(9789004183490 - A Companion To Henry of Ghent) VIII. Henry of Ghent On Individuation, Essence, and Being
(9789004183490 - A Companion To Henry of Ghent) VIII. Henry of Ghent On Individuation, Essence, and Being
HENRY OF GHENT ON
INDIVIDUATION, ESSENCE, AND BEING
Martin Pickavé
1 According to Stephen Brown, for instance, subsistence is Henry’s candidate for the
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
I. Individuation
2 For Henry’s debate with Giles and Godfrey on being and essence see Jean Paulus,
constitutive of a species.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
fully in Plato, Socrates, you, me and every other human being; there
are no degrees of ‘humanness’. The form is not divided like a cake is
divided among the people eating it; in fact, the form enjoys a special
kind of unity that makes it impossible that it could be divided like a
cake at all. What it means to be human (i.e., to be rational, having a
body etc.) is indifferent to the fact that it might be instantiated in this or
that individual, but there are many distinct human beings. The upshot
of this is that specific forms cannot be divided into many individuals
by something intrinsic to the forms or by other substantial forms, for
this would ultimately mean that Socrates and Plato differ in humanity.
Such a form can only be divided per accidens, i.e., by something extrin-
sic or accidental to it. For this very reason we talk about individuation
of forms, and not about their division; individuation applies to some-
thing that, as the name indicates, is in itself indivisible. As we see, for
Henry the issue of individuation concerns primarily the multiplication
of forms.4
What is the feature extrinsic to forms and capable of multiplying them,
the “cause and reason of individuation” (causa et ratio individuationis)?
Although it must be something accidental, for it relates to forms merely
extrinsically, the principle of individuation is of course not an accident in
the proper sense of accident. Accidents are ontologically posterior to the
things in which they inhere. Hence, they cannot cause the individuality
of their underlying substances. Rather the opposite: accidents are indi-
viduated by their subjects and only render their subject’s individuality
manifest.5
At least in case of material objects, matter is often taken to be what
causes the multiplication of forms. Henry agrees with this, broadly speak-
ing, Aristotelian picture of individuation. What allows matter to individ-
uate forms is the fact that matter, before it receives a substantial form, first
receives the form of quantity and so has extension and dimensions. But in
4 For Henry’s explanation of the meaning of individuatio see Henry of Ghent, Quodli-
bet V, q. , ed. Badius (Paris, ; repr. Leuven, ), fol. vGH; id., Quodlibet II, q. ,
ed. Robert Wielockx (Leuven, ), p. . For the different meanings the term individ-
uatio can adopt in the late th and early th centuries see my “The Controversy over
the Principle of Individuation”. This article also contains a more detailed interpretation
of Henry’s teaching on individuation than the one proposed here. In particular, it also
reflects on Henry’s sources.
5 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rIK; see also id., Quodlibet II,
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
6 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rvL. Here someone might object
that quantity is an accident and therefore, as was said earlier, unable to account for the
individuation of its subject, which is ontologically prior. Henry counters this with the dis-
tinction between determinate and indeterminate dimensions. The quantity that individu-
ates forms in matter simply gives extension and dimensions to matter, but not determinate
extension or dimensions. Understood in this sense, indeterminate dimensions are onto-
logically prior to the composite substance, whereas determinate dimensions are always
posterior. For the background of this distinction see Silvia Donati, “Materia e dimensioni
tra XIII e XIV secolo: la dottrina delle dimensiones indeterminatae,” Quaestio (),
pp. –.
7 See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet II, q. , ed. R. Wielockx, p. . For this expres-
sion see Etienne Gilson, “Les ‘philosophantes’,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et litteraire
du moyen âge (), pp. –; Pierre Michaud-Quantin, “Pour le dossier des
‘Philosophantes’,” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et litteraire du moyen âge (), pp. –
.
8 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet II, q. , ed. R. Wielockx, p. ; id., Quodlibet V, q. , ed.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
10 See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fols. v–rM. The expression
‘supposit’ has its origin in discussions on the nature of Christ. In the vocabulary of
medieval theologians, Christ has two natures (divine and human) in one supposit. On
Henry’s understanding of suppositum see Gordon Wilson, “Supposite in the Philosophy
of Henry of Ghent,” in Henry of Ghent. Proceedings of the International Colloquium on
the Occasion of the th Anniversary of his Death (), ed. Willy Vanhamel (Leuven,
), pp. –. Wilson also discusses Quodlibet V, q. at some length at pp. –
.
11 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet XI, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rV. See also id., Quodlibet III,
q. , ed. Badius, fol. vL. For God as the ultimate causa individuationis see id., Quodli-
bet II, q. , ed. Wielockx, p. .
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
12 Henry must have in mind here what his contemporaries refer to as “designated
supposito super formam quo habet esse hoc et quo per ipsam formam habet esse hoc,
quia est huius? Dico aliquid praeter materiam et praeter agens quod est quasi dispositio
suppositi inquantum suppositum est, quod non potest esse materia nec agens. Haec enim
dispositio derelicta est circa formam in supposito et facit suppositum esse suppositum,
ut habens formam et rationem compositionis ex forma et ratione determinationis in
ipsa. Hoc enim viso videbitur ratio suppositi et individuationis proxima et quid est quod
suppositum formaliter faciat in creaturis.” See also id., Quodlibet XI, q. , ed. Badius,
fol. rV.
14 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet II, q. , ed. R. Wielockx, p. , –: “Et sic non est
dicendum quod hoc solo differunt quia natura unius non est natura alterius—eadem,
dico, secundum numerum—, sed quia subsistentia unius non est subsistentia alterius,
quae facit differre essentiam ut est in uno ab ipsa ut est in altero . . . Ipsa enim subsistentia
in supposito omnino necessaria est ad essentiae existentiam actualem, tam in uno quam
in altero, non secundum idem numero, sed secundum aliud et aliud numero, consimile
tamen specie.”
15 On the meaning of the term ‘subsistence’ see below p. .
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
infinite regress. But since that is impossible, then the individuating ele-
ment must be either something negative or a positive relation. The latter
can be ruled out right away. For a relation is grounded in some really
existing thing, i.e., in a thing that is already a complete supposit. Thus,
there remains only something negative, a negation, and so Henry con-
cludes that individuation happens by a negation. He explains the nature
of this negation in the following terms:
This negation is not a simple one, but a double negation. For it removes
from the inside any possibility for plurification and diversity and removes
from the outside any identity, so that in this way the form is called this
form, because it is only this form, not having inside of it the possibility to
be this and another one, a possibility possessed by the form of a species.
And moreover, it is only this form because it is not the form of other things
of the same species.
Henry goes on to calls such a double negation the principle that individ-
uates essences and that establishes a supposit.16
John Duns Scotus had the negative account of individuation in mind
when he objected to Henry that a merely negative principle could never
cause individuation, because it could not cause anything at all.17 How-
ever, it should be clear that the negative account is only one side of the
coin, and the positive account, according to which subsistence individu-
ates, is the other side of the same coin. Modern interpreters too are often
unaware of this, but Henry explains the relationship himself. In Quodli-
bet XI, q. he concludes his discussion of the individuation of angels with
the following remark:
And in this way the positive individuation of the form takes place effec-
tively only through the producing agent and formally only through this
being [i.e., the being proper to the supposit]. But I have explained some-
where else how individuation happens to take place negatively.18
Notice that Henry here describes the subsistence (through which a
form has being in a supposit) as that which “formally” causes the indi-
viduation of a form.19 This does not mean that subsistence is a form,
but that among all the causes involved in individuation (such as the
16 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rM. See also id., Quaestiones
ordinariae (Summa), art. XXXIX, q. ad , ed. Gordon Wilson (Leuven, ), pp. –
.
17 See, e.g., Ordinatio II, dist. , p. , q. , nn. –, Opera omnia VII, ed. Vaticana
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
20 The idea to analyse individuation in terms of the four causes was quite common in
the late th century and it seems to have become even more common after Henry of
Ghent. See my article “The Controversy over the Principle of Individuation.”
21 In Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa), art. XXXIX, q. ad , ed. G. Wilson, pp. –
, Henry seems to anticipate Scotus’s objection. But there he simply refers to the
(extrinsic) agent as the positive thing effectively causing the individuation of a universal
essence.
22 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet II, q. , ed. R. Wielockx, pp. – and –; id.,
to Henry, we grasp and define unity in terms of a negation: one is what is not divided
in itself. But in reality unity is something positive. See, e.g., Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
ordinariae (Summa), art. XXV, q. , ed. Badius (Paris, ; repr. St. Bonaventure, NY,
), fol. vE. For Henry’s views about (transcendental) unity see my Heinrich von
Gent über Metaphysik als erste Wissenschaft: Studien zu einem Metaphysikentwurf aus dem
letzten Viertel des . Jahrhunderts (Leiden, ), pp. –.
24 This sort of criticism was put forward by Thomas Sutton. See his Quaestiones ordi-
nariae, q. , ed. Johannes Schneider (Munich, ), pp. –. See also Gyula Klima,
“Thomas Sutton on Individuation,” Proceedings of the Society for Medieval Logic and Meta-
physics [http://faculty.fordham.edu/hlima/SMLM/PSMLMS.pdf] (), pp. –.
25 For some of following see my Heinrich von Gent über Metaphysik, chapter IV. A sur-
vey of the debate about the distinction between essence and existence (and its sources)
can be found in John Wippel, “Essence and Existence,” in The Cambridge History of Later
Medieval Philosophy: From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasti-
cism –, ed. Norman Kretzmann et al. (Cambridge, ), pp. –. Henry’s
ontology is also discussed in a series of older studies: see Jean Paulus, Henri de Gand.
Essai sur les tendances de sa métaphysique (Paris, ); Paul Bayerschmidt, Die Seins-
und Formmetaphysik des Heinrich von Gent in ihrer Anwendung auf die Christologie: eine
philosophie- und dogmengeschichtliche Studie (Münster, ); José Gómez Caffarena, Ser
participado y ser subsistente en la metafísica de Enrique de Gante (Rome, ).
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
For Henry, every single existing thing has an essence, which deter-
mines what it is, and also has existence. Obviously there must be a dis-
tinction of some sort between the two. If my actual existence were iden-
tical with or part of my essence, then my existence would be necessary.
My existence would be part of my essence in the same way in which
the sum of angles equal to two right angles is part of the essence of
triangle. But that is obviously not the case, for it is clearly possible for
me not to exist. If, however, there is a difference between actual exis-
tence and the essence of an object, how can we best capture this differ-
ence?
Maybe essence and actual existence differ in the way two things (res)
differ. Henry, who accuses Thomas Aquinas of holding such a position
about the relationship between essence and existence,26 opposes this view
strongly. But rather than Thomas Aquinas, it was Giles of Rome’s recent
defense of the so-called real distinction between essence and existence
that prompted Henry to take a position on this issue in his first Quodlibet.
Henry uses four main arguments against the real distinction. The first
argument points out that if essence and existence were two things, then
every creature or contingent being would be a real composite of two
things and could never really be one substance (i.e., a true ens per se). The
second and third of Henry’s standard arguments ask what kind of thing
this added existence could be. Presumably the thing ‘existence’ would
itself be something created. But if that were so, then this existence would
have its own existence from something else. For it seems to be a feature of
creatures that they do not have their existence from themselves but from
their creator. But then we have to ask the same question about this other
existence. This leads to an infinite regress unless we stop at one existence
which has its being from itself. Yet there seems to be no good reason why
a particular created being should have its existence from itself and why
this should not have applied to the essence from which we started. The
third argument asks even more specifically: Of what sort is the added
thing ‘existence’. Is it a substance or an accident? Henry then goes on
26 See Henry’s remarks in Quodlibet I, q. , ed. Raymond Macken (Leuven, ), p. ,
where he blames certain theologians (theologi) for not spotting the apparent falsity of
this view. The direct quotations from Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae in other parts of the
quodlibetal question (see pp. –) leave no doubt that Henry has Aquinas in mind.
According to Edgar Hocedez, Henry is here mainly targeting Giles of Rome’s teaching; see
Edgar Hocedez, “Le premier quodlibet d’Henri de Gand (),” Gregorianum (),
pp. –.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
27 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet I, q. , ed. R. Macken, pp. –. Henry repeats some of
these arguments in Quodlibet X, q. , ed. Raymond Macken, (Leuven, ), pp. –.
The second argument can also be found in Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa), art. XXVII,
q. , ed. Badius, fol. vM. For an ‘Averroistic’ background of Henry’s arguments argues
Ruedi Imbach, “Averroistische Stellungnahmen zur Diskussion über das Verhältnis von
esse und essentia: von Siger von Brabant zu Thaddaeus von Parma,” in Studi sul XIV secolo
in memoria di Anneliese Maier, ed. Alfonso Maierù and Agostino Paravicini Bagliani
(Rome, ), pp. – at –.
28 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet I, q. , ed. R. Macken, pp. –. In other words:
For Henry the proponents of the real distinction have a misguided understanding of
what participation in being (and therefore creation) amounts to. For other passages in
which Henry accuses proponents of the real distinction of a mistaken understanding of
participation see ibid., pp. –; id., Quodlibet X, q. , ed. R. Macken, pp. –; id.,
Quodlibet XI, q. . For another error allegedly committed by them see id., Quaestiones
ordinariae (Summa), art. XXIX, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rF.
29 For Henry this amounts to making creatures into necessary beings like God. See
bet X, q. , ed. Raymond Macken (Leuven, ), p. . In this last text Henry writes
that he is not picky about what this distinction (or addition) is called.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
31 See, e.g., Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa), art. XXI, q. , ed. Badius,
fol. vP. In this passage, as in many others, Henry explains the relationship between
essence and existence by using the example of light (lux) and the act of shining (lucere)
or life (vita) and living (vivere). There is no act of living without life and no actual shining
without light. However, life is not strictly speaking the same as the act of living. One can
observe this in the way we speak: for if they were strictly identical it would be true to say
‘life is the act of living’ or ‘light is the act of shining’, which is not true. For these examples
see also ibid., fol. rTV and Quodlibet I, q. , ed. R. Macken, p. .
32 Quaestiones de esse et essentia, q. (ed. Venice, ), fol. va.
33 For the following see Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet X, q. , ed. R. Macken, pp. –.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
tually distinct from an animal. There are many animals that are not ratio-
nal. That this case is different from the other two can also be gathered
from the fact that it is certainly possible that an animal is not rational,
whereas it is impossible for something rational not to be an animal.34
Henry is convinced that the previous examples are strong evidence of
the need for an intermediary distinction, but I doubt his opponents were
much impressed. After all, a genus does not really exist without a specific
difference, so it is not clear what the example is supposed to show.35 But
Henry’s general point is less opaque than it seems. His point is only that
some items, when added to something, simply add something else (as
an accident adds to a substance), but that other items do not really add
anything but rather contract that to which they are added. To make this
clear is the primary goal of the example of genus and difference. In the
same way, existence contracts the essence, i.e., makes it an essence that
exists at a certain time and place.
The comparison between Giles of Rome, a defender of the real dis-
tinction between being and essence, and Henry makes clear that Henry
has a very strict understanding of what a thing (res) is supposed to
be. A thing is “whatever is a nature or some absolute essence having
an exemplary reason in God.”36 Hence it is obvious why being is not a
thing different from the essence. Being itself does not have an essence
or a corresponding divine idea. Being is simply the act of an essence.
But what does count as a true thing (res)? Henry’s teaching on divine
ideas provides us with some cues. For Henry there are divine ideas
only of species and moreover only of species of substances, quanti-
ties, and qualities. Genera, numbers, relations, fictitious beings etc. have
no corresponding ideas in the divine mind.37 The fact that he denies
34 Henry’s three examples are influenced by a similar distinction that we can find in
Thomas Aquinas’s Quaestiones disputatae de veritate, q. , a. . For this background see
my Heinrich von Gent über Metaphysik, pp. –. After Henry’s response to Giles in
Quodlibet X, q. , Giles responded to Henry with questions and of the Quaestiones
de esse et essentia. Here again he accuses Henry of proposing an unintelligible distinction.
A short time after (in ), Henry replied in his eleventh Quodlibet (q. , ed. Badius,
fol. vR–rX), accusing Giles of misunderstanding the nature of the intentional
distinction by failing to see that it is a distinction sui generis.
35 As we will see later, Henry himself holds that a genus does not have real existence
of res see also my Heinrich von Gent über Metaphysik, chapter IV.
37 See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet VII, qq. + , ed. G. Wilson (Leuven, ), p. ,–
. For this text see Theo Kobusch, “Heinrich von Gent und die neuplatonische Ideen-
lehre,” in Néoplatonisme et philosophie médiévale, ed. Leo Benakis (Turnhout, ),
pp. – at –.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
38 According to Henry, the mistake of the proponents of the real distinction (like Giles
of Rome) is that they do not see this difference and that they think everything that is not
distinct from something else by a real difference is strictly identical with it. See Henry of
Ghent, Quodlibet XI, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rQ.
39 See, for instance, Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet IV, q. .
40 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rE–F.
41 Compare also the third argument against the real addition of existence (see above
nt. ) and the argument in Quodlibet II, q. ad , ed. R. Wielockx, pp. –. Henry
argues in the first instance that existence cannot be a thing because it does not fall under
any of the ten categories (which he apparently considers as an exhaustive classification
of things); in the second case he uses this same line of thought to show that that which
causes something to be an individual form cannot be a thing.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
42 This is, for instance, what Godfrey of Fontaines takes subsistence to be (according
to John Wippel). See Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Godfrey of Fontaines, p. .
43 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet XI, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vQ. See also Quodlibet II, q. ,
ed. R. Wielockx, p. , where Henry distinguishes subsistentia in supposito and existentia
essentiae by explaining that the former is a necessary requirement for the later.
44 See also Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet III, q. . On Avicenna’s influence on Henry’s
est ex ratione essentiae ut est essentia absolute, duplex est in ea indifferentia. Uno enim
modo indifferens est ad esse actualis existentiae et ad non esse . . . alio vero modo est
indifferens ad esse universale et particulare.” For the distinction between subsistence and
existence see also Walter Hoeres, “Wesen und Dasein bei Heinrich von Gent und Duns
Scotus,” Franziskanische Studien (), pp. – at .
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
Henry is by no means the first to use the expression esse essentiae. It can already be found
in Roger Bacon’s questions on Aristotle’s Metaphysics. See Questiones supra libros prime
philosophie Aristotelis, lib. VII, ed. Robert Steele (Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi X,
Oxford, ), p. ; Questiones altere supra libros prime philosophie, lib. II, ed. Robert
Steele (Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi XI, Oxford, ), p. . The history of this
expression has still to be written.
47 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet I, q. , ed. R. Macken, pp. –. For the distinction
between esse essentiae and esse existentiae see also id., Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa),
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
art. XXI, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vK; ibid., q. , fol. rE–vG; ibid., q. , fol. rO–vR; id.,
Quodlibet III, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vE; id., Quodlibet III, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rO; id.,
Quodlibet X, q. , ed. R. Macken, p. , and many other texts.
48 For the accidentality of actual existence see, for instance, Henry of Ghent, Quod-
libet I, q. , ed. R. Macken, p. ; id., Quodlibet X, q. , ed. R. Macken, p. ; id.,
Quodlibet XI, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rvQ. For the view that esse existentiae is not the
object of knowledge see Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa), art. XXVI, q. , ed. Badius,
fol. rD. Henry does of course not claim that actual existence is an accidens—this would
be at odds with his rejection of the real distinction—but only that it behaves “in the way
of an accidens” (modum accidentis).
49 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet III, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rO. The edition has ad formam
being itself to be a relation. See, for instance, Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones ordinariae
(Summa), art. XXVII, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vM: “Esse existentiae cuiuslibet creaturae
non sit nisi esse quod est ad aliud se habere.” However, this means only that existence is
related to something else, but not that existence is a relation. For otherwise Henry should
rather have said that existence non sit nisi ad aliud esse. For Henry’s theory of relations
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
understood in the sense that there is one relatum, the creature, and the
other, God, and by means of the relations existing between them, the first
receives being. This would make the creatures somewhat independent of
the relation to God; but the creatures exist only as a result of the divine
production, namely as the endpoint (terminus) of such a production.
Thus without the relation existing in the first place there is nothing that
could be related to God at all. The talk about being resulting from a
relation to God simply means that creatures are dependent on their first
cause because they are caused by God insofar as God is their formal
and efficient cause. However, the two relations according to which the
creatures are related to the first cause are not only distinct with respect
to what they refer in God and to what they cause in the creatures,
they also differ from each other insofar as the relation to God’s ideas is
eternal, whereas the relation to God as the first efficient cause is only
temporal.51
As was already said, we should not imagine that there really exists
a set of essences of which some have essential being and some also
existential being, depending on their relation to God. In many places
Henry make clear that he considers it wrong to think that essences are
something absolutely prior in reality and that they receive, as subjects,
being of whatever kind.52 This picture has only heuristic value; it follows
our human way of capturing the ontological structure of a creature,
for we first think of a thing’s essence and then of its various modes
of being.53 Keeping this in mind, the reference to the formal exemplar
in God, the divine ideas, indicates that one of the roles of essential
being is to demarcate those essences that can possibly exist from those
see Mark G. Henninger, Relations. Medieval Theories – (Oxford, ), pp. –
; Jos Decorte, “Relation and Substance in Henry of Ghent’s Metaphysics,” in Henry of
Ghent and the Transformation of Scholastic Thought, ed. Guy Guldentops and Carlos Steel
(Leuven, ), pp. –, and Decorte’s publications mentioned below in nt. .
51 Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa), art. XXI, q. , ed. Badius, fol.
he denounces the proponents of the real distinction for committing this mistake.
53 Similarly, I consider the many passages where Henry analyses creatures starting
from the notion of res as passages aimed at a structural analysis of the different ontological
features of creatures. See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rD;
id., Quodlibet VII, qq. + , ed. G. Wilson, pp. ,–,; id., Quaestiones ordinariae
(Summa), art. XXI, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vK; id., Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa),
art. XXXIV, q. , ed. Raymond Macken (Leuven, ), p. . On these passages see
my Heinrich von Gent über Metaphysik, pp. – and –.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
that cannot exist and are pure figments of the mind.54 Presumably the
essences of goat-stags and unicorns—if it is even correct to talk about
essences here—have no essential being. For this would indicate that goat-
stags and unicorns are not only producible in principle (because they
do not involve a contradiction), but also actually producible, because
God would have decided that the actual world is a world in which goat-
stags and unicorns can exist. The reference to God may sound odd here.
Imagine that someone asks “Why do these animals exist in our present
world and not those?”, and someone else responds “Because only the first
have a corresponding idea in God.” Not everyone will be happy with
such an answer and many people will wonder whether this counts as
an answer at all. But that seems to be exactly Henry’s point: for things
that involve no contradiction in themselves we cannot give a reason why
they rather than other things have the capacity to exist, because that
depends entirely on God, and is therefore unknowable to us in this life.
This does not mean that it is up to God’s free will which essences the
world exhibits and which not. For Henry, creatures and their essences
are likenesses of God, and so are determined by God.55 However, in our
present state we have no cognitive access to God except by means of
the created essences themselves. And this process of gaining knowledge
of the divine will never lead us to a non-circular criterion for possible
essences.56
q. , ed. R. Macken, p. , where Henry makes the distinction between the esse essentiae
as based on the creatures’ imitational similitude with the divine essence and the esse
existentiae as grounded in God’s will. Notice that there is no contradiction involved when
Henry sometimes says that esse essentiae derives from a relation to the ideas in God and
sometimes claims that creatures and their essences are likenesses of God (or the divine
essence). The ideas in God are nothing else than the divine essence under the aspect of its
imitability. See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet IX, q. , ed. Raymond Macken (Leuven, ),
pp. –.
56 For a more detailed account of Henry’s teaching on possibilia see Pasquale Porro,
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
But at this point one might reiterate the question regarding the rela-
tionship between being and essences on the level of essences themselves:
how do essences differ from essential being? It is hard to imagine that
there could be a difference at all: Is it not through the same relationship
to a divine idea that something is an essence and has essential being? In
some texts, Henry therefore states that essence and essential being dif-
fer only rationally (sola ratione). The being of essence (esse essentiae) is
so intimately connected to the essence itself that there is no more robust
distinction possible.57 But in Summa art. XXI, q. , Henry seems to be
of a different opinion. There he explicitly speaks of an intentional dis-
tinction between essence and essential being.58 Scholars have tried to
explain this discrepancy by assuming a change of mind on Henry’s part,59
but for two reasons that is not entirely convincing. First, Henry goes
on to describe the relationship between essence and essential being as
a rational distinction even after the question in the Summa.60 Second,
article XXI, q. of the Summa is written in close temporal proximity to
the first Quodlibet and is full of cross-references to q. of the latter, in
which he defends the rational distinction between essence and essential
being. The puzzle disappears when we become aware of the two different
ways in which Henry uses the term ‘essence’ in these two sorts of texts.
In the Quodlibet and texts emphasizing the rational distinction, ‘essence’
is taken to signify the essence as a whole including its essential being.
A real essence, i.e., an essence that falls under one of the ten categories
and that can really exist because it corresponds to a divine idea, is not
distinct from its essential being. It is only conceptually distinguishable.
But if we use ‘essence’ not to denote the essence as a whole but to denote
the “thingness” (res) or “content” to which an idea may or may not cor-
respond in the divine mind, then such an essence only forms part of a
real essence as a whole. Here, essential being and the essence it qualifies
a form (for instance, a form that makes them actually existing), but rather insofar as they
can be the endpoint of a (possible) production. For this distinction see especially Henry
of Ghent, Quodlibet X, q. , ed. R. Macken, pp. –.
57 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet I, q. , ed. R. Macken, p. .
58 Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa), art. XXI, q. , ed. Badius, fol.
vQ.
59 See, e.g., Gómez Caffarena, Ser participado y ser subsistente, pp. –; Porro,
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
are more distinct, because together they make up the essence as a whole.
And since in this sense the essential being is said to contract the essence
to that which is actually possible, their distinctness must be of a different
kind.61
For some people, Henry’s talk about essential being sounds like the symp-
tom of an overly baroque ontology. Why introduce kinds of being? Is not
existence the only intelligible form of being? In the previous chapters we
have already encountered one of Henry’s motives for introducing essen-
tial being. We can imagine “essences” of things, but only some of them
are actually capable of existing; essential being distinguishes those from
the rest. Moreover, only of things that have this capacity of existing in
reality can we give a true definition, for only these things can be objects
of the intellect,62 the cognitive faculty through which we are able to form
definitions. And a definition expresses what a thing “is”.63 So real essences
must have some sort of being.
One of the worries is that the idea of essential being seems to lead to
a sort of Platonism. Remember that for Henry the relationship between
the divine ideas and the essence is eternal: does this not also mean that
the essential being is a being that the essence has from eternity? But
if something has such an eternal being, does it not then exist some-
where from eternity? Maybe in a separate realm of intelligibles? Some
interpreters approach the esse essentiae by asking whether it is a sort
of real being or a sort of mental being. In line with Avicenna, Henry
insists that everything that exists exists either in the mind or in (extra-
mental) reality. So the question is whether essential being is closer to the
first or to the second kind of being. But as Pasquale Porro and others
61 In the passage where he allegedly applies the intentional distinction to the relation-
ship between essence and essential being, Henry himself remarks on the different ways
of talking about essence and essential being. See Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones ordinariae
(Summa), art. XXI, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vP. For more on this see my Heinrich von Gent
über Metaphysik, pp. –.
62 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vD.
63 There are various passages in which Henry identifies the esse essentiae with the being
indicated in a definition. See, e.g., Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet I, q. , ed. Macken, pp. –
.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
64 See, e.g., Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet III, q. , ed. Badius, fol. vO. Porro, “Possibilità
ed esse essentiae,” pp. –. The most prominent defender of a “realist” understanding
of esse essentiae is John Wippel. See “The Existence of Nonexisting Possibilities,” pp. –
.
65 Porro, “Possibilità ed esse essentiae,” p. . See, for instance, also Henry of Ghent,
Quaestiones ordinariae (Summa), art. XXXII, q. , ed. R. Macken, p. , –: “A cuius
simplicitate deficit omnis creatura, scilicet quia ipsa res quae ipsa est non est cuius esse,
sed habet ab alio esse tam essentiae quam existentiae.”
66 See Jos Decorte, “Thomas Aquinas and Henry of Ghent on God’s Relation to the
World,” Mediaevalia (), pp. – at –; id., “ ‘Modus’ or ‘res’: Scotus’
Criticism of Henry of Ghent’s Conception of the Reality of a Real Relation,” in Via Scoti.
Methodologica ad mentem Joannis Duns Scoti. Atti del Congresso Scotistico Internazionale,
Roma – marzo , ed. Leonardo Sileo (Rome, ), pp. – at – and
; and id., “Relatio as Modus Essendi: The Origins of Henry of Ghent’s Definition of
Relation,” International Journal of Philosophical Studies (), pp. – at .
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
67 See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rD–vE: “Res creata in
pp. –.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
quality in Plato is changed so that he, Plato, becomes white. Socrates will
immediately become similar to him, and this without any kind of real
change (i.e., without the acquisition of a “thing”) in Socrates.69 This argu-
ment shows that a too realist conception of relations would lead to the
absurd consequence that things are constantly changing and in transfor-
mation because they constantly enter into relations with new objects.
The details of Henry’s teaching on relations do not have to occupy us
here. I used the example of relations only to illustrate that each categori-
cal being is a composite of a ratio and a res praedicamenti, although in
the case of relations the latter is even borrowed from that categorical
being on which the relation is founded. What is important here is that
Henry connects his compositional account of categorical being with the
essence/esse essentiae distinction: the esse essentiae is the ratio praedica-
menti.70 If this interpretation is correct, one of the philosophical motives
for Henry’s introduction of essential being lies in his account of the cat-
egories and what falls under them.
For Henry creatures are complex things. They are complex not because
they are composed out of many different things nor because they only
appear to us as complex, but because they have an intrinsic ontologi-
cal structure below the level of a real composition.71 An individual sub-
stance, a human being, for instance, is composed out of a res (which
accounts primarily for what a human being is), and a series of ‘intentions’
added to it: essential being, being in a supposit, existence and maybe oth-
ers. The res itself can be further analysed in term of the intentions that
69 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet VII, qq. + , ed. G. Wilson, pp. ,–,: “Si relatio
poneret propriam realitatem a realitate sui fundamenti in suo subiecto relato, tunc de se
non relatum aliqua relatione, puta similitudine, quia nullum habet in se respectu alicuius
alterius, puta Sortes albus in respectu ad Platonem nigrum, non fieret relatum ad illud
similitudine quam haberet in se de novo et prius non habuit, nisi quia res aliqua de novo
facta est in eo, quae prius in eo non fuit. Hoc autem non est possibile fieri in aliquo sine
propria sui transmutatione. Sortes ergo similis Platoni non posset fieri similis eidem sine
sua transmutatione reali. Consequens falsum est, quia Platone transmutato . . ., ut de
nigro fiat albus, statim Sortes sine omni sua transmutatione de novo factus est similis
Platoni.”
70 See, e.g., the text in nt. above. For more on this see my Heinrich von Gent über
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
make it up: in our case, in the intentions ‘animal’, ‘rational’ etc. Such an
analysis of objects in terms of their intentional composition characterizes
the metaphysician’s point of view.72
Henry’s choice of the term ‘intention’ (intentio) might not have been
so fortunate. Intentio is sometimes used as a synonym for ratio, which,
when used in contrast with the term res, often simply means ‘concept’ or
that aspect of a thing that has been captured by a concept, whereas for
Henry the intentio is clearly more then a mere concept or its content.
For each of the intentions corresponds to something distinct ex parte
rei; or to be more precise: to each intention corresponds something ex
parte rei intellectae et conceptae, because without an intellect capable of
grasping the various ontological aspects of a thing there would be no such
intentions.73 This explains why Henry says that every intentio is also a
ratio, but not every ratio is an intentio, for it is not necessary that rationes
correspond to a distinction ex parte rei.74
At this point someone might object and point to Henry’s views regard-
ing the distinction between species and genus. For Henry (ultimate)
species have a natural unity, independent of the human mind, whereas
a genus has only unity through the mind.75 In other words: species
seem to be truly real, but a genus does not. If the intentional analysis
of an object leads to intentions like ‘animal’ or ‘substance’ etc., which
are intentions corresponding to genera, then it looks as if it leads to
something to which nothing corresponds ex parte rei. Note however that
Henry’s remarks about the unity of species and genus do not translate
into statements about their reality. Ultimate species have a special sort of
72 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet IV, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rB. Henry himself calls such an
fol. rX. See also ibid., art. XXVII, q. , ad , ed. Badius, fols. vM–vR; id., Quodli-
bet V, q. ; ibid., q. , ed. Badius, fol. rXY. See also Hoeres, “Wesen und Dasein,”
pp. –; Porro, “Possibilità ed esse essentiae,” pp. –.
74 See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rV: “Quaecumque
differunt intentione, differunt ratione, non econverso. Propter quod frequenter intentio
ratio appellatur.”
75 See Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rE. The passage in question
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
76 For we cannot find in nature beings that are instantiations of genera but not of
species.
77 That, according to Henry, the intentions and the intentional distinction deal, in a
certain sense, with really existing differences (without dealing with differences among
things), can also be gathered from passages where Henry approaches the intentional
distinction to the real distinction. See, e.g., Henry of Ghent, Quaestiones ordinariae
(Summa), art. XXVII, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rN: “ . . . et sic quodammodo re differunt
essentia creaturae et esse eius . . .” But only quodammodo! For further discussion of
the differences between res, intentio, and ratio see Roland J. Teske, “Distinctions in the
Metaphysics of Henry of Ghent,” Traditio (), pp. –; Hoeres, “Wesen und
Dasein.”
78 On the general importance of the intentional distinction in Henry’s philosophy
vP.
80 Henry of Ghent, Quodlibet V, q. , ed. Badius, fol. rvL. See also Teske, “Distinc-
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
q. , fol. rO–vP for the identification of Avicenna’s esse proprium with Henry’s esse
essentiae. For Henry’s Avicennian background see also Porro, “Universaux et esse essen-
tiae.”
84 See my Heinrich von Gent über Metaphysik, pp. –.
85 There is of course the question whether Henry interpreted Avicenna correctly. This
does not have to occupy us here. But given Avicenna’s importance regarding the issues
mentioned, the debate Henry’s ontological views triggered also show elements of a debate
about the correct interpretation of Avicenna’s ontology.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
martin pickavé
86 For the debate about individuation see my “The Controversy over the Principle of
Individuation”; Ruedi Imbach’s list of authors involved in the debate over the distinction
between being and essence also includes many who are influenced (either positively
or negatively) by Henry. See “Gravis iactura verae doctrinae: Prolegomena zu einer
Interpretation der Schrift De ente et essentia Dietrichs von Freiberg O.P.,” Freiburger
Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Theologie (), pp. – at –.
87 See the literature in nt. above.
88 For a general survey of Henry’s influence see Pasquale Porro, “An Historiographical
Image of Henry of Ghent”, in Henry of Ghent, ed. W. Vanhamel, pp. –. For more
reactions to Henry’s ontology see Francis E. Kelley, “Two Early English Thomists: Thomas
Sutton and Robert Orford vs. Henry of Ghent,” The Thomist (), pp. –.
Raymond Macken, Bibliotheca manuscripta Henrici de Gandavo (Leuven, ), vol. ,
pp. – contains an impressive repertory of both abbreviations of Henry’s works
and of works composed to attack Henry’s teachings. A survey of Henry’s influence on
theologians at Oxford can be found in Jeremy I. Catto, “Theology and Theologians –
,” in The History of the University of Oxford. Vol. I: The Early Oxford Schools, ed.
J.I. Catto (Oxford, ), pp. –, esp. –.
89 For his criticism of esse essentiae see, e.g., Ordinatio II, dist. , p. , q. , n. , Opera
omnia VII, ed. Vaticana, p. . On Scotus’s response to Henry’s teaching on categories
see Giorgio Pini, Categories and Logic in Duns Scotus: an Interpretation of Aristotle’s
Categories in the Late Thirteenth Century (Leiden, ); id., “Scotus’s Realist Conception
of the Categories: His Legacy to Late Medieval Debates,” Vivarium (), pp. –.
90 See nt. above.
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College
henry of ghent on individuation, essence, and being
91 This has been shown, already some time ago, in Hoeres, “Wesen und Dasein.”
M. Pickavé - 9789004193451
Downloaded from Brill.com11/23/2021 11:19:50PM
via Boston College