield different sets of legal propositions. Without X, each mutually supporting
pair of model and set of legal propositions is as favored as any other such pair, and
indeterminacy threatens. X’s independence makes it possible for the interdepend-
ence of model and legal content not to lead to global indeterminacy.
In particular, what bearing practices have on the legally correct model depends
on which model is most X-justified in advance of any particular practices. For X
constrains the candidate models of practices and thus makes it possible for prac-
tices to determine anything. Practices themselves have something to say about the
second-order question of how practices contribute to the content of the law. But X
helps to determine what practices have to say on that question. Roughly speaking,
the legally correct model is the one that is most X-justified after taking into account
practices in the way that it is most X-justified to take them into account.⁴² In
other words, the legally correct model is the one that is most X-justified, all things
considered.
The second point can be brought out with an objection. Suppose it is
objected that X need determine only what considerations are relevant to the
content of the law but need not go further and determine how conflicts between
relevant considerations are to be resolved. According to this suggestion, X
would eliminate some candidate models as unacceptable but would have noth-
ing to say between models that give weight only to relevant aspects of law prac-
tices. The objector grants my argument that without an independent standard
of relevance, practices could not determine which models were correct. The
objector points out, however, that once we have an independent standard of
relevance, practices themselves might be able to determine which models are
correct.
⁴² In many legal systems, the practices, when taken into account in the way that is most X-justified
in advance of the practices, will support a model that is not the most X-justified in advance of the
practices. And when taken into account in accordance with that model, the practices may support yet
a different model. The question therefore arises of how important it is for a model to be supported by
the practices (taken into account in accordance with that model). (In the terminology of supra note
32, the more that a model is supported by the practices, the more the model is in equilibrium.) Since
X is the virtue of models, X is what determines how important it is for a model to be supported by the
practices. This is why it is fair to say, as I do in the text, that the legally correct model is the one that is
most X-justified after taking into account the practices in the way that it is most X-justified to take
them into account.
How Facts Make Law 259
Here is a brief sketch of a reply to the objector. In order for there to be determin-
ate legal requirements, X must do more than determine what considerations are
relevant; X must favor some resolutions of conflicts between relevant considera-
tions over others. Otherwise, given the diversity of relevant considerations and the
complexity of factual variation, law practices will not yield much in the way of
determinate legal requirements. Inconsistent propositions of law (and inconsist-
ent models) will typically have some support from relevant aspects of law prac-
tices. Therefore, in order for there to be determinate legal requirements, X must
not only help to determine what considerations are relevant but must also help to
determine the relative importance of elements of law practices and how such
elements interact.
In fact there is a deeper problem with the objection. It assumes that there are
discrete issues of what considerations are relevant to the content of the law and
how the relevant considerations combine to determine the content of the law. It
may be convenient to separate the two kinds of issues for expository purposes, but
we should not be misled into thinking that they are resolved separately. It is not
the case that there is an initial, all-or-nothing determination of whether a type of
consideration is relevant and then an independent, further determination of the
relative importance of the relevant considerations. Rather, the reason that a con-
sideration is relevant determines how and under what circumstances it is relevant
and how much force it has relative to other considerations.
For example, legislative history’s relevance to the content of the law derives, let
us suppose, from its connection to the intentions of the democratically elected rep-
resentatives of the people. Thus, in order to determine how important legislative
history is relative to other factors, we need to ask exactly how it is related to the rele-
vant intentions and what the importance of those intentions is. The point is that
the contribution to content of some aspect of a law practice and how it interacts
with other relevant aspects depend on why the aspect is relevant. If this suggestion—
that relevance and relative importance are not independent questions—is right, then
in helping to determine the relevance of various considerations, X will necessarily
(be helping to) resolve conflicts between relevant considerations.
I have argued that there is a certain kind of connection between law and value. I
would like to conclude by saying something about the implications of this con-
nection. Just for the purpose of exploring these implications, I will assume that X
is morality. The point of this assumption is to make clear that even if morality were
the relevant value, the consequences for the relation between law and morality
would not be straightforward. As I will show, it would not follow that the content
of the law would necessarily be morally good or even that the moral goodness of a
candidate legal proposition would count in favor of the proposition’s being true.
First, although (by assumption) morality provides legally relevant reasons
independent of the content of the law, the legally correct model is not simply
whatever model is morally best (or most justified). “Morally best” here means
most supported or justified by moral considerations in advance of consideration of
260 Mark Greenberg
the practices of the legal system. The legally correct model need not be the morally
best one in this sense because, as we have seen, practices also have an impact on
which model is legally correct.
Secondly, morally good models do not guarantee morally good legal proposi-
tions. Even if the legally correct model was a highly morally justified one, the
content of the law might be very morally bad. A democratically elected and
unquestionably legitimate legislature could publicly and clearly promulgate
extremely unjust statutes, such as a statute ostensibly excluding a racial minority
from social welfare benefits. The judicial decisions may rely on highly morally
justified models, ones that, among other things, give great weight to such morally
relevant features of legislative actions as the clearly expressed intentions of the
elected legislators. The most justified model, all things considered, will be a
morally good one yet will yield morally bad legal content. In fact, in such a legal
system less justified models could yield morally better legal content than more
justified models. (In such cases, a judge might sometimes be morally obligated to
circumvent the law by relying on the less justified model.)⁴³
Although morally justified models do not guarantee morally good legal prop-
ositions, it might be suggested that part of what makes a model morally justified is
that it tends to yield morally good legal requirements.⁴⁴ For example, assume that,
other things being equal, a legal requirement is morally better the more it treats
people fairly. Some models will in general have a greater tendency to yield legal
requirements that treat people fairly. According to the suggestion under consider-
ation, that a model has such a tendency would be one factor supporting that
model.
Suppose that the suggestion were correct. According to one line of thought, it
follows that the content of the law would simply be whatever it would be morally
good for it to be (or more generally, whatever it would be most X-justified for it to
be). In that case the practices would be irrelevant. This line of thought might
therefore be taken to provide a reductio of my argument for the role of value in
determining the way in which practices contribute to the content of the law.
The line of thought is not sound, however. First, even if the tendency of a
model to yield morally good legal propositions counts in favor of that model, a
variety of other moral considerations favor models that make the content of the
⁴³ The relation between a judge’s moral obligations and morally justified models raises interesting
issues, but space does not permit discussion.
⁴⁴ At the extreme, for example, a model could hold that in some circumstances the goodness of a
candidate legal proposition tips the balance in favor of that legal proposition and against competing
candidates. (A different way to describe such a position would be to say that value not only can help
to determine which model is best, thus indirectly favoring some candidate legal propositions over
others, but also can favor candidate legal propositions directly. I will not use this terminology.) As I
say in the text, such a model may be less supported both by morality and by practices than models
that give less weight to content-oriented considerations. I suggest below (see the last four paragraphs
of this section), that the role that such a model assigns to value facts is outside the role that this paper’s
arguments support.
How Facts Make Law 261
law sensitive to relevant aspects of law practices. A model may be morally better,
for example, to the extent that it respects the will of the democratically elected rep-
resentatives of the people, protects expectations, enables planning, provides notice
of the law, treats relevantly similar practices similarly, minimizes the opportunity
for officials to base their decisions on controversial beliefs, and so on.
Roughly, we have a distinction between content-oriented considerations and
practice-oriented considerations. The relative weight accorded by morality to
these two kinds of considerations is a question for moral theory that I will not take
up here. On any plausible account, however, morality will give substantial weight
to practice-oriented considerations. So the morally best model (considered in
advance of law practices) will make the law sensitive to relevant aspects of law
practices.
Secondly, as we have seen, the legally correct model also depends on the law
practices. Apart from the weight that morality gives to practice-oriented consider-
ations, the practices themselves may support models that make the law sensitive to
practices. (Contemporary positivists, my primary target in this paper, are likely to
be sympathetic to the view that practices support models that make the law sensi-
tive to practices.) For example, although I will not defend the claim here, in the
U.S. and U.K. legal systems, practices themselves strongly support models that
make the law sensitive to law practices. Practices are thus a second reason that the
role of value need not have the consequence that the all-things-considered best
model will be one that tends to yield morally good legal propositions. (Also, even
a model that has a tendency to produce morally good legal propositions may not
do so, given the law practices of a particular legal system.)
Thirdly and finally, if we reflect on the argument for value’s role in determining
the content of the law, we see that it supports only a limited role for value, one that
does not involve supplanting law practices or making them irrelevant. Our start-
ing point was that law practices must determine the content of the law and that
they must do so by providing reasons that favor some legal propositions over
others. The crucial step in the argument was that law practices cannot provide
such reasons without value facts that determine the relevance of different aspects
of law practices to the content of the law. The argument thus supports the involve-
ment of value facts in determining the content of the law only for a limited role:
determining the relevance of law practices to the content of the law.
We can apply this point to the specific question of to what extent a legal prop-
osition’s goodness can help to make it true: the goodness (in terms of morality or
of value X) of a candidate legal proposition is relevant to the proposition’s truth
only to the extent that its goodness contributes to making it intelligible that an
aspect of a particular law practice has one bearing rather than another on the content
of the law. I will call this the relevance limitation.
I want to emphasize that the point is only that the argument of this chapter
supports no more than such a limited role for value facts; the argument does not
show that the role of value facts must be so limited. Whether there is some other
262 Mark Greenberg
or more expansive role for value in determining the content of the law is left open.
This chapter’s argument for the conclusion that value facts play a role in determin-
ing legal content is that value facts are needed in order to determine the relevance
of law practices to the legal content. The argument therefore supports only that
role for value facts. There might, of course, be a different argument that shows,
say, that morality or some other value supplants the law practices (though of
course almost no contemporary legal theorist, least of all one of my positivist tar-
gets, thinks that there is such an argument).
Let us consider more specifically the implications of the relevance limitation.
The limitation does not imply that the goodness of a legal proposition can never
be relevant to its truth.⁴⁵ The goodness of a legal proposition will be relevant to
the extent that it has a bearing on the intelligibility of law practices’ supporting
that legal proposition over others.
A Dworkinian theory of law provides a helpful example.⁴⁶ Consider a model
according to which law practices contribute to the content of the law precisely that
set of legal propositions that best justifies those law practices. Whether this model
respects the relevance limitation will depend on the notion of justification involved
in the Dworkinian model. Consider a simplistic understanding of justification that
has the following implication: the set of propositions that best justify the law prac-
tices is that set that results from taking the morally best set of propositions and
carving out specific exceptions for the law practices of the legal system—exceptions
tailored in such a way as to have no forward-looking consequences. On this under-
standing of justification, the model would not respect the relevance limitation,
because value facts would not determine the significance of the practices; instead,
the practices would simply be denied any significance by a kind of gerrymandering.
On a more sophisticated notion of justification, to the extent that a legal pro-
position is bent or gerrymandered, it will be less good at justifying law practices.
(In the extreme case just considered, where a particular law practice is simply
treated as an exception without further application, that practice is not justified at
all by the propositions to which it is an exception.) I think it is plausible, though I
will not argue the point here, that, given a proper understanding of justification,
the Dworkinian model I have described respects the relevance limitation. (Below
I will consider a different model, often attributed to Dworkin, that arguably does
not respect that limitation.)
⁴⁵ It is easy to see that the goodness of a legal proposition could have evidentiary relevance to the
content of the law. Suppose that the intention of legislators matters to the content of the law. If there
is reason to believe that the legislators would have intended what is morally better (at least other
things being equal), the moral goodness of candidate legal propositions will have a bearing on their
truth because it will have a bearing on what the legislators intended. The discussion in the text con-
cerns the question of whether the goodness of candidate propositions can have constitutive rather
than evidentiary relevance.
⁴⁶ I say “a Dworkinian theory” rather than “Dworkin’s theory” to avoid questions of Dworkin
exegesis. I believe that the position I describe is the best understanding of Dworkin’s position. See also
infra note 47.
How Facts Make Law 263
⁴⁷ Dworkin sometimes seems to suggest such a rule. See, e.g., Dworkin, supra note 6, at 284–285,
387–388; R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously 340, 342 (1977). And his commentators typi-
cally interpret him in this way. See, e.g., L. Alexander & E. Sherwin, The Rule of Rules ch. 8
(2001); J. Finnis, On Reason and Authority in Law’s Empire, 6 Law & Phil. 357, 372–374 (1987);
Raz, supra note 3, at 222–223. I think that this is not the best understanding of Dworkin’s view (and
Dworkin has confirmed as much in conversation). On the best understanding, fit is merely one aspect
of justification, there is no threshold level of fit, and how much fit matters relative to other aspects of
justification is a substantive question of political morality. (The idea of a threshold of fit that inter-
pretations must meet to be eligible and beyond which substantive moral considerations become rele-
vant should be taken as merely a heuristic or expository device.) See R. Dworkin, A Matter of
Principle 150–151 (1985); R. Dworkin, “Natural” Law Revisited, 34 U. Fla. L. Rev. 165, 170–173
(1982); R. Dworkin, supra note 6, at 231, 246–247. A different point is that Dworkin sometimes
seems to suggest that there is an aspect of the question of the extent to which interpretations fit law
practices that is purely formal or at least not normative. See, e.g., Dworkin, Taking Rights
Seriously, at 107 (suggesting that how much an interpretation fits is not an issue of political philoso-
phy); see also Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, at 67–68 (perhaps suggesting that there are
aspects of institutional support that do not depend on issues of normative political philosophy).
264 Mark Greenberg
moral reason for favoring proposition A over proposition B is not itself a reason
provided by law practices, since it is independent of law practices. If this argument
is right, my argument for the role of value facts does not support a role like that
captured by R—one in which there is room for value facts to favor one legal
proposition over another independently of law practices. (Again, however, the
point is only that this paper’s argument does not support such a role for value
facts, not that such a role is necessarily illegitimate.)
In sum, even if value X were morality, it would not follow that the most morally
justified model would be legally correct, and even a morally justified model would
not guarantee morally good legal requirements. It is no part of the role of value
argued for in this chapter that the goodness of a proposition ipso facto counts in
favor of the proposition’s truth. The role of value is in determining the relevance of
law practices to the content of the law.
VII. Conclusion
I have argued that law practices, understood in a way that excludes value facts,
cannot themselves determine the content of the law. Different models of the con-
tribution of practices to the content of the law would make it the case that differ-
ent legal propositions were true, and a body of law practices cannot unilaterally
determine which model is correct. In order for there to be determinate legal
requirements, the content of the law must also depend on facts about value.
What is the role of such value facts? I have suggested that they support some
models over others—that is, they help to determine which features of law prac-
tices matter and how they matter. It is not that the goodness of a candidate legal
proposition counts in favor of its truth. Rather, the role of value is in helping to
determine how practices contribute to the content of the law. This chapter does
not attempt conclusively to rule out the view that the needed legal value facts are
internal to law. I have argued, however, that the proponent of such a view must
overcome significant obstacles to explain how internal legal value facts could be
independent of both law practices and genuine value facts. The chapter also
suggests a way forward: We can ask what the nature and source of legal value facts
must be in order for law to have its central features, for example, for a legal system
to be able to provide certain kinds of reasons for action.
11
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts:
How Facts Make Law II
Mark Greenberg
I. Introduction
In How Facts Make Law and other recent papers,¹ I argue that a full constitutive
account of the content of the law—of legal facts—must appeal to normative facts.
The project of HFML is to defend this position without assuming that legal facts
are themselves normative facts. The argument’s engine is a requirement that a con-
stitutive account of legal facts must meet. According to this rational-relation
requirement,² it is not enough for a constitutive account of legal facts to specify
non-legal facts that modally determine the legal facts. The constitutive determinants
of legal facts must provide reasons for the obtaining of the legal facts (in a sense
of “reason” that I develop). In HFML,³ I argue that non-normative, contingent
facts—descriptive facts, for short—do not provide such reasons without normative
facts.⁴
In the present paper, I focus on the rational-relation requirement. I deploy it in
three related projects. First, I respond to a family of objections that challenge me
to explain why normative facts and descriptive facts together are better placed to
provide reasons for legal facts than descriptive facts alone.⁵ A unifying theme of
¹ M. Greenberg, How Facts Make Law, supra Chapter 10 [hereinafter HFML]. See also
M. Greenberg, Reasons Without Values?, in 2 Social, Political, and Legal Philosophy (E.
Villanueva ed. in press 2006); Mark Greenberg, On Practices and the Law, 12 Legal Theory (in press
2006).
² In HFML, id., I use the term rational-relation doctrine. For elaboration, see infra text accompany-
ing notes 12–19. ³ HFML, supra note 1.
⁴ This paper was written substantially later than HFML, and my terminology has shifted slightly.
I use the term “normative facts” here in the way that I used “value facts” in HFML. Thus, I use the
term to include what are sometimes called “evaluative facts” such as facts about what is good or bad.
For further explanation of the notion of a normative fact, see HFML, supra note 1, note 22. I explain
another minor terminological shift in infra note 8 and accompanying text.
⁵ I am particularly grateful to Gideon Rosen for his written comments on HFML for the
Exploring Law’s Empire conference held at Princeton University in September 2004. In this paper, I
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II. Mark Greenberg.
© Oxford University Press 2006. Published 2006 by Oxford University Press.
266 Mark Greenberg
draw especially on his clear and powerful formulation of the objection. See G. Rosen, Comments on
Mark Greenberg, How Facts Make Law (unpublished manuscript, on file with author). Others who
have raised versions of the objection include Scott Hershovitz, Tom Nagel, Ram Neta, Ori Simchen,
and Enrique Villanueva. I would like to thank Scott Hershovitz, Herb Morris, Ram Neta, Keemin
Ngiam, Seana Shiffrin, David Sosa, and Nicos Stavropoulos for comments on a draft. I am indebted
to Scott Shapiro for many valuable discussions. I’m especially grateful to Scott Hershovitz for encour-
aging me to write this paper and for creating this volume.
⁶ I say “a Hartian account” rather than “Hart’s account” because I try to address the most powerful
and plausible version of a position in the neighborhood of Hart’s, rather than to be faithful to the
details of Hart’s own view. I will largely ignore questions of exegesis of Hart.
⁷ The point of the qualification “at the most basic level” is to exclude determinants of the legal
facts the relevance of which depends on the contingent facts of the legal system—on, to use a term
defined in the text two paragraphs below, the law practices of the legal system. As I explain in HFML,
law practices have an impact on the contribution of law practices to the content of the law. But in
order to satisfy the rational-relation requirement, there have to be additional determinants of the legal
facts, independent of the law practices. See HFML, Sections IV–V. These determinants are the ones
“at the most basic level.” For example, inclusive legal positivists think that normative facts can be con-
stitutive determinants of legal facts because of the dispositions and attitudes of legal officials.
According to inclusive legal positivism, therefore, the role of normative facts is not at the most basic
level. The ultimate issue in HFML and the present paper is whether normative facts must be among
the most basic constitutive determinants of the content of the law. See HFML, supra note 1. I will usu-
ally omit the qualification “at the most basic level.”
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 267
It is important that the all-or-nothing result does not depend on the ultimate
conclusion that a constitutive account of legal facts must appeal to normative facts,
but follows immediately from the rational-relation requirement. (After all, my
ultimate conclusion obviously implies that a Hartian legal system is not possible.)
The rational-relation requirement is a relatively weak premise, which, I claim,
most legal theorists implicitly accept. It therefore may be surprising that it rules
out an ecumenical position according to which some possible legal systems are
Hartian and some are not.
A bit of terminology will be helpful. A legal fact⁸ is a true legal proposition—a
fact about the content of the law. That contracts for the sale of land must be in
writing is a legal fact in many legal systems. Law-determining practices, or law prac-
tices for short, are ordinary empirical facts (paradigmatically, facts about the say-
ings and doings of members of constitutional assemblies, legislatures, courts, and
administrative agencies) that are determinants of the content of the law. I call the
relevant facts “law-determining practices” rather than “legal decisions” because
the term “decisions” tends to suggest judicial decisions in particular.⁹
A model of the contribution of law practices to the content of the law—or, for short,
a model—is a (putative) way in which law practices contribute to the content of
the law. A model is thus the metaphysical counterpart of a method of interpreta-
tion. For example, a Hartian rule of recognition (understood as constitutive of
legal facts rather than as a way of identifying legal facts) is a candidate model.
The correct model (in a given legal system at a given time) is the way in which law
practices actually contribute to the content of the law (in the legal system at that
time), not merely the way in which they are taken to do so. Note that correctness is
therefore legal correctness, not, for example, moral rightness.
In the next section (Section II), I lay out the structure of the argument of HFML.
In Section III, I give a brief account of why a Hartian account of legal facts fails to
satisfy the rational-relation requirement. In Section IV, I show that a Hartian
account requires it to be true in all possible legal systems that acceptance of a rule of
recognition by officials makes that rule the correct model for the legal system. In
Section V, I use this result to undermine an appeal to Hartian intuitions. Our reflect-
ive understanding of law does not support the Hartian position that acceptance of a
⁸ In HFML, I use the uglier term “legal-content fact.” HFML, supra note 1, at 226.
⁹ For ease of exposition, I use legal-content-laden terms, such as “legislature” and “court” in char-
acterizing law practices. Strictly speaking, however, the law practices should be understood to be the
underlying descriptive facts in virtue of which the relevant legal-content facts obtain. Since legal facts
are not basic, there must be non-legal facts that constitute the legal-content-laden practices. These
more basic facts will include descriptive facts—the facts that I am calling “law practices.” For example,
the fact that a legislature enacted a statute must hold in virtue of complex descriptive facts about
people’s attitudes and behavior and perhaps also normative facts. (If, in order to account for legal-
content-laden practices, we have to appeal not merely to descriptive facts but also to normative facts,
so much the worse for the positivist thesis that the content of the law depends only on descriptive
facts.) The convenience of talking as if law practices consisted in legal-content-laden facts about the
behavior of legislatures, courts, and so on should not obscure the fact that there must be more basic
facts in virtue of which the legal facts obtain. For elaboration of the notion of a law practice, see
HFML, supra note 1, Section II.C.
268 Mark Greenberg
rule of recognition by officials makes that rule the correct model for the legal system.
Section VI shows that an account that appeals to normative facts does not run into
the problems faced by the Hartian account. I conclude in Section VII.
¹⁵ See HFML, supra note 1, at 227–228. See also Greenberg, On Practices and the Law, supra
note 1. ¹⁶ Thanks to Seana Shiffrin for pushing me to address this point.
¹⁷ See HFML, supra note 1, at 252.
270 Mark Greenberg
what are taken to be normative facts are needed to satisfy the rational-relation
requirement. The imagined positivist strategy would be to maintain that merely
putative normative facts can provide rational intelligibility, which is consistent
with the positivist view that normative facts need not be among the deter-
minants of legal facts. As noted, however, only real facts can be constitutive
determinants of anything. Hence, once it is conceded that putative normative
facts are needed to satisfy the rational-relation requirement, it follows that (real,
not merely putative) normative facts must be among the determinants of the
content of the law.
Thirdly, the rational-relation requirement is not a requirement that the legal
facts be shown to be good or valuable.¹⁸ I express the requirement by saying that
the determining facts must provide reasons for the legal facts, but as noted above,
a reason in the relevant sense is a consideration that accounts for an explanandum
in rational terms, not a justification. In general, as I explain in HFML, non-
normative considerations can constitute such reasons.
The point is important because otherwise positivists could not accept the
rational-relation requirement. The strategy of the argument is to use the rational-
relation requirement, which I claim most legal theorists implicitly accept, to argue
for the controversial conclusion that normative facts must be determinants of
legal facts. One can accept the rational-relation requirement, while taking it to be
an open question whether non-normative facts could themselves provide reasons for
the obtaining of legal facts—and indeed whether normative and non-normative
facts together could do so.
In HFML, I sketch some reasons for believing that (3) is true,¹⁹ at least in the
U.S. and U.K. legal systems and perhaps in all legal systems,²⁰ though I do not
attempt anything like a full defense of that position. I also suggest that most legal
theorists implicitly take for granted that (3) is true in the legal systems with which
they are concerned.
In fact, I am not especially concerned with the question of whether (3) is true in
all possible legal systems. Throughout this paper, I will simply assume that (3) is
true in the legal systems with which we are concerned, and I will omit any quali-
fication to that effect. Readers who believe that (3) is true only in some legal systems
can understand my arguments as applicable only to those legal systems.
In HFML,²¹ I argue that:
(4) The law practices cannot themselves rationally determine any legal facts.
I will not repeat that argument here. The basic problem with law practices is that
there are many possible ways in which they could bear on the legal facts, and they
cannot determine their own relevance. For this reason, I sometimes express the
rational-relation requirement by saying that there have to be reasons that determine
¹⁸ See HFML, supra note 1, at 232–233. ¹⁹ See HFML, supra note 1, at 237–240.
²⁰ To be more precise, all those in which the legal facts are determined by law practices.
²¹ See HFML, supra note 1, Section IV.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 271
the contribution of law practices to the legal facts. This way of putting things
should not mislead us into thinking that the rational-relation requirement is a
requirement not only that there be reasons for the legal facts, but that there be rea-
sons that explain why those reasons are reasons. That line of thought could suggest
that an explanatory regress lurks.²² But saying that there have to be reasons for the
contribution of law practices to the legal facts is just an intuitive way of summariz-
ing why law practices by themselves do not provide reasons for legal facts. What
the rational-relation requirement demands is not higher-order reasons, but deter-
mining facts that together provide reasons for the legal facts.
From (3) and (4), it follows that:
(5) Something other than the law practices is among the determinants of the
legal facts.
The objections that I want to consider in this paper accept (3), (4), and therefore
(5). But they deny that I can reach the conclusion:
(6) The legal facts are in part determined by normative facts.
So for purposes of this paper, we can assume (1)–(5).
Hart provides the most influential account of how non-normative facts determine
legal facts.²³ In this section, I explore how that account fares with respect to the
rational-relation requirement.
The existence of a rule of recognition does the main work in Hart’s account.
Although Hart would not put the point this way, on Hart’s account, a model of
how law practices contribute to the content of the law is legally correct in virtue of
the existence of a rule of recognition specifying that model. Hart’s account of what
makes it the case that a rule of recognition exists is an application of his “practice
theory” of rules.
According to the practice theory, a “social rule” is constituted by certain atti-
tudes and dispositions.²⁴ We can call these dispositions and attitudes Hartian
dispositions, and, following Hart’s terminology, we can say that people who have
such dispositions for a particular rule accept that rule.²⁵ The notion of Hartian
²² I discuss below the idea that if normative facts are needed to explain the relevance of law prac-
tices, an infinite regress is generated. See infra Section VI, especially note 57.
²³ H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (2d ed. 1994).
²⁴ We can avoid the issue of what proportion of the people in a community need to have the
appropriate attitudes and dispositions because my criticisms of the Hartian approach will not depend
on that issue. When discussing examples, I therefore assume that all or the great majority of the rele-
vant people—in particular, the officials of a legal system—have the attitudes and dispositions.
²⁵ Because it avoids grammatical awkwardness, I will often use the “Hartian dispositions”
terminology rather than talking of “acceptance” of a rule.
272 Mark Greenberg
²⁶ See Hart, supra note 23, at 55–61, 255. Let us ignore any difficulties about the indeterminacy
of the rule for which officials have Hartian dispositions. If there are any such difficulties, they are
problems for the Hartian, not for me. For present purposes, I propose to give the Hartian the
strongest possible case by simply assuming that people’s Hartian dispositions uniquely determine, in
the way that Hart suggested, a particular rule. ²⁷ Id. at 55–57, 109.
²⁸ Id. at 107.
²⁹ Id. at 100–110. In his account of what constitutes a rule of recognition in a contemporary legal
system, Hart attributes a limited role to citizens who are not officials. Id. at 60–61. As it does not
affect the substance of the argument, I will omit reference to citizens in what follows. Thanks to Scott
Shapiro for help in formulating the assumption described in the text.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 273
cases according to the plain meaning of whatever Rex pronounces, to criticize other
officials if they fail to decide cases in that way, and so on. In other words, for R1 to
exist is, roughly speaking, for the officials to treat R1 as the correct model.
Suppose that the officials of a legal system accept R1. And suppose that Rex has
made only one pronouncement on the subject of foie gras, a pronouncement the
plain meaning of which is that the production of foie gras is prohibited. A Hartian
will now claim that the officials’ acceptance of R1 plus the fact of Rex’s pro-
nouncement make it a legal fact that the production of foie gras is prohibited.
It will be important in what follows that, on Hart’s account, what makes some-
thing a legal rule (other than the rule of recognition) is not that people have
Hartian dispositions for that rule. In our example, the law prohibits the produc-
tion of foie gras even if people lack Hartian dispositions for the rule that one is not
to produce foie gras. On Hart’s account, what makes a standard law is not that it is
accepted, but that it is identified by an accepted rule.³⁰
Given (3) (the rational determination premise), the non-legal facts have to make
rationally intelligible the obtaining of the legal fact that the law prohibits the
production of foie gras. It may be claimed that the officials’ Hartian dispositions
and Rex’s pronouncement together satisfy this requirement. Is this claim correct?
The facts about the officials’ Hartian dispositions are part of the law practices—
they are just more of the ordinary empirical facts about the attitudes and behavior
of various people that determine the content of the law. But by (4), law practices
cannot themselves rationally determine the legal facts. As I argue in HFML,³¹ the
problem is that ordinary empirical facts cannot determine their own relevance to
the legal facts.
Without repeating the arguments for (4), I will say very briefly why Hartian
dispositions in particular seem inadequate to satisfy the rational-relation require-
ment. Officials have Hartian dispositions for a rule that requires them to apply
certain standards. The Hartian needs this fact to explain why the standards are
law. The problem is that it is not clear why we should think that Hartian disposi-
tions for a rule have this significance. As a general matter—outside the legal
arena—a case has not been made that Hartian dispositions have explanatory
potency. For example, Hartian dispositions for a rule do not in general make the
rule binding on anyone or provide any reason for acting in accordance with the
rule.³² There are practices or organizations in which there are Hartian dispositions
for rules requiring people to haze new recruits, to sell children into sexual slavery,
and to use violence to extract “protection money” from shops. It does not follow
that these rules obtain or are binding on anyone in any non-trivial sense.
³⁰ See Hart, supra note 23, at 100–110, 256. Hart also suggest that, in addition to the rule of
recognition, “certain important legal rules” are social rules. Id. at 256.
³¹ HFML, supra note 1, at 178–185.
³² For fuller discussion of essentially this point, see Greenberg, On Practices and the Law, supra
note 1.
274 Mark Greenberg
The Hartian will likely respond that what is at issue is not whether the rule of
recognition is morally or all-things-considered binding or even whether there are
any (non-legal) reasons to act in accordance with it. Rather, the issue is simply
whether the rule is legally authoritative. According to this line of argument,
Hartian dispositions for a rule of recognition make it legally authoritative not
because of some general truth about Hartian dispositions, but because of some
truth specific to the legal case.
Consider, for example, Joseph Raz’s account of “why it is true that parliament-
ary legislation is binding on the courts:”
The answer is that this is so because of the practice of the courts which follow a rule to that
effect and because the rules practised by the courts of a legal system are rules of that system
according to the doctrine of identity.³³
Raz sees that the practice of the courts—their Hartian dispositions—by itself is
not an explanation. The “doctrine of identity”—a special truth about how things
are with law—is needed to complete the account. In the next two sections, we
will turn to the possibility that the Hartian could appeal to a truth specific to the
legal case.
It might be thought that there is an alternative to an appeal to a truth specific to
the legal case. A Hartian could argue that there is a realm that is broader than and
encompasses the legal domain in which acceptance of a rule of recognition has the
impact that the Hartian claims it has in the legal domain. One suggestion would
be that the relevant realm includes anything that is socially constructed. But this
suggestion is a non-starter. What makes something a celebration, a book, a
kitchen, or a fashion statement is not the acceptance of a rule of recognition.
A somewhat more promising suggestion would be that we should consider
rules of practices (including organizations, games, and so on). Notice, first, that
the Hartian cannot claim that ordinary legal rules are an instance of Hartian social
rules. As noted above, by the Hartian’s own account, the existence of a social rule S
is constituted by Hartian dispositions for S, not by officials having Hartian dis-
positions for a rule of recognition requiring officials to apply S. The Hartian needs
not a domain of Hartian social rules, but a domain in which acceptance of a rule
of recognition by officials charged with applying primary standards makes the
standards it specifies rules of the practice (regardless of whether there are Hartian
dispositions for those standards).³⁴ Call a domain that has this feature Hartian.
Many familiar social practices, such as etiquette, are obviously not Hartian since
they have no equivalent to legal officials, let alone to the acceptance by officials of
a rule of recognition.
There has been no serious attempt to pursue this approach to defending the
Hartian account of law. Rather than pursuing it here, I will simply register a few
comments about the task facing the Hartian who would take this route. First,
there is no obvious reason why an attempt to show that there is a domain of prac-
tices that is Hartian would fare any better than an attempt to show directly that
law is Hartian. (Indeed, Hart himself does not seem to recognize the possibility of
practices outside the legal domain in which acceptance of a rule of recognition
makes the standards it specifies rules of the practice.) Secondly, even if it were
shown that there is a Hartian domain, it would require further work to establish
both that law is a member of that domain, and that a legal norm is an instance of a
rule of a practice.
Finally, it would not be sufficient for the positivist to show that there are some
practices that are Hartian. As a preliminary matter, note that it is consistent with
my argument that there be some such instances. In the legal domain, constitutive
determination is rational determination. That is the source of the rational-relation
requirement. But it may be that in the case of some practices, the rules are not
rationally determined.³⁵ In such cases, there will be no requirement that the prac-
tices make the rules rationally intelligible. The correct model can be determined
arbitrarily, so it can be determined by Hartian dispositions, by normative facts, or
in any other way.
The Hartian seeks a non-legal truth that will help to explain the claimed role of
Hartian dispositions. If some practices are Hartian and some are not, that may
well be because they are members of a domain in which the determination of cor-
rectness can be arbitrary. In that case, however, the practices that happen to be
Hartian are no evidence of an explanatory truth that could help the Hartian.
(This is not to say that the Hartian needs an absolutely general truth. It might be
enough if there were an explanatorily significant class of practices—one that
forms a social kind—that is Hartian.)
In sum, the approach of identifying a Hartian domain, developing an
account of it, and showing that that account can explain the legal case seems
more daunting (and less developed) than the more direct approach of appealing
to a specifically legal truth. In this paper, at any rate, I focus on the latter
approach.
I close this section with a preliminary indication of why an account that
appeals to normative facts in addition to law practices is not vulnerable to the
problems that we have identified with respect to the Hartian account. We
should begin by saying something about the kind of normative facts that are at
issue. The relevant normative facts are facts about the bearing of law practices
on our legal obligations (or on other aspects of the legal facts). An example
might be that fairness supports a statute’s contributing its plain meaning to the
content of the law. Or that democratic reasons cut against a judicial decision’s
being able to create a standard that goes beyond what is necessary for resolution
of the dispute before the court.
We noted that Hartian dispositions are just more law practices, and thus sub-
ject to the arguments of HFML regarding why law practices cannot themselves
provide reasons for the legal facts. Unlike Hartian dispositions, normative facts
are not part of the law practices.³⁶ More substantively, the normative facts in ques-
tion seem to be just the sort of fact that, with law practices, could explain in rational
terms the obtaining of particular legal facts. Suppose fairness and democracy favor
plain meaning over all other models of the bearing of statutes on the content of
the law. On the face of it, that normative fact is the kind of thing that could sup-
plement facts about statutory language to yield an explanation of legal facts. I will
have more to say about this point in Section V below.
At this stage, we have reason to think that normative facts and law practices
together are not in the same position as law practices alone with respect to the
rational-relation requirement. It is therefore not open to an objector simply to
insist that if law practices cannot satisfy the explanatory demand, neither can norm-
ative facts and law practices together. In the next two sections, after developing the
Hartian’s position, we will take a closer look at strategies a Hartian might pursue to
argue that the Hartian account can satisfy the rational-relation requirement.
We mentioned in the previous section the possibility that there are fundamental
truths about law that enable the Hartian to meet the rational-relation require-
ment. For the Hartian positivist, the natural candidate for such a truth is some-
thing along the following lines:
(7) For any rule R (that specifies that standards with certain features are
law),³⁷ officials’ Hartian dispositions for R make it the case that a legal sys-
tem’s law practices contribute to the content of the law in accordance with R
and only in accordance with R (and if officials do not have Hartian disposi-
tions for any such rule, then there are no legal facts).
Proposition (7) is in effect a bridge principle, one that takes us from ordinary
empirical facts—law practices—to legal facts. (7), along with facts about Hartian
dispositions and other law practices of a legal system, is supposed to make ration-
ally intelligible the legal facts of the system.
Before we examine whether (7) (or some similar bridge principle) can play the
role it is introduced to play, we need to become clearer about (7)’s scope. Is it a
claim about all possible legal systems or merely about some legal systems?
³⁶ See HFML, supra note 1, at 235–236.
³⁷ On the proper formulation of rules of recognition, see supra text accompanying notes 27–29.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 277
Let us use the term Hartian legal system for a legal system in which Hartian
dispositions for a rule of recognition make that rule the correct model for the legal
system (and in which that is the only way in which the correct model can be deter-
mined). It is tempting for the Hartian to rest on the claim that a Hartian legal sys-
tem is at least possible.³⁸ I want to raise the stakes by arguing that a bridge
principle, such as (7), has to be true in all possible legal systems in order for it to be
true of any legal system. If I am correct, it is not an option to retreat to the mere
possibility of a Hartian legal system—it’s all or nothing.
³⁸ Rosen says: “One need not go all the way with Hart to think that it lies in the very nature of
legal systems that one way for a legal system to be in place is for Hart’s conditions to be satisfied.”
Rosen, supra note 5, at 6. This remark need not be understood to suggest that some legal systems
could be Hartian and others not. The remark seems to recognize that it would have to be a general
truth about law—“in the very nature of legal systems”—that Hartian dispositions for a rule of recog-
nition can make a model correct. Perhaps the possibility Rosen has in mind is that Hartian disposi-
tions for a rule are sufficient to make that rule the correct model in any possible legal system, but if
officials do not have Hartian dispositions for any rule of recognition, there are other ways for a model
to be correct. This possibility is consistent with there being a (disjunctive) principle about how legal
facts are determined that is true in all possible legal systems.
³⁹ Could it simply be a brute fact about a particular legal system (as opposed to about the law or all
possible legal systems) that it is Hartian, i.e. that there are no other facts about the legal system in
virtue of which the system’s being Hartian can be explained? The rational-relation requirement rules
out the possibility of a brute fact about a particular legal system. Accepting the possibility of such a
fact is tantamount to accepting that it can be arbitrary which model is correct. Notice that if it could
be a brute fact that a particular legal system was Hartian, two legal systems could be identical in every
respect, except that one was Hartian and one was not. Two such legal systems would be empirically
indistinguishable; they would not differ even in the participants’ dispositions, beliefs, and utterances.
278 Mark Greenberg
H. Hartian dispositions for a rule R are not sufficient to make it the case that R is
the correct model in H. Part of the explanation is that H has property X. The
supposition that (7) was true in H, but not in all possible legal systems has led to a
contradiction. Hence (7) is true in all possible legal systems or in none.
The foregoing argument does not exclude the possibility that in some legal sys-
tems, acceptance of a rule makes it the correct model, while in other legal systems
it does not.⁴⁰ It is just that there will have to be some property, X, in virtue of
which a given legal system falls in the former category. The full constitutive
account of the legal facts in legal systems in the former category will not be the
Hartian account because it will have to make reference to X. (And if the account is
to be a positivist one, X will have to be a non-normative property.)
Moreover, the revised account—the one that makes reference to X—will be
true in all possible legal systems. For if it were not, then there could be a legal sys-
tem with property X, but in which Hartian dispositions for a given rule fail to
make that rule the correct model for the legal system. But in that case, X is not the
property that makes Hartian dispositions operative, after all.
The point generalizes to any account of what, independent of the law practices,
determines the correct model of the contribution of law practices to the content of
the law. A full constitutive account of the legal facts in a particular legal system A
must specify some principle P that is independent of the law practices of A and
that, with those law practices, explains the legal facts.⁴¹ Suppose there is a legal
system B in which P is not true. In B, the legal facts can be different from those of
A in a way that is not explained by differences in the law practices. For example,
identical law practices would yield different legal facts in A and B. We have a viola-
tion of the rational-relation requirement.
Different models can of course be correct in different legal systems. If a prin-
ciple Q (about the relevance of law practices to the content of the law) is true in A,
but not in B, then that principle cannot be the whole story about what, inde-
pendent of law practices, determines the correct model. In order to satisfy the
rational-relation requirement, a constitutive account of the legal facts of A would
have to explain why Q is true in A. In other words, we will need a conditional
principle whose antecedent includes the condition that the legal system has the
critical property that makes Q applicable. The rational-relation requirement
ensures that there will be such a property. But the revised principle will be true
even in legal systems that do not possess that property. In sum, principles about
the relevance of law practices to the content of the law that are not themselves
derived from law practices must be true in all possible legal systems.
Hence the participants in two systems would not be distinguished even by their beliefs about whether
their own system was Hartian. It would thus be utterly mysterious what made one system Hartian
and not another.
⁴⁰ Another possibility is the one described in supra note 38 that Hartian dispositions are always
sufficient to determine legal facts, but that in the absence of such dispositions, there are other alter-
natives. The argument in the text applies, with appropriate modifications, to that possibility.
⁴¹ See HFML, supra note 1, Section IV.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 279
Returning to the Hartian account, we can conclude that, in order to satisfy the
rational-relation requirement, the Hartian needs a bridge principle whose scope is
all possible legal systems. Since the Hartian holds that (7) is a complete and
correct account of legal facts—that there is no property X—we can hereafter take
(7) as our candidate bridge principle.⁴² The Hartian needs (7) to be true in all pos-
sible legal systems. To save words, I will hereinafter understand “(7)” to make the
Hartian claim about all possible legal systems.⁴³
⁴² A positivist who thinks that some property X needs to be added to the specification of the cor-
rect bridge principle can substitute the appropriate bridge principle for (7) throughout. My argu-
ments will generally not be affected by the details of the bridge principle.
⁴³ In other words, the revised version of (7) is as follows: In all possible legal systems, for any rule R
(that specifies that standards with certain features are law), officials’ Hartian dispositions for R make
it the case that a legal system’s law practices contribute to the content of the law in accordance with R
and only in accordance with R (and if officials do not have Hartian dispositions for any such rule,
then there are no legal facts). ⁴⁴ See supra text accompanying note 8.
⁴⁵ See HFML, supra note 1, 226–227, 231–232, 237–240 See also Greenberg, Reasons Without
Values?, supra note 1; Greenberg, On Practices and the Law, supra note 1.
⁴⁶ See, e.g., HFML, supra note 1, at 227–228.
280 Mark Greenberg
intelligibility will be respected in name only. To put the point another way, to
allow a bridge principle (from non-legal facts to legal facts) to count as a
“non-legal fact” would trivialize the requirement that the relation between the
non-legal facts and the legal facts be rationally intelligible. Hence, in (3), the
phrase “non-legal facts” should be understood to exclude facts about how non-
legal facts contribute to the content of the law, even if those facts are not legal facts
in our technical sense.
We therefore find ourselves back to the question of whether (7) is rationally
intelligible in light of the non-legal facts, which is really just the original question,
addressed quickly back in Section III, of whether Hartian dispositions for a rule of
recognition R make it intelligible that the legal facts are determined in accordance
with R. Now that we have clarified what the Hartian needs—in particular that
what has to be rationally intelligible is that the Hartian bridge principle be true in
all possible legal systems—I want to address that question at greater length.
The Hartian is in a difficult position in trying to give reasons why Hartian dis-
positions for a given rule make it the case that law practices contribute to the con-
tent of the law in accordance with that rule. In Section III, we raised and set aside
the possibility of reasons that are not specifically legal. The present question con-
cerns reasons specific to law.
First, the Hartian cannot appeal to features of particular legal systems to explain
the relevance of law practices to the content of the law. The Hartian needs to explain
a truth about all possible legal systems. Secondly, empirical induction is not a
promising option. As we will see below, whether Hartian dispositions for a rule
make it the correct model in a particular legal system is not a straightforward empir-
ical question. Moreover, we will see that the evidence of our own legal system, if any-
thing, cuts against the Hartian. In the next section, I address the possibility that the
Hartian could explain (7) by appealing to our reflective understanding of law.
⁴⁷ Rosen puts the point this way: “The positivist claim is that someone who fails to see the
explanatory force of the sociological facts in this sort of case simply fails to understand what it is for a
law to be the law of a given community.” Rosen, supra note 5, at 6.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 281
Whether Themis is correct does not depend on whether the other officials come
to agree with her. But, to dramatize the story, we can suppose that they do. At time
T3, they come to agree not only about the current situation, but that their Hartian
dispositions for R2 were mistaken at T1, and have always been mistaken. Isn’t it at
least possible that they are correct? That is, couldn’t there be a legal system in which
the officials’ Hartian dispositions for a rule could turn out to be incorrect?
It might be objected that I have chosen an implausible or silly rule of recogni-
tion. But this objection misses the mark. In order for (7) to play the explanatory
role it is supposed to play, the merits of the rule of recognition cannot matter. If it
is a brute truth about legal systems that Hartian dispositions for a rule of recogni-
tion make it the correct model, then the merits of the rule are irrelevant. If, on the
contrary, Hartian dispositions for a given rule are effective in making that rule the
correct model only when the rule is sufficiently wise or sensible, then a constitu-
tive account of the legal facts that appealed only to (7) and the law practices would
be incomplete. A full account would have to make reference to facts about the
wisdom or sensibleness of the rule of recognition. Hence, if (7) is to play the
explanatory role it is supposed to play—making normative facts unnecessary—
the merits of the rule of recognition must be irrelevant. Therefore, in considering
whether there could be a legal system in which (7) is not true, it is fair game to
consider situations involving silly or bad rules of recognition. Indeed, we need to
consider such situations if we are to separate the work that is being done by accep-
tance of a rule from the work that is being done by the merits of the rule.
Let it not be objected that if the officials come to agree with Themis, they must
already have had a disposition inconsistent with Hartian dispositions for R2. This
objection is based on a mistake. From the fact that a person can be convinced that
doing X is the wrong thing to do, it does not follow that she was not previously
disposed to do X. A person’s dispositions can change. And, by hypothesis, that is
what has happened here. It is part of the description of the original situation that
the officials have Hartian dispositions for R2. The fact that they later decide that
their dispositions to follow R2 were mistaken, and consequently come to have
new dispositions, is consistent with that description.⁴⁸
We should not get too caught up in the details of an example. The issue is
simply whether there could be a legal system in which officials’ acceptance of a
rule is not the final word on how the content of the law derives from statutes,
judicial decisions, and other law practices. In such a legal system, judges and
other officials could unambiguously accept a particular rule of recognition, but
⁴⁸ We can also alter the facts to eliminate any worry of the sort addressed in the last paragraph.
We can suppose that none of the legal officials who are convinced by Themis at T3 were legal offi-
cials at T1—all of those who were legal officials at T1 have died or retired. Moreover, those who were
legal officials at T1 would not have been convinced by Themis that their acceptance of R2 was mis-
taken. In other words, the legal officials at T1 accepted R2, and were not disposed to reconsider that
acceptance.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 283
⁴⁹ See R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (1977); R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986).
⁵⁰ Alternatively, the Hartian might argue that the Hartian dispositions of the officials in our sys-
tem are for the following rule of recognition: statutes, judicial decisions, and other law practices con-
tribute to the content of the law in the way that the officials believe is most supported by the relevant
values. But notice that the hypothesis in the text is simpler and better accords with what the officials
themselves think and do. The officials do not think that the rule is to take law practices to contribute
to the law in the way that the officials believe is most supported by the relevant values. They think that
the rule is to take the law practices to contribute to the law in the way that is most supported by the
relevant values. For example, officials who know that they are in the minority with respect to some
dispute about the correct model do not automatically concede that they are mistaken, as they would
if they believed that the rule of recognition was the one described in this footnote. For discussion of a
related point, see M. Greenberg & H. Litman, The Meaning of Original Meaning, 86 Geo. L.J. 569,
608–609 (1998).
284 Mark Greenberg
in which values are ultimately doing the work—rather, at the most basic level,
dispositions to treat normative facts as relevant is what makes them relevant.⁵¹
It might be thought that this move by the Hartian leaves us with a stalemate.
Against this thought, however, I want to point out an asymmetry between the
positions. The positivist position is in tension with what the officials themselves
believe. In our legal system, when officials appeal to normative facts, they believe
that it is those facts, not other officials’ dispositions to be guided by those facts,
that ultimately matter.⁵² An official who appeals to fairness or democracy does not
think that fairness or democracy matters because all or most officials think it
does.⁵³ In contrast, the anti-positivist position is in harmony with what the offi-
cials believe. This asymmetry supports the view that our legal system is non-
Hartian because, other things being equal, a view that does not have the
consequence that the officials are systematically wrong about such a fundamental
matter is more plausible than a view that does. Again, the point of this brief dis-
cussion is not to argue that our legal system is not Hartian, but merely to refute
the claim that (7) is part of our reflective understanding of law, including of our
own legal system.
In sum, we have little reason to accept the Hartian’s claim that our understand-
ing of law includes an understanding that Hartian dispositions yield legal facts in
accordance with (7). If that is right, the Hartian needs to provide reasons why (7)
is true for all legal systems, and to do so without appeal to normative facts. We
remarked on the dimensions of this task in Section III. We can leave it as a chal-
lenge to the Hartian.
⁵¹ As readers will have noted, we find ourselves in the vicinity of a familiar debate. See, e.g.
J. Coleman, Negative and Positive Positivism, in Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary
Jurisprudence 28 (M. Cohen ed., 1984); R. Dworkin, Reply to Coleman, in Ronald Dworkin and
Contemporary Jurisprudence 252 (M. Cohen ed., 1984). The rational-relation requirement
provides a new perspective on the debate. From this perspective, the issue is whether the practices of
officials or the normative facts to which they appeal are the reasons that, at the most basic level,
explain the legally correct model.
⁵² I think this claim is very plausible, but it is an empirical one, and my basis for it is admittedly
unsystematic. I will simply assume that it is true in what follows. ⁵³ See supra note 50.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 285
The determining facts must both modally entail the legal facts and make the
obtaining of the legal facts intelligible in rational terms. Logical entailment may
be sufficient for rational intelligibility, but it is not necessary. (The inadequacy
of facts about Hartian dispositions was not that they do not logically entail legal
facts.)
The objection that there is a gap between the normative facts and the correct
model should instead be understood as challenging whether normative facts are
the right sort of material to combine with law practices to provide reasons for legal
facts. For example, it might be claimed that the fact that fairness militates in favor
of judicial decisions’ contributing to the law in a particular way does not provide a
reason that they do contribute to the law in that way.
Because what is at stake in the overall argument is precisely whether the content
of the law depends on normative facts, it would be question begging for the
objector to assume that there is an explanatory gap between normative facts and
the correct model on the ground that the content of the law is independent of
normative facts. (Equally, it would be question begging for me to assume that the
content of the law depends on normative facts.) The relevant question is not, at
this stage, the ultimate one of whether the content of the law is or is not independ-
ent of normative facts. (If we had the answer to that question, we would not be
engaged in the present discussion.) Rather, it is whether normative facts about the
bearing of law practices on legal facts are even the right sort of material to provide,
along with law practices, reasons for legal facts. To put it crudely, is the fact that it
would be fair or democratic or just for law practices to affect the content of the law
in a certain way the right kind of fact to make it rationally intelligible that law
practices do affect the content of the law in that way?
If we were trying to explain the occurrence of physical events, we might ques-
tion whether normative facts were the right sort of material. For such explananda,
causal explanations are needed, and normative facts will not feature ineliminably
in such explanations. Although it was long thought otherwise, in the physical
domain, how it would be good for objects to behave is no explanation of how they
do behave.
This platitude about causal explanation tells us little about rational intelligi-
bility. In fact, the platitude is consistent with the claim that facts about how it
would be good for objects to behave make it rationally intelligible that they
behave in that way. (In fact, it is tempting to speculate that part of the explana-
tion of why people long took for granted teleological explanations of occurrences
in the physical world is that people expected that the physical world would be
susceptible to being made intelligible in rational terms.) For rational intelligibil-
ity is neither necessary nor sufficient for causal explanation. On the one hand,
the best we can do to explain the occurrence of physical events may be to cite laws
or correlations that cannot be made intelligible in rational terms. And, on the
other, a putative causal explanation that makes a phenomenon intelligible may
be false.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 287
⁵⁵ For citations to Davidson and very brief discussion, see HFML, supra note 1, at 232 note 18,
238 note 25.
⁵⁶ I do not mean to endorse Davidson’s account. See HFML, supra note 1, at 238 note 25. Also, it
might be objected that Davidson’s view in the mental case is not parallel to my view of the determina-
tion relation in the legal case. According to this objection, what Davidson holds must be intelligible is
the content of the subject’s mental states, not the relation between determining facts and content facts.
On a better understanding of Davidson’s view—and on the understanding that is useful for our pur-
poses—the best interpretation of a person makes the person intelligible in light of his or her circum-
stances and behavior. For example, the attribution of a false belief on a particular issue makes the
person more intelligible rather than less if the person’s only evidence on the issue is misleading.
⁵⁷ Some commentators who have made objections in the general neighborhood of the one
described in the text have compared their objections to the point of Lewis Carroll’s famous dialogue
between Achilles and the Tortoise. See Lewis Carroll, What the Tortoise Said to Achilles, 4 Mind 278
(1895), reprinted in 104 Mind 691 (1995). On a straightforward interpretation of this comparison,
I would stand accused of mistakenly treating normative facts as premises rather than inference rules.
In other words, the objector’s claim would be that normative facts are analogous to inference rules
that allow one to move from law practices to legal facts. But this claim, whatever its merits, would be
no objection to my position that normative facts must figure in a full constitutive account of legal
facts.
The appeal to Lewis Carroll’s dialogue is perhaps more of a loose analogy than a direct application.
The idea seems to be that if I make an explanatory demand of the sort that makes it necessary to
appeal to normative facts, I open up an infinite regress. But this idea is mistaken.
In the text, I argue that normative facts and law practices together, unlike law practices alone, pro-
vide the requisite reasons for the law facts. The type of objection that I want to consider here grants
this claim, but maintains that the appeal to normative facts generates a further, higher-order explana-
tory demand. (And the satisfier of that further demand will generate a still higher-order explanatory
demand, and so on.)
288 Mark Greenberg
There seem to be two ways to develop the infinite-regress objection. According to the first, if a con-
stitutive account of legal facts appeals to normative facts, it will then have to explain the obtaining of
the normative facts. This is the objection that I address in the text.
According to the second version of the objection, if a constitutive account of legal facts appeals to
normative facts, it will then have to explain the relevance of those normative facts to the legal facts. As
noted above, I sometimes express the intuitive inadequacy of law practices as reasons for legal facts by
writing that we need facts that explain the relevance of law practices to legal facts. See supra note 14
and text accompanying note 22. Similarly, I sometimes write that we need reasons for the mapping
from law practices to the content of the law. In using these formulations, I may have misled readers
into thinking that the rational-relation requirement is a requirement not only of reasons for the legal
facts, but also of reasons for those reasons. The requirement is only that the constitutive determinants
of the legal facts together provide reasons for the legal facts.
A constitutive account appeals to normative facts not to satisfy a second-order explanatory require-
ment, but simply to meet the first-order explanatory requirement that law practices do not meet
themselves. It is tempting to express what is missing from an account that appeals only to law prac-
tices by saying that we need facts that explain the relevance of the law practices to the content of
the law. But, once again, this is simply a way of expressing the requirement that something must
supplement the law practices if the constitutive determinants are to provide reasons for the legal facts.
If the law practices and the normative facts together provide the requisite reasons for the legal facts,
the rational-relation requirement is satisfied.
⁵⁸ For a sketch of this picture of normative facts, see Greenberg, On Practices and the Law, supra
note 1, section IV.
Hartian Positivism and Normative Facts: How Facts Make Law II 289
to intuitions about what law is. It has been independently defended on the ground
that normative facts are the best candidate for what is needed in addition to law
practices to satisfy the rational-relation requirement. As pointed out above, we
should be skeptical of the reliability of thought experiments about what sorts of
legal systems are possible, especially in light of my all-or-nothing result. I have
used the rational-relation requirement to argue against a Hartian account. In the
face of this argument, thought experiments get no traction.
VII. Conclusion
In this paper, I have argued that normative facts and law practices together are bet-
ter placed to satisfy the rational-relation requirement than law practices alone,
including facts about officials’ Hartian dispositions. Normative facts about the
relevance of law practices to legal facts provide reasons why law practices have a
particular impact on the law, and facts about Hartian dispositions do not. That
law practices should have a particular impact on the content of the law makes
rationally intelligible that law practices do have that impact. For instance, that it is
fair for judicial decisions to have a certain precedential force is a reason why those
decisions in fact have that force. The mere fact that officials are disposed to give
decisions a certain precedential force does not by itself constitute such a reason.
Adding a purported truth about law, or bridge principle, to the effect that
certain attitudes and dispositions of officials have a certain bearing on which
model is legally correct does not help. If the officials’ attitudes and dispositions
do not provide reasons for the legal facts, the bridge principle is itself just a brute
fact about law.
By contrast, normative facts avoid the need to appeal to brute facts about law.
With law practices, they provide reasons for the legal facts. That it is fair or demo-
cratic for statutes or judicial decisions to have a particular impact on the law, com-
bined with facts about the particular statutes and judicial decisions of a legal
system, can explain the legal facts. We can sum up in an intuitive way by saying
that normative facts explain the relevance of the law practices to the legal facts. But
there is no further requirement to explain why the normative facts explain the rele-
vance of the law practices to the content of the law. Strictly speaking, the rational-
relation requirement demands only that the constitutive determinants provide
reasons for the legal facts.
Along the way, I argued that the rational-relation requirement yields the relatively
immediate result that, at the most basic level, legal systems cannot vary with respect
to what determines the relevance of law practices to the content of the law. The most
basic principles about the relevance of law practices to legal facts—the ones that do
not depend on law practices—must be true in all possible legal systems. One can
accept this result even if one rejects other parts of my argument for the conclusion
that normative facts must figure in a constitutive account of legal facts.
290 Mark Greenberg
The result has a variety of implications. It implies, for example, that our
convictions about what kinds of legal systems are possible cannot all be correct.
It therefore should make us dubious about the reliability of such convictions.
I mentioned that the result undermines the familiar claim that because Dworkin’s
arguments depend on properties of the U.S. and U.K. legal systems, those argu-
ments cannot show that Hartian legal systems are not possible. Of course, the
result is a double-edged sword. For example, an argument for the proposition that
one legal system is Hartian supports the conclusion that all possible legal systems
are Hartian.
Response
Ronald Dworkin
There is not space for a detailed comment on all of the essays in this collection so I
concentrate on replying to arguments that challenge the views l have defended
and say much less about essays that elaborate and deepen those views. This
response is therefore very unbalanced, devoting much space to some authors and
little to others, but I hope it is not necessary to say that the imbalance does not
reflect any opinion about the relative importance of the essays. The essays with
which I mainly agree and therefore comment on little stand on their own, and are
each an important contribution to legal theory. I am grateful for all the essays, and
grateful particularly to Scott Hershovitz for his exemplary choice of writers
and his imaginative editing. Justice Breyer’s introduction to this collection is also
an important contribution to its themes: I am very grateful for his remarks and
welcome them as a brief account of his own constitutional philosophy.¹
Eisgruber
Eisgruber believes, however, that my own concern with the virtue of integrity in
legislation as well as adjudication counts against my very broad reading of certain
provisions of our own Constitution: in particular the equal protection and due
process clauses. He suggests that I would have given more effect to the value of
integrity by reading these clauses to enjoin fidelity not to equality and fairness in
the abstract but rather to “traditional American principles of equality and fair-
ness.” These are different instructions, he believes, because the latter requires
respect for the actual practices of American history and so would give history a
much more important role than I seem to allow it. I disagree: I think that the latter
instruction would not encourage but subvert integrity. Indeed it would provide
only what I have called bare consistency which I have argued is very different from
integrity.⁴
Integrity requires coherence in moral principle and coherence is especially
important in constitution-making when the moral principles in play are funda-
mental. Integrity commands that the nation speak with one voice on such import-
ant matters of principle, and it therefore demands that when its historical
practices—of racial segregation, for instance—cannot be seen to be consistent
with principles elsewhere recognized, those practices must be abandoned. Respect
for settled practices has often been urged as a ground for constitutional decisions:
that was the basis of the Supreme Court’s decision upholding Georgia’s ban on
homosexual sodomy in Bowers v. Hardiwick.⁵ But the Court has since declared for
integrity over settled practice: it has overruled its Bowers decision.⁶ Constitution-
makers can provide integrity in their constitutional protections only by mandat-
ing a moral test that allows the community to identify the principles to which it
takes itself to be committed even when it recognizes that it has not kept faith with
those principles in the past.
In any case, Eisgruber says, my account of constitutional interpretation
remains incomplete because I have not given a basis for the moral reading in a
more general theory that explains why a nation should embed certain constraints
in a constitutional document that can only be amended by a super-majority with
super dedication. I meant to offer such a theory in Chapter 1 of Freedom’s Law,
however. I said that that device creates and protects the right kind of democracy. I
distinguished between a majoritarian and what I there called a “constitutional”
conception of democracy;⁷ I argued for the latter and offered that better concep-
tion as part of a justification for the moral reading. So I agree with at least a sub-
stantial part of the justification for constitutional protection that Eisgruber
himself has advanced, which he summarizes in his present essay in these words:
“More specifically, I argue that democracy differs from pure majoritarianism, so
⁴ See R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire 219–224 (1988). ⁵ 487 U.S. 186 (1986).
⁶ Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003).
⁷ I have called the latter a “partnership” conception of democracy in both earlier and later writing.
See R. Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality ch. 10 (2000).
Response 293
that democracy requires solicitude for the rights and interests of minorities as well
as majorities.”⁸ I hope I am right in supposing that we agree not only on the need
for a constitutional justification of the kind he describes but also on at least the
general form that such a justification should take.
Fleming
⁸ Eisgruber, 20.
294 Ronald Dworkin
must confront a crucial distinction between two kinds of intentions that history may
uncover: the semantic intentions of the “framers” who wrote and enacted constitu-
tional provisions—what they intended to say in using the words they used—and their
expectation intentions—what they hoped or expected would be the impact those
words would have on constitutional law in concrete cases.
Chief Justice Roberts insisted on the importance of that distinction in his
Senate confirmation hearings,⁹ and Professor Eisgruber emphasizes it in his con-
tribution to this volume. I have myself insisted on the decisive importance of
semantic originalism: it seems crucial to discover what the framers meant to say
because that determines what propositions the Constitution expresses. History is
of course at the center of that investigation as Eisgruber says. But expectation orig-
inalism is a different matter. If the best interpretive reconstruction of the framers’
semantic intention concludes that they laid down abstract moral principles rather
than their own understandings of what those principles require in concrete cases,
then expectation originalism, whether narrow or broad, is beside the point. I agree
that my arguments for that conclusion about semantic intention are rough and
might be improved by more careful attention to historical sources, though I also
bear in mind Justice Jackson’s skepticism on that score. Finally, Fleming’s advice to
“Do as Dworkin says not as Dworkin does” sounds to me very good advice.
Brown
Professor Brown is much too generous in assigning me credit for the enormous
improvement in constitutional theory and law that followed the Supreme Court’s
decision in the Brown case. But she has nevertheless written an elegant and dra-
matic history of that development and in that way contributed to the intellectual
as well as legal history of the period. I hope her own faith can be sustained even if,
as many fear, the Supreme Court soon leads lawyers through a period of regres-
sion. There must be another renaissance of constitutional law around another
corner and her spirit will be necessary to its success.
Hurley
⁹ See my article, Judge Roberts on Trial, 52:16 New York Review of Books 14 (October 20,
2005).
Response 295
case would be settled one way or another sharply limits the eligibility of
interpretive claims that fit actual settled cases but do not fit what “goes without say-
ing” in that hypothetical case. She uses this insight to deepen the problem posed for
integrity by Kenneth Kress.
She also responds effectively to that problem. Kress pointed out that independ-
ent judicial decisions that are made between the time of events that give rise to a
legal dispute and the judicial resolution of that dispute may affect what resolution
is then appropriate. He fears that this phenomenon might produce retrospective
application of new law: the intervening decision may change the law so that the
dispute is adjudicated under a different legal structure from the structure in which
the parties acted. Hurley points out that this can happen, as a result purely of an
intervening decision, only when that intervening decision is mistaken, and she
adds that it is hardly surprising that a mistaken decision results in retrospective
application of new law. That is what happens in the mistaken decision itself and
Kress has only pointed out that the mischief is not confined to that decision but
infects even a few later decisions that are, in themselves, correct. It is worth pointing
out, however, that this later mischief will be avoided if the intervening decision is
very mistaken: sufficiently mistaken that it can be labeled a mistake in the sense
I described in Taking Rights Seriously.¹⁰ Mistakes of that character have no gravita-
tional force in future decisions.
Hershovitz
because political power is more equal when a majority accepts that what it
provides for itself it must provide for all.
Smith
Professor Smith has constructed a very careful and challenging review of my ideas
about integrity and his review prompts me to correct an important misstatement
in my book, Law’s Empire. I agree substantially with his conclusions about how to
understand my complaint about checkerboard statutes, though I would formulate
the principles in play somewhat differently than he does. He identifies two dis-
tinct principles of integrity: one condemns checkerboard statutes and the other
requires coherence among the different departments of a community’s law. He
thinks it “obvious” that these are different principles, so that my defense of one has
no consequences for the other.¹¹ I think, on the contrary, that only a single princi-
ple is needed. I discuss checkerboard statutes (which are very rare) only to illus-
trate what I thought to be an obvious way of infringing a general principle of
coherence. If law must be coherent over great stretches of doctrine, it must surely
be coherent within a single statute; if law need not be coherent across doctrine,
then why need it be coherent even within a single statute?
Smith also thinks that the best statement of my view about checkerboard
statutes requires a distinction between two distinct charges: first, that such statutes
unjustly discriminate and, second, that the discrimination cannot be justified by
appealing to any “recognizable” principle of justice. Once again I would prefer a
single ideal: integrity requires that the community’s law be justifiable through a
coherent scheme of principle that provides an eligible interpretation of that law.
The idea of justification does indeed presuppose that only some explanations can
justify. But an adequate justification of a community’s political record also presup-
poses not just a “recognizable” principle but one that would be recognized as a
moral principle there, so that it could make sense to attribute that principle to its
law-makers. There might be communities organized around astrological princi-
ples whose citizens believe that the oddness or evenness of the year of one’s birth
carries the moral significance that for many of us is carried by rape or danger to a
mother’s health. But the fact that that would be “recognizable” as moral in some
communities hardly makes it eligible as a justification for us.
Smith believes that I have failed to show why integrity, understood as he
describes, should characteristically “trump” other political virtues in legislation
and adjudication. He notes, first, a frequent objection to my claim that it should:
that a community should not adopt an ideal that entails more discrete instances of
injustice. I have frequently replied to that objection. There is no reason to think
that requiring judges to seek integrity rather than justice in individual cases will in
¹¹ Smith, 149.
Response 297
fact produce more discrete unjust decisions in the long run.¹² Smith mainly
focuses on another political virtue, however: fairness. He asks why a checkerboard
statute, like a statute forbidding abortion only for women born in odd-numbered
years, could not be defended as improving political fairness even though it dis-
criminates among women in a way that cannot be justified by any moral principle.
Why should fairness be subordinated to integrity in the way I seem to suppose? I
argue that a political community is not legitimate unless it shows equal concern
for all its members, and that integrity in the community’s laws is essential to that
equal concern.¹³ But, Smith asks, why is fairness, which is the equal distribution
of political power, not also a requirement of equal concern? If it is, why is integrity
a more important requirement of equal concern than fairness?
These are important questions, and they call for the correction I mentioned.
But I will first say how I have answered them in books and articles other than Law’s
Empire. We must try to understand the various central political virtues, like jus-
tice, equality, liberty, political fairness, democracy and integrity, holistically so
that our account of each can be seen to be drawn from and reinforced by the
others.¹⁴ We can describe the concept of procedural fairness in politics in a very
abstract way as I did in Law’s Empire: fairness, I said, “is a matter of finding politi-
cal procedures—methods of electing officials and making their decisions respon-
sive to the electorate—that distribute political power in the right way.”¹⁵ But we
must then establish what “the right way” is. I argue that what political fairness
requires is not either equality of impact or equality of influence but rather a struc-
ture in which no one is denied vote or voice for impermissible reasons.¹⁶ So, once
that strict requirement is satisfied, political power should be distributed with an
eye to other values. In matters of policy, like decisions about where roads or air-
ports should be built, for instance, it is desirable that benefits and burdens should
be spread across the whole community in proportion to numbers and needs. So a
majoritarian decision procedure, in which compromises among interests are facili-
tated, is appropriate provided that that test of fairness is also met. In matters of
principle no such requirement holds, and fairness offers no objection to other
decision procedures including properly constructed judicial forums.¹⁷
¹² See my reply to Joseph Raz’s version of the objection in Dworkin and his Critics 383
(J. Burley ed., 2004).
¹³ I should say that Smith states my argument in what I take to be an odd way. He says that
integrity is needed so that law can be pervasive, that is, so that law can be extrapolated from recog-
nized explicit doctrine to cover cases unforeseen in that explicit doctrine. I think this puts the point
backwards: we need a legal culture in which law is extrapolated in that way in order to secure integrity
and equal concern.
¹⁴ See my article, Hart’s Postscript and the Character of Political Philosophy, 24 Oxford Journal of
Legal Studies 1 (2004), reprinted in R. Dworkin, Justice in Robes ch 6. (forthcoming 2006).
¹⁵ Law’s Empire, supra note 4, at 164.
¹⁶ See Sovereign Virtue, supra note 7, at chs 4 and 10. See also Freedom’s Law, supra note 2,
at Introduction.
¹⁷ I introduced the distinction between principle and policy in my earlier book, Taking Rights
Seriously, and explored the implications of the distinction for political fairness in several chapters of
that book.
298 Ronald Dworkin
Smith undertook to study only the arguments of Law’s Empire and I cite other
work, published before and after that book, not to criticize his essay but simply to
help in responding to the difficulties he raises. The overall structure and central
arguments of Law’s Empire are drawn from the more general arguments elaborated
in that other work. I emphasized in that book that integrity has no application to
matters of policy, for instance.¹⁸ But some of my remarks in Law’s Empire were
wrong and misleading. I said:
What is the special defect we find in checkerboard solutions? It cannot be a failure in fair-
ness (in our sense of a fair distribution of political power) because checkerboard laws are by
hypothesis fairer than either of the two alternatives. Allowing each of the two groups to
choose some part of the law of abortion, in proportion to their numbers, is fairer (in our
sense) than the winner-take-all scheme our instincts prefer, which denies many people any
influence at all over an issue they think desperately important.¹⁹
I made these remarks to show that integrity, which condemns checkerboard
statutes, is a political virtue distinct from political fairness. I could and should
have said only that fairness provides no argument against checkerboard statutes.
Since nothing in the way in which the checkerboard abortion law I imagined is
produced is necessarily unfair, we cannot explain our rejection of such laws by
appealing to political fairness. It was unnecessary for me to add the further, mis-
taken claim that fairness properly understood is advanced by such a statute or that
integrity and fairness so understood conflict. My argument for recognizing
integrity as a distinct virtue is in no way weakened by withdrawing that claim. I
am grateful to Smith for helping me to see and correct this mistake. But once the
mistake is corrected, and the argument of Law’s Empire made fully coherent with
my more general arguments in that book and elsewhere, his challenges to integrity
are all met.
Waldron
Jeremy Waldron has long been among the most astute legal philosophers. I am
grateful for his illuminating discussion here of what some writers have claimed to
be an important difference between my “early” and “later” suggestions about the
structure of law and legal reasoning. They believe that Hart and other positivists
answered my early arguments but have not so far responded effectively to my later
ones.²⁰ I agree with Waldron that the supposed difference between these two
stages of my work is largely illusory.
In this essay he resurrects a question I thought dead years ago. There is a radically
skeptical tradition in law: it surfaces cyclically. In the 1970s a group of legal
¹⁸ Law’s Empire, supra note 4, at 221. ¹⁹ Law’s Empire, supra note 4, at 179.
²⁰ I discuss this claim in ch 8 of my book Justice in Robes, supra note 14.
Response 299
theorists whom Waldron calls “Crits” argued, much in the fashion of the legal “real-
ists” of decades earlier, that American and other mature legal systems are fissured
with “contradictions” so that any attempt to discover unifying principles cannot
succeed. I believe that judges should seek integrity in law and Waldron asks
whether I have ever answered the Crits’ claim that this is a pointless search. He cites,
as a powerful example of the Crits’ argument, Duncan Kennedy’s thesis that Anglo-
American law exhibits a deep schizophrenia. There are contradictory altruistic and
individualistic strains in the law, Kennedy says, just as there are in particular peo-
ple’s individual moral commitments, and these cannot be reconciled by any higher
order principle that orders or integrates them. This thesis poses a great danger,
Waldron believes, to my claim that a search for integrity in a political community’s
law is required to carry forward that community’s commitment to equal concern.
He describes this danger as a dilemma. My thesis that judges can construct success-
ful interpretations of their community’s legal practices is plausible only if I suppose
that a justifying scheme of principle—say an altruistic scheme—can count as a suc-
cessful interpretation of a community’s law even though it fits at best only half of
the legal material it claims to interpret. But if I do weaken my account of interpre-
tation in that way, then I can no longer claim that interpretation is a method of
identifying that community commitment of principle.
It is crucial, in assessing this challenge, accurately to describe the kind of con-
tradiction in legal materials that Waldron supposes the Crits to have demon-
strated in, say, American law. Kennedy argues that in different stages of American
legal history one or the other of his two supposedly contradictory strains, individ-
ualism or altruism, was dominant in the American legal culture.²¹ As we shall see,
it is unclear what that claim means. But in any case no contradiction between
what the law permits or requires in different historical stages of a community’s cul-
ture can pose any difficulty for a contemporary judge seeking integrity within
contemporary law. A judge may find integrity across the law that the community
now enforces even though that law is strikingly different from what was enforced a
century or more earlier. So Waldron must suppose that the Crits have established
more than an historical claim: that they have shown contradiction in the
American community’s contemporary legal practice. But Waldron offers no
examples at all of the conflicts he supposes endemic in that practice—perhaps he
thinks conflict so apparent that no examples are needed—so we must construct
our own example.
A judge must decide whether a defendant who broke a contract may be ordered
to perform as agreed or whether he may be held liable only for the economic dam-
ages the plaintiff actually suffered in consequence of the breach. The judge distin-
guishes two justifying schemes. Scheme A, which he calls an “individualist” scheme,
emphasizes the rationality of permitting “efficient” breaches of contract, that is,
²¹ See D. Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685,
1725ff. (1976) [hereinafter, Kennedy, Form and Substance].
300 Ronald Dworkin
breaches that improve the economic position of the breaching party without
damaging the economic position of the other party. Scheme B, which he calls an
“altruistic” scheme, emphasizes instead the moral importance of people keeping
their promises. Now distinguish between two kinds of interpretive situation the
judge might confront. He might find, first, that both schemes “fit” all the perti-
nent precedent cases in his jurisdiction in the following sense: a judge guided by
either Scheme A or Scheme B would have declared exactly the verdicts, given the
facts in each case, that the judges actually declared in all the precedent cases.
(Perhaps the plaintiff in each of these cases had originally demanded only eco-
nomic damages so that a judge guided by Scheme B would have concluded that
the plaintiff had waived his right that the contract actually be enforced.) So the
judge in the fresh case, in which the plaintiff does demand performance, cannot
say that either the “individualistic” or the “altruistic” scheme fits the legal material
better than the other. He must find some other way to adjudicate between the two
schemes. I shall call this a case of “rival” eligible interpretations.
Or the judge might find, second, that neither Scheme A nor Scheme B fits any
more than one half of the pertinent precedent cases in his jurisdiction. The plain-
tiff had demanded specific performance in all the cases: in half that demand was
denied, in half it was sustained, and there were no pertinent differences in the facts
of any of these cases that made it distinguishable from the judge’s new case. Since a
scheme of principle cannot be said to represent a commitment of the community
if it was rejected in as many cases as it was accepted, neither scheme provides
integrity and the judge must find some other basis for his decision. I shall call this
a case of “no” eligible interpretation.
Waldron does not suggest, as I read his essay, that integrity would be a false goal
if American law were shot through with rival-eligible-interpretation situations.
He is explicit that it is no-eligible-interpretation situations that he had in mind:
the schematic structure of conflict he offers as paradigm is explicitly such a case. I
agree that if no-eligible-interpretation situations were systemic in American law
the pursuit of integrity there would be silly. But as I said, Waldron offers no exam-
ples to support his supposition that this situation is pervasive in American law. He
apparently relies on Kennedy to support the supposition, but his reliance is very
much misplaced because, so far as I can see, Kennedy does not even claim, let
alone try to illustrate, an endemic no-eligible-interpretation situation in
American law. He does not claim even a single case of such a situation.
Kennedy says that “individualism” and “altruism” are rival ideologies that can-
not be combined in a rational overall scheme that combines elements of both. He
agrees that most people have elements of each in their moral personalities, but he
suggests that this produces not any kind of amalgamation of the two but only a
moral schizophrenia within us all. These are very implausible claims and
Kennedy’s account of the two values does not sustain them. He believes that
“liberals” are dominated by “individualism” and “communitarians” by altruism.
Contemporary political philosophy shows his mistake. Utilitarianism is the most
Response 301
altruistic of influential political theories: it supposes that people have a basic duty
to count the welfare of others as equally important to their own welfare in identi-
fying moral and political principles. But it has provided the impetus for political
ideologies, including some forms of economic rationality, that Kennedy counts as
“individualistic” instead. More explicitly liberal political theories insist on indi-
vidual rights to liberty that communitarians reject but also insist on egalitarian
goals that communitarians also reject.²² These various accounts of justice claim to
do what Kennedy declares impossible: they offer a principled basis for recognizing
both individual rights and shared obligations of economic social justice not as
some Procrustean compromise but as flowing from more basic ideals of liberty
and equality. Nothing in Kennedy’s writings offers to show that the more sophisti-
cated integration of those values fails.Waldron is right that Critical Legal Studies
is now, as he puts it, “moribund.” That is in good part because its claimed founda-
tions in philosophy proved to be very fragile indeed.
We may put that broad criticism aside now, however, and assume that
Kennedy’s account of individualism and altruism as two wholly incompatible
mind-sets is persuasive. We must then notice that he claims, explicitly and repeat-
edly, that each of the two ideologies could justify almost all of the law in the sense
I indicated earlier: law-makers moved even wholly by one or the other might have
produced the very law that we have. Here are representative qualifications of his
claim that the ideologies he names clash:
When we set out to analyze an action, and especially a judicial opinion, it is only rarely pos-
sible to make a direct inference from the rhetoric employed to the real motives or ideals
that animate the judge. And it is even harder to characterize outcomes than it is personal-
ities or opinions. It will almost always be possible to argue that, if we look hard at its actual
effects on significant aspects of the real world, a particular decision will further both altru-
ist and individualist values, or neither. I will therefore avoid talking about “altruistic out-
comes” as much as possible.²³
Although individualism and altruism can be reduced neither to facts nor to logic,
although they cannot be used with any degree of consistency to characterize personalities or
opinions or the outcomes of lawsuits, they may nevertheless be helpful to this enterprise.²⁴
What enterprise? That is very far from clear, but here is Kennedy’s direct answer.
“The ultimate goal is to break down the sense that legal argument is autonomous
from moral, economic, and political discourse in general.”²⁵ I don’t know who
ever had that “sense”; I doubt Waldron means to suggest that I do.
So Waldron is wrong to appeal to Kennedy to support his own claim that con-
temporary American law is shot through with no-eligible-interpretation conflicts.
Kennedy argues at most that it is shot through with rival-eligible-interpretation
conflicts: that each body of law can be seen as representing the dominance of one
²² See, e.g., J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971), and my book, Sovereign Virtue, supra
note 7. ²³ Kennedy, Form and Substance, at 1723.
²⁴ Kennedy, Form and Substance, at 1724. ²⁵ Id.
302 Ronald Dworkin
or the other of his two ideologies. I would reject that latter claim—it is plainly
flawed if, as I believe, Kennedy has failed to state any ideology that could justify
any decision at all. But I need not pursue that claim because, as I said, Waldron
does not suppose that rival-eligible-conflict would produce the dilemma he poses
for integrity.
How might he show that no-eligible-interpretation is pervasive? He accepts that
any statement that the law is shot through with contradiction must be the product
of—not something antecedent to—interpretation. What interpretive strategy could
yield that formidable result? In my illustration I supposed that the no-eligible-
interpretation requires showing that Schemes A and B each fit no more that half
the interpretive data of past judicial decisions in the sense I described. A law-
maker guided by either would impose the verdict of only those past decisions,
given the facts the precedents presented, and would reject the verdict of the other
half. That seems very unlikely in any jurisdiction with even a weak system of
precedent: at least sufficiently unlikely to call for some examples to show that it is
nevertheless the case. Any appellate decision holding that specific performance
may not be ordered in a certain type of contract case would overrule and remove
from the interpretive data set previous cases of that type ordering that remedy.
It may be, however, that Waldron contemplates a less dramatic kind of no-eligible-
interpretation conflict. He may have in mind a situation in which only Scheme A
fits in that way a settled practice of denying specific performance in contract cases
but only Scheme B fits a settled practice of allowing punitive damages in breach of
contract cases. That is also very unlikely, however, because contradiction between
doctrine in areas of law so closely interconnected would almost certainly also be
eroded by the practices of precedent and academic criticism and restatement.
Perhaps Waldron has in mind conflict between areas of law much more widely
separated: that contract law is inconsistent with Scheme A but tort law is inconsis-
tent with any denial of Scheme A, for instance. But once again that would need
careful illustration. It would also require making good a very ambitious claim:
that no theory of why tort and contract should differ can justify that doctrinal
distinction between the two domains.
Of course I cannot demonstrate that no conflicts of these kinds can be found. I
must await actual supposed examples. However, Waldron adopts an entirely differ-
ent strategy than I just described: he offers to show that no-eligible-interpretation
situations are more common than I suppose not by widening the areas of doctrine
that an interpretation is asked to justify but by widening the data set that an inter-
pretation must confront within each area. He says that a scheme of principle is
not a successful interpretation of a single past judicial decision, even if a law-
maker guided by that scheme would have ordered exactly the verdict it imposed
on the facts it presented, unless the scheme also fits the reasoning of the judge’s
opinion that accompanied the decision. Even if all the precedent cases refused to
award specific performance as a contract remedy, Scheme A would fit only those
decisions accompanied by opinions in which a judge declared principles that the
Response 303
²⁶ Waldron, 170.
²⁷ See, e.g., Law’s Empire, supra note 4, at 247–248, 284–285; Taking Rights Seriously, supra
note 10, at chapter 4. ²⁸ 217 N.Y. 382 (1916).
304 Ronald Dworkin
long ago, there is nothing in what they once said for me to answer. We cannot
be sure, before we look, that constructive interpretation can produce integrity in
any particular area of the law. But we have no reason to think, in advance, that
it cannot.
I should comment on one further aspect of Waldron’s argument. He imagines
that if I were persuaded that no-eligible-interpretation situations are pervasive in
law, I would try to rescue the idea of integrity from that debacle by proposing that
judges should choose between rival eligible interpretations by adopting the inter-
pretation that best matches their own moral convictions. He says that that strategy
would not provide integrity; rather, it would concede that there was no integrity
to find. I agree with his conclusion that no-eligible-interpretation cases imperil
integrity, as I said. But one objection he makes to the strategy is odd and would
also apply to my claim that judges should prefer the morally better interpretation
in rival-eligible-interpretation cases.
He says that judges who choose what they regard as the morally best result are
only taking sides between parties who themselves disagree about exactly which
result is morally best. I hope it is clear, in spite of some of what Waldron says, that
in recommending that judges choose on moral grounds I am not assuming that
their choice is right because it matches their own convictions. Of course it does.
But a choice is right only when—and then only because—those convictions are
themselves right. It is nevertheless true, of course, that in choosing they are taking
sides about the issue in controversy. How can they not do that? When the law is
unclear the judge must in the end take sides about the very issue that divides the
litigants: they disagree about what the law requires. Presumably that fact furnishes
no objection to the institution of adjudication. In my view what the law is
depends, in some cases, on what morality requires. So in taking sides on the for-
mer issue, which he must do, a judge necessarily takes sides on the latter as well.
Perry
I agree, of course, that normative conditions must be met in order that associa-
tive obligations be genuine. People do not have obligations of family, friendship or
political responsibility whenever or just because they or their friends, family or fel-
low citizens think they do: the conditions of special and equal concern that I
described and that Perry reviews must be met. But these may be met without sup-
posing that the practice they structure itself has intrinsic value. Perry suggests that
my statement of these conditions needs revision because they are not all met even
in all the circumstances in which he and I agree that associative obligations arise. I
argue, for instance, that the mutual concern that sponsors genuine associative
obligations must be both personal and equal; he doubts that these conditions are
met in the case of political obligation.
“A general obligation to obey the law,” Perry says, “is usually thought to be owed,
if to anyone, to the community or state itself rather than to one’s fellow citizens
considered one by one.”²⁹ My own view is different, however. I believe that the
duty is owed not to the collective entity but to its members as individuals. Of
course the duty is enforced by a collective entity: it is that state that prosecutes (or,
indeed, waives) the duty. But the state acts, in this instance as well as all others, as
the agent of the citizens acting through it. The legislation that establishes particular
political obligations in a democracy is the creation of the citizens in the same way
and it is a condition of ideal democratic legitimacy, in my view, that what these citi-
zens do collectively can be justified as showing equal concern by each for each.
Perry also doubts that the concern that grounds obligations of family is always
equal concern. Consider, he suggests, the obligation a parent owes to a new-born
child. Perhaps that child will in due course acquire an obligation to care for his
parent, but the parent’s immediate obligation is nevertheless independent of any
prediction that the child will accept that responsibility. But the needed equality of
concern is only a background assumption of the practice, not a condition whose
realization can be demonstrated in every moment of the relationship. If a respon-
sible adult makes plain his rejection of any concern for his parents, or for the other
members of the family, their associative obligations to him are at least attenuated
and, if the rejection is sufficiently decisive, ended.
Gardner
²⁹ Perry, 191.
306 Ronald Dworkin
after all. But I do not understand his argument for that arresting claim any more
than I understand anything else.
My trouble begins—and perhaps ends—with Gardner’s breathtakingly
promiscuous personifications of law in all his Greek-letter propositions. He
spends much of his essay considering whether I embrace the proposition he labels
(␣): “Law aims to be morally justified”. He notices that I have objected to the
argumentative use some legal philosophers make of personification.³⁰ For exam-
ple, I do not think that Joseph Raz’s statement that the law necessarily claims
moral authority can be unpacked without making the resulting statement either
plainly false or incompatible with Raz’s positivist claims.³¹ Gardner labels Raz’s
statement () and defends it, so we should pause over his defense before returning
to the mysteries of (␣). Gardner says that Raz means only that there is no law in a
community unless its legal officials claim moral authority for their decisions. I
anticipated this reading of Raz, and said that it cannot seriously be thought that
whether or not law exists in a particular community depends on the meta-ethical
or moral opinions of its officials. Suppose, I asked, the bulk of a community’s offi-
cials hold the moral views of Oliver Wendell Holmes? Gardner does not accept
this counterexample. He concedes that Holmes’ “extrajudicial” writings express
the view I describe, and he does not cite any judicial writings in which Holmes
states any contradictory view. But he asks a series of questions about Holmes’ atti-
tudes, expecting the answer “yes.” In fact, the best answer to all these questions,
taken to be questions about the historical Holmes, is very probably “no.” But only
one question counts: since Holmes was deeply skeptical of the very idea of moral
authority, he would have denied that his judicial opinions have moral authority.
In any case, to rescue Raz, Gardner would need to claim not only that I am
wrong about Holmes but that there would not be law in America if most judges
came to hold the meta-ethical opinions I ascribed to Holmes, and the implausibil-
ity of that suggestion remains. A group of South African judges met in a clandes-
tine conference with officials of the then illegal African National Congress in
Britain in the last years of apartheid: these judges made plain that they did not
think the law they administered daily had any moral authority. Would Raz or
Gardner think that these judges were not legal officials, or that if a great many
other South African judges shared their opinion there was no law there?
Gardner’s discussion of Raz’s claim is mysterious for a further reason, moreover.
He says that although Raz means that legal officials claim moral authority his per-
sonification is not to be understood as an elliptical statement exhausted by that
fact. Though he agrees with me that “it takes a human being to make a moral
claim” he adds that “it does not follow that human beings are the only things that
³⁰ I am guilty, I know, of personifying law and much else in the titles of books and articles. I doubt
this non-argumentative and harmless personification has played any part in the spate of argumenta-
tive personification now popular, but I apologize if it has. I believe that the personifications that figure
in my own arguments can all easily be dissolved.
³¹ See supra note 14, Justice in Robes, chapter 7.
Response 307
make claims. Law makes claims through human beings acting on its behalf.” This
statement ruins any proposed redemption of Raz’s troublesome personification
because it simply invokes the personification all over again. Gardner uses “law”
presumably to refer either to a set of social practices or to a set of norms of some
kind. How can either have a “behalf ”? Is Hegel waiting in the wings? Or is there
some further dissolution of that further personification that allows Gardner’s
claim to make sense? Shall we say that it means only that legal officials claim that
legal requirements (rather than those of some other institution) have moral
authority? Then Gardner’s further elaboration of Raz’s claim is simply redundant.
So I remain perplexed what anyone could think () means who supposes that it
is true. I have exactly the same problems with Gardner’s (␣). What can it mean to
say that law aims to be morally justified? I have argued, in Law’s Empire and else-
where, that the concept of law is an interpretive concept, and that lawyers must
therefore identify what the law requires or permits on some matter through a
process of interpretation that seeks the best available moral justification of the
broad legal practices of their community.³² Is (␣) a baroque way of saying the
same thing? If so, then of course I accept it. But I doubt that is what Gardner takes
(␣) to mean, because he says that (␣) is entailed by my suggestion that interpreters
might sensibly take the practice they are interpreting to have, as its goal, the
appropriate regulation of the use of coercive force by the state. I emphasize,
throughout Law’s Empire and elsewhere, that interpreters who begin in that way
may sensibly, and certainly without contradiction, adopt very different, more
detailed theories of legal interpretation from my own, including a theory very like
legal positivism.³³ Should we understand (␣) instead in something of the same
way Gardner wants us to understand (), leaving out the Hegel? Then we would
have to say that legal officials all reason about what the law is in the way I recom-
mend, which is undoubtedly false, or that they are not really legal officials unless
they reason in the way I recommend, which is tempting but I fear overreaching. I
cannot assign any sense to (␣) that fits what Gardner says about its implications
and that is in the least plausible, so I am not surprised that he makes such heavy
weather of deciding whether I believe that proposition or not.
What shall we make of Gardner’s further proposition (␥): “Law is morally justi-
fied”? Does that statement claim that every true proposition of law is morally jus-
tified? If so, it is puzzling why Gardner would spend any space pondering whether
I accept (␥). Of course I don’t. The mystery deepens when he explains that (␥) and
(␣) contradict one another. His explanation assumes that (␥) means that law is not
just always justified but is necessarily justified, so that the contradiction is like the
contradiction some (but not all) theologians find in the proposition that God
aims to be moral and necessarily is moral. How can one aim to be what one neces-
sarily is? In fact there is no contradiction here if, as Gardner suggests, (␣) includes
³² This is only a very rough summary of my account of legal reasoning. For a recent fuller state-
ment, see the Introduction to my recent book, Justice in Robes, supra note 14.
³³ Id. at chapter 8.
308 Ronald Dworkin
the proposition that no one is a legal official unless he aims at morally justified law.
Then the conjunction would mean that those who are legal officials, because they
aim to produce justified law, necessarily do produce justified law, which is not a
contradiction though it is of course very silly. So either (␣) or (␥) must mean
something different from what first appears if they are to be, as Gardner insists
they are, incompatible. There may be some sense of (␥) such that it is a genuine
interpretive question whether I accept it. But I have no idea what that is. In any
case, however, my remarks about Nazis, which Gardner quotes, have nothing to
do with (␥).³⁴ I was explaining how we should understand someone who says that
the Nazis had no law: we should understand him as denying that their legal
arrangements were such as to justify coercion. The undoubted fact that some
people sometimes use the sociological concept of law to carry that moral freight
doesn’t entail that true propositions of law are always or inevitably morally justi-
fied. I believe that reading the entire section of Law’s Empire from which Gardner
takes his quotation makes that plain.³⁵
Now we come to the supposedly most consequential of the Greek-letter
propositions:
(␦) In any legal system, the law is made up of norms which are part of the law
only because some legal official engaged with them, and such an agent is a
legal official only because, by engaging with norms in certain ways, he or she
can make them part of the law.
I assume that (␦) is meant to state a version of legal positivism.³⁶ If (␦) is right, I
assume, then the proposition that a plaintiff who cannot prove which manufac-
turer made the drugs that injured her is entitled to market-share damages from
them all is false unless and until some judge so rules, because only then has an offi-
cial “engaged” with that proposition in an appropriate way.³⁷ So when a judge
does declare that proposition, and does award market-share damages, his decision
cannot be seen as applying the law but must be treated as making up new law
through his “engagement” and applying it retroactively. That is a familiar view
among lawyers who call themselves positivists: it is no doubt Gardner’s own view.
I have argued against it steadily over three decades, repeating my rejection in a
great variety of recent publications some of which Gardner cites. Gardner’s claim
that I actually embrace that view is therefore indeed “striking.”³⁸
³⁴ Gardner, 217.
³⁵ See also the Introduction to Justice in Robes supra note 14. I there distinguish the sociological
concept of law which someone uses when he denies that the Nazis had law from the doctrinal concept
which Law’s Empire mainly explores.
³⁶ In any case, the formulation plainly needs tidying in various ways. We need to know more
about what “engaging” is and we need to take account of the fact that many people—district attor-
neys, for instance—are legal officials even though no amount of “engaging” by them makes law.
Presumably Gardner has or will remedy these obvious defects and I shall ignore them.
³⁷ See my description of “Sorenson’s Case” in Hart’s Postscript and the Character of Political
Philosophy, supra note 14. ³⁸ Gardner, 220.
Response 309
coercion so that no set of practices that cannot plausibly be said to serve that aim
could count as “law.” But I was talking about strategies of legal interpretation and
therefore about interpreters. I said that it would be helpful if a view about the
“point” of law were sufficiently widely accepted in a community so that, as I put it,
interpretive arguments could take place “on the plateau it furnishes” and proceed
by contrasting different conceptions of how that point is best understood and
achieved.⁴² I did not say that amenability to that interpretive strategy is a concep-
tual necessity so that anyone who rejected it would make a conceptual mistake.
On the contrary I conceded that there are “theories that challenge rather than
elaborate the connection [my suggestion] assumes between law and the justifica-
tion of coercion.”
I certainly did not say, as Gardner apparently believes I did, that this interpre-
tive strategy would be appropriate everywhere we find anything we might be
tempted to call law: it would not be appropriate if angels had to interpret God’s
law of angelic duties. Gardner’s misreading is another example of the serious
confusion that has been engendered in legal philosophy by a failure to distinguish
between the sociological and doctrinal concepts of law. We have great leeway in
deciding whether angelic law (or international law or Nazi law) should be called
“law.” The sociological concept of law in play in those questions is an indetermin-
ate criterial concept: we can give either answer so long as we make plain what
point we mean to make. We must not confuse that concept with the doctrinal
concept in play when we ask which interpretive strategies are appropriate to decid-
ing what the law of some community really is.⁴³ My suggestions about the justifi-
cation of coercion are claims about the right strategy in communities of the kind
lawyers are normally called upon to interpret.
Greenberg
In How Facts Make Law, Greenberg argues only for proposition (2), and we
should therefore notice that the most influential contemporary versions of legal
positivism accept (2) and argue only against (1). They argue, for example, that
democracy is better served, or that a political community is more efficient, or that
authority is better respected, or that citizens are more likely to be critical of their
government, if judges accept that moral or other normative claims are not relevant
in deciding what the law requires. In that way these “political” positivists appeal to
“value facts” at what we might call the jurisprudential level of analysis to show the
irrelevance of such facts at the doctrinal level. It is true that some positivists argue
against (1) on what they claim to be purely conceptual grounds that are consistent
with rejecting (2) as well. I agree with Greenberg that these arguments are mys-
terious and in any case fail. But my arguments in Law’s Empire are meant to sup-
port (2) as well as (1).
I should add that I agree with Greenberg’s interpretation of my own views
about the interaction of the dimensions of fit and justification in legal interpreta-
tion.⁴⁵ As I have tried to explain elsewhere, these dimensions are best understood
as each drawn from a political value. I said in Law’s Empire and elsewhere that the
crude “threshold” account of the interaction of the two dimensions was meant
only to illustrate the difference between them.⁴⁶ However, I am uncertain that
Greenberg has located any metaphysical difficulty in that crude account. If we
supposed that two interpretations of the legal record fit that record equally well,
and decided between them on moral grounds, we would not be treating the legal
record as irrelevant to the content of the law. If the record had been different, the
better interpretation might not have been available at all.
⁴⁵ See Greenberg, supra Chapter 10, notes 46 and 47, and pages 262–63.
⁴⁶ See Dworkin and his Critics, supra note 12.
Index
abortion autonomy 29–30, 80–1, 292
checkerboard solutions 121–4, 128–37,
139–41, 249–50, 297 beliefs 252, 269
coherence 133–5 Bill of Rights 52–3, 62
irrelevant considerations 129–33, 135 Brown v. Board of Education 41, 43–6, 48
justice 135–7 criticism of 44–5
law practices and the content of law 249–50 democracy 46
rape victims only, for 129–33, 135–6, equality 63
140–1 judicial review 53
actual settled cases moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
coherence 70–2, 85, 89–96, 98, 100–1 55, 58–9, 294
hypothetical cases, asymmetry between 70, public and private views of 45
91–2, 94 racial segregation 43–5, 55
jurisdictions, cases from other 95–6
mistakes 90, 95, 100–1 certainty, value of 111
state courts, precedents from 95–6 checkerboard solutions, Ronald Dworkin and
stronger requirement 89–90, 93–4, 98 abortion 121–4, 128–37, 139–41, 249–50, 297
weight of 85, 89–90, 93–4, 98 arbitrary distinctions 122, 125–9
altruism 164, 166–70, 174, 181, 299–302 coherence 120–2, 125–6, 133–5, 296
arbitrariness 122, 125–9 compromise 122–3, 127–9, 134, 136–8, 140–2
associative obligations consistency 133
academic colleagues 193, 304 criticism of 125–42
attitudes held by members of group 193 definition 121
commercial partnerships 198, 304 differential treatment 125–6, 139–41,
conditions 188, 190–5, 305 144–8, 296–8
consent 190, 197 equal treatment 139–41
Dworkin, Ronald 176, 178, 190–7, 304–5 fairness 120–5, 128–9, 133, 135–40, 145,
equal concern 191–2, 305 297–8
fairness 188–9 injustice, minimising 123
family relationships 190–4, 198, 304–5 integrity 119–53, 296–7
friendship 190–7, 304–5 interpretation 126–8, 140–2
gender equality 191–2 irrelevant considerations 129–33, 136
instrumental obligations 198 justice 120–5, 133–9, 140–1
integrity 188–9, 198–205 differential treatment 140–1, 296
interpretation 194–7 recognizable principles of 135–9
intrinsic value 195–7, 304–5 justification 125–6, 138, 140–2
Law’s Empire 196 law practices and the content of law 249–50
legal outcomes as 176, 178 Law’s Empire 119–42, 297
meaning 189–90 legislation 121–5
moral obligations 194–5, 197 morality 121–2, 129–33, 135–8
normative conditions 305 political compromise 137
obedience to law 183–9, 191, 194–5, 305 political integrity 119–53
political obligations 183–9, 191, 193–5, preferences 123–4
198–205, 305 principle, matters of 122, 133, 135
practices 194 compromise 122–3
promises 190 conflict between 122
special obligations 189–97, 305 ranking 122
value 195–8, 304–5 recognizable 135–9
assumptions or beliefs 252 rape, abortion only for victims of 129–33,
attitudes and dispositions 271–6, 280–3, 287, 135–7, 140–1
289 religion 138–9
314 Index
checkerboard solutions, precedent 86
Ronald Dworkin and (cont.) punitive/regulatory distinction 96–7
social welfare 122 settled 71–2, 81, 83–4, 90–1, 94–7, 294–5
unreasonable compromises 128 thought experiments, as 81–4
coercion indifference curves 90
justification 188, 217, 308 integrity 88, 98, 133, 143–8, 150, 152,
laws aims in Law’s Empire 208–9, 216–17, 162–5, 171, 175, 178–9, 292
309–10 intervening cases, problem of 84–101
political obligation to obey the law 188, 203 mistake 86, 95, 99–101
coherence, legal reasoning and 69–84 precedent 85–101
abortion 133–5 prospective application 85–7, 93
actual settled cases 71–2 retroactivity and 69–70, 84–9, 92–5,
hypothetical cases, asymmetry between 100–1
70, 91–2, 94 jurisdictions, cases from other 95–6
jurisdictions, cases from other 95–6 justice 133–5
mistakes 90, 95, 100–1 Kress, Kenneth 70, 74, 84–92, 98, 100–1,
state courts, precedents from 95–6 295
stronger requirement 89–90, 93–4, 98 law practices and the content of law 248–9
weight of 85, 89–90, 93–4, 98 law-making 162
alternatives legislation 86, 93, 147
non-reductionism 82 like cases alike, treating 82–4
ranking of 71 mistake 86, 90, 95, 97–101, 295
reasons that apply to the 70–3 model 248–9
background 156 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
checkerboard solutions 120–2, 125–6, 292
133–5, 296 morality 114–16, 292
coherence function 71 non-evaluative acts 82–3
compromise 134 normative role of legal reasoning 82
conservatism 89, 90–2 political integrity 143–8, 150, 292
consistency 81, 88, 89, 133 practical reasoning 69–70, 89
data gathering 71–2 precedent 69–101, 114–16, 118
decision theory 90 actual settled cases, weight given to 85
deliberation discretion 88
abstract characterization of 70–4 fairness 94
deliberative matrix 72–3, 75, 77 hypothetical cases 86
ethical, examples of 74–82 intervening cases 85–101
examples of 74–81 jurisdictions, cases from other 95–6
legal, examples of 74–81 legislation 86
reasons 73 mistake 97–101, 295
stages of 71–2 prospective effect 85–7, 93–4, 97–8
determinacy, assumption of 100 retroactivity 94–101, 295
discretion 88 settled cases 83–94
Dworkin, Ronald 91–2, 133 state courts, decisions of 95–6
intervening cases, problem of 85, 95, stronger requirement 89–90, 93–4, 98
98–101 preferences 90
Law’s Empire 69, 87–8 principles 133, 135, 150, 158
political integrity 143–8, 150, 292 prospective application 85–7, 93–4, 97–8
ethical deliberation 74–82 punitive/regulatory distinction 96–7
extra-judicial developments 92–4 rationality 69
fairness 94, 133, 135 reasons 73
federal statutes, states’ interpretation of 95–6 reflective equilibrium 69
generalizations 81 retroactivity 69–70, 74, 84–9, 92–101, 295
hypothetical cases 70, 294–5 revisionary concept of law 92–4
actual settled cases 70, 91–2, 94 ripple effect 84–5
answers to 84 scientific theories 81–2, 94
generalizations 81 settled cases 83–94
mistake 97 actual 70–2, 85, 89–96, 98, 100–1
Index 315
hypothetical 71–2, 81, 83–4, 90–1, 94–7, Brown v Board of Education 41, 43–6, 48
294–5 democracy 43, 46–8
like cases alike, treating 82–4 Dworkin, Ronald 41–2, 48–56
precedent 83–94 elections 46
weight of actual 85 equality in US Constitution, concept of
settled preferences 90 41–5
social practices, changes in 93 individual rights 46, 48
stare decisis 114–16, 118 legislatures 42, 43
state courts, precedents from 95–6 liberty claims 42–4
thought experiments 81–4 Justices of the Supreme Court
underdetermination 100–1 activism 42
communal obligations see associative liberty claims 41–4
obligations passivity 42
communitarianism 175, 300–2 restraint 48
compromise judicial review 44, 48
checkerboard solutions 122–3, 127–9, legislature, policy-making and 46
134–7, 140–2 majority rule 47, 48
coherence 134 New Deal 43–4
political 137, 142–3, 145, 152 police powers 43
principle, matters of 122 populism 43, 46–7
unreasonable 128 racial segregation 41, 43–5, 47
conservatism 34, 89, 90–2 social change 42–3
consistency constitutions see also constitutional judges,
checkerboard solutions 133 constitutional theory, United States
coherence 81, 88, 89, 133 Constitution
conservatism 89 constitution constructivism 28–9
integrity 15–16 constitutional purposes, importance of
moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s 17–19
50 constitution-perfecting theory 29–30
stare decisis 115 democracy 26–8, 30
United States Constitution 15–16, 50 making 17–19
constitutional judges 1–4 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
activism 42, 54, 59 6, 7
control of 2 super-majoritarianism 17–18
democracy 1–3 constructivism 156–7, 168–70, 173, 175,
Dworkin, Ronald 1–4 177–81
guardian or rights, mistrust of judges as 42 contents of the law see also law-determining
guiding principles, identification of 56 practices and contents of the law,
international human rights crimes 3 relationship between
interpretation 4, 42 context 11
job description 56–7 coordination of conduct for common good
jurisdiction 3 207–12, 215
liberty claims 41–4 counter-majoritarian difficulty 26
minimalism 60 Critical Legal Studies movement, Dworkin’s
moral decisions by judges 1 theory of integrity and 155–81
moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s altruism 164, 166–70, 174, 181, 299–302
50–1, 54, 56–60 associative or communal obligations, legal
objectives, definition of 3 outcomes as 176, 178
passivity 42 background 155–61, 179
personal preferences 50–1 coherence 156, 162–5, 171, 175, 178–9
reason, use of 2–3 communitarianism 175, 300–2
restraint 48, 58 competing principles 166
standards, enforcement of 1–2 conflicting entities in law 163–4, 299
Supreme Court 41–4, 48 constructivism 156–7, 168–70, 173, 175,
constitutional theory 41–67 177–81
Bickel, Alexander The Least Dangerous contradictions 165–6, 171–4, 179–80, 299
Branch 45–7, 53–4 demonstrability 171–2, 180
316 Index
Critical Legal Studies movement, Dworkin’s deliberative matrix 72–3, 75, 77
theory of integrity and (cont.) democracy 27, 28–9
descriptive optimism 155 discrimination 78–9
discrete norms 159 drugs, searches for 75–6
egotistical tendencies 167 Equal Protection Clause 77–9
elitism 162–3 estoppel 74–5
equality and liberty, integration of 301 ethical deliberation
fairness 177 autonomy 80–1
fit 173, 300 examples of 74–81
foreground elements 160–1 lawyers enabling clients to do acts which
fraud, no one should benefit from own 161 are legal but not ethical 80–1
identification of norms 159 examples of 74–81
individual and society 163–4, 166–9 home-vehicle distinction, police powers of
individualism 164, 166–71, 174, 181, search and 75–7
299–303 hypothetical cases 76–80
interpretation 157, 166, 169–72, 175–8, illegitimate children, unmarried fathers and
299–304 78–9
judicial opinions 303 lawyers enabling clients to do acts which are
justice 160, 162, 166–8, 175–7, 181 legal but not ethical 80–1
justification 160 legal, examples of 74–81
law-making 162–3 non-discrimination 78–9
Law’s Empire 156, 160–1, 166, 175, 179 privacy 75–7
legislature 165, 169–70 promissory estoppel 74–5
legislative supremacy 165 reasons 73, 75–8
legitimacy 176–7, 181 search, police powers of 75–7
liberalism 300–2 stages of 71–2
moral theory 166–7, 172, 180, 299–300, democracy
304 Brown v Board of Education 45
no-eligible interpretation conflicts 301–4 conditions for 27–9
norms 161 constitutional democracy 20
phenomenology 172–3 constitutional judges 1–3
policies, principles distinguished from deliberative democracy 27, 28–30
158–60 elections 57–8, 293
positivism 159, 166 equal concern 53, 59, 62
post-interpretive claims 160 equality 26
pragmatism 156, 175–7, 181 judicial review 53
precedent 300, 302–3 justice 53–4
principles 158–61, 166–8, 177 majority rule 1, 2, 26–30, 53–4, 57–9, 61,
skeptics 155–7, 164–72, 177–80, 298–9 292–3
social goals 158 minorities, protection of 58
theories of legal background 155–7 pre-conditions for 28–9
utilitarianism 300–1 procedural liberties 30
culture 33–5 representation 57–9, 61
standards 4
dead hand of the past theory 19–22, 38 substantive liberties 30
decision theory 90 super-majoritarian amendment rules 20, 292
deference, stare decisis and descriptive facts
class, decisions deserving deference as a 107 Hartian positivism 265–6
fairness 112–13 law practices and the content of law 227–9,
individual decisions deserving 107 234–7
normal justification theory 107–8 normative facts 265–6
purpose of 103 rational-relation doctrine 265–6
deliberation relevance of 254
abstract characterization of 70–4 value facts 235–7, 240, 254
alcohol, prohibition on sale to males under determinacy
21 of 79 coherence 100
autonomy 80–1 legal propositions 230, 247
Index 317
rational determinism 228–9 Brown v Board of Education 55
social facts 229 democracy 53, 59, 62
distinctive purpose of law 207–12, 215 Due Process Clause 52–3, 63
distinguishing cases 104, 109, 113, 116–18 Equal Protection Clause 7
doctrinal and sociological concept of law, Fourteenth Amendment 52–3
distinguishing between 310 gender equality 191–2
Due Process Clause individual rights 52
Dworkin, Ronald 13–15 integrity 199
equal concern 52–3, 63 liberty 63–6
interpretation 7, 13–15, 292 meaning 7
liberty 63–5 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
moral reasoning 13–15, 21, 52–3, 63–5, 292 52–3, 55, 59, 61–6
positivism 13–14 parental powers 191–2
same sex sodomy 63–6, 292 political integrity 151
Dworkin, Ronald see also checkerboard solu- political obligation to obey the law 188,
tions, Ronald Dworkin and, Critical 199, 201–3
Legal Studies movement, Dworkin’s recognizable conception of 151
theory of integrity and, Law’s Empire, Equal Protection Clause
moral reading of US Constitution, deliberation 77–9
Dworkin’s, political integrity, Ronald Dworkin, Ronald 14–15
Dworkin and equal status and concern, meaning of 7
associative obligations 190–7, 304–5 historical reasoning 7
coherence 85, 95, 98–101, 133 interpretation 6–8, 14–15, 292
constitutional judges 1–4 moral reasoning 6–7, 14–15, 21, 38, 50–2,
constitutional theory 41–2, 48–56 63–4
Due Process Clause 13–15 non-discrimination 78–9
Equal Protection Clause 14–15 precedent 7–8
fidelity 23–5, 35–6 prejudice 14–15
Freedom’s Law 41 racially discriminatory laws, prevention of 6
historical reasoning 8 reasons 77–8
integrity 15–17, 104, 113–16 same sex sodomy 38, 50–2, 63–4
intervening cases 69, 85, 87–8, 95, 98–101 equality see also equal concern, Equal
majoritarian premise, US Constitution and Protection Clause
6, 19–21, 25–31, 292–3 checkerboard solutions 125–6, 139–41,
moral reading of US Constitution 26, 41, 144–8, 296–8
49–56 democracy 26
New York Review of Books, essays on constitu- differential treatment 125–6, 139–41,
tional theory in 36 144–8, 296–8
political obligation to obey the law 183–7, integrity, promoting reduction in 146–7
198–205 judicial review 63
precedent 6–8, 104, 113–16 justice 140–1, 144–8, 150–2, 296
super-majoritarian amendment rules 6, 19–21 justification 150–2
Taking Rights Seriously 41 liberty and, integration of 301
United States Constitution 15–17, 25–31, majoritarian premise 26, 28–30
41, 49–56, 292–3 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
26, 38, 50–2, 63–4
efficiency, stare decisis and 108–12, 118 nepotism 146–7
elections 46, 57–8, 293 political integrity 144–8, 295–8
elitism 162–3 political obligation to obey the law 199
empiricism 11, 231 racial segregation 41, 43–5, 47
entrenchment United States Constitution 26, 28–30, 41–5
integrity 16 estoppel 74–5
stare decisis 110–12 ethics see morality
super-majoritarian amendment rules 20
United States Constitution 6, 16, 18, 20 facts make law 225–64, 310–11 see also
equal concern law-determining practices and con-
associative obligations 191–2, 305 tents of the law, relationship between
318 Index
facts make law (cont.) bent 249–52
abortion 249–52 better 254
aesthetic facts 228 coherence 248–9
antipositivitism 227–9 conceptual truth 254–5
beliefs 252 consensus 255
content of law, determinations of 225–37 legal propositions 248
descriptive facts 227–9, 234–7 legally correct 258–60
legal problem of content 241–5 morally best 259–60
metaphysical determination 226–8 relevant considerations 258–9, 263–4
non-legal content 241–5, 248 sentences, meaning of 245–6
rational determinism 228–9 specification of 246
reasons 233, 237–9 standards for 256
supervenience base 235 morality 259–60, 263–4
value facts 227–8, 235–6 non-legal content 241–5, 248
Critical Legal Studies movement 239 positivism 225–8, 256
descriptive facts 225–37 rational determinism 228–9
aesthetic facts 228 realism 239
content of law 227–9, 234–7 reasons 233, 237–40
executive, legislature or judicial behaviour, relevance limitation 262–3
facts about 236 relevant considerations 258–63
law practices 234–7, 252 sentences
reasons 240 legal content, effect of non-legal content
types of 236 on 242–3
value facts 235–7, 240 meaning of 242, 245–6
determinate legal requirements 237 non-legal content 242–3
Dworkin, Ronald 226–9, 226, 254, 262, words and 245–6
310–11 social facts 225–6
empirical facts 225, 231 standards 248–52
executive 236 statutes, constitutions, judicial and adminis-
foundational practices 247–8 trative decisions 230–1, 235, 237–47
Goodman’s problem about green and grue substantive factors 252–64
249 supervenience base 235
Hart, HLA 225–6, 239 text 243–4
higher-level facts 229 truth
indeterminate nature of law 239 conceptual 254–5
judicial behaviour, facts about 236 relevance of 254, 256
justification 226, 262 superficialist notions 254
Kripke’s problem about plus and quus 249 words, use of 254–5
law books 253 utterances and mental states 241–5
law-determining practices 236–45 value facts 225–8, 233, 235–7, 254–64,
descriptive facts 234–7, 252 310–11
justification 262 conceptual truth 254–5
law books 253 content of law 227–8, 235–6
legal requirements 237, 240 descriptive facts 235–7, 240, 254
reasons 237–40 exclusion 235–7
relevance 229 legal 256
substantive factors 252–64 models 254–5, 258
text 243–4 morality 259–62
types of 236–7 nature of 255–6
value facts, exclusion of 235–7 positivism 256
legal propositions 230, 246–8 relevance of 254
legal requirements 237, 240 role of 257–64
legislative history, relevance of 259 substantive 255–6
legislature 236, 253 truths 254–7
lower-level facts 229 values 252–4, 256–7
metaphysical determination 226–8 fairness
model 245–51 associative obligations 188–9
Index 319
checkerboard solutions 120–5, 128–9, 133, acceptance of rules 278, 281–3
135–40, 144–8, 297–8 all legal systems 276–82, 288–90
coherence 133, 135 all or nothing 277–82, 288–90
deference 112–13 brute fact about law, appealing to 280–1
democracy 1, 2 content of law, legal facts relevant to
Hartian positivism and normative facts 288 278–80, 289
integrity 144–5, 151–3, 177, 292, 297–8 Hartian dispositions 280–1, 283–4, 289
justice 136–9 Hartian legal systems 277–82, 288
legislature 2 intuitions about nature of law 281–3, 288–9
majority rule 1, 2 law practices
non-comparative claims of 112 content of law, relevance to 278–80, 286
political integrity 144–8, 296–8 legal facts 276, 283–6
political obligation to obey the law 188, 198 legal facts
precedent 94, 111–12, 118 brute fact about law, appealing to 280–1
United States Constitution 292 law practices 276, 283–6
family relationships model of 277–9
associative obligations 190–4, 198, 304–5 non-legal facts, determined by 279–80
intrinsic value of 198 normative facts, appeals to 281–6, 288
federal statutes, state’s interpretation of 95–6 reasons 277
federalism 19 logical entailment 286
fidelity mistake 281–2, 288
Dworkin, Ronald 23–5, 35–6, 50, 282 model, determination of correct 277–9
improvement 25 281–3, 286, 288
integrity 25–6, 292 non-legal facts 279–80
moral reading of US Constitution 23–5, normative facts 281–6, 288–9
31–2, 33–4, 38, 50, 292 positivists and anti-positivists 284
originalism 23–5, 31, 33–4, 38 reasons 277
synthesis, as 24 recognition, rule of 277, 280, 282–4
United States Constitution 292 reflective understanding of law 280–4
fit relational-rational requirement 276–80,
Dworkin, Ronald 35–6 289
integrity 173, 300 Hartian dispositions 271–6
interpretation 36–7, 38 all-things-considered binding 274
moral reading of US Constitution 35–7, 38 attitudes and dispositions, constituted by
political obligation to obey the law 203–4 271–6, 280–3, 287, 289
Fourteenth Amendment 13–15, 52–3 bridge principles 280–1, 283–4, 289
Freedom’s Law 26, 60 identity, doctrine of 274
friendship law practices
associative obligations 190–7, 304–5 legal facts 275–6, 285
intrinsic value of 195–7, 304 normative facts 275–6
reasons 276
gender equality 191–2 legal facts
generalizations 81 acceptance of 273
government power, limits on 40–50, 52 law practices 275–6, 285
guiding principles of the United States reasons for 276
Constitution 50–6 legislation binding in courts 274
authority of 53 non-legal facts 273
Brown v Board of Education 55 normative facts 275–6
identification of 56 practice theory of rules 271
judges 56 precedent 289
personal preferences 50–1 Raz, Joseph 274
sources of 50–1, 54 reasons 276, 289
recognition, rule of 271–6
Hart, HLA see Hartian bridge principles, relational-rational requirement 271, 273
Hartian dispositions, Hartian posi- social rules 271–6
tivism and normative facts standards 272–5
Hartian bridge principles 276–85 truth, appeal to 274
320 Index
Hartian positivism and normative facts precedent 69–101
265–90 punitive/regulatory distinction 96–7
all or nothing result 266–7, 270 settled 71–2, 81, 83–4, 90–1, 94–7, 294–5
beliefs and facts 269 thought experiments, as 81–4
descriptive facts 265–6
fairness 288 identity, doctrine of 274
false propositions 269 individual rights 46, 48, 52
law-determining practices 267–8, 270–1, individualism 164, 166–71, 174, 181, 299–303
284–5 instrumental obligations 198
legal facts 265–7 integrity see also Critical Legal Studies
good or valuable 270 movement, Dworkin’s theory of
law-determining practices 268, 270–1, integrity and, political integrity,
284–5 Ronald Dworkin and
meaning of 267 adjudication, in 116–17
rational-relation requirement 265–6, associative obligations 188–9, 198–205
268–71, 288 checkerboard solutions 124–6, 136–8,
reasons 268, 270, 287 296–7
mind, radical interpretation theory of 287 coherence 88, 98
model of contribution of law practice to consistency 15–16
content of law 267 Dworkin, Ronald 15–17
parallel objections 284–9 entrenchment 16
physical events 286 equal concern 199
putative normative facts 270 fairness 292
rational intelligibility 286–7 fidelity 25–6, 292
rational-relation requirement 265–6, interpretation 16–17, 292
268–71, 286–9 irrelevant considerations 131–2
beliefs 269 justification 138
descriptive facts 265–6 laws aims in Law’s Empire 212
legal facts 265–6, 268–71, 288 legislation 116
non-legal facts 265 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
normative facts 269–70,289 24, 35–6, 54, 292
putative normative facts 270 morally, striving to act 114–15
reasons 266, 268, 270, 287 political obligation to obey the law 186–9,
recognition, rule of 267–8 198–205
historical reasoning precedent 16–17, 104, 113–17, 292, 295
Dworkin, Ronald 5–9, 23–39, 49–51, United States Constitution 15–17, 24,
292–4 25–6, 54, 292
Equal Protection Clause 7 interpretation
internal role of 8 abstraction 37
moral reasoning 5–9, 23–39, 49–51, associative obligations 194–7
292–4 checkerboard solutions 126–8, 140–2
United States Constitution 6–8, 22 constitutional judges 42
history see also historical reasoning constructive 218–21, 308–9
fit 35–7, 38 creative 219, 309
moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s Due Process Clause 7, 13–15, 292
32–8 Equal Protection Clause 6–8, 14–15, 292
originalism 32–5 favoured 142, 149–53
reclaiming 32–5 federal statutes, state’s interpretation of 95–6
stare decisis 104 fit 36–7, 38
human rights crimes 3 integrity 16–17, 119, 142–3, 149–53, 157,
hypothetical cases 166, 169–72, 175–8, 292, 299–304
actual settled cases 70, 91–2, 94 judges 4
answers to 84 justification 36–7, 38
coherence 70–2, 81–4, 86, 90–7, 294–5 laws aims in Law’s Empire 208, 211, 215–20,
deliberation 76–80 307–10
generalizations 81 majoritarian premise, US Constitution
mistake 97 and 30
Index 321
mistakes 309 recognizable principles of 135–9, 148–53
moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s single conception of 198–9
4–15, 21–39, 51–5, 291–3 justice, checkerboard solutions and 120–5,
no-eligible interpretation conflicts 301–4 135–9
norms 219 abortion 135–7
political obligation to obey the law 187–9, coherence 133–5
199–200, 203–4 compromise 135–7
United States Constitution 4–6, 16–17, 30, differential treatment 140–1, 296
292 Dworkin, Ronald 136–8
intervening cases, problem of fairness 136–9
coherence 84–101 integrity 136–8
mistake 86, 95, 99–101 irrelevant considerations 136
precedent 85–101 justification 138
prospective application 85–7, 93 minimising injustice 123
retroactivity and 69–70, 84–9, 92–5, 100–1 moral principles, recognizable 135–8
intuition about the nature of law 281–3, principles of, recognizable 135–9
288–9 rape, abortion only for victims of 136–7
irrelevant considerations religion 138–9
abortion 129–33, 135–6 justification
checkerboard solutions 129–33, 136 checkerboard solutions 125–6, 140–2
Dworkin, Ronald 129–31 coercion 217, 308
integrity 131–2 constructive interpretation 220
justice 136 deference 107–8
moral irrelevance 129–33 differential treatment 150–2
rape, abortion only for victims of 129–33, integrity 142–52, 160
135–6 interpretation 36–7, 38
laws aims in Law’s Empire 210–13, 306–8
judges see also constitutional judges moral 211–23, 306–8
integrity 303 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
judicial process 2–3 36–7
opinions 303 normal justification theory 107–8
resources of 108–9 norms 218, 221
stare decisis 108–9 positivism 223, 308
judicial review stare decisis 104, 106–8, 113, 295
Brown v Board of Education 55
constitutional theory 44, 48 law-determining practices and contents of the
democracy 53 law, relationship between 226, 229–52
equality 63 abortion 249–52
individual rights 48 assumptions or beliefs 252
limits of 44 checkerboard solution 249–50
majoritarian premise, US Constitution and coherence 248–9
19, 29 conditions 241–5, 251
moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s content-oriented considerations 261
53, 55, 63 descriptive facts, as 227–9, 234–7
super-majoritarian amendment rules 19 empirical facts 231
jurisdictions, cases from other 95–6 epistemic determinants 226, 228, 230, 240,
justice see also justice, checkerboard solutions 248–9, 251
and foundational practices 247–8
democracy 53–4 Hartian bridge principles 276, 278–80,
differential treatment 150–2 283–6, 289
integrity 120, 135–9, 142–53, 160, 162, Hartian dispositions 275–6, 285
166–8, 175–7, 181, 296–8 legal facts 226–8, 234–5, 268, 270–1,
justice-seeking 30–1 275–6, 284–5
majoritarian premise, US Constitution and mappings 232
30–1 meaning 230, 267
political obligation to obey the law 198–9, metaphysical-determination doctrine
202 226–8, 230–2, 234, 237–9, 251–3
322 Index
law-determining practices and contents of the South Africa 306
law, relationship between (cont.) unifying purpose of law 207–12, 215
models 245–51, 258 Law’s Empire see also law’s aims in Law’s
non-legal content 241–5 Empire
normative facts 275–6 associative obligations 196
partial determination of content of law 233 checkerboard solutions 119–42, 297
practice-oriented considerations 261 coherence 69, 87–8
rational determination 228–9, 231–3 integrity 119–20, 143, 156, 160–1, 166,
rational-relation doctrine 231–2, 237, 245 175, 179, 295, 297–8
reasons 233, 237–40, 276 irrelevant considerations 129
role of 230–4 political obligation to obey the law 183,
sentences 186–7, 201
meaning of 242–3, 245–6 Suggested Purpose 208–10, 212, 216
words and 245–6 legal facts
standards 248–52 acceptance 273
statutes, constitutions, judicial and adminis- brute fact about law, appealing to 280–1
trative decisions 230, 235, 237–47 good or valuable 270
transparency 232 Hartian bridge principles 277–86, 288
utterances and mental states 241–5 Hartian dispositions 273, 275–6, 285
values, beliefs about 252 Hartian positivism 265–71, 284–5, 287–8
value facts 227, 233–4, 252, 254–64 law practices 268, 270–1, 276, 283–6
law’s aims in Law’s Empire 207–23, 306–10 model of 277–9
agency, failure and success of 216 non-legal facts, determined by 279–80
claims, making 213–14 normative facts, appeals to 281–6, 288
coercion 208–9, 216–17, 308–10 rational-relation requirement 265–6,
constructive interpretation 220 268–71, 288
co-ordination of conduct for common good reasons 268, 270, 276, 277, 287
210 legal positivism see positivism
distinctive purpose of law 207–12, 215 Legal Process school 60
Dworkin’s Suggested Purpose 208–10, 212, legal propositions
216 determinacy 230, 247
guidance 210 facts make law 230, 246–8
Holmes, Oliver Wendell 215, 306 meaning 230
human beings making claims 214, 222, model 248
306–7 truth 230, 246–7
integrity 212 legal reasoning see also coherence, legal
interpretation 208, 211, 215–21, 307–10 reasoning and
justification 210–13, 217, 306–8 legislation
law officials, claims made by 213–14, binding on courts 274
307–8 checkerboard solutions 121–5
legal content, determination of 211 coherence 93, 147
mistakes 309–10 federal statutes, state’s interpretation of 95–6
moral ideal of law 212 history, relevance of 259
moral justification 211–23, 306–8 integrity 116
nature of law 212–13 law practices and the content of law 230,
Nazi law 217, 308 235, 237–47
norms 207, 209–10, 218–23, 307 political integrity 147
personification of law 212, 306–7 precedent 86
plain fact view of law 221 prospective changes 93
positivism 220, 222–3, 305–6, 308–9 Raz, Joseph 274
pragmatists 219 stare decisis 116
purpose, serving or having a 216 legislatures
Raz, Joseph 212–15, 217, 221–2, 306–7 constitutional theory 42, 43
sociological and doctrinal concept of law, democracy 43
distinguishing between 310 facts make law 253
society of angels thought-experiment 208–9, fairness 2
309–10 guardians of principle 30
Index 323
integrity 165, 169–70 mistake
policy-making 46 actual settled cases 90, 95, 100–1
political obligation to obey coherence 86, 90, 97–101, 295
the law 187, 202 Hartian bridge principles 281–2, 288
supremacy 165 hypothetical cases 97
legitimacy 176–7, 181, 188 interpretation 309
liberty intervening cases, problem of 86, 95, 99–101
claims 42–4, 63–7 laws aims in Law’s Empire 309–10
demeaned existence of claimant, whether precedent 97–101, 295
state had 64 preferences 90
equal concern 63–6 stare decisis 103–7, 109, 115, 118
equality and, integration of 301 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
fundamental liberties 64–5 5–12, 22, 49–56
majoritarian premise, US Constitution and abstraction 37, 51, 53
26, 30 administrative law 60
moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s application of concepts 9–10
63–7 aspirational principles 38
police powers 43 Bill of Rights 52–3, 62
procedural liberties 30 Brown v Board of Education 55, 58–9, 294
racial segregation 43–4 coherence 292
states, liberty of 66 consequentialist pragmatism 61
substantive liberties 30 consistency 50
Supreme Court 42–3 constitutional law and 6, 7
tradition 64–5 context 11
critical attitude, encouraging a 38
majoritarian premise, US Constitution and culture 33–5
25, 26–31 dead hand of the past theory 38
administrative law 60 democracy 26, 53–4, 57–9, 61–2, 293
autonomy 29, 293 drafting 51
community 26 Due Process Clause 13–15, 21, 52–3, 63–6,
constitution-perfecting theory 29–30 292
constitutional constructivism 28–9 elections 57–8, 293
constitutional democracy 26–8, 30 empiricism 11
constitutional theory 47, 48 equal concern and respect, notion of 52–3,
counter-majoritarian difficulty 26 55, 59, 61–6
deliberative autonomy 29 Equal Protection Clause 6–7, 14–15, 21,
deliberative democracy 27, 28–30 63–6
democracy 26–30, 47–8, 53, 292–3 equality 26, 38, 50–2, 63–4
Dworkin, Ronald 25–31, 53, 58–60, 66–7, fidelity 23–5, 31–4, 38, 50, 292
291–3 fit 35–7, 38
equality 26, 28–30 Fourteenth Amendment 13–15, 52–3
fairness 1, 2 Freedom’s Law 26, 41, 60
forums of principle, courts as 30 government power, limits on 49–50, 52
guardians of principle, legislatures as 30 guiding principles 50–3
interpretation of Constitution 30 authority of 53
judicial review 29 Brown v Board of Education 55
justice-seeking 30–1 identification of 56
liberty 26, 30 judges 56
minorities, protection of 58–9 personal preferences 50–1
personal autonomy 30 sources of 50–1, 54
process-perfecting theory 29–30 Hart Ely, John. Democracy and Distrust
super-majoritarian amendment rules 19–21, 57–61
292–3 historical reasoning 5–9, 23–39, 49–51,
metaphysical-determination doctrine 226–8, 292–4
230–2, 234, 237–9, 251–3 history
mind, radical interpretation theory of 287 fit and 35–7, 38
minorities, protection of 19, 58–9 reclaiming 32–5
324 Index
moral reading of US Constitution, text 32–4, 49–50, 62
Dworkin’s (cont.) tradition 33, 64–5
improvement 25 utilitarianism 49, 60–1
individual rights 52 morality see also moral reading of US
integrity 24–6, 35–6, 54, 292 Constitution, Dworkin’s
intermediate theory 8–9, 25, 31–2, 37–8 associative obligations 194–5, 197
interpretation 4–15, 21–39, 51–5, 291–3 checkerboard solutions 121–2, 135–8
judges coercion 217
activism of 54, 59 coherence 74–82, 114–16
guiding principles, identification of 56 commitment to 114
job description 56–7 constitutional judges 1
minimalism 60 constructive interpretation 220
personal preferences 50–1 ethical deliberation 74–82
restraint 58 facts make law 259–60, 263–4
judicial review 53, 55, 63 ideal of law, moral 212
justice 53–4 integrity 114–15, 145, 166–7, 172, 180,
justification 36–7, 38 299–300, 304
Legal Process school 60 irrelevant considerations 129–33
liberty claims 63–7 justice 135–8
demeaned existence of claimant, whether justification 211–23, 306–8
state had 64 laws aims in Law’s Empire 212
fundamental liberties 64–5 model, morally best 259–60
states, liberty of 66 norms 218, 221
tradition 64–5 obedience to law 194–5
meaning of 9–10 political obligation to obey the law 184,
majoritarian premise 25, 26–31, 53, 58–60, 187–8, 200–3
66–7, 291–3 positivism 223, 308
minorities, protection of 58–9 recognizable moral principles 135–8
ordinary meaning of words 10–12 recognition, rule of 274
originalism 6–9, 12, 16, 23–6, 31–8 stare decisis 114–16
broad 24–5, 31–8, 293–4 striving to act morally 114–15
conservative ideology, as 34 value facts 259–62
culture 33–5
dead hand of the past theory 38 Nazi Law 212–13
fidelity 23–5, 31, 33–4, 38 New Deal 43–4
history, reclaiming 32–5 norms see also Hartian positivism and
narrow 24–5, 32 normative facts
revisionism 24, 31 associative obligations 305
semantic 294 authority, normative force of 105–7
text 32–4, 49–50 background 159, 161
philosophy 23–39 discrete 159
positivism 49 Hartian dispositions 275–6
practice 33 identification of 159
pragmatism 8, 61 integrity 161
precedent 7–8 interpretation 219
racial segregation 55 laws aims in Law’s Empire 207, 209–10,
representation 57–9, 61, 62 218–23, 307
revisionism 24, 31 law practices 275–6
same sex sodomy 63–6, 292 legal facts 281–6, 288
state determination 66–7 legal reasoning 82
states, liberty of 66 moral justification 218, 221
structure 32–4 political obligation to obey the law 185,
substantive theory of the US Constitution 201–2
26–31 principles 161
super-majoritarian amendment rules 292–3 putative normative facts 270
Supreme Court, Dworkin’s influence on 61 rational-relation doctrine 269–70, 289
Taking Rights Seriously 60 stare decisis 105–7
Index 325
obedience to law see also political obligation to legislation, coherence of 147
obey the law more than one principle of integrity 149
associative obligations 183–9, 191, 194–5, moral solutions 145
305 nepotism in employment 146–7
moral obligation of 194–5 principles 148, 150
obligations see also associative obligations reduction in integrity 146
instrumental 198 political obligation to obey the law
moral 194–5 associative obligations 183–9, 191, 193–5,
political 183–9, 191, 193–5, 198–205, 305 198–205, 305
special 189–97, 305 coercion 188, 203
ordinary meaning of words 10–12 conditions 183, 185–6, 188
originalism cooperation 183–4
broad 24–5, 31–8, 293–4 Dworkin, Robert 183–7, 198–205
conservative ideology, as 34 equal concern 199, 201–3
culture 33–5 equality 199
dead hand of the past theory 38 fairness 188, 198
Dworkin, Ronald 6–9, 12, 16, 23–6, 31–8 fit 203–4
fidelity 23–5, 31, 33–4, 38 force of law 185
history, reclaiming 32–5 general obligations to obey law 184–5, 188,
moral reading of US Constitution 6–9, 12, 202–4
16, 23–6, 31–8, 49–50, 293–4 grounds of law 185
narrow 24–5, 32 instrumental considerations 203–5
revisionism 24, 31 integrity 186–9, 198–205
semantic 294 interpretation 187–9, 199–200, 203–4
text 32–4, 49–50 intrinsic value 201–2
overruling cases 104–5, 107, 111, 113, 116–18 justice 198, 202
single conception of 198–9
parental powers 191–2 legislature 187, 202
parliaments see legislatures legitimacy 188
personification of law 212, 306–7 morality 184, 187–8, 200–3
phenomenology 172–3 norms 185, 201–2
philosophers, constitutional judges as 5–22 scepticism 187
plain fact view of law 221 self-legislation 201
police powers 43 state, value of individual’s
political integrity, Ronald Dworkin and relationship with 200
119–53 unjust laws, obedience to 185
benefits of integrity 143 populism 43, 46–7
checkerboard solutions 119–53, 296–8 positivism see also Hartian positivism and
coherence 143–8, 150, 292 normative facts
compromise 142–3, 145, 152 anti-positivism 284
differential treatment 144–8, 150–2, Due Process Clause 13–14
296–8 facts make law 225–8
equal concern, recognizable conception hard 226, 256
of 151 Hartian bridge principles 284
equal treatment 144–7, 295–7 integrity 159, 166
explicit rules 143–4 laws aims in Law’s Empire 220, 222–3,
fairness 144–5, 151–3, 292, 297–8 305–6, 308–9
favoured interpretation 142, 149–53 moral justification 223, 308
fidelity 292 moral reading of US Constitution,
interpretation 119, 142–3, 149–53, 292 Dworkin’s 49
justice 120 social facts 225–6
integrity trumping 142–8, 296–8 soft 226, 256
principles of, recognizable 135–9, value facts 226, 256
148–53 practical theory of rules 271
justification for integrity 142–52 pragmatism
Law’s Empire 119–20, 143, 295, 297–8 consequentialism 8, 61
legality 120 integrity 156, 175–7, 181
326 Index
pragmatism (cont.) rational-relation doctrine
laws aims in Law’s Empire 219 beliefs 269
moral reading of US Constitution, descriptive facts 265–6
Dworkin’s 8, 61 Hartian bridge principles 276–80, 289
policy making 8 Hartian dispositions 271, 273
super-majoritarian amendment rules 19–21 Hartian positivism and normative facts
precedent see also stare decisis 265–6, 268–71, 286–9
coherence 205 law practices and the content of law 231–2,
discretion 88 237, 245
Dworkin, Ronald 6–8 legal facts 265–6, 268–71, 288
Equal Protection Clause 7–8 non-legal facts 265
fairness 94 normative facts 269–70, 289
Hartian dispositions 289 putative normative facts 270
hypothetical cases 69–101 reasons
integrity 16–17, 300, 302–3 constitutional judges 2–3
intervening cases, problem of 85–101 deliberation 73, 75–6
jurisdictions, cases from other 95–6 Equal Protection Clause 77–8
legal reasoning 69–101 facts make law 237–40
legislation 86 Hartian bridge principles 277
mistake 97–101, 295 Hartian dispositions 274, 276, 289
moral reading of US Constitution, Hartian positivism and normative facts 266,
Dworkin’s 7–8 268, 270, 287
prospective effect 85–7, 93–4, 97–8 law practices and the content of law 233,
retroactivity 94–101, 295 237–40, 276
settled cases 83–94 legal facts 268, 270, 287
state courts 95–6 judicial process 2–3
United States Constitution 16–17 legal facts 276
preferences stare decisis 106–7
checkerboard solutions 123–4 recognition, rule of
coherence 90 all-things-considered binding 274
judges, personal preferences of 50–1 Hartian bridge principles 277, 280, 282–4
mistake 90 Hartian dispositions 271–6
moral reading of US Constitution, Hartian positivism and normative facts 267–8
Dworkin’s 50–1 legal authority of 274
settled 90 morally binding 274
principles practice theory or rules 272
checkerboard solutions 122–3, 135–9 standards 272–5
coherence 133, 135 reflective equilibrium 69
compromise 122–3 reflective understanding of law 280–4
conflict between 122 reliance, certainty and 111
integrity 158–60 religion 138–9
justice 135–9, 148–53 retroactivity
moral, recognizable 135–9 coherence 70, 74, 84–9, 92–101, 295
norms 161 intervening cases, problem of 69–70, 84–9,
policy distinguished from 158–60 92–5, 100–1
ranking 122 precedent 94–101, 295
privacy 75–7 revisionary concept of law 92–4
process-perfecting theory 29–30 revisionism 24, 31
promissory estoppel 74–5 rule of recognition see recognition, rule of
punitive/regulatory distinction 96–7
scientific theory 91–2, 94
racial segregation 41, 43–5, 47, 55 search, police powers of 75–7
racially discriminatory laws, segregation 41, 43–5, 47, 55
prevention of 6 sentences
rape, abortion only for victims of facts make law 242–3, 245–6
checkerboard solutions 129–33, 135–7, law practices and the content of law 242–3,
140–1 245–6
justice 136–7 meaning 242–3, 245–6
Index 327
model 245–6 reliance, certainty and 111
non-legal content 242–3 research, costs of 109
words 245–6 Student Judiciary of the University of
social change 42–3 Georgia 116–17
social goals 158 vertical 103, 108
social practices, changes in 93 statutes see legislation
social rules 271–6 super-majoritarian amendment rules 6, 17–21
social welfare 122 constitutional democracy 20
sociological and doctrinal concept of law, dead hand theories of constitutionalism 19,
distinguishing between 310 20–1, 22
South Africa 306 democracy 20, 292
special obligations 189–97, 305 Dworkin, Ronald 6, 19–21
standards entrenchment 20
constitutional judges 1–2 federalism 19
democracy 4 judicial review 19
facts make law 248–52 localism 19
Hartian dispositions 272–5 minorities, protection of 19
law practices and the content of law 248–52 moral reading 292–3
model 256 pragmatism 19–21
recognition, rule of 272–5 purpose of 19–20
stare decisis 103–18 reform, incentives for improving quality of
adjudication, integrity in 116–17 20
certainty, value of 111 short-termism 20
coherence 114, 115–16, 118 stable political institutions, establishment of
consistency 115 19–20
deference US Constitution
class, decisions deserving deference as a 107 Supreme Court
fairness 112–13 Dworkin’s influence on 61
individual decisions deserving 107 liberty claims, approach to 42–3
normal justification theory 107–8 moral reading of US Constitution 61
purpose of 103 police powers 43
distinguishing 104, 109, 113, 116–18 populism 43
Dworkin, integrity and 104, 113–16 racial segregation 43–4
efficiency 108–12, 118
entrenchment 110–12 Taking Rights Seriously 60 text
fairness 111–12, 118 Bill of Rights 62
non-comparative claims of 112 moral reading of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
higher court judges, expertise of 108 32–4, 49–50, 62
history 104 originalism 32–4, 49–50
horizontal 103–18 tradition 33, 64–5
illegitimacy 105 truth
integrity 104, 113–17, 292, 295 conceptual 254–5
judicial resources 108–9 facts make law 254–6
justification 104, 106–8, 113, 295 Hartian dispositions 274
legislation, integrity in 116 legal propositions 230, 246–7
liability rules 109–10 model 254–5
merits of decisions 104–7, 112–13, 118 relevance of 254, 256
mistakes 103–7, 109, 115, 118 superficialist notions 254
morality value facts 254–7
coherence 114–16 words, use of 254–5
commitment to 114
morally, striving to act 114–15 underdetermination 100–1
no difference theory 105–6 unifying purpose of law 207–12, 215
normal justification theory 107–8, 113 United States Constitution see also Due
normative force of authority 105–7 Process Clause, Equal Protection
overruling 104–5, 107, 111, 113, 116–18 Clause, majoritarian premise, US
planning, certainty and 111 Constitution and, moral reading
reasons 106–7 of US Constitution, Dworkin’s
328 Index
United States Constitution (cont.) certainty 111
amendments 6, 17–18 family relationships 198
change, prevention of 6, 18 friendships 195–7, 304
consistency 15–16 political obligation to obey the law 201–2
democracy, standards of 4 positivism 226
Dworkin, Ronald 15–17 state, value of individual’s relationship with
entrenchment 6, 16, 18 200
equality 41–5 substantive factors 253
fairness 292 value facts 225–8, 233, 254–64, 310–11
fidelity 282 see also value, values
Fourteenth Amendment 13–15, 52–3 conceptual truth 254–5
guiding principles of the United States content of law 227–8, 235–6
Constitution 50–6 descriptive facts 235–7, 240, 254
historical reasoning 5–8, 22 exclusion 235–7
integrity 15–17 legal 256
interpretation 4, 5–6, 16–17, 292 models 254–5, 258
judges’ approach to interpretation 4 morality 259–62
precedent 16–17 nature of 255–6
purposes of 17–19, 22 positivism 256
rigidity of, justification for 18 relevance of 254
social change 42–3 role of 257–64
substantive theory of 26–31 substantive 255–6
super-majoritarian amendment rules 19–21, truths 254–7
292–3 values see also value, value facts
unjust laws, obedience to 185 beliefs 252
utilitarianism 49, 60–1, 300–1 facts make law 252–3, 256–7
utterances and mental states 241–5 law practices and the content of law 252
substantive factors 253
value see also value facts, values
associative obligations 195–8, 304–5 words 10–12, 254–5