Essay - Pitari - Severino On Specialization
Essay - Pitari - Severino On Specialization
1, 2019
ABSTRACT: To our contemporary eyes, science appears as the most reliable guide to
the human enterprise. However, we possess little awareness as to what the proper
meaning of scientific specialization is, and this knowledge is indispensable if we are not
to proceed mindlessly in our relationship with being. Italian philosopher Emanuele
Severino sees in scientific specialization the most coherent consequence of humanity’s
most ancestral interpretation of the world, which all human decisions and actions
enact. To him, this coherency is what makes the dominance of scientific specialization
on our time necessary. By focusing on one of Severino’s major theoretical works (Oltre
il linguaggio, 1992), and with reference to other key texts, this essay introduces
international readers to a specific facet of Severino’s discourse. In doing so, it translates
passages of his works that have never appeared in English.
KEYWORDS: Emanuele Severino; Scientific specialization; Species; Techne; Decision
1
Emanuele Severino (1929-) is a contemporary Italian philosopher. He wrote around eighty or
more books. As of today, only one has been translated into English: The Essence of Nihilism (Verso
Books, 2016). English readers can also find a collection of essays, edited by Nicoletta Cusano,
entitled Nihilism and Destiny (2016). The present essay introduces English readers to only one facet
www.cosmosandhistory.org 366
PAOLO PITARI 367
of Severino’s discourse. N.B.: I translated all the titles and passages from Severino’s work here
cited. The Italian originals are always reported in parenthesis after the translation. The
bibliography lists them in alphabetical order according to the original Italian title.
COSMOS AND HISTORY 368
contemplates the world is far more ancient. It dates back to when man
began to perceive himself as an autonomous center of action, capable of
decision. Decision makes acting autonomous. To act without deciding is to
depend on something other. The meaning of scientific specialization is
essentially tied to the meaning of decision. But what does this mean, and
how is this proposition justifiable? (Il carattere specialistico della scienza
appartiene ormai all’essenza della ricerca e della prassi scientifica. Non c’è scienza
dove non c’è specializzazione, ossia applicazione del metodo sperimentale a un campo
particolare di oggetti. Si tratta di una circostanza piuttosto recente nella storia della
nostra civiltà. Ma il modo di considerare il mondo, che viene messo in atto nella
specializzazione scientifica, è molto più antico. Risale al tempo in cui l’uomo
incomincia a sentirti un centro autonomo di azione, cioè capace di decidere. Il decidere
rende autonomo l’agire; se si agisce senza decidere, si dipende da altro. Il senso della
specializzazione scientifica, diciamo, è essenzialmente legato al senso del decidere. Ma
che senso ha, e come è possibile questa affermazione?, OL 57).
Severino points out that specialization means to look at the species. The
original Latin meaning of species is “image,” “appearance,” “spectacle,’
“form.” The related verb specere means “to observe,” “to watch,” “to look
at,” “in the strong sense of ‘looking toward an object, a destination, a
goal’” (“nel senso forte di ‘guardare verso un oggetto, una meta, uno scopo,’” ibid.).
The species is what lets itself be seen. And in turn, “it is by virtue of its
visibility that the species can be observed, analyzed, controlled,
measured, desired, feared, refused, shunned” (“la visibilità della species è ciò
per cui quest’ultima può essere osservata, analizzata, controllata, misurata, desiderata,
temuta, rifiutata, fuggita,” ibid. 58). The visibility of the species is inversely
proportional to its blending with its surroundings. In other words, the
species must not confuse itself with its context: it must be separate from all
other species and from the totality of all species to be seen, i.e., to be itself.
We interpret things as species and enact specialization, and scientific
specialization is “the certainty of the difference between things” (“la
PAOLO PITARI 369
convinzione della differenza tra le cose,” ibid.) put into practice in the most
coherent and powerful manner: science “isolates a part (species) of reality;
it separates it from the other parts in order to be able to observe […] its
configuration and behavior” (“isola una parte (species) della realtà, la separa
dalle altre per poterne osservare […] la configurazione e il comportamento,” ibid. 58-
59).
In Philosophy from the Greeks to Our Time: Contemporary Philosophy (La
filosofia dai greci al nostro tempo: la filosofia contemporanea, 1996), Severino
writes that while science does seek unification – see e.g. the International
Encyclopedia of Unified Science –, nonetheless it aims to “unite dimensions
that it conceives as originally separate, and thus destined to remain so
and to render accidental, precarious, temporary, and contingent every
unification” (“unisce dimensioni che essa concepisce come originariamente separate e
quindi destinate a rimanere tali e a rendere dunque accidentale, precaria, provvisoria,
contingente ogni loro unificazione,” FGT 482).
Like scientific specialization, all human actions interpret things as
species, i.e., as discrete, separate and isolated from one another. When we
say “human life” we give voice to our belief in our power to exert agency
over things and transform them. This belief entails the interpretation of
things as species as the original necessary precondition for transformation:
if things weren’t species, transformation would be impossible. For agency
to be conceivable, for decisions to be real, the “world” must be
constituted by a series of isolated and isolatable things. We can observe,
analyze, measure, control, desire, despise, save, and kill things only
because of their original separateness. Humans can exist as the beings
who organize means, realize ends, make decisions and transform the
“world” only in virtue of the prior ontological isolation of all things.
This basic interpretation of reality establishes the foundation of our
civilization. Accordingly, within the thought of our civilization, scientific
COSMOS AND HISTORY 370
2
To give just one example: in History of Western Philosophy (1946), Bertrand Russell writes about
the Hellenistic age that “specialization characterized the age in all departments, not only in the
world of learning” (HWP 260). With due specifications, such statements can be extended all the
way to archaic human beings.
COSMOS AND HISTORY 372
questo, agendo e decidendo, non si sente separato e isolato dal Tutto; e in questo senso,
propriamente, non ‘decide,’” ibid. 59).
In myth, human beings do not decide. A “decision” is an act freely
chosen by an individual, and there can be no freedom for individual
decision in myth, where every action is an Act of the Whole. The
individual cannot be an autonomous center of action: one must enact the
Will of the Whole and therefore one cannot decide. Properly speaking,
one cannot even act if by “action” we mean an endeavor that was chosen
and could have been otherwise because it originates within the
autonomous force of an individual. “To decide” means “to make a choice
from a number of alternatives” (OED). In myth, there are no alternatives
and therefore no decisions. The Whole must be unchanging, unalterable,
inflexible, and so human beings cannot do otherwise.
Human freedom and the Whole are mutually exclusive. In myth, the
opposition resolves in the victory of the Whole. In science, human
freedom wins. 3 Scientific specialization is what happens when belief in
human freedom becomes concrete action. The history of humanity is the
process of becoming ever more coherent with our original belief in
human freedom. Thus, after myth “come the epochs when human
beings no longer feel the Whole in their acting and begin to perceive
themselves as autonomous centers of action and will” (“vengono le epoche in
cui l’uomo non sente più il Tutto nel proprio agire, ma incomincia a percepirsi come
centro autonomo di azione e di volontà,” ibid.). In these epochs, human beings
begin to feel themselves as separate and isolated from the things of the
3
Human history is pervaded by giant myths, Christianity and Islam above all, that claim to allow
the coexistence of human beings and the Whole. We cannot describe the critique that these
myths deserve here. But we can mention the reasoning that points to the solution. Can God be
surprised by human actions? No, or He wouldn’t be omnipotent. But if God cannot be surprised,
then there can there be no space for human freedom.
COSMOS AND HISTORY 374
the means whereby myth frees itself from its contradictions. This is the
sense in which our civilization develops according to necessity.
Scientific specialization is a recent configuration of human
civilization because of the historical dominance of myth. In other words:
it takes a long time for myth to free itself from its contradictions. Today,
scientific specialization must fight other ideologies that claim the right to
shape human civilization because myth isn’t quite dead yet. The
traditions of the West still live, but they are dying (religions and all other
forms of the epistéme: capitalism, communism, politics, ethics, etc. – these
are our myths and traditions). Scientific specialization is uncontainable
and destined to bring about the age of technology because every ideology,
even myths and traditions, believes in humans as technological beings:
that is, every ideology, even those who seem to oppose science, believes
in the same fundamental and ancestral ideas about the nature of reality
that make scientific specialization the most coherent concrete realization
of the unquestionable evidence of being.
Scientific specialization is the most coherent and powerful action that
results from our conceptualization of reality. For this reason, it is natural,
righteous, and just. Emanuele Severino argues that technology can be
questioned only if, before, one questions the fundamental beliefs that
everyone shares about reality and the meaning of human life.
I do not ever consider whether or not to take the sun in hand. The
decision never presents itself to me because I do not think that I am an
autonomous force powerful enough to do so, and because I do not think
that the sun will let itself be taken. Yet, tomorrow this too could become
a decision, if scientific specialization will allow it. The very idea that we
make decisions and act freely entails that we are technological beings in
a universe of species, and that the only limitations to our power are
limitations within it (these could thus be overcome, and so the ethos of
technology becomes infinite power).
Technology also entails belief that oneself is a species: the necessary
COSMOS AND HISTORY 378
precondition for autonomy, force, and action is one’s own separation and
isolation from all other things, otherwise decision, action, and power
would be impossible. Our belief in our ability to analyze, measure,
control, transform, and dominate things thus entails that we ourselves are
things and that so are other people (why should one not treat oneself and
others as things, then?). Even in our simplest and smallest decisions and
actions, we enact the essence of scientific specialization: the
interpretation of being that justifies our domination of the world.
Therefore, we always enact our belief that we and others are things, and
that the fundamental ethos of humanity must be the indefinite increase
of power. If you think you decide and then decry scientific specialization,
you are in contradiction. In To Caesar and to God (A Cesare e a Dio, 1983),
Severino writes that
if one were convinced that things are tied to one another by an
inseparable tie, so as to form an unbreakable web, then one would never
decide to take even the lightest and easiest-to-take object in hand,
because the attempt would involve the entire web to which the object is
inseparably tied. Moving the smallest thing would equal moving the
entire universe. One thinks one can modify reality – and technology
establishes itself by the conviction that it is the most effective power that
can transform reality – only if one thinks one is looking at a world where
things are separate, not tied by a web” (“se si fosse persuasi che le cose sono
legate tra di loro e legate con un legame inscindibile, in modo da formare una rete che
non può essere spezzata, allora non ci si deciderebbe nemmeno a prendere in mano il
più leggero e afferrabile degli oggetti: il tentativo coinvolgerebbe tutta la rete in cui
l’oggetto sarebbe inserito. Smuovere la cosa più piccola equivarrebbe a smuovere l’intero
universo. Si crede di poter modificare la realtà – e la tecnica si costituisce attraverso la
convinzione di essere la potenza che trasforma la realtà nel modo più efficace – solo se
ci si tiene dinanzi un mondo in cui le cose sono separate, non sono legate da una rete,”
CD 147).
If you believe you decide, you believe in technology. The belief in human
PAOLO PITARI 379
crack, smash, break”; “To use up, consume, destroy”; “to devour” (OLD
275).
In the original meaning of decision, then, separation and killing are
united as the essence of technology. In meaning “I kill,” caedo also relates
to “the Latin oc-cido” (“dal latino oc-cido,” OL 60), and again: “occido,
~dere” means “to cause the death of, kill, slaughter”; “To involve in
disaster or failure, bring about the ruin of, do for”; “To cut up, break up,
crush to pieces”; “To fall or collapse in the way”; “To die (esp. by violent
means, in battle, etc.), be struck down, fall”; “To sink into nothingness,
pass away”; etc. (OLD 1356-7).
Here, Severino insists on the equivalence between occido and ob-caedo:
ob- indicates that against which caedere is implemented. Occidere (to kill)
means to implement separation, breaking, undoing, tearing to pieces and
dismembering against someone or something. Occidere and decidere
indicate two closely related actions: to kill and to decide. Killing is the
most extreme decision: the decision to separate a thing from Being.
Further glottological proof comes from the meaning of the original Latin
“decido, ~dere”: “to fall down”; “To fall in ruin, collapse”; “To die”; “To
fall or lapse from a better into a worse or less elevated condition”; “(of
things) to fail, go wrong”; “To detach by cutting, cut off, cut out”; etc.
(ibid. 538).
Originally, then, “decision” itself explicitly indicates violent
separation, destruction, death, and killing. Today, the indication has
become implicit. In our contemporary languages, we split off these
meanings into different terms, but the graphic and auditory vicinity of
decision and killing remains. English maintains the essential sameness of
decision and killing in the use of the combining form “-cide,” which
“denotes a person or substance that kills” and “an act of killing” (OED)—
and which itself derives from the Latin caedere (OED). Thus, English says
PAOLO PITARI 383
“decide,” and with the combining form “-cide,” it builds all verbs and
nouns related to killing: “homicide,” “patricide,” “matricide,” “suicide,”
“ecocide,” “genocide,” “biocide,” “deicide,” etc. Relatedly, the term “kill”
sounds and looks different, because it is “probably of Germanic origin”
(OED), but the conceptual sameness is not lost: “kill originally denoted a
stroke or blow […], in the sense of ‘strike,’ ‘beat,’ and also ‘put to death’”
(OED), just as the Latin decido and occido did.
This essential sameness of decision, separation, and killing appears in
our languages from their origins. And if language reveals the meaning
human beings confer to the world, then the meaning of decision betrays
how we relate to our own existence: in every decision, we must feel the
killing of infinite lives. Severino writes that “to say that deciding kills the
life that one could have lived is not an exaggeration” (“dire che il decidere
uccide la vita che si sarebbe potuto vivere non è una esagerazione,” OL 60). We think
of life as an infinity of possibilities within which we decide what will be
and what will not be. We think we decide the configuration of the world.
We think of ourselves as the “I” that chooses what possibility must be and
what other infinite possibilities “I” must condemn to nothingness. This
must be our self-definition in technology, and this must mean that every
instant of our lives feels like an absolute infinity of abortions and murders,
of our own selves and of others as well (whether we are conscious of this
or not).
Every decision (even the smallest of decisions) comes forth as the
eternal killing of infinite possibilities in order to let only one possibility
be. In every instant, we must decide to murder infinities into absolute
nothingness in order to let be the one configuration of the world we want
to be. In so believing we decide, we think that Being is subject to our will.
In this interpretation of existence, every moment becomes not only a
decision that is the killing of an infinity of possible selves and of possible
COSMOS AND HISTORY 384
others. Also, every decision becomes the killing of our present self and of
all present others. In every moment and in every decision, “I” and all
others are killed, forever lost into nothingness, and they will never be
recovered. In light of this extreme violence, paralysis in front of decision
seems rational. Decision now appears to entail unbearable isolation,
loneliness, solipsism, suffering, despair, and violence. It now also appears
as an unbearable burden: the burden of being fully responsible for the
violence of infinite killing in each moment, without the possibility of ever
going back. How can one rationally ever forgive oneself for making the
wrong decision? How can one rationally ever avoid being crushed by the
awareness that every moment is a decision that entails this infinite
responsibility none can bear?
Ours is the civilization of technology and therefore of extreme
decision. For Severino, this entails extreme suffering and violence. The
West is the “Occident,” which too derives from the Latin “occidens, ~entis,”
which itself derives from occido. Occidens is occid-ens. Occido means killing
and ens is the present participle of sum, “to be,” “being,” “that which is.”
Therefore, occidens is “the violent being that kills, slaughters, causes
disaster, brings to ruins”; “the being that decides, separates, isolates,
kills.” Not coincidentally, the English word “Occident” contains the
combining form “-cide.” Occidens is the West, the affirmation and
actualization of our unquestionable belief in technology, our ability to
decide and dominate. We are our interpretation of things as “accidental”
and “incidental,” words that themselves contain the combining form “-
cide” because this interpretation of things allows us to “-cide” them.
We are the Occidens, the West. We pray at the altar of individual
freedom, elevating our belief in our power to be technological beings to
the ultimate truth. Severino reminds us that technology is a theory, not
the absolute truth, and as such is not unquestionable. He invites us to
PAOLO PITARI 385
consider that there may be good reason to doubt what we take for
granted. Only through an interpretation of reality entirely other could one
question the ethos of technology (the ethos of power). Only if the
technological interpretation of reality is wrong, the ethos of power could
and should be questioned. Throughout his works, Severino argues
precisely that the technological interpretation of reality constitutes the
greatest folly, that it belongs to the essence of nihilism and that it is the
origin of every form of violence ever since the original appearance of
human thought. This is the heart of the matter, but it shall be discussed
elsewhere.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Glare, P.G.W. (2012). Oxford Latin Dictionary. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2012.
Hornby A.S. (2013). Oxford Advanced Learner’s Dictionary. Oxford: Oxford UP:
2013.
Neurath, Otto; Carnap, Rudolf; Morris, Charles W. (eds.) (1969). Foundations of
the Unity of Science: Toward an International Encyclopedia of Unified Science.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1969.
Russell, Bertrand (1946). History of Western Philosophy. London: Routledge, 2004.
Severino, Emanuele (1983). A Cesare e a Dio. Milano: Bur, 2007.
---. (2012). Capitalismo senza futuro. Milano: Bur, 2012.
---. (2013). Intorno al senso del nulla. Milano: Adelphi, 2013.
---. (1996). La filosofia dai greci al nostro tempo: la filosofia contemporanea. Milano: Bur,
2017.
COSMOS AND HISTORY 386