TL 1 'LL, ' Is
TL 1 'LL, ' Is
** Tl 1
'll
, ■’ IS
•■ .:■••••• .
• :: :
qj&iSsO?--- '; _
“A brilliant essay in cultural history,
gracefully written and full of wide-rang¬
ing imaginative insights. Saisselin’s book
is a pioneering contribution to the his¬
tory of consumer culture.”
—Jackson Lears
THE BIBELOT
Digitized by the Internet Archive
in 2018 with funding from
Kahle/Austin Foundation
https://archive.org/details/bourgeoisbibelotOOsais
New Brunswick, New Jersey
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Bibliography: p.
Includes index.
1. Art and society—History—19th century. 2. Civilization, Modern—19th
century 3. Art—Collectors and collecting. 4. Art as investment. I. Title.
N72.S6S24 1984 701'.03'09034 84-4701
ISBN 0-8135-1062-7
Illustrations vii
Preface ijc
Abbreviations yvii
ONE
Tivoli: Art and History 1
TWO
Paris and the Aesthetics of the Flaneur 17
THREE
FOUR
FIVE
six
Cosmopolis, or the Snob’s Progress 117
SEVEN
v
VI
Contents
Indey 181
I-L-L-U-S-T-R-A-T-I-O-N-S
Brutus (painting)
1
vu
Vlll
Illustrations
i
Preface
I
Preface
There was a time when the tourists at Tivoli did not get out of buses to
find a square filled with souvenirs and kitsch. There was a time when
only ladies, gentlemen, cognoscenti, amateurs of the arts, scholars and
artists, poets and writers came to Tivoli. They stepped out of coaches
to sketch, and think, and seek inspiration, or just to have been there;
for Tivoli was part of a gentleman’s education in the eighteenth cen¬
tury. And in the romantic period of the nineteenth century, the liter-
arily inclined wrote as they set on some stone bench in the gardens of
the Villa d’Este, or in the shadows of the pines, by rippling waters,
pages on beauty and human destiny. They knew that works of art and
monuments were not bibelots, that art and time and history were very
serious matters. And these travelers also knew—and found appropri¬
ate—that it was not given to all, and ought not to be given to all, to
pose in the Roman countryside or climb the hill to Tivoli.
When Corinne, heroine of fiction created by anything but a fictitious
Madame de Stael, nee Germaine Necker, adoring daughter of a Gene¬
van banker turned minister of finance under Louis XVI, took her lover
Lord Oswald to her villa at Tivoli, there were no bibelots sold in the
village square. She took Lord Oswald, romantic, melancholy, and pro¬
found man of the North, to show him her collection of paintings,
which were not bibelots. They were in a literal way significant; they
were signs; they had meaning, presumably universal. The collection
3
4
was made of paintings that; since Corinne was published in 1807, have
become famous and familiar to innumerable undergraduates taking
low-numbered art history courses for easy credits at high prices. Co¬
rinne possessed histories, religious pictures, poetries, and landscapes.
More important, Corinne, being as well-read, intellectual, and inspired
as Madame de Stael, had arranged her collection in a sequence that
made philosophical and historical sense; for the collection illustrated
the literary-historical philosophy of Madame de Stael, who was none
other than Corinne—as Madame Vigee Lebrun and the Baron Gerard
both knew since they both painted her as Corinne.
The first of Corinne’s history pictures was the famous Brutus by
Jacques Louis David; its pendant, the Marius at Minturne, was by Jean
Germain Drouais, one of David’s best students; while the last of her his¬
tories was the now lost Belisarius of Baron Gerard, one of the master¬
pieces of Napoleonic painting. All these works, taken together, had a
specific meaning: Brutus signified civic virtues that, in fact, resembled
crime; Marius, who is shown exposing his breast to a Cimbrian war¬
rior sent to kill him, while the latter is hiding his face in shame, exem¬
plified glory as the cause of personal misfortune; while the Belisarius,
a favorite of neoclassical art, was an obvious example of unjust per¬
secution. The sacred pictures, a Christ asleep upon the cross by Al-
bano, a Christ falling under the burden of the cross by Titian, also had
their meaning, signifying, in contrast to the histories, the redemption
and hope of the Christian faith as opposed to the hopelessness of the
pagan world. Monsieur Necker had written a book on the consolations
offered by Christianity, especially to the poor whose lot in this world
would be lightened by thoughts of rewards in the next.
As for the poetries and landscapes, they too had a significance. One
was a theme taken from Tasso; another was taken from the Aenead; a
third from Racine; a fourth from Shakespeare. One landscape was a
Salvator Rosa rustic scene; another, a heroic landscape showing Cin-
cinnatus leaving his plow to take up the defense of his country. Finally,
5
Corinne also had an Ossianic landscape that brought tears to Lord Os¬
wald’s eyes. In mood, subject matter, and in association, these poetries
and landscapes corresponded to Madame de Stael's cultural differ¬
entiation between the literature of the North—Shakespeare and Os-
sian—and that of the South—Tasso and Racine—and, by extension,
two different and often opposed temperaments and civilizations. Hers
was a theme that would flourish in the course of the nineteenth century
since the South would ever prove a fatal attraction to poets and painters
of the North from Winckelmann to Goethe, Feuerbach, and Thomas
Mann’s Gustav von Aschenbach, who found his death in the decadent
Venice of Bernard Berenson and Mrs. Isabella Stewart Gardner of
Boston.
Obviously Corinne’s pictures were not merely works to please the
eye, like some rococo nudes or pastorals; together, they represented
more than the collection of an amateur. The choice and arrangement
of the pictures, Corinne’s private guided tour, all signified what art
after the French Revolution had come to mean in the new age of the
arrived bourgeoisie: art works were the signs of history, and hence the
collection presented a rather coherent set of historical and cultural
values, values that distinguished the new ruling class from the old no¬
bility which now had to share social preeminence with the bour¬
geoisie. The old nobility had had lineage, ancestors, breeding, military
glory, and the right to bear arms to distinguish it from the commoners,
as well as debts incurred in keeping up the necessary appearances.
The bourgeoisie would have culture to distinguish itself from the for¬
mer nobility and the threat of commoners who might legally aspire to
its ranks and new ruling status. The principle that all men were equal
under the law, taken seriously by some of the working lower orders,
posed serious problems of authority and prestige for the bourgeoisie.
Surely all men were created equal and were so under the law, but
equally surely some were rather better than others. It was essential to
keep the lower order low and maintain the better sort of people in the
6
right places. It was found that both education and art could do a great
deal in maintaining a social balance. There soon arose what one critic
of the French education system in the twentieth century was to cadi
the aesthetics of distinction. The entire educational system of the
French bourgeoisie in the nineteenth century was founded on the ne¬
cessity of creating a level of distinction that would be an effective bar¬
rier to the lower orders: hence the baccalaureate degree, the achieve¬
ment of which required nonutilitarian Latin, the right table manners,
the right gloves, the right linguistic usage, the proper dress, quite dis¬
tinct from the dress and manners of the working class, the knowledge
of how many glasses to put at a place setting and where to put the
right knives, forks, and spoons. There is no doubt that art could also
play a distinguishing role for a ruling class whose individual members
had often only recently arrived. As the educational system tended to
be increasingly democratized, the idea of distinction in the aesthetic-
artistic realm was bound to become more and more attractive since
the arts were rich in associations of nobility, beauty, leisure, heritage, a
beau monde, and the general phenomenon of snobbism that marked
the world in the time of James and Proust. Aestheticism of the fin de
siecle was implicit in the bourgeois avid for distinction and in the very
foundation of his society.
True daughter of the Enlightenment and of a successful banker,
Madame de Stael was an optimist who believed in progress, liberal¬
ism, and the elite to which she belonged. Her contemporary, Jean
Chrysostome Quatremere de Quincy belonged to the same elite of
bourgeois notables, but he was no banker’s son and so tended to be
somewhat less optimistic than Madame de Stael. Originally a sculptor,
he turned antiquarian and made the acquaintance of the painter Da¬
vid in Italy, became a political exile during the Revolution, returned to
serve Napoleon and then the Bourbons, was appointed perpetual sec¬
retary of the reformed and revived Academy of Painting, transformed
7
under various regimes into the Classe des Beaux-Arts of the Institut.
Having been to Italy; he too had come to think of the arts in noble and
exalted terms. Friend of Canova, he had come to represent the up¬
holder and the defender of the Greek ideal in art. But as he lived on
during the reign of the Citizen-King Louis Philippe, who used to ap¬
pear in public with an umbrella like any bourgeois, Quatremere came
to have fewer and fewer illusions about the status of art in an age of
steam, speed, manufactures, money, art collections, public art exhibi¬
tions, and museums.
For Quatremere had come to understand and explain in prose only
slightly more lucid than Hegel’s, who had understood the same thing,
what no one dared say out loud: art was dead. By this he did not mean
that paintings and sculpture or public monuments were no longer
produced. The contrary was perhaps only too true: too much was
being produced. But he sensed that the nineteenth century—the
modern world—was in a profound disharmony with the forces that in
the past had been the conditions or the “causes” productive of art. The
Greek world had known harmony between its beliefs and the causes
productive of art and for this reason had produced the only valid
canon for art and beauty, and in the mind of Quatremere and his fol¬
lowers both terms were written with capitals and were seen as insepa¬
rable: Art is Beauty. The individual work of art was an intimation of
universal ideal beauty. The theory was Platonic. The models of univer¬
sal beauty were the Greek works that had survived. And the harmony
between Greek life, religion, and art was such that beauty, incarnate in
works of art as well as healthy and handsome Greek youths and maid¬
ens, seemed the product of an ideal nature. But this was far from the
situation of the nineteenth century in which art could only be an evo¬
cation of a lost harmony, an aspiration to regain or reestablish har¬
mony, in short, the ideal. Education in the arts came to be seen as one
way to establish this lost harmony within the modern world. Witness
8
the efforts of academies to maintain high art, or the efforts of men like
Ruskin and William Morris to counter the effects of industry and the
machine by preaching for a return to art as craft.
The result of this general malaise about the state of art and beauty in
the new industrial world and its great cities in Europe and North
America was an idealization of art in general and a reverential attitude
toward works of art in particular. The state became concerned with art
as it formerly had with religion. Indeed; in Anglo-Saxon countries reli¬
gion was sometimes confused with art; or vice versa.
It is possible to separate idealism in the arts into various strains; but
those who used the word ideal often failed to draw sharp distinctions
unless they happened to be professional philosophers who lectured
on beauty. The word thus remains a vague but useful term characteris¬
tic of an age. One thing was clear: the ideal was always spiritual; it was
never sensationist and certainly not sensational. And it was never
vulgar. In the early nineteenth century the ideal was the opposite of
the subversive; sensationist; materialistic philosophy of the Enlighten¬
ment; which; as all the well-to-do knew, had been responsible for the
Revolution. Materialism was dangerous to social values and to the sta¬
bility of society. The bourgeois, who had finally arrived after centuries
of climbing, was an idealist, at least in his salon if not on the market¬
place. The bourgeoisie had even found its ideal professor to expound
this doctrine of the new trinity of the true, the good, and the beautiful.
Victor Cousin, eminent eclectic philosopher, pillar of the establish¬
ment, was quite clear on the distinction between the truly aesthetic
from the snares of sensation: the "judgment of beauty is absolute, and
as such, entirely different from sensation.”1 Just as the neoclassical
painters and sculptors jumped right over the art of the baroque and
rococo to find inspiration with the Greeks, so Victor Cousin dismissed
eighteenth-century philosophy to find inspiration in Plato. Plato in-
sisted on the Idea of Beauty rather than a thing of beauty. The thing
wa§ material; but the Idea was spiritual; intangible, eternal, transcen ¬
dent. Given these premises an artist who produced a thing of beauty
would always be at a disadvantage since beauty was spiritual. He
could only approximate the ideal; but, if successful, his work would
provide an intimation of that ideal.
Sensation, titillation, and strong emotion were thus effectively sepa¬
rated from the admiration of an object of art. Love of beauty and love
of art remained spiritual and therefore pure. The sentiment for beauty,
according to Cousin, the aesthetic judgment, according to Kant, was
so defined as to exclude desire. For the essence of beauty according to
these philosophers was not to prompt desire but, rather, to purify and
ennoble it. “The more a form is beautiful,” wrote Cousin, “not of that
common and gross beauty by which Rubens vainly animates his ar¬
dent colors, but that ideal beauty known to Antiquity, Raphael and
Lesueur, the more is desire tempered by an exquisite and delicate sen¬
timent and sometimes even replaced by a disinterested cult of beauty
before such noble creations.”2 Art and religion were thus not far apart.
The ideal led to thoughts of eternity and the true and absolute ideal
was none other than God. A romantic view of the artist as somehow
close to God and the infinite was thereby joined to a classical aesthetic
theory and its concomitant taste for the works of the Greeks. It was
conveniently forgotten that the Greeks had been pagans and far less
“spiritual” than Winckelmann.
This philosophical-aesthetic idealism was formulated in a variety of
ways and forms. Theophile Gautier, poet, journalist, critic, novelist,
wrote an entire novel about it, namely his famous—or, rather, in¬
famous—Mademoiselle de Maupin of 1835. He also thought that “the
verses of Homer, the statues of Phidias, the painting of Raphael have
raised the human soul more than all the treatises of the moralists.
2. Ibid., p. 145.
10
like that he came to wish for death. For it was a world of money valua¬
tions and what he called materialist considerations in the arts. By this
he meant museums, exhibitions, private and public collections, all of
which he despised. The enemy of art was not only romanticism in its
myriad manifestations, but also, perhaps more so, the ignorant lover of
the arts and that figure from the seventeenth century, the tulip specu¬
lator, who, in the eyes of Quatremere, came to represent the acquisitive
and speculative spirit that seemed, like democracy, to be conquering
the world. Quatremere looked at the tulip speculator as Tocqueville
looked at rising democracy. And the tulip speculator had, in the mod¬
ern world, become the art speculator, the collector, the curator, the ac¬
cumulator, the dealer. One might say he came to symbolize all those
byproducts of art that Joseph Alsop so knowledgably outlined as in¬
separable from the rare art traditions. Yet even at the Institut, where he
presided and where his authority was undisputed, there were fools
and optimists who saw in the greater and greater production of works
of art, in the exhibitions, collections, and museums, a sign of progress.
As if, Quatremere called out in a speech to the members of the acad¬
emy, the increasing number of boutiques in Paris were proof of greater
civilization!
ered the bourgeois, and in the preface to the Salon of1846 he stressed
what the power of this new public meant: "You are the majority, num¬
ber and intelligence; you are therefore power, which is justice.”4 He
saw and understood that this new public would have to be educated
in matters aesthetic, whereas Quatremere simply viewed the unedu¬
cated public as dangerous.
Baudelaire the poet saw what Quatremere had missed in the new
social and political situation in which the arts had to live, namely, the
fascination of the modern city. London and Paris in the eighteenth
century had been relatively large, but until the nineteenth century, the
arts had flourished by and large in slow-paced and modest-sized cit¬
ies. Industrialization under Victoria and Napoleon III increased the
size and population of cities, which effected a qualitative change in life
in such cities as Paris, London, Berlin. What Baudelaire understood
about the city and its effects on life and the arts may be gleaned from
two sonnets that stand as pendants to each other. The first is entitled
Beauty:
too well that by 1800 what had been the space of the arts was becom¬
ing a museum. Art was being severed from the source of life. In retro¬
spect even Corinne’s villa looked a trifle educational. Tivoli signified
the end of the classical aesthetic; Paris, that of the modern to come.
r
The Passage des Panoramas. Photograph by Anne F. Saisselin.
It often seemed to Mallet that he wholly lacked
the prime requisite of an eypert flaneur—
the simple, sensuous, confident relish of pleasure.
To make the opposition of art in the classic sense and the modern city
clear, let us have recourse to symbolic spaces: the museum and the
experiences it furnishes may be opposed to the modern city and its
stimulants. The classic aesthetic experience was in the past associated
not only with pictures and sculpture, but also with gardens, parks,
views, and the trappings of the noble life; these, in turn, implied cer¬
tain spaces: palace, town house, chateau, and galleries within. The
nineteenth century turned some of these spaces into museums and
created new spaces of aesthetic experience. But these were quite dif¬
ferent and associated with different forms of life and activities. The
new spaces to rival those of art were the passages, or arcades, and the
department stores. There is no doubt that these had predecessors on
the architectural level: the passage can conceivably be regarded as a
gallery adapted not to hang pictures but for some other commercial
purpose, while the department store, with its interior galleries, grand
staircase, majestic grand entrance, great halls, and even cabinets, was a
species of new palace. It was in these new spaces that the nineteenth-
century aesthetic observer discovered the most powerful aesthetic ac¬
tivity and experience of the modern man and, even more important,
the modern woman: the attraction of commodity and luxury items
and the pleasure of purchasing same; in short, the aesthetics of buying
and selling.
I was led to rediscover these new aesthetic spaces of Paris by reading
Walter Benjamin on Baudelaire and Paris. In his study of this poet he
poses the existence of a new aesthetic observer, the flaneur, the walker
19
20
in the city. And what happened in the city as one walked about with
the only purpose of seeking out what it had to offer, is that it affected
the imagination. One was stimulated as never before. Quatremere had
not neglected the necessity of the imagination in the appreciation of
works of art; but he had not seen the city would prove a much more
powerful stimulant to it than a masterpiece. And so during lunch
breaks when I worked at the Bibliotheque Nationale, I, too, wandered
in the footsteps of Baudelaire, Benjamin, and Zola’s Nana to discover
these first modern spaces that were to rival the classic spaces of art,
the passages.
The first passage I discovered was the Passage Choiseul, opened in
1825. Soon I discovered others, both in the area and farther away, such
as the famous Passage des Panoramas, one of the early ones-—built in
1800—and made famous not only by Nana but the panorama, stage for
perfectly illusory painting on the grand scale of Paris, London, Rome,
Naples, Athens, Jerusalem, as well as the battles of Tilsitt and Wagram.
These vast panoramas had been patented by Robert Barker of Edin¬
burgh, but two years later, in 1789, the American Robert Fulton and
Pierre Prevost, a landscape painter, joined forces to create one in Paris.
Their panorama is now gone, but the passage is still lined with a vari¬
ety of boutiques. Later I stumbled on the Galerie Vivienne, 1823; the
Passage Verdeau, built about the same time as that of the Panorama;
the delightful Galerie Vero-Dodat, excellently preserved; and later, the
last to be built, the Passage des Princes, 1860. These galleries or pas¬
sages date from the late eighteenth century, such as the Galeries
du Palais Royal, 1786, and the Passage du Caire, very much in neo-
Egyptian style, of 1799. There are, of course, others: the famous and
nearly colossal Galleria in Milan, the Burlington Arcades in London,
and a fine example in Cleveland, Ohio. These passages are interesting
not only sociologically but also architecturally. The Parisian ones date
from the late neoclassicism of the Restoration and the reign of Louis
Philippe. Their motifs are thus neoclassical, but the modernity of the
21
arcades lies in the glass roofs that allow daylight to illuminate their
long galleries and the often elegant mosaic and tile floors. These
spaces rivaled those reserved for art and were those of commodity
capitalism. They were also the privileged haunts of that product of the
new city the flaneur.
The nineteenth-century city produced a revolution in aesthetic per¬
ception and attitudes toward works of art that is still with us. The city
expanded the range of the seeable. The art object was redefined, as
was the status and definition of the artist. The eye began to take in far
more than it had in the preindustrial city; some critics have referred to
this widened range of attention as a new eye. This so-called new eye is
sometimes linked to the camera as well as to impressionism. But this
new eye of man in the modern city does not so much presuppose
photography as photography presupposes a new eye. In other words,
the stimulation of the modern city—its multitudes, its variety of ob¬
jects, its thriving life—transformed the gaze and the observer; and the
photographer went hand in hand with the new aesthetic observer of
the modern city, the flaneur.
This new eye was the result of the novel conditions of the bourgeois
regime. Writers, poets, and artists found themselves in a world of eco¬
nomic values, imperatives, and products rather than the religious,
mythic, or traditional values founded on landed wealth. The new re¬
gime incorporated new forms of capital, banking, commerce, and
manufacturing; and the city that resulted was complex, dynamic, and
expanding.
The city as aesthetic or literary experience was not new at all. Louis
Sebastien Mercier’s Tableau de Paris of the late eighteenth century is a
case in point, as are the innumerable pictures from that time of Rome,
Venice, London, Dresden, Paris, and Amsterdam. And it is well known
how Dr. Johnson appreciated and thrived in his beloved London. But
these were still relatively small cities by later standards. The Paris of
Louis Philippe and Napoleon III was on a grander scale, and the new
22
the libraries are open to every comer, and the museums, where
centuries of fine arts have heaped up all their splendours. ... I
hope this is a sufficiently extensive theatre for lounging.1
The lounger, Janin went on, did not perceive himself as such; he was
no idler but a very busy person who set out to his business every
morning and was distracted by the spectacle of the city. The street
transformed him into a lounger who was seen everywhere, and no¬
where: “He is in the gardens of the Palais Royal, to regulate his watch
by the cannon which fires off, discharged by the rays of the midday
sun. He is on the quai Voltaire, occupied in contemplating the antiq¬
uities of the curiosity vendors, or looking at the celebrated men of
Madame Delpech” (165). He can be seen in the rue de Richelieu, the
rue Vivienne, the Place de la Bourse, but above all, “we shall find our
man, in the Passage de l’Opera, at the hour when the rehearsal com¬
mences, and there, he sees passing, in every kind of dress, in satin
shoes, in slippers down at the heel, and even without any shoes at all,
the pretty little danseuses, to whom glory has not yet held out her
hand, filled with laces and cashmeres. Lounger! That word implies
everything” (AP, 166). But there was another arcade the lounger found
particularly to his taste and loved to frequent because of its congenial
atmosphere: “The Passage des Panoramas is his abode. There he is un¬
der shelter, there he is at home, there he receives friends, and makes
his appointments, and there you are sure to meet him. And what finer
saloon can he have, than this Passage des Panoramas? where will you
find more numerous visitors, and more liberty? find prettier faces in
the morning, and more brilliant gas in the evening? Never was a saloon
more fitted with masterpieces, music, refreshment of every kind” (166).
Jules Janin was not the only writer to have spotted the flaneur as a
1. Jules Janin, The American in Paris, or Heath’s Picturesque Annual for 1843 (London:
Heath’s, 1843), 164-165.
25
new city type. Victor Fournel, in Ce qu’on voit dans les rues de Paris
(1858), also devoted a few pages to him and compared him to a pas¬
sionate and mobile daguerrotype, sensitive not only to every trace,
changing reflection, event, and movement of the city, but also to the
spirit, antipathies, and admirations of the ever-present crowd. The
flaneur was seen as a free spirit and the phenomenon of lounging, of
being a flaneur, as so novel as not yet to have entered a dictionary.
Fournel distinguished between the flaneur and the idler, thereby rais¬
ing the flaneur to philosophical type: for the simple flaneur observes
and reflects and is in possession of his own individuality. The idler, or
badaud in French, on the contrary, tends to disappear into and allows
himself to be absorbed by the world around him, the crowd, the city
and its life which ravishes his personality, affecting him to the point of
inebriation and ecstasy. “Under the influence of the spectacle the
badaud becomes an impersonal being; he is no longer an individual,
he is public, he is crowd.”2 The flaneur remained a conscious observer
for whom the word boredom had become meaningless: he animated
all he saw, admired all he perceived. He strolled, observed, watched,
espied, and generally amused himself within these newly created
spaces that would eventually transform art and letters: the passages
and arcades of the age of Louis Philippe with their glass roofs and their
shops filled with what were called articles de Paris or articles de
nouveaute but that, today, are more likely to contain anything from an¬
tiques to kitsch, toys, gloves, canes, stamps, curios, books, old photos,
post cards, visiting cards, cameras old and new, lead soldiers, lingerie,
pipes and tobacco, masks, bonnets, oriental goods, and even pizza.
However, his observation of the phenomena of the city life was a
double-edged sword, for he lost his innocence, alienated himself from
the observed, turned into the outsider looking in. In a sense the
flaneur might be seen as a prototype of Steppenwolf. He had turned
2. Victor Fournel, Ce qu’on voit dans les rues de Paris (Paris: Delahays, 1858), 263.
26
into the aesthetic observer, somewhat apart from the modern, indus¬
trial city in which the lines of demarcation between life and art, art
and industry, beauty and mere fashion were becoming increasingly
blurred.
In earlier days these had been the new shops of commodity and lux¬
ury capitalism, places of predilection for the flaneur as well as for the
shopper; for shopping had at that time recently become a novel plea¬
sure. Passing from one street to another, piercing entire blocks of
buildings, they sheltered from inclement weather and the mud of still
unpaved streets. Within the great city they were little cities, micro¬
cosms of human activity, taste, desires, temptations. Here the flaneur
might come to get away from a meager garret and stroll at ease, enter¬
tained by the spectacle about him, which was free; here, too, he could
play the chronicler and philosopher of the life of the city and its vari¬
ous and seemingly inexhaustible products, made known by the color¬
ful advertisements called affiches. Here in the passages and the city
the flaneur might escape boredom. For as Baudelaire, Constantin
Guys, and also Gavarni pointed out, only a fool could find himself
bored by the crowd: for it had become a continuous spectacle. Gavarni,
returning from Paris to his room in Montmartre, wrote in his diary in
1828: “Each time I return from Paris I am convinced it yet remains to
be discovered and I am tormented by the desire to try it. Every time I
go there, at every step, I find so much; and as for the feelings I experi¬
ence there in a day, I should need a year to express them.”3 This em¬
phasis on the city’s spectacle as a therapy for boredom is suggestive of
a shift from Pascalian divertissement to modernity.
Pascal in the seventeenth century, the abbe Du Bos in the eigh¬
teenth, and later the architect Jacques Frangois Blondel, had all ar¬
gued that the arts were a noble way of avoiding and overcoming the all
too human condition of ennui. Now if Benjamin is right in following
Baudelaire and Guys in their opinion about the relation of the city and
ennui; then it becomes possible to see in the city and its products, its
commodities and luxuries, its articles de nouveautes and its shop win¬
dows, a way to construct a new aesthetics, closely linked to capitalism,
built on the need to dissipate ennui. In this sense the flaneur is no
longer the successor of the eighteenth-century spectator but, rather, of
that age's curieuy and collector Only he is a new type of collector, in¬
terested not only in small works of art but also in the products of mod¬
ern capitalism. His attention has shifted from the consecrated object
of the collector and curieux to the products of the city, its spaces,
types, sensations. Fashion and advertising became a redoubtable rival
of art as more and more art was used to promote the products of lux¬
ury. Hairdressers and tailors used fashion plates in their windows;
hairdressers and milliners used wax figures to show off their wares.
“As for the wax busts I’ve contemplated so often through the windows
of milliners and hairdressers,” writes Fournel, “Pradier or Canova
never turned more voluptuous contours, more rounded forms, or
more irreproachable outlines.”4
The flaneur could also note the ingenuity of the merchants’ efforts
to attract passing crowds. The affiches, printed advertisements usually
on colored paper, were a new type of literature raised to an art by the
eloquent use of typography and seductive vignettes, and appealing to
the new fascination with color. As the seventeenth-century critic Roger
de Piles had argued, a good picture really ought to stop a spectator in
his tracks, so the new advertisements stopped the idler, the flaneur,
the shopper in the street, attracting him or her to new products,
awakening new desires, creating new necessities. Zola, in his novel His
Excellency Eugene Rougon, describes in a long chapter the pomp and
circumstance of an imperial procession advancing in magnificent cos¬
tumes to Notre-Dame for an imperial baptism. But when it is all over
noux's boutique, were a mean between the street and the interior, pub¬
lic and private space, commerce and art. Arnoux’s shop offered the
bourgeois a look at his own interior, one that would most likely be
strictly separated from his work place. It was at this time that the pri¬
vate interior came to be separated from the work place; in the course
of the century the two would come to represent increasingly distinct,
almost antagonistic spheres. It was a separation great with conse¬
quences for art and attitudes toward the arts. For much as religion in a
highly secular society came to be reserved for Sunday, so the arts in
bourgeois society came to be the pretext of special occasions, special
spaces, a special experience, and a life divorced from work. Art came
to be reserved for the private domain, the intimate interior, the private
world of the bourgeois, so that it came to be associated with an imagi¬
nary universe at variance and sometimes in conflict with the public
world, values, and activities of the bourgeois. Hardheaded in business,
the bourgeois might be softheaded in art. The bourgeois interior, in
contrast to the spaces in which others worked for him, became the
space of private fantasies. Here, as Benjamin put it, he gathered objects
from remote places and the past to create the space of his dreams and
secret longings; here, too, his psyche betrayed itself through the ob¬
jects he gathered.
As Arnoux’s shop was the model of a potential interior, so real sa¬
lons, interiors, and houses were later described, photographed, and
published as models for those who wished to create a “house beauti¬
ful,”—which, as Lewis Mumford found in The Brown Decades (1931),
was often confused with a house filled with bric-a-brac. Earl Shinn,
alias Edward Strahan, published the art objects that made up the
“nineteenth-century clutter” of the Vanderbilt mansion in a ten-
volume limited luxury edition.6 Despite its colossal size and expense,
the house of Mr. Vanderbilt was still referred to as a “home,” implying
6. See Jan Cohn, The Palace and the Poor House: The American House as Cultural Symbol
(Lansing, Mich.: Michigan State University Press, 1979), 119.
30
When the flaneur wandered into the new department stores he did
not have to enter as a consumer. He went through the doors as freely
as he had entered the passages from the streets. He was free to look,
free to touch, free to allow himself to be seduced, open to desire
for . . . things. The commodities and luxuries existed to be gazed at,
were exhibited to attract, stimulated and induced a state of desire that
transcended need. What distinguished the new department stores
from the old shops and boutiques was precisely their invitation to de¬
sire. Whereas Arnoux’s shop in the Rue Montmartre was attractive, the
department stores were veritable magnets, for you could enter without
having to buy.
The first department store, the Bon Marche, was founded in 1852 by
Aristide Boucicaut; however, it was not until 1869 that Boucicaut ex¬
panded it by building the grand building that still stands on the Rue
Babylone and that Michael Miller, in his study of the store from 1869 to
1920, sees as an embodiment or central institution of what he calls
bourgeois culture. The Bon Marche’s originality as a business venture
lay in its small mark-up of price, compensated for by a high volume of
sales and a rapid stock run. The merchandise was sold at fixed prices,
whereas the old shops and boutiques, which you entered only as a
consumer, never as a flaneur, charged what the buyer could bear or
what he or she was willing to haggle over. Fixed prices were a demo¬
cratic feature, as was free entry into the store. Anyone could enter,
look about, and leave without having to purchase anything. And an¬
other innovation: Boucicaut allowed returns and exchanges for items
bought in his store. Something simple and common today, but genial
at the time; that, too, gave desire free rein, for it was no longer limited
33
34
by the article bought and unreturnable. If you could return the article
you could also indulge another desire if the initial item no longer satis¬
fied. There was no longer any regret following the satisfied desire.
The Bon Marche inspired others to follow suit and the second half
of the nineteenth century became an age of great department stores:
Chauchard and Heriot founded the Magasin du Louvre in 1855; Jalazet
the Printemps in 1865; Cognacq the Samaritaine in 1869, the same year
Boucicaut and his wife were expanding theirs. There were parallel de¬
velopments in the United States: Stewart’s of New York, later absorbed
by Wanamaker’s of Philadelphia; Marshall Field in Chicago; Lord and
Taylor’s and Macy’s in New York. The efficiency of department stores
was soon increased in the United States: the first lift was introduced by
Strawbridge and Clothier’s of Philadelphia in 1865; Macy’s and Wana¬
maker’s were using electric lighting by 1878 and the first electric lifts in
the 1880s. Jordan Marsh introduced the telephone into his store in
1876, Marshall Field the pneumatic tube system in 1893, and the cash
register came into use in the course of the 1880s. But these stores also
necessitated a new architecture: new construction materials such as
iron and steel, reinforced concrete, and the vast use of glass all made
for grander spaces and more light, while lifts allowed the construction
of higher and higher buildings. Capitalism had found its palace.
The crowd and passages that had lured the flaneur out of his garret
now drew him into the department stores, which, as Benjamin put it,
put him to use for commodity circulation. But Benjamin, following his
flaneur into the department stores that marked the end of the pas¬
sages, had thought of these stores as a vast marketplace, which they
surely were; yet he seemingly missed the true intent or direction of
these new institutions, namely, their appeal to women.
As Zola saw it, they aimed to victimize women, or, as we might say,
to exploit them. But there is another way of looking at this novel phe¬
nomenon of women and department stores. Instead of exploitation,
one might speak of a certain education of women, if not, indeed, the
35
Carrie passed along the busy aisles, much affected by the re¬
markable displays of trinkets, dress goods, shoes, stationery,
jewelry. Each separate counter was a show place of dazzling in¬
terest and attraction. She could not help feeling the claim of
each trinket and valuable upon her personality and yet she did
not stop. There was nothing there which she could not have
used—nothing which she did not long to own. The dainty slip¬
pers and stockings, the delicately frilled shirts and petticoats,
the laces, ribbons, hair-combs, purses, all touched her with indi¬
vidual desire.1
1. Theodore Dreiser, Sister Carrie (Baltimore, Md.: Penguin Books, 1981), 22.
36
Unwittingly Carrie was taking lessons from the new stores and their
creation, the new woman. And in her relation to the department store,
Carrie, as any other woman, was the same in Chicago, New York, or
Paris. Yet it was in Chicago that social conditions, economics, and
Marshall Field had created what came to be known as the new woman,
member of the social set, later of the Junior Council, and part of the
new elite that in the United States would set the fashions and moral
values for other women. The new woman’s husband was in business,
usually doing well, and she, accompanied or not, would make a pil-
37
grimage to Europe, coming back loaded with new dresses and other
luxilries as well as with talk of the splendors of Paris and the aesthetic
movement in London. On Chicago’s Michigan Avenue, or New York’s
Fifth, or in her Newport summer residence the new woman might
have lived in an interior that we would probably find rather cluttered
and garish. But she knew that she aspired to taste, art, refinement, and
what was generally referred to as art’s elevating influence. In Europe
this elevating influence was usually called the ideal and was associ¬
ated with art and noble sentiments, but not department stores. Yet it is
undeniable that in the aesthetic education of women, in the formation
of her interior, in the creation of the new woman, and even in this aspi¬
ration for the ideal, the department stores played a very important
role. Historically speaking, they preceded the museums that the new
woman would eventually join as a member of the Junior Council, as a
patron, or even as a member of the education department.
Yet supporter of the arts was not the new woman’s only role. For if
we are to believe Schopenhauer, who thought women looked on men
as the earners of the money they would spend, within the new woman
was the old Eve, cause of man’s fall. In the nineteenth century this
meant women devoured luxuries, ruined man as a demimondaine,
and drove him sick in his money making, only to fall victim herself to
the shiny capitalist apples seen in shops and department stores. Sister
Carrie quite innocently ruined Hurstwood—innocently because she
was unaware of the evil involved in her rise to a life of luxury and suc¬
cess. But Hurstwood himself was a victim of the same belief in material
success since he assumed man had to heap trinkets upon women.
In Au Bonheur des Dames, Zola likens the department store to a ca¬
thedral of modern commerce dedicated to woman. To use Henry
Adams’s famous historical metaphor, the Virgin of Chartres had turned
into the new woman and the dynamo into a department store. In
Adams’s view the power of the dynamo had displaced that of the Vir¬
gin over men’s imagination. In Zola’s world, the dynamic department
38
store devours woman. The Bonheur des Dames, Mouret’s store, is not
only a cathedral but a machine into which woman is attracted and se¬
duced. It is worth noting that this view has an eighteenth-century pre¬
cedent in the doctrine of architecture parlante. A tale by Bastide,
called La Petite Maison, tells of the seduction of a woman by the archi¬
tecture of the house, its decor, its sensuous effects, its very luxury.
Zola’s brilliant interpretation of the department store improves upon
this phenomenon by altering the scale of the seduction: the intimate
seduction of the rococo is turned into the mass seduction of a crowd
of women rendered frantic by a new type of artist, neither the archi¬
tect of architecture parlante nor the grand couturier, but the genius of
advertising and display.
The Bonheur des Dames, like its prototype the Bon Marche—and,
as we shall see, Wanamaker’s in Philadelphia—was an architectural
marvel: stone for the base, brick and iron for the rest of the structure,
thus creating an effect of light and spaciousness. Mouret’s expanded
store included two lifts, a buffet, a reading room, and an art gallery.
Owner and manager of the store, Mouret was an advertising genius
who offered the women free drinks and free balloons for the children.
There were also catalogues, posters, and advertisements in the papers.
The Bon Marche issued some 200,000 catalogues of which 50,000 were
sent abroad. Mouret was a brilliant psychologist who claimed that
woman could not resist a sale or publicity and that she tended naturally
to be attracted by noise. To overcome whatever resistance she still pos¬
sessed, he invented returns and lowered prices. He also exploited the
aesthetic effect of displays on his customers, much as the eighteenth-
century architects of expressive architecture had argued that forms,
masses, the play of light and dark affected the soul. Thus for one spe¬
cial sale he created a fairylandlike effect, an atmosphere of spring by
the profuse use of colored umbrellas, and light, colored fabrics floating
in the air. Obviously these special effects had their origin in the the-
39
ater: the stage was no longer fixed to the theater and its special space;
theater was made to enter the department store and daily life. The aes¬
thetic experience was generalized and democratized.
As advertising was a species of new literature; so the display of con¬
sumer goods and commodities was a new type of staging. But the en¬
tire machine of the store—the architecture; special displays; special
sales and events—was directed to one end: the seduction of woman. It
was the modern devil tempting the modern Eve. As in the original fall,
in this modern version, it was man again who would be made to pay
for the apple. Mon Dieu que les hommes sont betes went one of Offen¬
bach’s songs, sung by a woman. In Zola’s words:
It was woman the department stores fought over for their busi¬
ness, woman they continually entrapped by their bargains, after
having made them dizzy by their displays. They had awakened
in her flesh new desires and had become an immense tempta¬
tion to which they fatally succumbed, yielding first to the pur¬
chases of a good and careful housewife, then won over by co¬
quetry, finally devoured. By increasing sales, by democratizing
luxury, the stores became a terrible agency of spending, creating
havoc in homes, working up women to the madness of fashion
which was ever dearer and dearer.2
On the one hand this style remained tributary to the feudal pe¬
riod, as witness the cheap horrors spread by industry and called
Louis XV, Louis XVI, or Empire (stiff little chairs with fragile legs,
and heavy chimney pieces). But on the other hand one must
recognize that woman created the conditions of an “intimate”
style of interior decor, precisely a typical modern bourgeois idea
which neither the petite bourgeoisie of the seventeenth or the
*
It was in the intimacy of her interior that woman put all those things
4. R. W. B. Lewis, Edith Wharton: A Biography (New York: Harper and Row, 1975), 374.
42
The department stores were very much aware of their cultural im¬
portance and mission. They pioneered methods of art education that
would later be undertaken by museums in the United States, though
whereas the stores sold works of art, the museums exhibited them and
taught art appreciation. But stores did form taste. Marshall Field in
Chicago “set diligently to educate western taste—his conception of a
merchant s task. ... If the American woman yearned to imitate the
wealthy classes of Europe and the society leaders of the Eastern cities,
44
It is not only the person whose soul sings through his lips, or
who puts his thought on canvas with a brush, who is an artist.
The vehicle of expression does not matter. It is the spirit that
counts. The woman who arranges a room charmingly, who
dresses to express her personality, or serves dinner with grace;
the man who binds a book in good taste, or turns out a chair
that is a pleasure, or lays out a garden to give delight—all are
artists in their way. So too is the store that lives up to its highest
ideals.6
This philosophy was also exemplified in the very building of the store.
As Wanamaker told his architect:
What you must do for me ... is to strive to say in stone what this
business has said to the world in deed. You must make a build¬
ing that is solid and true. It shall be of granite and of steel
throughout. It shall stand four-square to the city—simple, un¬
pretentious, noble, classic—a work of art, and, humanly speak¬
ing, a monument for all time. . . . And who shall say that just to
5. Lloyd Wendt and Herman Kogan, Give the Lady What She Wants: The Story of Marshall
Field and Company (New York: Rand McNally, 1952), 155.
6. John Wanamaker Firm, The Golden Book of the Wanamaker Stores (Jubilee Year,
1861-1911), 245-246.
45
live in its shadow and to pass daily through its great Corinthian
' pillars is not turning the minds of thousands of men and women
toward a larger appreciation of the fitness and nobleness and
sincerity of art? (246-247)
There is probably no other store in the world that has gone into
the Paris salons and purchased the pictures best worth having
46
From 1892 through 1903 Wanamaker’s bought 250 paintings from the
salons, “so comprehensive in subject and characteristic of contempo¬
rary French painting as to be of unquestionably great educational
value to American art students, as well as a source of true pleasure to
the thousands who came to see them” (250). And in 1903 the store
bought 300 paintings, practically the entire stock of the studio of one
Vacslav Brozik who died in Paris in 1901, a historical painter described
as the equal of the greatest. Old masters at these exhibitions were rep¬
resented by copies: there was a bronze cast of the Venus de Milo, a
copy of Atalanta and Hippomenes at the north and south ends of the
grand court, colossal Roman eagles, and a statue of Joan of Arc. The
mural decorations for the New York store auditorium had been done
by Frederick X. Frieseke of the Societe Nationale des Beaux-Arts, while
H. O. Tanner produced biblical pictures, and Anna Estelle Rice did “a
large group of mural decorations, reminiscent of the days of Louis XVI,
which are destined when completed, for the wall panels above the ele¬
vators in the new Philadelphia Wanamaker Stores” (254). But art was
not only used to decorate the stores and educate the public, it was
also applied to advertisement pages. The store also organized painting
and drawing exhibitions for children and art students.
This ambitious program for educating and forming public taste was
also carried on in the New York stores once Stewart’s had been ab¬
sorbed by Wanamaker’s. A new store was built next to the old Stewart’s
and the two buildings were joined by a Venetian-style bridge called,
appropriately, the bridge of progress. There were in fact three stores in
47
this complex of buildings: women’s wear; men’s and boys’ wear; and
furnishings and decoration. The new building was composed of a se¬
ries of galleries that acted as a teaching museum since it included the
House Palatial of twenty-two rooms and a summer garden. Wana-
maker’s galleries of furnishings and decoration thus comprised forty-
four furnished period rooms “representing various periods, to enable
architects and homemakers to study and select proper furniture and
home adornments, and to enable them to individualize their homes
from the mere commercial furnishing way” (295). When the new gal¬
leries and the House Palatial opened there were more than seventy
thousand visitors on the first day alone. The House Palatial was meant
to be a model “representing the home of a family of taste and wealth;
the best of its type that can be seen in Fifth Avenue, of Hyde Park, Lon¬
don.” Its cost, including the furnishings, amounted to $250,000, which
may seem extravagant, but it was considered “as an educational fea¬
ture that will enable houseowners and architects to judge decorative
schemes and furnishings, . . . without parallel in the world” (296).
idealism of James Jackson Jarves and others who made a cult of art
offer any answers. More likely the truth lay with Wanamaker’s. In
France the opposition between the ideal and the materialism of con¬
temporary civilization took the form of an institutional opposition be¬
tween art as represented by the Beaux-Arts tradition, doctrine, and
methods of teaching, and the works of art produced for the market,
the salons, the various deviations from the ideal. It was an opposition
much like that between religion and secular snares. The world was
represented by money, luxury, Parisian articles, the attractions of the
market, a modern art for modern times, and the salons des refuses,
officialdom’s concession to artists working outside the canons of the
Ecole des Beaux-Arts. The power of the modern thus made for an ever
wider gap between official doctrine and practical realities.
In the United States the opposition between the museum and the
department store took a different form since, as we have seen, the de¬
partment store—like museums and like theorists of the arts—believed
in art and insisted on educating the public. The museum, the depart¬
ment stores, the publicists, the moralists, and the reverends were
agreed on the value of art. Indeed, there was no opposition; for Ameri¬
cans, after the Civil War, had come to be convinced that art and cul¬
ture—“Kulcher” as Ezra Pound would later put it—were a good thing.
The only debatable question was which art and which culture was
best for Americans. The symbolic opposition of department store and
museum that I have used metaphorically to explain the internal con¬
tradictions of bourgeois aesthetics took an entirely different form in
the United States, one between aestheticism and vulgarity. The ideal
was associated with a definite type of art, much as in Europe, but it
was opposed not so much to luxury as to the world of commerce,
money, materialism, and progress, even democracy. In France the op¬
position between the conservatives of the Institut and the Ecole des
Beaux-Arts, and the promoters of the art of the modern world, called
materialists or positivists (the realists and impressionists, for example),
49
was ultimately an opposition within the world of art, the issue being
the' relation of art to the modern world. But in the United States the
champions of art were aesthetes at odds with their own country and
who fled to Europe on the erroneous assumption that true art, true
culture, and true taste could only be found there. If in Europe the
idealists were conservative intellectuals, in the United States they were
sentimental aesthetes.
But the museum and the department store, used here metaphor¬
ically to explore the nature of bourgeois aesthetics, are also typical of
the bourgeois’s way of apprehending and understanding art. Not only
is he an idealist in his views of high art, but he is also a materialist at
the same time. The idealist in the bourgeois would deny his material¬
ism, but this is not a difficult task since the bourgeois world depends
on the strict separation of the moral and the business world. As an
idealist the bourgeois loves art, speaks of it in the loftiest terms, writes
long treatises on aesthetics, develops the history of art, introduces the
study of art in universities, endows museums and collections, and, fi¬
nally, even if he owns a department store, thinks of educating the pub¬
lic in the realm of art and interior decoration. But as a materialist the
bourgeois, through his spouse, produces a cluttered private interior
and ultimately thinks of art objects as so many items to be collected
and exhibited, even bought and sold if need be. And so the bourgeois
as idealist flaneur and the woman on a shopping spree, converges to
alter radically the nature and status of the art object. What the nine¬
teenth century succeeded in doing through the museum, the bou¬
tiques, and the department stores, was to bibelotize art. In this gen¬
eralized bibelotization woman played a role as significant as that
potential consumer, the flaneur; for in an age in which art was a spe¬
cies of new religion, woman, as in the old religion, was also the tempt¬
ress, and the bibelot her apple.
Bedroom, 1905. Photograph by Byron. The Byron Collection.
Museum of the City of New York.
Everyone wants to have a mistress,
as everyone wants to go hunting,
frequent watering places and go to the beaches,
and be seen at theatre premieres.
Maxime du Camp,
Paris, ses organes, ses fonctions et sa vie dans
la seconde moitie du XIXe Siecle.
53
54
not insignificant^ nor for that matter is the date. It is the time of Louis
Philippe, of the passages that fascinated the flaneurs, and the address
is located in a quarter not far from such arcades or from the new
apartments designed as the bourgeois equivalents of the old noble
apartments that were formerly the attributes of the hotels particuliers.
The narrator, being not only a man of leisure but also an amateur de
curiosite, did not fail to go to the sale at the appointed time. Once
there, he immediately noticed that the apartment was already filled
both with men and with women who, though dressed in velvet and
cashmere, looked with astonishment but also admiration, at the lux¬
ury spread out before them. He later understood the women’s reac¬
tions when he realized the apartment in question was that of a demi-
mondaine, a kept woman. The rosewood furniture of the apartment
was superb; there were pieces by Boulle, Sevres and Saxe porcelains
and statuettes, as well as fine Chinese porcelain, velvets, and laces;
nothing was missing from what constituted the luxury and bibelots of
the time.
In the preface of his novel, which is based on a real character,
Dumas, by way of an object (an eighteenth-century ormolu clock), es¬
tablished a link between Marie Duplessis, la dame au?c camelias, and
the Pompadour as well as Madame Du Barry Thus both the bibelot
and woman as luxury items had their precedents in the Paris of Louis
XV and Louis XVI, what with the production of fine furniture, Sevres
figurines, terra-cottas by Clodion, magnificent jewelry, snuff boxes,
and other such small but finely executed and expensive luxury items.
The demimonde in the eighteenth century did not exist in the manner
of the nineteenth, but it was there on a restricted scale, in the form of
an imitation court of women recruited from the theater and the opera,
a class of professionals not only of music and acting, but of what Sten¬
dhal might have described as amour-gout. In the nineteenth century
the possession and flouting of mistresses and courtesans was one way
the successful bourgeois sought to appear noble, aristocratic, worldly,
55
dashing even, and at the same time show off his success. Thus, woman
as'well as what she wore and purchased or received as gifts, was an
item of conspicuous consumption supposing a lavish scale. Mar¬
guerite, Dumas’s “heroine” tells young Armand, who has foolishly
fallen in love with her, that if she were his mistress, she would cost him
100,000 francs a year, which, for 1840, was a very considerable sum in¬
deed. Luxury was thus linked to sexuality, as was buying, as we shall
see; and hence haute prostitution was not only a grand luxury but also
a commercial enterprise. The men were considered as possible invest¬
ments for the women: they were carefully looked over and their in¬
comes were investigated before being accepted.
The demimonde, like the real world, and like the financial world
centered about the stock exchange, had a specific setting and a spe¬
cific ritual. The rue d’Antin was one indication as to setting, but there
were other ritual practices: the daily appearance, in a carriage, on the
Champs Elysees, the ride in the Bois de Boulogne, and of course the
loge in the theater or the opera. It was in these places that the demi-
mondaine made her appearance: object of desire, object of luxury,
actress in the ritual of the demimonde, but also actress in the market
place; for all these places in which she appeared, exhibiting herself to
advantages just as articles de Paris were shown to advantage in the
boutiques, were in a sense her bourse.
The link between royal mistresses such as the Pompadour, the Du
Barry, and the Marguerite of Dumas, not to mention the real high
courtesans of the time, implies that a certain type of noble life was
continued by the demimonde. Indeed this demimonde of luxury,
women, gambling, theater, riding, dining and wining, represented for
the bourgeois the noble life of the aristocracy he tried to imitate. It rep¬
resented, also, considerable expense. As Prudence, Marguerite’s
friend, explains to Armand: “How do you expect the kept women of
Paris to maintain their style of life (le train qu’elles menent), without
having three or four lovers at the same time? No single fortune, no
56
1. Alexandre Dumas, fils, La. Dame au?c camelias (Paris: Nelson ed., Calmann-Levy, n.d.),
141-142.
57
2. Hyppolite Taine, Notes sur Paris: Vie et opinions de Monsieur Frederic Thomas Grain¬
dorge (Paris: Hachette, 1901), 7.
59
sumptuous salon artfully littered with the house’s latest creations and
presided over by Monsieur Arthur, who is dressed like a diplomat. Not
being a regular customer, Madame Derline has to see Monsieur Arthur
in his cabinet, which is decorated by photographs of the Princess
Eugenie. Upon learning that the stranger before him is the beautiful
Madame Derline (he had just read the morning paper), Monsieur
Arthur decides he will find the time to create something for her even
on such short notice and begins to study her: "He walked slowly about
Madame Derline, examining her with a profound attention; then took
a few steps back, looked at her from a little farther off. . . . His face was
serious, worried, anxious. A great man of science seeking to solve a
great problem. He wiped his brow with his hand, raised his eyes to
heaven, looking for inspiration in his birthpangs; but suddenly his
brow brightened; the spirit above had answered his call.’’3 Madame
Derline is redesigned in Monsieur Arthur’s mind—the most beautiful
woman of Paris would have a beautiful dress indeed.
But, realizing that her other dresses were no longer fit for her,
Madame Derline leaves only after having bought several other trifles at
800 francs each. Once outside in the rue de la Paix, seeing all the splen¬
did carriages lined up, she also realizes that her old carriage, faithful
servant of seventeen years, will no longer do, so a new carriage is
bought, upon which it becomes obvious that the old horse will no
longer do either and that the old coachman will not fit in with either
the new carriage or the new horse. Art, fashion, beauty, publicity, and
cost are inextricably mixed. No wonder the philosophical Thomas
Graindorge concludes that women share a subtle but certain kinship
with the nature of works of art: “Women and works of art are related
creatures: both may be overtaken by the same kind of fall; they share
3. See Ludovic Halevy, Karikari (Paris: Calmann-Levy, 1892), 179; “La Plus Belle” is one
story in this volume.
60
the same incapacity to adore and produce. They are no longer the
dreams which imagination or illusion may embody What is really
wanted of them is possession or exhibition” (TG, 307).
Woman was the most expensive jewel men wore in society. Saccard,
Emile Zola's financial genius and adventurer of LArgent, bought one
night with Madame de Jeumont for 200,000 francs, a price that entitled
him to exhibit her at a ball. The emperor had made the prestige of that
particular lady by paying 100,000 francs. It is obvious that Marguerite
was right: such women were not only objects to be possessed and ex¬
hibited, but they also shared another characteristic of works of art,
they had a pedigree, a provenance. And as some pictures were valued
in part because of their preceding possessors, so these women were
esteemed, desired, and priced for the same reasons. Graindorge might
have added to his comparison of women and works of art the rela¬
tively low price of works of art compared to the cost of keeping a
mistress.
The purchase of the favors of such women had nothing to do with
amour-passion, save in novels, but, as Prudence knew, everything to
do with male vanity. Madame de Jeumont on Saccard’s arm was as
certain a sign of his financial success as a diamond pinned to his cra¬
vat. She advertised his success. Paul Bourget, writing novels and
stories about a later generation, said much the same thing. In Un
Homme d’affaires, he writes: “One does not keep one of the glories of
the Comedie to amuse oneself,—but to have the air of a man of taste,
almost a patron of the arts and of artists; but also to advertise one’s
talents as a financier and to hear whispers of He must be making a
great deed of money, the rascal, to spend a hundred thousand a year
on Favier.”4
It must not be thought that this confusion between woman and ob¬
ject was confined to those who frequented the Parisian monde or
5. See Viola Hopkins Winner, Henry James and the Visual Arts (Charlottesville: University
of Virginia Press, 1970), 132.
6. Henry James, Portrait of a Lady (New York: Penguin, 1978), 304.
62
The department stores had fostered an extravagant taste not only for
clothes but also for “things one might do without.” This desire for
“things” was, as noted in the preface, already remarked upon by the
Goncourt brothers, and by the end of the century it had become a
commonplace observation and object of psychological investigation.
When Laura Jadwin, in Frank Norris’s novel The Pit (1903), realized that
her husband Curtis was lost to her because he was entirely taken up
with bold speculations and making an immense fortune, “she began to
63
indulge in a mania for old books and first editions. She haunted the
stationers and secondhand bookstores, studied the authorities, fol¬
lowed the auctions, and bought right and left, with reckless extrava¬
gance.”7 According to this Pascalian logic, shopping had become one
vast escape into divertissement, literally, a diversion from an inner
emptiness. The philosophical essayist Max Nordau saw this desire for
things as a symptom of decadence or, to use his more medical term,
“degenerescence”: “The present rage for collecting, he wrote, the piling
up in dwellings, of aimless bric-a-brac, which does not become any
more useful or beautiful by being called bibelots, appear to us in a
completely new light when we know that Magnan [a French doctor
concerned with degenerates] has established an irresistible desire
among degenerates to accumulate useless trifles/’8
Whatever the explanations given for this generally observed accu¬
mulation of bric-a-brac, the result according to sociologist Rene Konig,
was the bourgeois style of interior decoration, which expressed the
general if at times unconscious or at least unstated values of bourgeois
society, but also, the true status or situation of the art object in that
society. Art joined with fashion, only to be in turn bibelotized. The
bibelot thus became the general characteristic of this bourgeois style
and could be anything, from any time, and any place. In the American
home of the later nineteenth century, the bibelot had been displaced
from a piece of furniture called a whatnot to the more artistic, sup¬
posedly more appropriate, and certainly more up-to-date “Empire
cabinet” designed for bibelots. "Empire” here obviously referred not to
the first empire of the great Napoleon, but to the second empire of
Napoleon III. How else can we explain Harry Leon Wilson’s descrip¬
tion of such a cabinet “with its rounding front of glass, its painted
7. Frank Norris, The Pit (New York: Doubleday Page, 1904), 353.
8. Max Nordau, Degeneration (New York: Appleton, 1897), 27.
64
Watteau scenes, and its mirrored back” in his novel, The Spenders, of
1902? The difference between the old whatnot and the new Empire
cabinet marked not only a movement from the new West to the older
East but also an advancement of culture:
For the latter showed the superior taste of its owner, the superiority
of taste and culture over mere sentimentalism. The bourgeois interior
thus also came to resemble a museum, smaller in scale than the na¬
tional or local institutions, but private, intimate; and yet, the richer it
was, the more capable it was of one day being turned into a public
museum by donation. As such the bourgeois collection was not neces¬
sarily a gallery or collection geared to some historical view of the de¬
velopment of art or the visual expression of some guiding aesthetic or
historical principle. It might be thus among some amateurs or histo¬
rians; but as expressive of the general tendency of the times, it tended
to bric-a-brac, clutter, accumulation.
Santayana, in a once famous novel, The Last Puritan, an astute study of
the New England conscience and mind, described Mrs. Van de Weyer’s
Newport drawing room and the impression it made on Nathaniel
Alden, a Boston Puritan: "The room was littered with little sofas, little
armchairs, little tables, with plants flowering in porcelain jars, and
flowers flaunting in cut-glass bowls, photographs in silver frames,
work baskets, cushions, footstools, books and magazines, while the
walls were a mosaic of trivial decorations (not the work of deserving
artists like those in his own house), but etageres with knick-knacks and
9. Harry Leon Wilson, The Spenders. A Tale of the Third Generation (Boston: Lathrop,
1902), 36-37.
66
10. George Santayana; The Last Puritan (New York: Scribner’s, 1936), 45.
67
12. Paul Bourget, Nouveauy essais de psychologie contemporaine (Paris: Lemerre, 1888),
149.
70
modern world and its boredom, spread even to those who had no ar¬
tistic sensibility at all. It is here the department stores and boutiques,
with the help of modern industry, intervened to produce the inexpen¬
sive, industrialized bibelot that could be afforded by those who could
not purchase the authentic one. The bibelot was thus to be found ev¬
erywhere and it was this ubiquity and clutter that turned into bric-a-
brac. Bourget thought the bibelot mentality so pervasive that he per¬
ceived its influence in the literary style, phrase, and vocabulary of the
Goncourt brothers, who were inveterate collectors. Their collection
took no less than three volumes of description and cataloguing for
their catalogue, Maison d’un artiste. “By indefinitely looking at works of
art/’ wrote Bourget, “they developed in themselves the impression of
the contour and projection which every object projects against a back¬
ground of atmosphere, so that a sentence describing such an object
seems to them exact only if it also necessarily reproduced this contour
and sally. That is why they proceed by inversion, hoping thereby to
give a species of swelling to their prose, as a line delineates a model”
(186). It was a style, thought Bourget, ultimately derived from Cha¬
teaubriand, based on love of color and the description of sensations,
and this explained why it lent itself so well to the description of the
neurotic sensibility. But one wonders whether Bourget’s observations
on the Goncourt style do not also illuminate some of the characteris¬
tics of Henry James, for example his preoccupation with the defining
of exact psychological nuances, the use of the precise term, word,
nuance, or weight of a sentence. Indeed, may we not say that the bour¬
geois psychology of the novelist, the ever-finer analysis of character, is
also that of observers of objects, of clinicians as of experts of art ob¬
jects? The novelist’s reactions, as well as those of his characters, his
descriptions and analyses, all betray a similar preoccupation with de¬
tail, akin to the almost manic connoisseur of precious objects. But
then this aesthetics of the bibelot, central to the bourgeois interior,
may also be gleaned in the dense universe of Marcel Proust so rich in
71
and clutter had blurred the distinction between a mere bibelot and an
objet d’art. Anyone could acquire bibelots—all you needed was
money. But not anyone could collect or acquire objets d art: "Good
objects of art give to a room its crowning touch of distinction. Their
intrinsic beauty is hardly more valuable than their suggestion of a
mellower civilization—of days when rich men were patrons of the
‘arts of elegance’ and when collecting beautiful objects was one of the
obligations of noble leisure. The qualities implied in the ownership of
such bibelots [i.e., works of art] are the mark of their unattainableness.
The man who wishes to possess objects of art must not only have the
means to acquire them, but the skill to choose them—a skill made up
of cultivation and judgment, combined with the feeling for beauty that
no amount of study can give, but that study alone can quicken and
render profitable.”13
Taste could save one from the general debasement of the passion for
bibelots caused by the industrial production of knickknacks by re¬
establishing the distinction between mere bric-a-brac and art. Taste
also established but two conditions for the use of bibelots in a room:
that they be in scale with the room and that it not be crowded.
Wharton’s critique of bourgeois clutter aimed to preserve the dis¬
tinction of possessing the ultimate bibelots, works of art, by drawing
aristocratic lines between the passionate, democratic, acquisitive
spirit and the commercial bibelotization of fashion. The principle of
aristocratic taste, based on judgment and knowledge of art, was used
to counter the effects of industry and department stores. But at the
same time, as we shall see, it sublimated the work of art by distinguish¬
ing the mere bibelot, associated with commerce and industry, from
the objet d’art, associated with nobility and noble leisure. But this dis¬
tinction did not restore the work of art to its function in prebourgeois
13. Edith Wharton and Ogden Codman, Jr., The Decoration of Houses (New York:
Scribner’s, 1901), 187.
73
and preindustrial society. The work of art was simply raised to the
rank of sublime bibelot; distinct from the one anybody could buy in a
novelty shop or a department store, or some antique dealer’s shop. But
given the nature of capitalist society, the bibelot, sublime or not, re¬
mained a marketable item.
Historically speaking, the bibelotization of art is worth pondering.
There had always been collectors of works of art, but nineteenth-
century collecting was perhaps unusual not only in scale but also in
kind; for the bourgeois era, in fact, collected anything because it col¬
lected the past, history as well as art. Anything could enter a collec¬
tion. The Gardners of Boston, in 1897, started amassing more than
paintings as they brought home a French Gothic double door, a round
wooden screen for a circular staircase, a beamed paneled ceiling,
stone lions, a Spanish wheel window, a Roman mosaic pavement with
the head of a gorgon, and so forth. Parts of buildings—indeed, entire
buildings—were removed and transplanted to foreign shores. The
past itself was turned into a gigantic quarry of bibelots.
Bibelotization then may well be the bourgeois way of apprehending
and understanding art. It is related to possession, acquisition, and
production. It implies the bourgeois love of the inheritance and pas¬
sion for selling and buying and finding a bargain. Bibelotization even
makes it possible to put the past up for auction. With art nouveau the
link to the past is untied as the bibelot finds its general style as furni¬
ture, statuettes, vases, lamps, perfume bottles, jewelry, all disciplined
into a flowing line that lent a space and the objects within it a unity. Yet
the objects of that style, intended to be objects of art, remained re¬
producible on an industrial scale as some vases or lamps were pro¬
duced unsigned while others were distinguished by a signature. Art
nouveau thus made Alexandre Arnoux’s dream of uniting art and in¬
dustry come true. Like the photograph in its silver frame among the
other bibelots on the table or the etagere, the art nouveau object re¬
mains as an instance of the reproducibility of the bibelot and testifies
74
77
78
I. Henry Blake Fuller, With the Procession (New York: Harper’s, 1895), 141.
80
that Jane, his daughter, kept up with the general advance of culture.
But this was hardly acceptable in a man, and his son, unfortunately,
had decided, upon his return from Europe, to be interested in art!
Mr. Marshall, who died from exhaustion just as he and his wife
moved into their new home in a more fashionable part of Chicago, was
an honest man. He summed up one way the bourgeois thought about
art: as adornment. It was for women not men, for a man’s life was sup¬
posed to be dedicated to making money. Mr. Marshall’s views were
similar to those of his European bourgeois counterpart in that equally
aggressive and philistine society of Napoleon Ill’s second empire or
Bismarck’s dynamic new reich or Mr. Gladstone’s prosperous and
moral England.
But, unlike the European bourgeois, Mr. Marshall had not lived in a
world in which the arts had survived from former societies and were
part of the social ambiance, indeed, sometimes even part of the furni¬
ture, and accorded some sort of official status and recognition through
public patronage. Thus Mr. Marshall, though a member of the nouveau
riche, did not, like his European counterpart, think of hiding his lowly
origins and his new money beneath a veneer of culture and art. His
wife and daughters, however, did. They had been to Europe and they
saw other Chicagoans doing that. Mr. Marshall was not ashamed of
being a bourgeois. It had probably never occurred to him he was one;
he had probably never even heard the word. Nor had it even occurred
to him art might be an investment.
But Mr. Marshall was behind the times. He died feeling vaguely that
the world was getting harder and harder and wondering whether it
had been wise to want a new home; he had been content in the old
one. He had not had the social ambitions of his wife and daughter,
dazzled not only by Europe but also by the new houses and the luxury
of a Chicago bent on surpassing the East Coast. But Mr. Marshall was
also out of tune with the new type of capitalist, one who wanted the
81
arts to adorn his triumph and not be thought weak for it. Mr. Marshall
was-not Frank Algernon Cowperwood, Dreiser’s “Titan.” Mr. Marshall
belonged to the old Chicago society and “those who, having grown
suddenly rich from dull poverty could not so easily forget the village
church and the village social standards.”2 His was the “dullest and most
bovine” of Chicago social classes; for him money was the sole standard
of success and society consisted in weekday receptions and Sunday
afternoon calls in which one saw the others and was seen in turn.
Cowperwood was an entirely different sort of capitalist and en¬
trepreneur. He belonged to the newer element of Chicago, having
moved west from Philadelphia; for him the arts were not only useful
adornments but a subject of fascination. Cowperwood loved art,
though he was not an aesthete.
Insofar as he is representative of American attitudes toward the arts,
Cowperwood occupies a middle position between the incomprehen¬
sion of Mr. Marshall and the aestheticism of certain Henry James char¬
acters. Cowperwood is intrigued by art though he is not sure why. But
he desires works of art as he does power and women. He thus invests
in it and sees it playing a role in his future. But when he begins collect¬
ing in Chicago, he has a curiously quantitative approach to it, thinking
first of the sum to spend rather than the works to get:
2. Theodore Dreiser, The Titan (New York: John Lane, 1914), 60.
82
He goes on the American Grand Tour with his wife Aileen, first to Lon¬
don, where he meets Lord Leighton, Dante Gabriel Rossetti, and Whis¬
tler, thanks to an art dealer who sees in Cowperwood a future client.
But Cowperwood is not attracted to artists as such: “These men saw
only a strong, polite, remote, conservative man. He realized the emo¬
tional, egotistic, and artistic soul. He felt on the instant there could be
little in common between such men and himself in so far as personal
contact was concerned, yet there was a mutual ground on which they
could meet. He could not be a slavish admirer of anything, only a
princely patron" (59). Already the capitalist would be a Renaissance
prince. He buys a Raeburn in London, then goes on to Paris where he
purchases a plowing scene by Millet, a small Jan Steen, a battle piece
by Meissonier, and a romantic courtyard scene by Isabey. Later we
learn that at his first reception in their new house on Michigan Ave¬
nue, his guests were shown not only Aileen’s somewhat showy yet re¬
freshingly apt portrait but also a brilliant Gerome, then highly popular.
Cowperwood’s taste at this stage of his life reflected rather faithfully
the taste of the 1870s in the United States, and his collection corre¬
sponded to those considered the best in the country, namely, those of
the Astors and the Vanderbilts, collections essentially of modern works
from the French and Belgian schools but also containing pictures from
the Diisseldorf school as well as a few old Dutch pictures.
Later Cowperwood’s taste refines itself and he begins collecting old
masters. On a second trip to Europe he becomes aware not only that
Aileen is not the ideal wife but that there are other places to see and
know besides London and Paris. His collection accordingly becomes
more ample and rises to a higher aesthetic level. He brings back a Peru-
gino, a Luini, a Previtali, and a Pinturricchio portrait of Caesar Borgia,
83
brandt, Titian. By the end of the century the salon moderns would be
threatened and eventually displaced by the rival claims of aestheticism
and modernism, namely a presumably higher and more spiritual taste
for Italian primitives and masterpieces, or, at the other extreme, a taste
for impressionists and later even for twentieth-century painters.
Cowperwood, like Frick, Morgan, and Mrs. Gardner of Boston, also
built a splendid house in New York to serve as a museum. The style
chosen for this mansion was symbolic of Cowperwood and the tri¬
umphant post-Civil War capitalists. His career in Philadelphia had be¬
gun with a home in the style of modified Gothic; his Michigan Avenue
home had been solidly Norman-French; his New York residence could
only be an Italian palace of medieval or Renaissance origin. It was
meant to reflect his private tastes but also to “have the more enduring
qualities of a palace or even a museum, which might stand as a monu¬
ment to his memory” (WP, 439). The house was to have not one gallery
but two: one for pictures, the other for sculpture and large works of
art. A smaller lounge on the second floor was to exhibit his jades, por¬
celains, ivories, and other small objects. The modern condottiere of
free enterprise would not build a fortress on a hill but a museum on
Fifth Avenue.
Though a man of business, Cowperwood was a very different type
from Mr. Marshall. He was no philistine, no matter what a snob might
have thought, and it was more than means that made him buy his
works of art. Undoubtedly social considerations had played a role, as
had what he had seen in Europe. But Cowperwood was drawn to
beauty, feminine as well as artistic. Like Cardinal Mazarin he would, at
night, go into his gallery and wonder:
cause greatness itself, rank, high station, and the appearance of such
were, not distinct: appearance was reality. An unmagnificent king was
unthinkable. The luxury spending of the financier class in the eigh¬
teenth century was an attempt to gain nobility through the creation of
the appearance of nobility. This meant chateaux in the country, mis¬
tresses, an hotel particulier and furnishings, including a gallery of pic¬
tures. But neither all the rich nor all the financiers were that osten¬
tatious; nor was all such spending considered highly or admired. Nor
were such spenders necessarily lovers of the arts.
The Rothschilds, Morgans, Vanderbilts, and others who accumu¬
lated art objects in the nineteenth century may have been in the tradi¬
tion of the financier class of eighteenth century, but they were under
no obligation to maintain the appearance of nobility, the grandeur as¬
sociated with an ancient name, or the honour of being in the service of
the king. The Due de Choiseul as first minister of Louis XV had little
choice but to appear magnificent and to overspend and find himself
ruined upon his dismissal. Men in high places were expected to spend
in the grand manner.
But while the millionaires of the nineteenth century might have
spent more even than princes on works of art, they did so within a
mental universe wholly unlike that of the late baroque world, for their
economic mentality was still dominated by that of the bourgeoisie, a
“saving for future ethos," to quote Norbert Elias.3 To Veblen, conspicu¬
ous consumption might have looked like the potlatch, but millionaires
were hardly ruined by their collecting. The bourgeois saves for a future
he believes in; the grand gesture in spending is an attribute of the old
baroque court nobility. Debts were no disgrace for that nobility. Debts
and bankruptcy were, on the other hand, a disgrace for Balzac’s Cesar
Birotteau.
Finally, there is another essential difference between the conspicu-
ous spending of the millionaire and the noble spending of the old
court nobility: the aesthetic center had been displaced. The million¬
aire collected once the cult of art had been elaborated; the aesthetic
part of his life was centered on acquisition, on objects of beauty. But
the aesthetic of the old court nobility was centered on appearance,
grandeur, magnificence. The aesthetic was in the service of nobility
and not a sign of the possession of pecuniary wealth.
Cowperwood is a complex character. He is no barbarian, no mere
rich man who has made his pile in a none too scrupulous manner and
is trying to pass as a man of culture. For he is drawn to the ideal. This
is what makes him a bourgeois, while his energy, daring, dynamism,
and business acumen distinguish him from his European counterpart
as a particularly American type. There were other American types
who, like Mr. Marshall, did not consider art very important and yet
supposed that perhaps it was one’s moral duty to support the arts and
endow museums. Thus Nathaniel Alden, Santayana’s splendidly drawn
Puritan, had a “weakness” for art—a word that speaks volumes—but it
was not such a great weakness as to lead him to like art, only to sup¬
port local artists by buying their pictures as a public duty. But Alden
belonged to an older generation and to New England, and his attitude
was that of the citizen of a new proud republic who thought it a duty
to support the arts in a new society. Cowperwood belongs to a post-
Civil War generation that would be disturbing precisely to the New En¬
gland conscience. |Boston believed in art, and, by the 1890s, as Van
Wyck Brooks remarks, “Boston girls grew up with Botticelli manners.”
An ideal Renaissance, composed of Botticelli, Dante, and Petrarch, as
well as Browning and Ruskin, had been, so to say, Bostonized.4
But how had it come about that Boston girls had Botticelli manners
and that the Renaissance had been Bostonized? Ruskin provides one
4. Van Wyck Brooks, New England Indian Summer; 1865-1915 (New York: Dutton, 1940),
435.
89
elevating and educating the upper and middle classes, that is, the
monied classes. In Europe the conservative aesthetic was associated
with state institutions and an artistic tradition, and little attempt was
made to educate the nouveau riches of the empire or the third re¬
public by writers, who preferred to ridicule rather than instruct. This
does not mean the bourgeoisie did not have its apologists. One has
only to think of Octave Feuillet or Georges Ohnet, who wrote genteel
novels complete with pure and faithful wives, but there were also the
scandalous Flaubert, Maupassant, and Zola. Indeed it would be easier
to posit an antigenteel tradition in France rather than a genteel one.
Taste was inseparable from class, and it was ever associated with some
historical background.
But in the United States art was not defined by or in the same condi¬
tions. It was, interestingly enough, first defined in writings—from the
lectern, the pulpit, and the editorial chair. Indeed, as a new people, the
Americans of the early decades of the Republic had an advantage over
older peoples, for they started out in history knowing what art was. In
the early decades of the nineteenth century, essays on art undoubt¬
edly outnumbered works of art in the Republic; definitions of art and
beauty, inspired by Alison’s Essays on the Nature and Principles of
Taste (1811) or Hugh Blair’s Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles Lettres
(1783) had, in practical, protestant, and utilitarian America, a moral
and utilitarian bias. For in the old world (corrupt) art had all too often
been associated with courts, luxury, and effete nobility.
Later on Americans would also be lectured to on art by Ralph Waldo
Emerson, the sage of Concord, whose essays on art and nature com¬
bine to make up a telling example of an American, New England ver¬
sion of a supposedly universal idealism: romantic, transcendental,
moral, spiritual, neo-Platonic; and yet, strangely enough, if one takes
account of Emerson’s peculiar view of nature, this idealism is both
natural and godlike. Emerson’s view of art is as fine an updating of neo¬
platonism as one may find anywhere. It is also significant that he
91
tioned by God. Behind the doctrines of the Ecole des Beaux-Arts and
the writings and polemics of Quatremere de Quincy—even behind the
statements and opinions of painters and critics, variously described as
romantics, classicists, realists, or naturalists—lay centuries of ques¬
tions about art, theories, and traditions, religious and secular patron¬
age: questions and answers passed on through time by savants and
institutions founded as early as the sixteenth or the seventeenth cen¬
tury. And in Europe there were countless examples of art works de¬
viating from the canons of taste that were in the process of being dis¬
covered and about to be collected.
Behind the theories of art circulating in the United States, there was,
above all, enthusiasm. And whereas in Europe aesthetic choices im¬
plied questions of class, politics, markets, and attitudes toward the es¬
tablished taste, in the United States aesthetic choices tended to reflect
moral and religious beliefs and attitudes. The American businessman
who came to be interested in art and decided to collect may have been
tough-minded, ruthless, and even unscrupulous in his business deal¬
ings and the amassing of his fortune; but when it came to art, he—or
his wife, or his daughter, perhaps even his son, who might have
thoughts, God forbid, of not going into business—was an idealist. This
idealism was not that formulated by a Quatremere de Quincy or Taine.
It was closer to Victor Cousin; it might be said ultimately to derive
from Winckelmann or Hegel, though such an idealistic businessman
may never have heard those names. But as an American he had learned
his art from the great followers of Buskin: James Jackson Jarves,
Charles Eliot Norton, Enrest Fenollosa, a Hegelian, and also from
Emerson, Hawthorne, Henry James, and Henry Adams.
5. On Ruskin’s importance in the United States, see Roger B. Stein, Ruskin and Aesthetic
Thought in America, 1840-1900 (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967).
93
spiritualists. Yet, Ruskin s appeal lay in his religiosity and style. Ruskin
was eloquent in a century in which eloquence of the pulpit was a
highly regarded literary form. Max Nordau in his work Degeneration
pointed out what appealed to the “anglo-saxon mind ’: he was turgid,
fallacious; yet a master of style; and he was a bigot; also emotional; and
a man of deep sentiment; with the temperament of an inquisitor. In¬
deed; Nordau called him the “Torquemada of aesthetics” (D, 77). Ver¬
non Lee; an English writer living in Florence; put it in a less pictur¬
esque manner: “His philosophy is of far greater importance than any
other system of aesthetics; because it is not the philosophy of the ge¬
nius, evolution or meaning of any or all art; but the philosophy of the
legitimacy or illegitimacy of all and every art.”6 An apt philosophy for a
new nation.
It is precisely this moralistic and Christian inquisition into art that
could appeal to American Puritans and transcendentalists who; as yet;
had no art to speak of in their own country. Art itself became a moral
lesson to be read. And in reading this lesson of art; the American fol¬
lowers of Ruskin were Jansenists in a world going over to the Jesuits.
James Jackson Jarves was not only the first American disciple of
Ruskin, he was the first American to write about art on a theoretical
level; the first great American collector of Italian primitives; and the
first to write art history, art criticism, and aesthetics. His publication
list included Art Hints: Architecture, Painting, Sculpture (1855), Art
Studies: The Old Masters of Italy: Painting (1861); The Art Idea (1864);
and Art Thoughts (1870). His story was told in a novel of Edith Whar¬
ton’s called False Dawn, which implied that his message had come too
soon to a country not yet prepared to accept art, at least as he under¬
stood it. He had considerable trouble trying to sell his collection and
finally gave it to Yale University where it still is. But Jarves was not too
early in bringing art thoughts and ideas to America; for after the Civil
6. Vernon Lee, Belcaro, being Essays on Sundry Aesthetical Questions (London: W. Sat-
chell, 1881), 197-198.
94
War the United States was ready to listen. His ideas he had learned
from Ruskin whom he had met in Italy and it was thus through Jarves
that Ruskin’s great influence began in the United States. From Jarves
this influence passed to another disciple, who had also been to Italy
Charles Eliot Norton of Harvard.
The philosophy of art Jarves built up in the course of his life and
that he expressed in his writings was a coherent doctrine concerned
with the history of art and the importance of art in the future of the
United States. Jarves's emphasis on the role of art in the United States
is important because it distinguishes the uses of art in America from
the uses of and attitudes toward art in Europe. In Europe history in¬
cluded a long past whose art was a heritage to be accepted, denied, or
challenged, and even bought and sold. But in the United States history
brought no such wealth of art; history was more the promise of a fu¬
ture, but what the future would be depended in part upon the correct
reading of the past. Since the United States had no past to speak of, the
lessons of the past had to be learned from Europe.
Jarves was no art historian in our professional, university sense of
the word. He had no Ph.D. But he did think of art in historical rather
than purely aesthetic terms. However, because he thought of history in
moral and American terms, he connected art and its development
with the rise and fall of the states and civilizations. For Jarves, as for
Ruskin, the arts were thus signs of the moral stages of developing so¬
cieties. But since in the United States history included the future, art
could play a useful role in the construction of this future. Beauty could
help men perform their moral duties; art might inspire morality and
high ideals and thereby insure the nation’s prosperity and adherence
to the path set by God who had implanted the laws of art within the
laws of nature.
In the early history of aesthetic thought in the United States then, art
and religion were closely linked: not so much in fact or through in¬
stitutions such as the church, as had been the case in Europe, but in
95
the minds of those who thought and wrote about art. They had read
Ruskin, not Kant. There was an additional reason for this union: “Men
like Jarves, Ruskin, and even Norton, were seeking a religion that cut
across questions of creed, a religion of the heart.”7 In Europe, if you
think of art and religion you think immediately of the Roman church;
but the curious thing about Jarves, Ruskin, and Eliot was that they dis¬
missed the Roman Church from their thoughts and talked instead
about the Middle Ages, conveniently forgetting that even the Middle
Ages had been Roman Catholic. The paradox is easily understood
once it is realized that they dismissed the baroque and the rococo as
the corrupt forms of art of a post-Renaissance corrupted church. Such
a view meant of course that historically, valid art is narrowed down to
certain types of ancient and medieval art, mostly Italian: “The medieval
art of Italy seemed to Jarves to be the purest expression of the religious
ideal in art. He pardoned what he felt to be faulty execution in the
works of Giotto, Sano di Pietro and Fra Angelico, and many others be¬
cause these artists had faith” (R, 137). Things had somehow gone
wrong in the Renaissance when sectarianism arose; and the Reforma¬
tion, despite its laudable aim of purifying Roman corruption, led to
fanaticism and the opposition of art and religion. The other villains in
the drama were the Medicis; with them art started its decline because
it ceased to be free. It had to serve princes.
Jarves, and others after him, saw Italian history from the perspective
of the United States. Early republican Florence was perceived as a
democratic city-state permeated by the wholesome spirit of labor and
trade, similar to the early United States. But the Florence of the Medi¬
cis was that of bankers and princes and was marked by the luxuries of
the rich rather than the simple tastes of craftsmen. Looking at the
7. Stein, Ruskin and Aesthetic Thought, 130. On aesthetics in fin de siecle America, see
also Jackson Lears, No Place of Grace: Antimodernism and the Transformation ofAmeri¬
can Culture (New York: Pantheon, 1981).
96
world about him did not induce Jarves to change his mind; it simply
confirmed his views of Florentine history. If art had gone wrong in
the sixteenth century the modern world of the nineteenth century
showed only too blatantly that art without faith was but technical abil¬
ity and luxury bereft of the spirituality of true art; it was without ideal.
Quatremere de Quincy had seen in the modern world the real dan¬
ger to the art of the ideal and had spoken scathingly of those who be¬
lieved in progress; Americans tended to think likewise. The modern
world was a danger to the kind of free, moral; democratic art as had
been obtained in the early Renaissance. And modern Paris—thriving;
luxurious; attractive—was opposed to the virtuous Florence of the late
medieval period when art was filled with the spirit of true religion.
Paris came to play in the American imagination much the same role
as it had assumed among Europeans: it stood for modernity but it was
also the antithesis of virtuous America and also of democratic Amer¬
ica. In Jarves’s case Paris was that of Napoleon III. And like the Medicis;
it pointed to the same lesson regarding the effects of despotism on art:
“Despotism has made of Paris a brilliant bazaar; cafe; and theatre; in
truth a well-baited trap for money and morals. Its standard of human¬
ity is low; ambitions narrow; knowledge contracted to selfish aims; and
chase of fleeting pleasure intense.”8 There was no denying; Jarves ad¬
mitted; that it was a brilliant; well-planned; attractive city calculated to
make a good and pleasing impression; just like its shop windows and
the ladies’ toilettes. But it was spiritually destitute. And this brio and
the emperor’s political success were due to the same cause: lack of
morality in the country at large. Jarves had learned his Ruskin to per¬
fection: art; morality society and politics were all united.
This view of Paris was general among Americans who were; after all;
very earnest. Thus Henry Adams; serious about his education; knew it
was frivolous to go to Paris: “France was not serious, and he was not
8. James Jackson Jarves, Art Thoughts (New York: Hurd and Houghton, 1870), 255.
97
serious in going there. He did this in good faith, obeying the lessons
his teachers had taught him; but the curious result followed that,
being in no way responsible for the French, and sincerely disapprov¬
ing of them, he felt quite at liberty to enjoy to the full everything of
which he disapproved. Stated thus crudely, the idea sounds derisive;
but, as a matter of fact, thousands of Americans passed much of their
time on this understanding.”9 One is tempted to say that if Paris had
not existed in the nineteenth century it would have been necessary to
invent it to save Americans from Boston.
Be that as it may, it is clear that Paris in the American aesthetic
played a role similar to that which it occupied in the minds of ideal¬
ists, traditionalists, the minds of members of the Ecole des Beaux-Arts.
It is also obvious that if in the French aesthetic Paris represented the
temptations of the modern, in the American mind it represented the
temptations of sin. The American was ambivalent: Paris was all wrong
about art, yet it was attractive. And the attractions were feminine: lux¬
uries, department stores, fine restaurants, the attractions of the senses,
the toilettes of women, the demimonde—in short, the materialist aes¬
thetic that was disapproved of by the Ruskinians as well as by the
idealists, in whose view art had a mission. But in truth the attractions
of Paris were also American attractions: for after the Civil War the
United States, like Napoleon’s Paris, was becoming a modern, dynamic,
progressive, bustling, thriving, materialist country. New York’s Fifth
Avenue was meant to rival anything Paris or London could offer, so
that the “art idea,” introduced by Jarves into a United States at the
crossroads of virtue and luxury, came to be a moral and aesthetic
weapon against the rising tide of vulgarity.
Whereas Jarves had pioneered “art thoughts” in the United States,
Charles Eliot Norton, another friend of Ruskin, fought the good fight
against the ever-mounting tide of post-Civil War American bad taste, or,
as Norton used to say, “the horrible vulgarity of it all.” Art education
was not only a moral duty but an absolute and urgent necessity since
the American Medici were capturing the public imagination and oc¬
cupying Renaissance chateaux and pallazi on New York’s Fifth Avenue.
Santayana sketched a marvelous portrait of the new champion of art:
11. Robert Luther Duffus, The American Renaissance (New York: Knopf, 1928), 18.
100
return home for good. But it is obvious that teaching in bustling, ex¬
panding, energetic America could not mean what studying art had
come to mean among the few Europeans engaged in that activity: the
scholarly, almost neutral, professional study of the arts in history, in
which their development was followed, the various schools deline¬
ated, and a survey of civilization made. Art also meant, for Norton and
others who began to teach art history—art, for short—after the Civil
War in eastern universities, as Vanderbilt put it, preaching “the gospel
of art.’| Norton had three well-defined aims in mind when, in 1874, he
began to lecture on art: to reveal the significance of the fine arts as an
expression of the moral and intellectual conditions of the past; to illus¬
trate the baseness of present America by way of contrast with the great
moments of the past; and to refine the sensibilities of young men at
Harvard.
Although he began lecturing in 1874, it was not until 1878 that he
lectured on the Renaissance, and not until 1896 that he began using
lantern slides to show the monuments he lectured on. Apparently
Norton lectured as much on Dante as on Italian art. And since the
great moments were Athens and the Gothic period in Florence and
Venice, his task was facilitated. His aesthetic principles were simple:
the aim of poets and artists was, through the imagination, to achieve
the beautiful and the good. He was not at all in accord with trends at
that time linking art and literature with beauty rather than with truth,
and he deplored the views of a James or Flaubert, according to which
the integrity of art existed irrespective of subject matter. Nor was he
sympathetic to Zola, whose ignoble subject matter vitiated the sense of
beauty and craftsmanship. Norton rejected the modern not only in its
incarnation as fashion but also in its arts. He was no more tolerant of
the art-for-art’s sake tradition or the aesthetic movement; for that also
separated art from morality and could potentially be perverse enough
to lead to a fascination with the ugly, the strange, the foul, and the evil.
Norton was an idealist who, had he been French, would probably have
101
12. Hyppolite Taine, Philosophic de I’Art, 2 vols. (Paris: Hachette, 1909), 2:223.
102
sure he gave the rein to his instincts, and in regard to art he was
so full of its relation with religion that he would admit of no
divergence between the two. Art and religions might take great
liberties with each other, and both be the better for it, as he
thought.13
neutralize that of the dynamo. For such people, as James put it in one
telling phrase, “life was a matter of connoisseurship” (PL, 262). Thus
Gilbert Osmond’s sole accomplishment, his fastidious taste, compen¬
sated for all his negative qualities: lack of talent, lack of genius, lack of
prospects, and lack of wealth. There are traits of the dandy in Osmond
but not of the European dandy a la Wilde, Baudelaire, or Gautier, all of
whom were artists, creators, and fighting a war of style against the bour¬
geois. Osmond is the bourgeois aesthete, sterile and possessive, snob¬
bishly fastidious. As Madame Merle said, he had to have the best, even
in women, which he assimilated to his bibelots. Osmond refined his
taste to the most exclusive snobbism. It was his way of asserting his
difference in a democratic society. But it was not nobility that required
a role or meant obligations. In Osmond, aestheticism, taste, fastidious¬
ness, “implied a sovereign contempt for everyone but some three or
four very exalted people whom he envied, and for everything in the
world but half a dozen ideas of his own” (PL, 430). This was the Pu¬
ritan’s certainty of his election on the aesthetic plane. Everything was
damned, everything was vulgar, everyone more or less lost; and he, Pu¬
ritan that he was, must keep himself unspotted. His fastidiousness was
a species of perverse saintliness, perhaps the only one open to the late
Puritan type. Osmond’s view of the world is indeed reminiscent of
what students used to say about Norton’s continuous harping on the
“horrible vulgarity of it all.” But for all his contempt of the world, Os¬
mond did not withdraw from it; for he needed it to assert his superi¬
ority, live his false aristocratic life, and assume his pose, which was
good enough to have seduced even as bright a girl as Isabel Archer.
And the pose he assumed was a pose in the void.
It was an instance of a pervasive nihilism. Osmond himself put the
finger on what was wrong with his position and that of most Ameri¬
cans living in Europe: "I sometimes think we’ve got into a rather bad
way, living off here among things and people not our own, without re¬
sponsibilities or attachments, with nothing to hold us together or keep
105
Every day the young woman went forth with her Baedeker. Ar¬
rived in some museum she went either to the left or right and
stopped before the first wall of pictures, looked an instant into
her guide, raised her eyes back to the painting, looked at it for a
time more or less long, then recommenced with another picture
and repeated the exercise for hours with a real pleasure and
unequalled conscientiousness. She was not wrong in her admi¬
ration and sincerely enjoyed the sight of these masterpieces.
106
Annie was dutiful about enjoying art. She may even have been to Vas-
sar and taken an art history course and undoubtedly was far more
knowledgeable about art than her husband the marquis. He did not
bother reading Baedeker at all. He looked at far fewer pictures than she
did, but he felt, was touched, by what he looked at. It meant something
else to him. One evening, as they left Saint Peter’s basilica at dusk, they
heard the angelus ringing and the effect of light and sound and the
grandeur of the architecture was such as to stop the marquis in his
tracks and to mutter How beautiful, as he was seized by the moment.
“ ‘Superb! immense!’ Annie cried out, but I don’t remember how many
feet the piazza and colonnade measure; I must go see’” (233).
Annie was obviously not a Henry James character, though she did
have sensibility and intelligence and was undoubtedly more sophisti¬
cated about art than Newman who had masterpieces copied to take
home with him. The difference between Annie and the marquis is cul¬
tural. And it would take time for Annie to note the subtle differences
between Americans and Europeans even though they might share the
same art works—the Americans having purchased them; the Euro¬
peans having inherited them and sometimes lived with them so long
they were taken for granted until some such experience as the mar¬
quis underwent made them take notice. Annie needed time to under¬
stand the difference. As she settled in her Parisian life and the sum¬
mers at the ancestral chateau in the Bourbonnais, she noted the
differences: “By comparing the old manor house with the finest dwell¬
ings of New York, she realized better than she ever had, the difference
which exists between an aristocracy and a plutocracy” (282).
This difference existed also in Europe between the old nobility and
But if Boston represented America’s high culture, the price paid for it
was a certain dryness and sometimes even exile, that is, maintaining
the purity abroad.
16. Th. Bentzon, Les Americaines chez elles (Paris: Calmann-Levy, 1893), 113.
108
Osmond and, to a lesser degree, Ned Rosier and Mr. Verver ex¬
emplify this peculiarly American high ideal of culture, taste, and artis¬
tic perfection almost to the point of death. It implies the museum
mentality, the association of culture with a past, and the consequent
rejection of the modern, thriving, vulgar, but living world, which is,
after all, the condition of their disdainful aestheticism. But the fastidi¬
ous aesthete who had to have nothing but the best was but one ex¬
treme of the American intervention in the art world.
The other extreme shall be called "the swooping barbarian.” The
aesthete picked and chose; he might exile himself, lose himself in the
rarefied atmosphere of Europe’s own cosmopolites, aesthetes, dec¬
adents, and nobles out to regild their arms by marriage to an Ameri¬
can heiress. But not everyone was high church, capable of being saints
in the world of high culture. The swooping barbarians—the wife and
daughter of Mr. Marshall of Chicago, or the graduates of Vassar, Bryn
Mawr, Smith, and even Wells College—all found a more direct way of
acquiring culture. After the proper preparation of some course on art
history or appreciation or simply reading Ruskin, they simply traveled
to Europe, did the sights, and returned with culture to create mu¬
seums, perhaps even teach courses in art. For even the barbarians—
and the word was hard and rather unfair—believed in culture after
Jarves, Ruskin, and Norton. It was preached at them in Harvard; it was
lectured on at Yale and Princeton; even in Minnesota, thanks to Pro¬
fessor Gabriel Campbell of the Department of Mental and Moral Phi¬
losophy, art was taught. It was, indeed, a most noble and elevating sub¬
ject, taught by a great many reverends: the Reverend John Bascom, the
Reverend John Lansing Raymond, the Reverend James Mason Hoppin.
They all prepared the great descent that the older generation of Henry
James found somewhat vulgar. But the swoopers knew they were shop¬
ping for the ideal. As Paul Bourget noted on his tour of the United
States in 1893: "You have to hear the Americans pronounce the word
art, simply and with the article, to understand the profound zeal they
110
feel to refine themselves, and also tliis word refined, ever on the lips of
my fellow writers as I visit their club.”17
The result of the American search for the ideal was, much as in Eu¬
rope, the bibelotization of art. Because there was a great dead of money
in the United States, there were a great many bibelots to be bought. For
swooping down on Europe for the ideal meant shopping in the great
bibelot bazaar. For Newman, an international flaneur, Europe—indeed
the world—was "a great bazaar where one might stroll about and pur¬
chase handsome things; but he was no more conscious, individually
of social pressure than he admitted the existence of such a thing as an
obligatory purchase.”18
A further result of this international shopping for the ideal mani¬
fested itself in the bibelotization of the American home. The Gilded
Age was the eclectic bibelot age. Paul Bourget saw in Newport what he
considered the result of American shopping abroad: Elizabethan
houses, French Renaissance chateaux, French eighteenth-century
chateaux or town houses, Italian villas, and, within these, riches be¬
yond belief, all of which he thought a result of the unconscious desire
or need of the American to ennoble himself with a sense of the past, an
honest need, Bourget thought, and one that saved these houses from
what would otherwise have been brutal vulgarity. There was some¬
thing pathetic, yet poetic about this need for something from the past
in this materialistic world of the “check and the chic.” And yet, there
was perhaps just a trifle too much from the past.
In a novella called Deuy menages, Bourget is given a letter of intro¬
duction to a Mrs. Tennyson R. Harris of Fifth Avenue, who lived in a
white marble construction in the manner of the Chateau de Blois.
However, as she is in Newport for the season, the narrator takes him¬
self there to be received by Mrs. Harris in a room that is meant to seem
Parisian but does not quite succeed:
17. Paul Bourget, Outre-mer, 2 vols. (Paris: Lemerre and Meyer, 1894-1895), 1:49.
18. Henry James, The American (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1907), 66.
Ill
Mrs. Harris knows all the latest Paris gossip, has read all the latest
books, so late indeed that Bourget hasn't even seen them in the Paris
bookshops. Bourget got the impression of an America with a thin Eu¬
ropean veneer. And the dinner too, that evening, is also just too lux¬
urious, what with Meissen dinnerware, a Sevres service of imperial
origin, and the portraits of Louis XVI and Marie Antoinette, duly in¬
scribed donne par le Roy, hanging on the wall. And when Bourget ac¬
companies Mr. Harris to Georgia in his private train he also notices a
small library of 200 volumes, all first-rate and beautifully bound, and
learns that in his off hours Mr. Harris works at his culture: “It is a big
word which Americans always have on their lips and on their mind,
and which they apply with equal seriousness to morals and gymnas¬
tics, as in ethical and physical culture” (V, 168). Poor Mr. Harris, Bourget
also finds out, is the slave of Mrs. Harris’s cultural snobbism and ambi¬
tion. This truth is revealed to him in a curious performance they wit¬
ness together in which a husband-wife team perform in a variety show.
The wife declaims sublime poetry in free verse of her own creation
19. Paul Bourget, Voyageuses (Paris: Nelson ed., Calmann-Levy, n.d.), 161.
112
Mrs. Ralph Dagonet of a distinguished New York family; still later Com-
tesse'de Chelles—Paris meant luxury shopping; clothes; modernity
Italy, being art; meant boredom. And for Undeen, one of the Jamesian
swoopers; art meant bibelots that could be exchanged for the life of
luxury. Undeen marries de ChelleS; who, being noble and burdened
with a chateau in the country can hardly afford to live in Paris. When
Undeen wants to leave the country to live in Paris continually de
Chelles says they cannot afford it. Undeen then immediately thinks of
selling the Boucher tapestries in the chateau that have been with the
family since the eighteenth century whereupon de Chelles says: “Ah;
you don’t understand.” Indeed; for de Chelles and many representa¬
tives of his class, Boucher tapestries; family portraits; pictures, old fur¬
niture, all represent their past, their race, their traditions, their very
being as nobles, not to mention the remains of a lost position. These
were no mere bibelots. Given the right price, they were something an
American could obtain. The clash between the swoopers and the
swooped upon was inevitable and de Chelles unleashes his anger at
Undeen:
derstand anything about the things that make life decent and
honorable for us!20
20. Edith Wharton, The Custom of the Country (New York: Scribner’s, 1913), 545.
115
And the money was to be for all the more exquisite things—for
all the most exquisite except creation, which has to be off the
scene altogether; for art, selection, criticism, for knowledge,
piety, taste.21
But ostensibly it was all to educate the sense of beauty to the soul and
the mind; it was all for the spirit, the trade value of the objects being
merely accidental and incidental. But James seems to be hinting, by
his insistence on acquisition, that in bourgeois society even acquisi¬
tion has been sublimated onto the aesthetic plane. "The Museum, in
short,” he continued, “was going to be great, and in the geniality of the
life to come such sacrifices, though resembling those of the funeral-
pile of Sardanapalus, dwindled to nothing.”22 The funeral pile was
really that of the Old World; and it was a pile of bibelots.
One may read this magnificent intimation of the meaning of the
Metropolitan Museum, and perhaps of the American type of museum,
as the synthesis of two conflicting tendencies regarding art observed
within Americans: the idealist strain tends toward aestheticism; and
the swooping tendency was to accumulate, acquire, consume, pile up.
The American museum of art was the result of a partnership among
Osmond and Moffat and Undeen Spragg. The museum had become
possible because the world of exiles and shoppers was part of a huge,
international, though not always obvious, art market, the cosmopolis.
21. Henry James, The American Scene (New York: Harper’s, 1907), 186.
22.Ibid.
V
: K: ^ -
Cosmopolis, or the
Snob’s Progress
Promenade des Anglais. Nice, France. 1881.
Historical Pictures Service, Chicago.
Titles, no matter what anyone may say,
have more value than ever.
A title is as pretty as period furniture or old Gobelin tapestries,
and it decorates a woman far better
than her toilette or her diamonds.
119
120
In this bourgeois search for the material grail, Paris was a school for
distinction and snobbism, providing instruction in the various stations
to be reached, the indispensable lines to know, the best shops to fre¬
quent. In this new version of a rake’s progress, the snob’s progress,
Paris as well as London offered the flaneur in his last incarnation the
image of a life-style in which the bourgeois thought he at last ap¬
proached the poetic, aesthetic, dashing (and now defunct) nobility of
the old regime. Ah, but was it really noble? Was it really the real thing?
The preconditions of the snob’s progress were two: letters of intro¬
duction and letters of credit. The latter was most important. Money,
which Henry James found to be in the air about the Metropolitan Mu¬
seum of Art, circulated around the grand hotels, the famous beaches,
the casinos and villas of the cosmopolitan set. Generally, money meant
unearned income, based on vast holdings of real estate, bonds, or
stocks; or, if recently acquired, money usually meant income from a
huge stock market coup or cleverly arranged bankruptcy followed by
even more cleverly arranged suppression of scandal, though there
were bound to be whispers about such and such. In this world of cos¬
mopolis represented by the novelists of the fin de siecle, only the
Americans were singled out as having made their fortunes the hard
way. They might be in Europe on a tour, but they kept up with affairs at
home, directing them from afar and ready to be called back at any time
to save a situation. There were intimations of disasters, of immense
deals and immense wealth. The American man of business abroad ap¬
peared not as a robber baron but, rather, as a new type of feudal lord.
In contrast, the Europeans seemed to be connected with banking,
which allowed one a certain leisure. But, generally speaking, it was
best to avoid talk of background and the origins of someone’s fortune:
122
whatever was not connected with income from noble land was bound
to be somewhat vulgar, just as the Medicis had appeared somewhat
vulgar to Henry Adams. In any case, work (meaning a few hours at the
office or the stock market) played no role in cosmopolis, was not talked
about, was not even assumed, though money was. The ideal was to
have an income more than sufficient to be free from having to step into
an office at regular times, or at least for a time short enough to leave
the evenings open for a social life. And if, like Dickie Marsh (a Paul
Bourget character described as a Napoleon of business from Marion-
ville, Ohio), you had to keep an eye on your vast holdings and their
management, then you might travel on your yacht, along with three
secretaries who kept continually in touch with affairs at home so that
any important decision might be made on the spot. But if you had
enough wealth to live in the accustomed luxury and felt no inclination
to oversee your investments too closely, then you had twenty-four
hours a day on your hands and the question arose as to what to do
with them.
The form that leisure took among the inhabitants of cosmopolis ex¬
plains why some Americans preferred to stay in Europe rather than
return home, quite aside from their search for culture and refinement.
For as Ned Rosier said succinctly: "There's nothing for a gentleman in
America.” It was a country where everybody worked. Mr. Marshall
could not understand why his son, upon his return from Europe,
wished to live the life of a gentleman and, rather than work, do some¬
thing vaguely connected with art. Even that very refined gentleman
Charles Eliot Norton worked; he taught art at Harvard. There was no
place in the United States for someone whose occupation was doing
nothing. For a man there seemed no alternative to work. Bourget, in
Newport, had been struck by the lack of adventurers and fortune hunt¬
ers. Cannes, Nice, Baden-Baden, Cabourg, Biarritz, all had had their
adventurers—men who were gallant to women and lived by gambling
and marrying rich heiresses, who went about with the rich and fre-
123
quented the best circles, but in any case, did not work. Women in the
United States, the women of the rich, that is, were the true leisure class
as Europe understood the term. They had their clubs, teas, social ambi¬
tions, charities, churches; accordingly leisure had come to be thought
of as something for women, and husbands the guarantors of such lei¬
sure and what went with it, namely, culture and refinement.
But in Europe, a gentleman by definition did not work and found
there were a great many agreeable ways of doing nothing, such as
spending accumulated capital. Interest in art or culture provided but
one possible answer to the question of how to spend one’s time and
money in the rites, activities, and displacements of cosmopolitan so¬
ciety. This high life, which was not necessarily aesthetic though it had
its style, produced several social types of which the Jamesian aesthete
is the exception; one does not imagine Ned Rosier or Gilbert Osmond
at the races. Aside from the general category of snobs, a term widely
used to designate most of “society” before 1914, there were the viveurs
and the fetards, high livers and prototypes of what would later be
called playboys, themselves derived from previous types of an earlier
age such as dandies and lions of the romantic period.
Raymond Casal, one of Paul Bourget’s characters, is a good example
of the better type of viveurs. Better in that he was no vulgar fetard or
noceur and had style, dash, and a shrewd knowledge of the world that
kept him from being taken in by it. Intelligent, worldly, a good sports¬
man, an excellent shot—highly important in a society that still settled
affairs of honor by duels—and a known seducer, he was no aesthete;
neither was he particularly interested in the arts or in letters, horses
and women being more his affair. Casal outlined the life of a viveur one
night in a moment of boredom in which he had two hours to fill but
nothing to fill them with:
This life required not only a good constitution but also a good deal of
money. Bourget estimated that the viveur required an income of about
150,000 francs a year to live in style. With that, Paris was his. He might
belong to one or two chosen clubs that the young bourgeois sought
vainly to enter. Such was the viveur de grande espece who married at
forty to recoup his fortune and continue his life by spending his wife’s
dowry. As for the society he belonged to and in which he moved, it had
a hierarchy, constitution, unwritten rules and customs, and even a ge¬
ography. It was a cosmopolis:
Half European, half French which filled the greater part of the
hotels situated around the Parc Monceau and the Arc de Tri-
omphe, as well as a small number of old hotels on the Left Bank.
This society has well-established revenues, a strict etiquette, gal¬
leries of authentic pictures, carefully kept carriages, loges at the
opera, sensational receptions, in brief, an opulent high life decor.
This modern society resembles the age to which it belongs and
whose luxury-aristocracy it represents. Like the times it is
mobile and improvised, all of contradictions, and deprived of
tradition. A great fortune, provided it was acquired without too
much scandal, will force open the door, as will talent, provided it
does not show its native egotism. But ruin, on the other hand,
. puts a lock on this door which is hardly ever unlocked.2
The geography alluded to in this passage, the Right Bank and the few
hotels of the Left Bank, points to a merging of the bourgeoisie, the cote
de chez Swann in Proust, with the old nobility of the Faubourg Saint-
Germain, the cote de Guermantes; but this merging also included the
new money aristocracy of well-to-do Jewish families involved in bank¬
ing and finance. It was not an open society but exclusive, despite the
fact that it was based on something classless in theory, namely, money.
As Claude Larcher, one of Bourget’s many writer-characters, explains
to Rene Vincy, a budding writer just invited to his first reception in
society:
You will enter society, my dear, and you will be received often;
but you will never be part of it, no more than I am, no more than
any other artist, no matter how much genius he may have, be¬
cause, quite simply, you were not born in it, and because your
family is not of it. You will be received and parties will be given
in your honor. But try to marry into it and you will find out. . . .
As for those women you dream of as being delicate, fine, and
aristocratic! if you only knew them! They are vanities dressed up
by Worth and Laferriere. . . . There are not ten among them ca¬
pable of true emotion.3
tures” were mentioned by Bourget as signs of this world, the use of the
epithet is significant as it implies not only a search for the real thing
but also a world of the inauthentic, in close proximity, that must at all
costs be avoided. The alliance between art and this millionaire society
was likely to be based on luxury rather than that of true taste and dis¬
cernment cherished by the connoisseur, amateur, or scholar.
Bourget explained in Pastels that democracy in the nineteenth cen¬
tury had had both a political and an economic effect, the latter in the
realm of commodities and the world of luxury. The democratization of
society and the economy had put in the reach of all what he aptly
called:
The nearly enough sufficed to satisfy the many who could not afford
the real thing. The real thing could only be bought and acquired by
those who had real fortunes, that is, very great ones. Thus the viveur or
higher liver with his 150,000 francs a year could live the real thing: but
below him, at a lesser level of fortune, lived his a peu pres, his imita¬
tion, almost but not quite the real thing, who lacked a l>je ne sais quoi
and the great Donatello. And there was so much to learn in those
mornings in Florence as one wandered about the city with Mr. Rus-
kin’s little red book, entitled, precisely Mornings in Florence. But the
city also satisfied and stimulated the diseased, languishing, fragile,
and slightly perverted souls summarized and defined by the lily and
the iris. The atmosphere of Florence was definitely Paterian; Jarves
and the other Puritans who had approved of early and late medieval
Florence but frowned on the Renaissance were gone; it was all right to
love the Mona Lisa, to ponder Leonardo, and to talk of Michelangelo.
And in the hills above the city of Alberti and Brunelleschi, those evoca¬
tive names conferring distinction on those who knew them, the rich
and cultivated, the cognoscenti and the aesthetes, the rich Americans
and the English milordi lived in villas set in delightful gardens, studied
and described by Mrs. Wharton and illustrated by the late post-pre-
Raphaelite Maxwell Parrish. Here were the privileged of cosmopolis,
who knew the real thing and were aware of their art sensations. But for
the cognoscenti and those sincere Americans ever on the search for
culture—or for a bargain—even this place of privilege was not enough.
Those in the know went beyond Florence into the hills, to Siena or Pisa,
and to the Umbrian hills where hidden treasures might be glimpsed in
little hillside churches, where perhaps truer sensations might be felt
than at the Uffizi, already so crowded, already threatening one’s art
sensations and obfuscating the tactile values.
And of course there was Venice, also a special place of pilgrimage for
the lover of beauty and the seeker of special sensations. It was, per¬
haps, a more complex aesthetic experience than Florence, which, as
everyone knew, was the Renaissance, a bit intellectual, even if spiritual.
Venice offered something else. If in the eighteenth century one had
come to Venice for the carnival, in the fin de siecle bourgeois culture
one went to Venice for romantic associations, remembrances of great
loves past, Musset and George Sand who had loved and wept there
and written books about it later. Wagner had died there; and Nietzsche,
130
too, had stayed in Venice. Venice sefemed to attract those aesthetes fas¬
cinated with death and decay, an association best captured by Thomas
Mann’s Death in Venice, in which the city represents both the south,
light, and warmth but also its corruption and misery, its far niente,
and its end to the categorical imperative. And for the less effete bour¬
geois, there was the ritual of life at the grand hotel, the hour for tea, the
beach, the visits to churches and museums, the princely life in some
rented pallazo on the Grand Canal.
Indeed, if Florence induced a dream of spirituality or spiritualized
sensations, Venice was the experience of the beauty of matter, color,
delight in the senses, delight in the pleasures of sight. It was also a
perfect refuge from progress, that terrible progress that turned the
world ugly with its factories and produced an ugly mood among the
working classes. In Venice the lower classes were so much happier;
they sang as they maneuvered the gondolas for the rich tourists. It was
almost a privilege to be poor in such a place of beauty. Venice with its
watery world, its shimmer and gliding gondolas, was an image of the
vague, the fluid, the infinite, the eternally languid that the fin de siecle
loved so much. Venice was a watery Carriere, the dissolution of form
in Turner and Monet, a grand opera in Tiepolo, a masquerade, the ulti¬
mate illusion of beauty in which the false aristocracy of cosmopolis
mirrored itself. But there was a touch of death about the place, and a
melancholy and romance summed up in Giorgione. Here the tactile
values of a school of art inspired by mind and form yield to optic val¬
ues. The divine Sandro yields to the tender reverie of Giorgione. Here,
on the Rialto and among the still, brilliant waters of the lagoons, rather
than in misty Holland, one could find the true reflection of Baude¬
laire’s /uye, calme, et volupte.
One could also speak of Rome, Naples, Pisa, and Orvieto, and so
many other cities, all with their sense of place, their particular sensa¬
tions, their treasures—but there are enough guide books for that.
From another point of view Italy was not so much sensations as a mar-
131
ketplace for both swoopers and aesthetes. It was the ultimate bazaar
whgre culture lay within reach and could sometimes be had for a
song. Here Americans might safely turn into dilettanti. Here at last that
American desire to satiate the eye, which Paul Bourget thought devel¬
oped among Americans to a higher degree than among Europeans,
could be fulfilled. But the delight in works of art, the seeking out of
aesthetic and artistic sensations, was but the sublime surface of some¬
thing that had different motivations. The ultimate experience was per¬
haps not so much the contemplation of beauty but its possession, and
the ultimate aesthetic activity and sensation, acquisition. On his visit
to the United States, Bourget did not fail to notice this alliance of the
aesthetic with speculation, quoting an overheard remark apropos of
the then current financial crisis: “The Italians are rather low down just
now, and there are things to be had sub rosa. But in this moment no¬
body can profit by it” (OM, 1:74).
Italy was a beautiful market. But it was a market that required guides
or investment counselors, for the real thing was not immediately ap¬
parent or to be found by or offered to all. The bourgeois as collector
wanted the real thing, the best, the sure thing, the safe thing, the au¬
thentic, and thus it is that in bourgeois society even disinterested
scholarship and the mania for attribution could prove indispensable
and turn into something delightfully unexpected such as a profit or a
corner on the market.
The general bibelotization of art in the nineteenth century, with its
search for the real thing, its nearly so, and its approximation was
bound to come up against the problem of authenticity. Since the object
of art had been uprooted from its ancient sites and functions, stripped
of its religious and social and political associations, it had become, re¬
gardless of the definitions of philosophers, an object with an exchange
or trade value. Thus the moment of the expert had arrived. And the
flaneur as American tourist seeking culture, refinement, and the real
thing, made his way to I Tatti.
4
I Tatti, or
Sublimating Sales
Bernard Berenson inside I Tatti.
Photograph by Robert M. Mottar, Scope Association, Inc.
Courtesy of Fogg Art Museum, Harvard University.
The snob is the bourgeois gentilhomme of aesthetics.
135
136
tune behind him; but he was the American taking the bibelots of old
Europe very seriously indeed; making of culture a discreet com¬
modity of the objet d art a sure thing; all on a discreet; genteel; exclu¬
sive level. At I Tatti about the luncheon table the ambiguities of bour¬
geois culture were carefully veiled and never allowed to show.
Berenson was not from an ancient family fallen on hard times be¬
cause of a generation of viveurs; he came of immigrant stock; from
people who had come to the United States to “make it” in the new
country. The missing aristocratic background was made up for by
Boston’s aesthetic culture and Harvard, which prepared the young
Bernard Berenson for his future achievements and his transsubstan¬
tiation into the divine B.B., sage of I Tatti. And Harvard meant, in Be-
renson’s youth, Charles Eliot Norton and his particularly Bostonian,
transcendentalist, and Unitarian view of art and Italy. But it also meant
for Berenson the discovery of Walter Pater, of whom Norton disap¬
proved but with whose aestheticism Berenson fell in love, envisaging a
Paterian, epicurean way of life that was dedicated to art. Boston and
Harvard, corrected or softened by Pater, thus gave Berenson that pecu¬
liarly idealist view of art that derived from Ruskin by way of Jarves, was
filtered by reverends, expounded by Norton, and somewhat sensu¬
alized by Pater, who, as George Moore once remarked, always had some¬
thing of a vicar about him. Indeed, Pater’s aestheticism was implied in
Norton’s philosophy of art even though the Puritan in him could not
admit this. To Norton’s New England mind there had to be more to art
than the famous hard, gemlike flame of aesthetic appreciation.
Berenson, when he left Boston for Europe in 1887, had first thought
of being a writer. He had been seduced by Pater’s prose, and Mrs.
Gardner had helped Berenson financially on the understanding he
would cultivate himself further in Europe and turn into a writer, per¬
haps like Francis Marion Crawford who also had been patronized by
Mrs. Gardner. But Berenson in Europe became more and more fasci¬
nated by pictures, though his dream of being a writer was somewhat
138
realized in his library and love of conversation. But the eye became
Berenson’s dominant sense and was turned not toward a white page
to be written on but, rather, toward pictures to be scrutinized, ana¬
lyzed, photographed, classified, and compared, so that seeing turned
into knowing. The literary life envisaged as self-cultivation, the dream
of his Paterian utopia, took second place to the activity of purchasing
books and building up a library, reading, conversing, and in the very
setting of these activities, the villa I Tatti. Only later in life did Berenson
turn into an essayist, producing not only essays on art but also jour¬
nals and an essay on aesthetics. The Harvard aesthete had turned into
a cosmopolite expert posing as a great humanist.
Berenson can be considered a representative of late bourgeois cul¬
ture in its Boston variety. Logan Pearsall Smith, his brother-in-law,
points to the role of culture in this society in his memoirs: “I became
vaguely aware of Culture, not indeed as a thing of value in itself, but as
bestowing a kind of distinction upon its possessors, a distinction supe¬
rior in some mysterious way to that of the big-game killer which had
hitherto been my ambition and my dream.”1 Logan’s initiation into
culture had been instigated by his sister Mary, later Mary Costelloe,
later still Mary Berenson. Likewise, Berenson had been converted to
the culture that later became a ritual at I Tatti. And culture as these
two understood it was a mixture of Boston and Pater and, beyond
these, Matthew Arnold and his “best that has been known and said in
the world.” Although Arnold’s famous definition is that of a moralist
and writer, Berenson needed only to add the best that has been
painted for the definition also to be his. Certainly culture conferred
distinction upon him as it was meant to do upon the money magnates
of the time. In a letter to Mary, Berenson defined culture in purely Pa¬
terian terms as “the real selfish passion for training oneself to have en¬
joyment of the exquisite and beautiful thing lead on to the enjoyment of
1. Logan Pearsall Smith, Unforgotten Years (Boston: Little, Brown, 1939), 82.
139
2. See Sylvia Sprigge, Berenson: A Biography (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1960), 107.
3. Edith Wharton, A Backward Glance (New York: Scribner’s, 1964), 261-262.
140
Berenson’s involvement with art was thus more than that of the art
expert. It was inseparable from culture as it was thought of in the pe¬
riod of about 1880-1914. And the relation of Berenson as critic and ex¬
pert to the art market, as well as his pose as a man of culture, ex¬
emplify the role of art in bourgeois culture at its apogee. Culture at this
time was far different from what it had been: different from that of the
eighteenth century; from that of a Montesquieu and the nobility of the
robe with its sense of history, just as it was different from the historical
imagination of a Chateaubriand, also a great poseur; or from that of
Macauley or Madame de Stael. Presumably it was true hellenism. Pater
in this respect is rather revealing. He makes some interesting false re¬
marks about Voltaire that help to define the Paterian view of true cul¬
ture: “Voltaire belongs to that flimsier, more artificial, classical tradi¬
tion, which Winckelmann was one day to supplant, by the clear ring,
the eternal outline, of the genuine antique.”5
Voltaire may have been many things, but he was not flimsy and did
not belong to the classical tradition but, rather, to a modernity particu¬
lar to his age. But then Pater’s and Berenson’s views of culture were
even beyond the idealism of Jarves, Ruskin, Arnold, or Norton. Beren¬
son’s views belonged to the culture of cosmopolis, which is why he
4. Bernard Berenson, The Bernard Berenson Treasury, ed. Hanna Kiel (New York: Simon
and Schuster, 1962), 38.
5. Walter Pater, The Renaissance (London: Macmillan, 1935), 169.
141
and its history, very Bostonian in its Italian and Japanese orientation;
Anglo-American in its emphasis on the Renaissance; and Germanic in
assuming a pure, disinterested aesthetic experience and its pretension
to scientific expertise. Berenson’s view of civilization was that of a Pa¬
ter; his hellenism was Victorian and had nothing in common with that
of Nietzsche who saw the barbarians beneath the polish of Greek art.
The polar opposite of this hellenism was not barbarism but nineteenth-
century philistinism. Hellenism; with its association with beauty as
well as paganism; was the bourgeois’s latest way of not appearing
bourgeois. For Berenson hellenism ignored Greek science and philoso¬
phy. In the words of Meryle Secrest; the latest of Berenson’s biogra¬
phers; “To him the summit of human achievement was the Greek con¬
cept of the human form; and his criteria were those of the Golden Age:
clarity proportion; order, and harmony. That art might exert its power
through its ability to evoke terror primitive awe; fear or disgust, was
outside his philosophy. For Berenson, the beginning and end of art
was delight.”6
Berenson’s views were far less advanced than those of a Quatremere
de Quincy or a James Jackson Jarves and the generation of the neo-
classicists who were convinced that art might serve as an instrument
for the education of mankind. Berenson’s “philosophy” of art com¬
bined eighteenth-century epicurean aesthetics with Pater’s view of the
Renaissance as itself an aesthetic moment. But then cosmopolis,
which included in part Berenson’s clientele and guest list, could
hardly be expected to espouse a philosophy of art not based on plea¬
sure: acquisition and possession were pleasure, and in the last analy¬
sis the entire aesthetic rested on desire, no matter how veiled or subli¬
mated to something presumably spiritual.
Berenson judged art, as his critic Georges Waldemar remarks, ac-
6. Meryle Secrest, Being Bernard Berenson (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1979),
187.
143
marily that of an aesthete. Form and content were one; the end of art
was delight; subject matter was secondary a mere pretext for the art¬
ist’s expression of formal values and their execution. The image was
neither a key to the meaning of the work nor a thread to follow in a
world of ideas and the imagination that existed beyond the frame of
the picture and belonged to the world in which the artist had lived. It
was not B.B. who invented the science of iconography. It was left to the
later Panofsky to “read” pictures, as one might an emblem book, just as
it was left to Max Dvorak to think of art history as Geistesgeschichte, an
aspect of the history of the human spirit, which it already was for the
Enlightenment, Hegel, Quatremere, and Madame de Stael. As a thinker
about art and its relation to social forces, Berenson did not even rise to
the level of Jarves or Norton, and he never produced a cultural history
such as Burckhardt’s. But perhaps their work smacked too much of
professionalism and was thus repugnant to the aesthete for whom art
was pure enjoyment. In Berenson’s views, art seemed to have nothing
to do with myth, magic, religion, power, politics, or ostentation. Aes¬
thetic art was for aesthetic enjoyment. The counterpart of scientific
criticism was scientific aesthetics, as the counterparts of the market
value of art were tactile values and life-enhancement. Berenson’s views
of culture and art, as well as his aesthetics, were what they were be¬
cause they eminently suited cosmopolitan society, its market, its hedo¬
nistic view of art, and art’s position as supreme bibelot. Expertise was
assessing the bibelot; aesthetic enjoyment was enjoying the bibelot.
But it was not enough to assert such views of art and culture: the valid¬
ity of these views had to be demonstrated scientifically. The aesthete
had to justify himself to the Puritan; hence, the curious nature of fin
de siecle aesthetics.
for you. The market was far more limited than that for Guiness, but it
made up in quality and mark-up what it lost in volume.
When Berenson asked himself why one felt pleasure before a work
of art he came up with the idea of “tactile values.” He formulated this
theory in his book Florentine Painters of the Renaissance and elabo¬
rated on it in his later book, far more theoretical than his others, Aes¬
thetics and History: “Tactile values occur in representations of solid ob¬
jects when communicated, not as mere representations (no matter
how veracious), but in a way that stirs the imagination to feel their
bulk, heft their weight, realize their potential resistance, space their
distance from us, and encourage us, always imaginatively, to come into
close touch with, to grasp, to embrace, or to walk around.”7
Although these tactile values are connected with the materiality of
things represented, as opposed to the much touted spirituality of art,
these tactile values are precisely those qualities of the work of art that
make it “life enhancing”: “Tactile values are life enhancing and do not
excite mere admiration, but give gratification and joy. They therefore
furnish a basis upon which, as critics, we may erect our standards of
judgment” (AH, 60).
The emphasis on gratification and joy, this promise of a special ex¬
perience as opposed to mere admiration, is worth underlining since
all the nouveautes, articles de Paris, laces, bibelots, and dresses in chic
shops and department stores were also instruments of gratification, so
gratifying as to prompt purchasing. The work of art with its tactile val¬
ues was a powerful bibelot indeed. And what made it a bibelot was
that the tactile values had nothing to do with the subject matter. Had it
been otherwise the Puritans who purchased all those Italian madon¬
nas would have had to take account of the subject matter, which was
associated with the detested Roman church. But tactile values, not
subject matter, made primitive stone carvings, as well as Florentine
7. Bernard Berenson, Aesthetics and History (New York: Pantheon, 1948), 63.
146
and their effects is avoided by defining the joy prompted by the work
of art as being pure of desire. Life-enhancing, ideated sensations “must
remain intransitive, inspiring no definable desire, stimulating no ap¬
petite, rousing no lust for sensual enjoment. We must not glide or slip,
or still less leap from ideated to real sensations, from art to actuality”
(.AH, 70). And thereby is the Puritan saved from damnation, and all
those Italian virgins in the frames remain safe, and buying art is no sin,
but an intimation of a higher, purer, truer, and more perfect life. Tac-
tility being imagined, sensations being ideated, remain safe, disinter¬
ested, as the old idealism is saved despite all the talk of joy, tactility,
and sensations. The church of art is saved from the bazaar.
In Henry James’s The American the Reverend Babcock finally parts
with Newman because although they both love pictures, Newman en¬
joys them and Europe too much like an “unregenerate epicure.” Before
separating, Babcock sermonizes Newman: “Art and life seem to me in¬
tensely serious things, and in our travels in Europe we should espe¬
cially remember the immense seriousness of Art. You seem to hold
that if a thing amuses you for a moment, that is all you need ask of it;
and your relish for mere amusement is also much higher than mine.
You put, moreover, a kind of reckless confidence into your pleasure
which at times, I confess, has seemed to me—shall I say it?—almost
cynical” (A, 72). In Berenson’s aesthetic the almost cynical is made safe
by spiritualizing the sensations, defining the amusement as disin¬
terested life-enhancement. At the same time the reintroduction into
the aesthetic argument of the notion of disinterestedness, borrowed
from Kant and a safe Pietistic background (as distinct from the same
notion to be found in the abbe Du Bos, which is that of the man of the
world judging a work of art without the jealousy and “interest” of art¬
ists and professionals), also removes the supreme bibelot, the work of
art, from the dangerous place of desire, the market.
The work of art thereby once more finds its specific place in the
realm of the ideal, so dear to fin de siecle aesthetes and the wives of
148
millionaires who knew that money wasn’t everything. “For ideated sen¬
sations,” Berenson continued, “that constitute the work of art belong
to a realm apart, a realm beyond actuality, a realm of contemplation, of
‘emotion remembered in tranquility,’ a realm where nothing can hap¬
pen except to the soul of the spectator, and nothing that is not temper¬
ing and refining” (AH, 70). But ideated sensations and tactile values will
give you much more than a glimpse of the ideal; they lead to that rare
moment, the secularized religious experience that frees you of desire
and the world, the aesthetic experience:
You, too, can know through art the ecstasy of Saint Theresa. But of
course what the visionary sees or unites with in the contemplation of
a work of art is not God but something less theological, something
much more vague, “the inner life of things,” to use a phrase of T. E.
Hulme’s. The artist, for Berenson as well as for his contemporary Berg¬
son, was less of an inventor than a seer. “Artistic personalities are
equivalent to distinct modes of seeing, and are something in the na¬
ture of a sport,” writes Berenson in one of the few places of Aesthetics
and History in which he considers the artist (AH, 222). This sport can
149
be in the nature of genius: what the artist sees, he places before the
public, and he is followed in turn by other artists who adopt his vision
and propagate the vision of the genius by their skill: “Something new,
something never seen before was placed before the eye of a public as¬
tonished and fascinated by Leonardo. His vision of things was popu¬
larized by scores of pupils” (AH, 223). And, most marvelous of all,
Leonardo created unconsciously, because artists are not really thinkers
but craftsmen: “The real artist, if at the moment of creation he thinks at
all, thinks of little but his craft, the action and arrangement chiefly, and
of the skill and mastery he has acquired previously—I mean how to
draw, how to paint, what proportions, what types to give his figures”
(AH, 103). It is a remarkable attitude for a man who is sometimes taken
for the last humanist, a great Renaissance connoisseur, and represen¬
tative of hellenism. For in this view art is deintellectualized and the
idealism of Berenson and the fin de siecle avers itself to be very differ¬
ent from that of the academic tradition, for, to use Reynold’s terms,
painting was a mental activity and no mere mechanical skill. The ideal¬
ism of the fin de siecle was not to understand art as something about
beauty, the ineffable, the mystic vision that art supposedly prompted.
The aesthetic experience is something the mind cannot grasp. This
view was widely held at the time and it is worthwhile exploring why.
This mystical approach may be attributed to Bergson, as it was by his
arch enemy Julien Benda who engaged in a long polemic with him
and the times; in addition, it was also attributed to Berenson by his
disciple T. E. Hulme.
tion is written with a small ‘a’, not a large one.”8 If this is art then it is
less activity than contemplation. Art is confused with the aesthetic, the
aesthetic moment with mysticism, and creation is a kind of vision. The
work, as object, as superbibelot, has somehow disappeared. It is as if
intelligence were excluded from creativity, as if Leonardo had never
filled all those notebooks of his with speculations about the nature of
his art, as if innumerable poets had not reflected upon their art and
written poetics, as if painters had never written academic discourses,
as if works did not exist save in that ideal realm of contemplation; fi¬
nally, it is as if history had been eliminated. The reason for this radical
spiritualization of art and its experience lies in Bergson’s strict separa¬
tion of intellect (the mechanical) and life (the intuitive). But then for
Bergson, according to Hulme, the artist is not an inventor in the classic
Renaissance or even baroque sense but someone who dives into the
flux of life and comes out of it with a shape or form he attempts to fix
forever as a work of art: “He cannot be said to have created it, but to
have discovered it, because when he has definitely expressed it we
recognize it as true” (152).
Thus art reveals reality, as it did for the neo-Platonic mannerists,
though their respective realities may differ. The artist, in contact with
reality—not the world of Platonic forms or ideas but the flux of life—
makes others see what he has seen and as such remains, though not
an inventor, an exceptional being: “It is only by accident, and in one
sense only, that nature produces someone whose perception is not
riveted to practical purposes; hence the diversity of the arts. One ap¬
plies himself to form, not as it is practically useful in relation to him,
but as it is in itself, as it reveals the inner life of things” (152). This is at
once a romantic and bourgeois view of the artist; he is born that way,
he is privileged, he is the romantic genius; but he is impractical, he is
8. T. E. Hulme, Speculations. Essays on Humanism and the Philosophy of Art, 2d ed. (Lon¬
don: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965), 149.
151
based on art that promoted life lived as art, stressing not the spirit of
art but its sensuous qualities. Evangelical purism was supplanted by
aesthetic fastidiousness and the result was aesthetic criticism, as dis¬
tinct from historical or intellectual criticism. Pater aestheticized his¬
tory, making of the past a vast romantic affair that resulted in a craving
for the picturesque. The art work was thus transformed from a his¬
torical monument or sign into a vehicle of enjoyment for either the
aesthete’s refined pleasure or for the crowd of tourists. The grand tour¬
ist of the eighteenth century was not the direct ancestor of Cook’s tour
or Baedeker’s guide. The grand tourist of the fin de siecle and the late
bourgeois world went to Italy for sensations and acquisition more
than for education or accomplishment. The work of art, that supreme
bibelot of the sleeping-car set, was ultimately but a very select and rare
consumer item, an article de nouveaute from a romantic past rather
than a modern department store. History had been eliminated by an
aesthetic based on the latest science, psychology.
9. Vernon Lee, Art and Life (East Aurora, N.Y.: Roycroft Print Shop, 1896); The Beautiful, an
Introduction to Psychological Aesthetics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1913).
156
10. Julien Benda, Belphegor. Essai sur lesthetique de la presente societe franqaise (Paris:
Emile Paul, 1918), 40-41.
158
11. Frances Spalding, Roger Fry; Art and Life (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1980), 68.
160
The distinction between the higher and the merely pleasurable arts
implied distinct classes of people. It is tempting to make taste, in this
scheme, correspond with an upper class and mere pleasure with the
lower classes; but, in fact, it did not work out that way. In Vernon Lee’s
terms the distinction was not so much one of class or income as one
between a true aesthetic elite and the philistines. One might be of the
elite and yet not be rich in the ordinary sense of the word. “Our real
aesthetic life,” she writes, “is in ourselves, often isolated from the beau¬
tiful words, objects, or sounds” (AL, 53-55). And this aesthetic life pre¬
sumably has nothing to do with the possession of beautiful objects.
The true aesthete is thus isolated from the merely rich by separating
the aesthetic realm from the notion of property, from the possession of
bibelots. Aesthetic experience is defined as good, unselfish, altruistic.
For the center of the experience, that mystic moment of union, is not
in the object, which can be possessed, but in the emotion: “All strong
aesthetic feeling will always prefer ownership of the mental image to
ownership of the tangible object; any desire for material appropriation
or exclusive enjoyment will merely be so much weakening and adul¬
teration of the aesthetic sentiment. In every person who truly cares for
beauty, there is a necessary tendency to replace the legal illusory act
of owning by the real spiritual act of appreciation’’ (AL, 53-55).
The bourgeois concept of private property is thus separate from the
aesthetic domain. The rich with their bibelots need not feel they have
deprived anyone of aesthetic enjoyment, which is not guaranteed by
ownership. And they do a positive good by endowing museums, build¬
ing collections, and supporting the acquisition of objets d art. At the
same time this separation of the object possessed from the aesthetic
experience, which is internal and emotional, makes possible the crea¬
tion of an infinite number of art history courses built on slides that
“represent” the object not present in the classroom, courses that may
prepare the student for the aesthetic experience. A vague, ideal realm
of aesthetic experience is posed as open to all with the proper pre-
161
paratory askesis. The aesthetic realm is the old paradise, though there
was, in the novel conditions of the late bourgeois world, no one to
write that it was more difficult for a rich man to enter this paradise
than for a camel to go through the eye of a needle. But the separation
of true aesthetic appreciation from ownership of the object that
prompts it consoles nonowners. They are not aesthetically deprived.
They may look at but not touch the works of art. They need not envy
the owner of a Botticelli to truly appreciate his work as, in the crowded
Uffizi, before the Birth of Venus, "the tactile imagination is roused to a
keen activity, by itself almost as life-heightening as music. But the
power of music is even surpassed where, as in the goddess’s mane-like
tresses of hair fluttering to the wind, not in disorderly rout but in
masses yielding only after resistance, the moment is directly life¬
communicating. The entire picture [B.B. continued] presents us with
the quintessence of all that is pleasurable to our imagination of touch
and movement. How we revel in the force and freshness of the wind, in
the life of the wave.”12
12. See Ernest Samuels, Bernard Berenson. The Making of a Connoisseur (Cambridge,
Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 1979), 231.
162
manist with his exquisite hands and his astounding eye; may have felt
superior to the American millionaire who bought a Bernardo Luini
without batting an eye because it was supposed to make him appear
cultured (if you have to ask the price, you can’t afford it, noted J. P.
Morgan); and the aesthete might look on such as mere philistinism
and mutter to himself that, after all, the newly rich are always vulgar.
But these were the consolations of those who had to ask the price. In
the long run, the presence of the picture bought, the objet d art ac¬
quired, and the bibelots seen in the salon and the drawing room lent
their owners part of their aura; indeed, the aura of the work was trans¬
ferred to its owner. And in time, with gifts to museums, parties and
dinners in black tie and tails given for curators and directors and even
scholars, the possessors ceased to be merely “proud possessors” and
became spiritual, cultured, genteel, and ever so generous. The trans¬
formation of the merely nouveaux riches into the cultural elite follows
logically, though not explicitly, from the doctrine of life-enhancement.
How could the rich remain vulgar once they had glimpsed, thanks to
the effect of tactile values and ideated sensations, the realm of the
ideal? How could you still be vulgar after a mystical experience? They,
too, learned to savor, appreciate, enjoy that higher realm which awaited
them after a long day at the office, the firm, Wall Street, and the cares of
business. The art works possessed were, aesthetic theory notwith¬
standing, the concrete form of the ideal: a collection, a chateau, a villa,
a house on Fifth Avenue. Askesis was for the less wealthy. With enough
wealth you could always buy enough indulgences to be exempted
from askesis. In the end the aesthetics of cosmopolis was Januslike:
exclusive for the poor, open to the rich. And the rich knew it. That is
why in questions of authenticity they relied on experts and not on the
aesthetic experience.
B.B. was not a philosopher; neither was he an art historian, and for
all his talk of culture, his humanist pose, he was first and last a con-
163
_ 4
13. Paul Bourget, La Dame qui a perdu son peintre (Paris: Plon-Nourrit, 1910), 36-37.
165
14. Count Umberto Morra, Conversations with Berenson (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1965),
254-255.
166
the Renaissance was still held: it localized the source of true aesthetic
value and experience, it explained the sensuality of tactile values as
reconciled with the spirituality of aestheticism, as Giotto and Dante,
Botticelli and Ficino, may define the sensuous and tactile joined to the
mystical. But I Tatti defined a fin de siecle view of the Renaissance,
closer in spirit to Pater and Burckhardt; and if the Medicis are remem¬
bered it is not as bankers and astute politicians, using art in a pro¬
pagandist^ way, but as aesthetes, patrons, presumably disinterested,
of the arts. Life in the Renaissance had been “artistic,” picturesque as
in the poems of Browning. But Florence was safe too for the taste of the
times; ik^yas prebaroque; it was not a city associated with the art of a
corrupted, sensuous, theatrical Roman Catholicism, so that even the
location of I Tatti near Florence exemplifies the Jarves-Norton view of
art history.
On a less sublime level, however, disregarding the gentlemanly pose,
the chitchat at the table, the image of the last humanist, Berenson
eventually turned into a Medici in reverse. For whereas they trans¬
muted gold into the works and riches of art, he transformed the riches
of art into an income, though one exquisitely veiled by the fin de siecle
humanitas in the form of love of art, a fine library, some choice pic¬
tures, and conversation in which money was never mentioned. The
culture of I Tatti was that of the rich at a particular historical moment,
that in which culture still played the role of distinction, and it was sold
with the art work. I Tatti, the grand hotels and the rich beaches, were
but the setting of a discreet art business. As the high courtesans of
the second empire had had their setting in the luxury of the theater
and opera, the Bois or the Champs Elysees, the villa outside Florence
was the setting of the great expert, a kind of grande cocotte of the art
world.
Commerce, aesthetics, and astheticism, expertise and trade were all
inextricably confused in the figure of B.B. who had worshipped at the
feet of Walter Pater; posed as an aesthete devoted to art and beauty,
168
169
170
bibelots, they are still very much with us, marketed not only in a vari¬
ety of department stores or gift shops but also, thanks to glossy pho¬
tography, unsolicited mail order catalogues sent out by firms that
sometimes call themselves collections. But despite this mass market¬
ing, the aura of art survives: thousands still line up for hours for a
Cezanne, Picasso, or King Tut exhibition. For all those in the lines, art
and the art work is still something special, unique, a once-in-a lifetime
event, and that aesthetic experience, despite the discomfort of lines
and tired feet, is a must. Indeed, may one not say that after all the work
of the experts of the period of B.B., exhibitions are more of a must than
ever before, because one may now be sure that the works are, at last,
identified and absolutely authentic? That they are, at last, as Henry
James might say, “the real thing”?
Consider then the storm in the teacup of the art world when a few
years ago an eminent collector of modern art (modern art has finally
been accepted as nearly equal in status, in some circles at least, to cin-
quecento madonnas), a former governor of an imperial state, allowed
the reproduction of ninety-six selected pieces from his collection—-in
a limited edition, of course. At about the same time a famous former
director of an equally famous museum endorsed, in writing, an expen¬
sive reproduction of an Andrew Wyeth painting. A famous art critic,
the very model of an art establishment figure, rose to the defense of art
and wrote of “hype,” “shamelessness,” and “selling of haute schloch.”
The eminent critic’s literary shock seemed to betray a curious lack
of historical understanding of what the German social literary critic
Theodore Adorno referred to as the "aporetic” nature of art. Indeed,
why be surprised or indignant at the marketing of reproductions
when art works, old or new, great, good, bad, indifferent—or even
kitsch—are also marketed even by art critics? Why write of “haute
schloch” in an age that includes antiart in museums of fine art? The
bourgeois connoisseur, as we have seen, has always loved, desired, and
accumulated art, not to mention match boxes, bottle caps, stamps, glass
171
bottles, locks, keys, dolls, toys, etcetera, etcetera, etcetera. And since
modern, efficient, sophisticated marketing techniques may be used to
sell even a president to a people, there is no reason not to sell art, as
well as reproductions and bibelots, in the same way The not-too-well-
off bourgeois who has taken an art course in the wrong college and
has been motivated by all those glossy slides, the less rich petit bour¬
geois, the blue-collar worker aspiring to class, the half-educated col¬
lege student, the Ivy League, Harris tweed proletariat may, thanks to
reproductions, live in an art environment made up at least in part by
endorsed reproductions. After all, ours is an age of plastic flowers.
But what would the marketing of these endorsed and prestige, or
shall we say “elite," reproductions do to the status of the original work
of art? Would they pose a new threat to the aura of the authentic art
work? Would the long work of art education be lost among the public
rushing to buy endorsed reproductions? Would people cease to un¬
derstand the distinction between the unique and the series? Were
graduates from the business school threatening graduates in art his¬
tory? Walter Benjamin had only explored the loss of aura within a spe¬
cific historical context, that of his childhood, in which original works
were posed on easels in the salon, curtains drawn tightly, green plants
watered by maids, and places set with at least three different glasses.
But Benjamin’s Marxist eschatology had blinded him to the marvels of
post-business school capitalism. He had not foreseen that aura, far
from being lost, would be regained—and marketed. The shocked
critic of Fun City had failed to understand the true significance of the
endorsed collection of reproductions. The marketing of art and se¬
lected endorsed reproductions can of course be denounced on the
plane of idealism, as Quatremere de Quincy did the art world of his
day; or it can be dismissed, gleefully, as an inevitable aspect of corrupt
bourgeois culture. But both positions are founded on the failure to see
that the aesthetic experience has shifted from the contemplation of
the work of art to its acquisition. Modern techniques of reproduction
172
B-I B L I O G R A P H Y
175
176
Selected Bibliography
Selected Bibliography
Selected Bibliography
Selected Bibliography
'
• : ■ ■
I • N • D • E • X
181
182
Index
Indent
Indey
l
Cousin, Victor, 8, 92; idealism and, and, 40-41, 49; leisure and shop¬
89,101 ping and, 39-40; the new woman
Couturier, 58-59 and, 36-37; parallel between mu¬
Crawford, Francis Marion, 137 seum and, 41-44, 47-49; Zola on,
Culture: acquiring (in Europe), 34-35, 36, 37-38, 39
109-114; American concern with, de Piles, Roger, 27
77; Berenson and, 137, 138-141; Display (department store), 38-39
Bourget and, 141; difference be¬ Dreiser, Theodore, 35-36, 37, 81-83
tween American and European, Du Barry, Madame, 54, 55
106; difference between North and Du Bos, Jean Baptiste, 26
South and, 5; James and, 78, 79; Duffus, R. L., 99
men and, 111; Norton on, 99; San¬ Dumas, Alexandre (fils), 53-57
tayana and, 139; Wharton and, 139 Dvorak, Max, 144
Custom of the Country (Wharton),
105; meaning of bibelots and, Education, 90; in the arts, 7-8, 98;
112-114 department stores and art, 45-47,
49; department stores and women
La Dame auy Camelias (Dumas), and, 34-35, 37; French, 6
53-57 Education sentimentale (Flaubert), 28
Daumier, Honore, 22 Elevators, 34
Death in Venice (Mann), 130 Elias, Norbert, 87
Deau menages (Bourget), 110 Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 90-91
The Decoration of Houses (Wharton), Essays on the Nature and Principles
71-72 of Taste (Alison), 90
Degas, H. G. Edgar, 146 Esther (Adams), 101-102,103
Degeneration, 63, 67, 69 Europe: American leisure in,
Degeneration (Nordau), 93 122-123; Americans collecting in,
Delacroix, Ferdinand, 10, 12 109-114; Americans living in,
Democratization of society, 126,139, 104-109
159; reproductions and, 173-174 Europeans, as collectors, 77
Department stores, 11,19, 70, 74; ar¬ L’Evolution du Gout auy Etats Unis
chitecture of, 34, 38, 44-45; art d’apres les collections (Brimo), 83
education and, 45-47, 49; creation
of, 33-34; displays and advertise¬ False Dawn (Wharton), 93
ments and, 38-39; Dreiser’s Sister Fashion: art joined with, 63;
Carrie and, 35-36, 37; extravagant bibelotization of, 72; as rival to art,
taste and, 62; interior decorating 27; women as bibelots and, 62
185
Index
Index
Italy: art and, 119-120; cities in, 124-125; shopping and depart¬
127-130; Jarves and, 95-96; ment stores and, 39-40
as marketplace, 130-131; Norton Leonardo, 149, 150
and, 99 Lesueur, Daniel, 9
I Tatti (Berenson villa), 166-168 Letters of credit, 121
Letters of introduction, 121
Lewis, R. W. B., 41
James, Henry, 81,100,101,103,105,
Life-enhancement, Berenson and,
107, 109, 120, 144, 170, 174, art and,
146-147,154
147; collection of bibelots and, 69;
Lighting (department store), 34
culture and, 78, 79; financial suc¬
Literature: art in U.S. and, 90-91;
cess and women and, 61; meaning
Berenson and, 138; cities and, 22;
of bibelots and, 112; Metropolitan
collecting in, 103; women and, 67.
Museum and, 114-115,121; as ob¬
See also names of specific authors
server of objects, 70
and specific literary works
Janin, Jules, 23-24
Luxury, 53, 54, 57, 126; women as
Jarves, James Jackson, 142; art and,
item of, 58-59, 62
93-94, 95-96, 97-98, 99; idealism
of, 48
Mademoiselle de Maupin (Gautier),
Johnson, Samuel, 21, 23, 152
9, 89
Journalism, 22
Maison dun artiste (Goncourt broth¬
Joy, Berenson and, 145,146, 147
ers), 70
Manet, Edouard, 10
Kant, Immanuel, 156 Mann, Thomas, 130
Kogan, Herman, 44n
Mansions. See Houses
Konig, Rene, 40, 63 The Marble Faun (Hawthorne), 91
Marriage, 61
The Lady Who Lost Her Painter (Se- Marshall Field, 36, 43-44
crest), 164 Martin-Fugier, Anne, 67
The Last Puritan (Santayana), 65-66 Materialism, 8, 47; as enemy of
Lectures on Rhetoric and Belles art, 11
Lettres (Blair), 90 Maupassant, Guy de, 90
Ledoux, Louis, 45 Meilhan, Senac de, 86
Lee, Vernon: Berenson and, 155-158, Men: art as adornment and, 80,
160; Ruskin and, 93 81-83; as collectors vs. women as
Leisure: forms of American (in Eu¬ consumers of objects, 68; conspic¬
rope), 122-123; for high livers, uous consumption of women and,
187
Index
40; as department store flaneur, 41; New eye (city observation), 21,22
leisure and, 123; the "new” woman Newspapers, 22
and, 37; real world and, 67; with New York City, 99
no interest in art, 79-81; women Nobility, 74; old and new, 106-107;
and financial success and, 55-58, spending and, 86-88
60-61 Nordau, Max, 63, 67, 69, 93, 102
Mengs, Anton Raphael, 91 Norris, Frank, 62
Mercier, Sebastien, 21 Norton, Charles Eliot, 104, 122, 137,
Metropolitan Museum of Art, 143; art and, 97-101; Jarves and,
114-115,121. See also Museums 94, 95
Miller, Michael, 33
Mistresses, 54-57, 60 Ohnet, Georges, 90
Modernity: art and, 48-49; idealist Oswald, Lord, 3, 5, 16
art and, 15; Quatremere de Quincy Ownership, 160-161
and, 96
Monet, Claude, 151 Paget, Violet. See Lee, Vernon
Money: class distinctions and, 174; Painters: Berenson and, 143,
fortunes of high society and, 148-149,150-152; collection in
126-127; playboys and, 124; un¬ Corinne and, 4; Cowperwood (The
earned income and, 121-122 Titan) and, 85-86; department
Monnier, Henri, 22 stores and, 46; Florence and,
Moore, George, 137 128-129; high society and, 125;
Morgan, J. P., 86, 162 Ruskin and, 95; in Vanderbilt col¬
Mornings in Florence (Ruskin), 129 lection, 84
Morra, Count, 141,165 Paintings: Berenson and Titian,
Mumford, Lewis, 29 165-166; in Corinne, 4, 5, 16; de¬
Museums, 172; bourgeois interiors partment stores and, 45-46; emo¬
resembling, 65; James and, tional responses to, 105-106; in
114-115,121; modern city and, 19; Newport villas, 112
parallel between department Panoramas, 20, 22
stores and, 41-44, 47-49; patrons Paris, 121; aesthetic space in, 19-20;
of art and, 11-12; wealthy houses city observation and, 21-30; mod¬
as, 85 ernity and, 96-97; Norton on, 99;
passages in, 20
Nation, 78, 99 Parrish, Maxwell, 129
Necker, Jacques, 4 Pascal, Blaise, 26
Needham, H.A., lOn Passages, 19,119; analysis of, 20-21;
188
Index
Index
bourgeoisbibelotOOsais
bourgeoisbibelotOOsais
II
bourgeoisbibelotOOsais
COPLEY SQUARE
GENERAL LIBRARY