Human Dignity and The Future of - Mark P. Lagon
Human Dignity and The Future of - Mark P. Lagon
GLOBAL INSTITUTIONS
HUMAN DIGNITY AND THE
FUTURE OF GLOBAL
INSTITUTIONS
15 14 13 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 First printing
Preface
JOHN J. DEGIOIA
Contributors
Index
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
References
Bellah, Robert N., Richard Madsen, William M. Sullivan, Ann Swidler,
and Steven M. Tipton. 1992. The Good Society. New York:
Vintage.
Glendon, Mary Ann. 2001. A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt
and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. New York:
Random House.
Rummel, R. J. 1994. “Important Note.” In Death by Government.
New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Accessed February
20, 2013. http://www.hawaii.edu/powerkills/NOTE1.HTM.
Introduction
Human Dignity in a Neomedieval
World
MARK P. LAGON AND ANTHONY CLARK AREND
The Ancients
Among the ancient philosophers, self-worth is a crucial notion. Plato
observed in The Republic that a person only lived well when the
three parts of his soul were properly in balance—the rational,
appetitive, and spirited. Spiritedness, or thymos, is associated with
feeling valuable, not just insularly but relationally—valuable in the
eyes of others in society (Bloom 1991). We will return to the
importance of this element of dignity.
In addition to self-worth, “potential” plays a key role in the
thinking of the Ancients. Aristotle believed the ultimate goal that is
unique to human beings is the realization of human potential in the
form of what he called eudaimonia—human flourishing.
Foreshadowing a modern notion of responsibility necessarily
accompanying freedom, this value is not a state of mind or thinking
but is developed and exercised in ongoing activity. It involves
developing character traits that fuse reason to virtue (Bartlett and
Collins 2012). This lofty conception of human potentiality is to be
distinguished from that of Epicurus, who associated achievement of
eudaimonia with maximizing hedonistic pleasures.
Judeo-Christian Thinking
The dignity and worth of humankind is a primary focus of the Judeo-
Christian faith traditions. In these traditions, every human is made in
the image of God. Genesis 1:26 holds, “And God said, Let us make
man in our image.” This opening text from the Hebrew scriptures
goes on to say human beings were given dominion over all other
creatures and resources—fish, fowl, cattle, and the Earth. Genesis
2:19–20 suggests, no less, that the Creator brought all beasts and
fowl “unto Adam to see what he would call them” and he named
them. An animal rights or environmental activist today might resist
these notions at a literal level, but the implication that human beings
all have a special status and role is central. George Kateb’s quite
secular 2011 study, Human Dignity, adopts this “breed apart”
formulation about human beings, based on their level of
consciousness. Moreover, beyond naming other creatures, that each
human has a distinct name implies value in each. This idea echoes
Aristotle’s view of the unique function and value of human beings.
The innate value of human life is, of course, embodied in one of
the great Ten Commandments given to Moses: Thou shall not kill. Or
to provide a more literal translation of the Hebrew: You shall not
murder. In the Torah, this commandment is established as a law: No
human being has the standing to kill unjustifiably.
Within the Jewish tradition, human dignity is also affirmed in the
injunctions to provide special care for those possessing special
needs: the poor, the widow, the orphan, and the stranger (e.g.,
Deut. 26:12; Zech. 7:10, Jer 7:6). Isaiah, for example, issues a
strong condemnation to those who do not tend to the
disenfranchised:
the King will say to those at his right hand, “Come, O blessed of
my Father,
inherit the kingdom prepared for you from the foundation of
the world;
for I was hungry and you gave me food, I was thirsty and you
gave me
drink, I was a stranger and you welcomed me,
I was naked and you clothed me, I was sick and you visited me, I
was in
prison and you came to me” (Matt. 25:34–36).
Kantian Idealism
A slightly different tradition, that of modern German idealism, also
places special emphasis on human worth. Immanuel Kant justifies
the claim that humans have intrinsic dignity by pointing to the fact
that humans are agents: They must choose their own actions and
give themselves goals. Humans, therefore, are not just beings with
value but also the sort of beings that create or construct value to
begin with. It is their capacity to give things value that implies they
are, more precisely, “above all value.” Kant’s admonition to never
treat another human being as a mere means is based on the equal
value of all human beings. Kant argues that humans only act freely
(and actually live a life of dignity) when they act on a law that
requires that they give of themselves. The law that persons must
give of themselves to be free must take a form such that it applies
to everyone, no matter who the person is or what the person
desires. This categorical imperative of acting as if an action could be
generalized into a universal principle implies that other people and
their worth must be treated with consistency rather than
capriciously. No one can make an exception of themselves, including
autocrats.
Capabilities-Based Development
Contemporary thinkers about human development have picked up
on the ancients’ concept of tapped potential and thriving and echoed
the New Haven School’s focus on catalyzing people’s ability to freely
pursue values of choice. As the United Nations Development
Programme (UNDP) administrator Helen Clark of New Zealand
observed on March 9, 2010:
Sen helped fashion the Human Development Index for UNDP’s first
Human Development Report in 1990 with the late economist
Mahbub ul Haq, the series founder. He and American scholar Martha
Nussbaum have elaborated on an approach to development based
on enabling the capabilities of individual human beings. Nussbaum
identifies ten crucial capabilities: life, bodily health, bodily integrity,
senses (imagination, thought), emotions, practical reason, affiliation
(community, association, social basis of self-respect), other species,
play, and control over one’s environment (political participation,
personal property). In Women and Human Development, she argues
that each of these capabilities is needed in order for a human life to
be “not so impoverished that it is not worthy of the dignity of a
human being” (Nussbaum 2001, 72).
This book has two purposes. First, it will seek to examine the degree
to which several prominent traditional and emerging institutions are
already advancing human dignity as a central mission. For example,
Tod Lindberg’s chapter 2 on the International Criminal Court (ICC), a
traditional institution, explores the role of the ICC in providing
restitution to atrocity victims and thus affirming their dignity. Rosalía
Rodriguez-García’s chapter 8 examines a hybrid institution, the
Global Fund to Fight AIDS, Tuberculosis, and Malaria, and discusses
how it advances dignity by helping HIV-positive populations
transcend social stigma.
Second, in the spirit of developing best practices and prescriptive
recommendations, the book examines how to make human dignity a
greater focus of international institutions’ work. It seeks to identify
the strategies, methods, and modalities to make them all the more,
as it were, agencies for agency.
These aims entail several challenges. One challenge is to develop
a method to build on the achievements of the human rights tradition
while detaching a dignitarian agenda from stale and stalled debates,
such as those between political-civil rights and socioeconomic rights.
One must take care that breaking through stalled debates and
stalled implementation is not a rupture. The answer lies in viewing
human dignity not as a newer successor concept to human rights
but as an older foundational concept upon which the rights tradition
was erected. In order that norm-creation more often becomes norm-
implementation, we propose this “back to basics” approach.
Another challenge is to take full advantage of the great potential
for consensus across countries, regions, cultures, and faiths human
dignity offers. McDougal and Lasswell saw that potential fully six
decades ago. How can it be realized in practice?
There are clearly numerous paths to establishing human dignity’s
centrality. Drawing inspiration from the historic 1945 San Francisco
Conference on International Organization where the UN Charter was
adopted, some might suggest that it is time for a new “San
Francisco moment.” Yet, in a neomedieval world or what one might
call a state of “mosaic multilateralism,” there could not be an actual
new San Francisco Conference to redirect institutions or create new
ones. A conference or summit would not be a feasible vehicle to
realize consensus in a neomedieval context precisely because of the
multiplicity and dissimilarity of the actors. Moreover, the process of
establishing the centrality of human dignity cannot be reduced to a
“moment.” Instead, it should be an ongoing dialogue. The dialogue
this book offers is meant to hasten the social construction of
consensus (Wendt 1992).
A final challenge remains: Once consensus is built, who will
organize the mosaic multilateralism of today to privilege dignity
above other goals? Needless to say, there will be numerous actors
who will play an organizing role. But, we believe the United States
ought not to be coy. While it does not have the hegemonic power it
enjoyed seventy or even twenty years ago, it has a special role to
play as catalyst. Like no other longstanding or rising power, the
United States will remain a leading player to most of the institutions
and partnerships in question. Its role will not be hegemonic norm-
setter and guarantor. Nor will it solely be that of convener in formal
organizations. Not least because of the way in which ideals are
intermingled with interests in US statecraft, the United States has a
special role to play in making a consensus on dignity an
implemented reality. To succeed, the US approach must not be “our
way or the highway,” but it can fruitfully enable this agenda in
varying roles as thought-leader, coach, quasi-pastor, co-opter, hub of
networks, and partner to other actors. Without the United States, it
is less likely to become implemented in reality.
Notes
1. Melinda Gates: “For far too many women with HIV: they take
the blame for this disease, even when they’re blameless. We can’t
cure these women, but we can help them live with dignity.” The
World Economic Forum, Davos, January 25, 2007.
Jack Welch: “Dignity is not only ‘the right thing to do’ from a
moral perspective, it invariably makes companies more competitive.”
With Suzy Welch, “The Difference Dignity Makes,” Business Week,
June 2009.
Aung San Suu Kyi: “A most insidious form of fear is that which
masquerades as common sense or even wisdom, condemning as
foolish, reckless, insignificant or futile the small, daily acts of
courage which help to preserve man’s self-respect and inherent
human dignity.” Accepting the Sakharov Prize for Freedom of
Thought, July 10, 1991.
Former Archbishop of Canterbury Rowan Williams: “Shared
dignity is the condition for what you could call ‘civic warmth’—the
sense of being able to trust not only immediate neighbours but the
wider social fabric. If government is visibly working for dignity in
citizenship, trust will follow.” Sermon for the New Parliament,
Westminster Abbey, June 8, 2010.
The Dalai Lama: “Buddhism too recognises that human beings
are entitled to dignity, that all members of the human family have an
equal and inalienable right to liberty, not just in terms of political
freedom, but also at the fundamental level of freedom from fear and
want.” Buddhism and Democracy, Washington DC, April 1993.
George W. Bush: “No nation owns these aspirations, and no
nation is exempt from them. We have no intention of imposing our
culture, but America will always stand firm for the non-negotiable
demands of human dignity.” State of the Union Address, January 29,
2002.
President Barack Obama, accepting the Nobel Peace Prize: “Only
a just peace based upon the inherent rights and dignity of every
individual can truly be lasting.” Oslo, Norway, December 10, 2009.
References
Aga Khan IV. 2006. “Cosmopolitan Society, Human Safety and Rights
in Plural and Peaceful Societies.” Remarks by His Highness the
Aga Khan IV at Evory University Symposium. February 12. Evora,
Portugal.
Arend, Anthony Clark. 1999. Legal Rules and International Society.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Arend, Anthony Clark, and Robert J. Beck. 1993. International Law
and the Use of Force: Beyond the United Nations Charter
Paradigm. London: Routledge Press.
Bartlett, Robert C., and Susan D. Collins, trans. 2012. Aristotle’s
Nicomachean Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Bloom, Allan David, trans. 1991. The Republic of Plato. New York:
Basic Books.
Bull, Hedley. 2002. The Anarchical Society. New York: Columbia
University Press. First Published 1977.
Fukuyama, Francis. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. New
York: Free Press.
Glendon, Mary Ann. 2001. A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt
and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. New York:
Random House.
Grotius, Hugo. 1925. “Prologomena” of De Jure Belli Ac Pacis. In
Robert J. Beck, Anthony Clark Arend, and Robert D. Vander Lugt.
1996. International Rules: Approaches from International Law
and International Relations. New York: Oxford University Press.
Haugen, Gary, and Victor Boutros. 2010. “And Justice for All:
Enforcing Human Rights for the World’s Poor.” Foreign Affairs 89
(3): 51–62.
Kateb, George. 2011. Human Dignity. Cambridge, MA: Belknap
Press.
Khan, Irene. 2009. The Unheard Truth: Poverty and Human Rights.
New York: W. W. Norton and Company.
Lagon, Mark P. 1994. The Reagan Doctrine: Sources of American
Conduct in the Cold War’s Last Chapter. Westport, CT: Praeger.
Lo, Pilgrim W. K. 2009. “Human Dignity—A Theological and
Confucian Discussion.” Dialog: A Journal of Theology 48 (2):
168–78.
Mandela, Nelson. 1994. “Inaugural Address as President of South
Africa.”
McDougal, Myres S., and Harold D. Lasswell. 1959. “The
Identification and Appraisal of Diverse Systems of Public Order.”
American Journal of International Law 53 (1): 1-29.
Nussbaum, Martha. 2001. Women and Human Development.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Pope John Paul II. 1993. “Encyclical Letter: Veritatis splendor.”
Origins 23 (18): 298-334.
Reisman, W. Michael, Siegfried Wiessner, and Andrew R. Willard.
2007. “The New Haven School: A Brief Introduction.” Yale Journal
of International Law 32: 575–82.
Rosen, Michael. 2012. Dignity: Its History and Meaning. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Strange, Susan. 1996. The Retreat of the State: The Diffusion of
Power in the World Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Tipson, Frederick S. 1973. “The Lasswell-McDougal Enterprise:
Toward a World Public Order of Human Dignity.” Virginia Journal
of International Law 14: 535.
Wendt, Alexander. 1992. “Anarchy Is What States Make of It: The
Social Construction of Power Politics.” International Organization
46 (2): 391–425.
Yadollahpour, Behrouz. 2011. “Human Dignity and Its Consequences
in the Holy Qur’an.” International Proceedings of Economics
Development & Research 10: 551–55.
PART I
TRADITIONAL INSTITUTIONS
When one reflects upon institutions poised to promote human
dignity, the work of traditional institutions comes most readily to
mind. As the term is used in this book, “traditional institutions” refers
to intergovernmental institutions—international organizations that
states join in their official capacity. Part I of this book explores
several such institutions, including the United Nations Security
Council, the United Nations Secretary-General, the International
Criminal Court (ICC), regional organizations, and international
financial institutions.
Not surprisingly, one of the main roles these institutions play in
promoting human dignity is norm creation. In chapter 1, Nancy
Soderberg discusses the role of the Security Council in promoting
and developing the norm relating to the “responsibility to protect.”
Similarly, in chapter 3, Abiodun Williams explores how Secretary-
General Kofi Annan acted to advance both that norm and others in
service of human dignity. In a slightly different direction, Tod
Lindberg, in chapter 2, explores the unique role of the ICC in
developing what he calls the “responsibility to respect” the victims of
atrocities by providing them with restitution. Likewise, in chapter 6,
Mark P. Lagon and Ryan Kaminski examine a broad range of norms
developed by a variety of global institutions that form the “human
rights architecture.” And, finally, in chapter 7 Anthony Clark Arend
discusses the need for clearer norms relating to the treatment of
terrorism suspects.
But these chapters also explore another critical role of traditional
institutions: norm implementation. Not only is it necessary to
develop norms, human dignity demands that norms be made real in
practice. Lagon and Kaminski stress the gap between rights norms
and implementation. Soderberg, Williams, Lagon and Kaminski, and
Lindberg explore in detail the implementation of several norms
aimed at advancing dignity. Chester Crocker in chapter 4 pays
special attention to the role of regional organizations as norm
implementers in the area of conflict resolution. And in chapter 5,
Anoop Singh examines the vital role of international financial
institutions—including the International Monetary Fund—in
promoting strong domestic institutions needed to realize the
economic opportunity that is critical to human dignity.
CHAPTER 1
Recommendations
These very different instances of UNSC intervention to protect
human life and dignity demonstrate the difficulties of this challenge
in the twenty-first century. Political will is the biggest hurdle,
followed by the lack of regional capabilities. The P-5 play a key but
uneven role in the decision to intervene—and thus interventions will
be inconsistent and sporadic. From the discrepancy between legality
and legitimacy to the conflict between sovereignty and the need to
back up diplomatic efforts with a credible use of force, the
challenges for action will likely remain for some time. In a
neomedieval world, where an increasing number of actors are
playing a critical role, the protection of civilians will require a varied
and multifaceted approach that includes state actors, regional
organizations, nongovernmental organizations, and global bodies.
Going forward, there are no easy solutions or quick fixes. Each
avenue offers trade-offs between legality, legitimacy, sovereignty,
and effectiveness. The world may have adopted the principle of
Responsibility to Protect, but it is far from creating any kind of
standards for actually implementing it. Regrettably, that is likely to
remain the case so long as half of the world is not democratic and
wants to maintain its immunity from outside interference. And the
democratic half often is unwilling to assume the responsibility to
intervene.
The UNSC, which was founded to be the chief protector of global
peace and security, must do better. The international community can
take steps to increase the legitimacy of the UNSC actions, the
capacity of the operations it authorizes, and the use of instruments
to protect human dignity more boldly.
Conclusion
These recommendations are meant to provide a series of options to
further human dignity in the new century. As outlined above, the
global environment regarding human dignity is complex, but there is
great promise. Increasingly, the world is seeing individuals around
the globe standing up for their economic and political rights. At the
same time, international institutions are increasing their role in
international politics and thus have a growing responsibility in
protecting these rights. The UNSC is the most powerful organization
when it comes to matters of war and peace, and it must adapt to
the changing nature of global politics in the twenty-first century.
Over a dozen years into the twenty-first century, international
politics continues to develop at a dynamic and rapid pace.
Democratic developments have pushed forward—unevenly across
the Middle East but dramatically so with Aung San Suu Kyi being
elected to parliament in Burma and South Sudan obtaining
independence. These events offer tremendous opportunity for
progress—but also risk descending into chaos. Also, the long
festering conflicts in Somalia, Yemen, the Democratic Republic of the
Congo, and Kashmir as well as the civil war in Mali and the crisis in
Syria will demand greater attention. Surely, the instances of
violations of human dignity will continue to pose challenges for
decades to come.
Especially as awareness and capacity to act grow, calls to address
violations of human dignity will grow too. Whether the UNSC will be
up to the task will depend in large part on stronger US leadership in
the decades ahead. We must meet that challenge to be, as President
Obama has said, on the right side of history (Obama 2011).
Notes
1. In 1965, the UN Charter was amended to expand the UNSC
from eleven to fifteen members, adding four impermanent members.
Amending the Charter requires approval of two-thirds of the UN
General Assembly and ratification of domestic implementing
legislation by two-thirds of the member states, including all of the P-
5.
2. Some disagree with this assertion. Ian Hurd has an interesting
essay arguing that enlargement might not add to legitimacy. See Ian
Hurd, “Myths of Membership: The Politics of Legitimization in UN
Security Council Reform,” in Paul F. Diehl and Brian Frederking, The
Politics of Global Governance: International Organizations in an
Interdependent World, 4th ed. (Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner, 2010),
91–110.
3. See UNSC Resolution 2085, UN.org.
4. Current Critical Rule of Law and Other Civilian Capability Gaps
in United Nations Peacekeeping Operations, June 2, 2010, 1. Note
that the United States built barracks for the Congolese armed forces
battalion trained in the Democratic Republic of the Congo, African
Union: email exchange with DOD November 1, 2010.
References
Annan, Kofi. 1999. “In Statement to North Atlantic Treaty
Organization.” Brussels, Belgium. January 28.
Bellamy, Alex J., and Paul D. Williams. 2011. “Côte d’Ivoire, Libya
and the Responsibility to Protect.” International Affairs 87: 825–
50.
Coughlan, Geraldine. 2011. “Interview with U.S. Ambassador-at-
large for War Crimes Issues, Stephen Rapp.” Radio Netherlands
Worldwide. January 7.
Council on Foreign Relations. 2011. “Public Opinion on Global Issues,
Chapter 8: World Opinion on Human Rights.” Accessed April 18,
2014. http://www.cfr.org/thinktank/iigg/pop/index.html.
———. 2012. “The International Criminal Court: A New Approach to
International Relations.” Accessed September 21, 2012.
http://www.cfr.org/courts-and-tribunals/international-criminal-
court-new-approach-international-relations/p29351.
Holt, Victoria, and Glyn Taylor. 2009. “Protecting Civilians in the
Context of United Nations Peacekeeping Operations: Successes,
Setbacks, and Remaining Challenges.” New York: United Nations.
Human Rights Watch. 2012. “UN Security Council: Address
Inconsistency in ICC Referrals.” Accessed January 6, 2013.
http://www.hrw.org/news/2012/10/16/un-security-council-
address-inconsistency-icc-referrals-0.
International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty
(ICISS). 2001. “Responsibility to Protect.” Ottawa: International
Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty.
Khan, Azmat. 2012. “Violence Intensifies in Homs after U.N.
Resolution on Syria Fails.” PBS. February 6.
http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/frontline/foreign-affairs-
defense/syria-undercover/violence-intensifies-in-homs-after-u-n-
resolution-on-syria-fails/.
Kumbaro, Dajena. 2001. “The Kosovo Crisis in an International Law
Perspective: Self Determination, Territorial Integrity and the
NATO Intervention.” Albania: North Atlantic Treaty Organization.
Lynch, Marc. 2012. “Making the Arab League Work.” Foreign Policy,
April 8.
http://www.foreignpolicy.com/posts/2012/04/08/making_the_ara
b_league_matter#sthash.40aiT9qJ.dpbs.
McDonald, Kara and Stewart Patrick. 2010. “UN Security Council
Enlargement and U.S. Interests.” Council on Foreign Relations.
Accessed August 1, 2013. http://www.cfr.org/international-
organizations-and-alliances/un-security-council-enlargement-us-
interests/p23363.
Mohammed, Arshad and Andrew Osborn. 2013. “Kerry: Syrian
Surrender of Chemical Arms Could Stop U.S. Attack.” Reuters,
September 9. Accessed April 18, 2014.
http://www.reuters.com/article/2013/09/09/us-syria-crisis-kerry-
idUSBRE9880BV20130909.
Obama, Barack. 2011. “Remarks by the President on the Middle East
and North Africa.” May 19. Department of State, Washington, DC.
Pew Research Center for the People and the Press. 2013. “America’s
Place in the World 2013.” Accessed December 3, 2013.
http://www.people-press.org/2013/12/03/public-sees-u-s-power-
declining-as-support-for-global-engagement-slips/.
Scheffer, David. 2012. “America’s Embrace of the International
Criminal Court.” Jurist Forum, July 2.
http://jurist.org/forum/2012/07/dan-scheffer-us-icc.php.
Soderberg, Nancy E. 2007. “U.S. Support for UN Peacekeeping;
Areas for Additional DOD Assistance.” Center for Technology and
National Security Policy. National Defense University Press.
———. 2011. “Enhancing U.S. Support for UN Peacekeeping.” Prism
2 (2). National Defense University Press.
United Nations. 2000. “Report of the Panel on United Nations Peace
Operations—Brahimi Report.” UN Document A/55/305-
S/2000/809. August 21.
United Nations Department of Peacekeeping Operations and
Department of Field Support (UNDPKO and DFS). 2009. “A New
Partnership Agenda Charting a New Horizon for UN
Peacekeeping.” New York: United Nations Department of
Peacekeeping Operations and Department of Field Support.
United Nations General Assembly. 2005. “60/1 2005 World Summit
Document.” UN Document A/RES/60/1. October 24.
United Nations Secretary-General. 2006. “Peace Operations 2010
Reform Strategy.” New York: United Nations.
United Nations Security Council. 1998. “Resolution 1199 (1998).” UN
Document S/RES/1199. September 23.
———. 2000. “Resolution 1315 (2000).” UN Document S/RES/1315.
August 14.
———. 2002. “Resolution 1422 (2002).” UN Document S/RES/1422.
July 12.
US Agency for International Development (USAID). Accessed April
18, 2014. http://www.usaid.gov/crisis/syria.
US Department of Defense. 2010. “Quadrennial Defense Review.”
Washington DC: US Department of Defense.
US National Security Council. 2010. “National Security Strategy.”
White House. Washington DC.
CHAPTER 2
A Critical Review
Although the ICC and various NGOs have created a unique
framework for the protection of victims’ rights and respect for their
dignity, the ICC remains a mostly untested institution, and many
problems remain. First, it is clear the ICC has a large outreach
dilemma. Although NGOs have been useful in collecting information
on cases and helping victims apply, many potential victims still see
the ICC as “just a rumor, more or less” (Glassborrow 2007). The ICC
must work on globalizing awareness of its operations so that victims
of atrocity crimes will feel more comfortable stepping forward.
Far from The Hague, the operation of the Court is often
misunderstood. People who have been victims of atrocity crimes
often fail to understand why the Office of the Prosecutor chooses to
investigate certain specific incidents and not others. Victims in
regions of Ituri (Democratic Republic of the Congo) not covered by
present charges, for example, do not understand why “victims who
suffer from the same atrocities, by the same groups, were not taken
into account by investigators” (VRGW 2010, 13). But of course the
prosecutor cannot feasibly investigate every atrocity incident, nor is
it the function of a Court to do so: The guilt of perpetrators needs to
be decisively proven, not comprehensively so in the sense of each
atrocity committed. Yet this process leaves some victims on the
outside. The Court must do all it can to keep them informed and to
attend to their needs as well. But this limitation points to a need for
broader institutional support for victims of atrocity crimes
internationally.
Furthermore, the ICC has been an institution that works slowly
and is consistently backed up with paperwork. The Registry, for
example, has often been unable to process victim applications in a
timely fashion, resulting in the denial of participation to persons who
should legitimately be classified as victims (VRWG 2011, 7). The ICC
must work to streamline its operations if it wishes to maintain the
standards it has set for itself.
Other institutional growing pains are also apparent. The Rome
statute and RPE state that victims must be informed at various
stages of the proceedings, but as of this writing, no clear
understanding has emerged of what that entails (ICC 2002a, 53; ICC
2002b, 50, 59, 69). Also, the extent of victims’ rights will continue to
evolve as judges make different rulings concerning victim
participation (Spiga 2010, 185). It is too soon to say with any
precision where the Court will end up and therefore too soon to
assess its ultimate adequacy in attending to the human needs of
victims.
The slow pace of trials and the paucity of convictions have
contributed to a feeling of lassitude for some victims directly
participating in the ICC. For victims, justice delayed can indeed look
like justice denied. The boost to the credibility of the Court from the
generally cautious manner in which it has operated is one side of the
coin; the other is a loss of credibility that comes from moving slowly.
Observers report that off-site victims often fail to understand the
Court’s practical successes. The Court’s own self-assessment notes
that victims in Ituri feel they are “shadows, without a face, without a
voice, without light, wondering when the truth on … the crimes will
be revealed” (VRWG 2010, 16).
Some have expressed concern that the Court’s concern for the
rights of victims goes too far, impinging on the rights of the accused.
One critic cites the lack of clarity as to the type of fact-finding the
Court employs with regard to victim participation: a judge-driven
inquisitorial method or a partydriven accusatorial method (Zappalà
2010, 139). Some commentators have expressed concern that the
decision in the Lubanga case represents a “systemic encroachment
on the rights of the accused” (Guhr 2008, 127).
A stocktaking session devoted to the Court’s treatment of victims
at its Assembly of States Parties review conference in Kampala in
2010 frankly acknowledged a number of challenges the Court faces,
especially in outreach. The Court has now made a priority of
outreach to women and children (ICC 2010a, 80). The review
conference also acknowledged the potential problem of development
of unrealistic expectations among victims: “[I]t is inherently
impossible to repair the losses and fully alleviate the suffering
caused by heinous international crimes” (ICC 2010a, 97). Awareness
of the existence of the TFV may itself create undue expectations for
relief; the TFV will never have sufficient assets to meet the needs of
all claimants and will accordingly have to target its efforts (Keller
2007).
As the Court matures, it must build on its symbolic and
substantive successes in the expansion of victims’ rights and respect
for the dignity of victims to include concrete improvements in the
lives of victims. The ICC currently offers the most forward-leaning
example of victim advocacy in the international system. Gioia Greco
calls its work “a glaring achievement in the international field” (2007,
531). But there is much work still to do to fully operationalize its
commitment to victims (Bachvarova 2011). And as noted, the court
by the nature of its mandate will never reach all victims of atrocities,
only those harmed by the specific crimes charged in each case. This
leaves a substantial gap that other institutions and national
governments must fill.
Notes
Thanks to Carly Hafner for research assistance.
1. I leave aside consideration of so-called victimless crimes.
2. A copy of this form can be found at “Application Form,”
http://www.icc-cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/48A75CF0-E38E-48A7-A9E0-
026ADD32553D/0/SAFIndividualEng.pdf.
3. Some, of course, do think they have a right not to be offended
or affronted. It is the responsibility of liberal political and juridical
order to address the requirements of their dignity without granting
this right. The International Criminal Court has been accused of an
imperialist propensity, namely the imposition on others of a narrowly
Western set of values. I reject this characterization but agree that
the Court is a classically liberal institution.
References
Bachvarova, Tatiana. 2011. “Victims’ Eligibility before the
International Criminal Court in Historical and Comparative
Context.” International Criminal Law Review 11 (4): 665–706.
Bassiouni, M. Cherif. 2006. “International Recognition of Victims’
Rights.” Human Rights Law Review 6 (2): 203–79. doi:
10.1093/hrlr/ngl009.
Funk, T. Markus. 2010. Victims’ Rights and Advocacy at the
International Criminal Court. New York: Oxford University.
Glassborrow, Katie. 2007. “ICC Struggles to Reach Out to Darfuris.”
Institute for War and Peace Reporting. October 26. Accessed
August 1, 2013. http://iwpr.net/report-news/icc-struggles-reach-
out-darfuris.
Greco, Gioia. 2007. “Victims’ Rights Overview under the ICC Legal
Framework: A Jurisprudential Analysis.” International Criminal
Law Review 7 (2–3): 531–47.
Guhr, A. H. 2008. “Victim Participation during the Pre-Trial Stage at
the International Criminal Court.” International Criminal Law
Review 8 (1–2): 109–40. doi: 10.1163/156753608X265259.
Herman, Judith. 1997. Trauma and Recovery. New York: Basic
Books.
ICC (International Criminal Court). 2002a. Rome Statute of the
International Criminal Court. Available at http://www.icc-
cpi.int/en_menus/icc/legal%20texts%20and%20tools/official%20
journal/Pages/rome%20statute.aspx.
———. 2002b. Rules of Procedure and Evidence. Available at
http://www.icc-
cpi.int/en_menus/icc/legal%20texts%20and%20tools/official%20
journal/Pages/rules%20of%20procedure%20and%20evidence.as
px.
———. 2006. Situation in the Democratic Republic of Congo, Case
No. ICC-01/04-101: Decision on the Applications for Participation
in the Proceedings. Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.vrwg.org/VRWG_DOC/2010_Apr_VRWG_Impact_of_I
CC_on_victims.pdf.
———. 2009a. Assembly of States Parties. “Report of the Court on
the Strategy in Relation to Victims.” Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.icc-cpi.int/iccdocs/asp_docs/ASP8/ICC-ASP-8-45-
ENG.pdf.
———. 2009b. “Summary Report” (paper presented at The Round
Table on the Protection of Victims and Witnesses, The Hague,
January 29–30, 2009). Accessed August 1, 2013. http://www.icc-
cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/19869519-923D-4F67-A61F-
35F78E424C68/280579/Report_ENG.pdf.
———. 2010a. Assembly of States Parties. “The Impact of the Rome
Statute System on Victims and Affected Communities.” Annex
V(a) to Official Records. Review Conference of the International
Criminal Court. Kampala. May 31—June 11: 77-101.
———. 2010b. Office of Public Counsel for Victims. Helping Victims
Make Their Voice Heard: The Office of Public Counsel for Victims.
Accessed August 1, 2013. http://www.icc-
cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/01A26724-F32B-4BE4-8B02-
A65D6151E4AD/282846/LRBookletEng.pdf.
———. 2010c. “Summary Report on the Seminar on Protection of
Victims and Witnesses Appearing before the International
Criminal Court.” Accessed August 1, 2013. http://www.icc-
cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/08767415-4F1D-46BA-B408-
5B447B3AFC8D/0/ProtectionseminarSUMMARY.pdf.s.
———. 2010d. Trust Fund for Victims. Learning from the TFV’s
Second Mandate: From Implementing Rehabilitation Assistance to
Reparations. Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.trustfundforvictims.org/sites/default/files/imce/TFV%
20Programme%20Report%20Fall%202010.pdf.
———. 2010e. Victims before the International Criminal Court: A
Guide for the Participation of Victims in the Procedure of the
Court. Accessed August 1, 2013. http://www.icc-
cpi.int/NR/rdonlyres/8FF91A2C-5274-4DCB-9CCE-
37273C5E9AB4/282477/160910VPRSBookletEnglish.pdf
———. 2011a. “Registry and Trust Fund for Victims Fact Sheet.”
http://www.iccnow.org/documents/Victims_Factsheet_March_201
1.18apr1832.pdf.
———. 2011b. Trust Fund for Victims. “United Kingdom Contributes
GBP 500,000 to the Trust Fund for Victims.” Accessed August 1,
2013. http://www.trustfundforvictims.org/news/united-kingdom-
contributes-gbp-500000-trust-fund-victims.
———. 2012. Trust Fund for Victims. “ICC Trust Fund for Victims
Assists over 80,000 Victims, Raises Reparations Reserve.”
Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.trustfundforvictims.org/news/press-release-23-
march-icc-trust-fund-victims-assists-over-80000-victims-raises-
reparations-res.
IFHR (International Federation for Human Rights). 2010.
“Reparations and the Trust Fund for Victims,” in Victims’ Rights
before the ICC. Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.fidh.org/IMG/pdf/10-CH-VII_Reparations.pdf.
Keller, Linda M. 2007. “Seeking Justice at the International Criminal
Court.” Thomas Jefferson Law Review 29 (2): 189–217.
Kojève, Alexandre. 2000. Outline of a Phenomenology of Right.
Translated by Bryan-Paul Frost and Robert Howse. Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield.
Minow, Martha. 1998. Between Vengeance and Forgiveness. Boston:
Beacon Press.
Mosteller, Robert P. 1997. “Victims’ Rights and the United States
Constitution: An Effort to Recast the Battle in Criminal Litigation.”
Georgetown Law Journal 85: 1691–715.
O’Hara, Erin Ann. 2005. “Victim Participation in the Criminal Process.”
Journal of Law and Policy 13 (1): 229–47.
Pizzi, William T. and Walter Perron. 1996. “Crime Victims in German
Courtrooms: A Comparative Perspective on American Problems.”
Stanford Journal of International Law 32 (1): 37–64.
Rosen, Jeffrey. 2000. The Unwanted Gaze. New York: Random
House.
Rosen, Michael. 2012. Dignity: Its History and Meaning. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
SáCouto, Susanna, and Katherine Cleary. 2008. “Victims’
Participation in the Investigations of the International Criminal
Court.” Transnational Law and Comparative Problems 17: 73–105.
Spiga, Valentina. 2010. “Indirect Victims’ Participation in the
Lubanga Trial.” Journal of International Criminal Justice 8 (1):
183–98. doi: 10.1093/jicj/mqq007.
VRWG (Victims’ Rights Working Group). 2010. The Impact of the
Rome Statute System on Victims and Affected Communities.
London: VRGW.
———. 2011. The Implementation of Victims’ Rights before the ICC.
London: VRGW.
Zappalà, Salvatore. 2010. “The Rights of the Victims and the Rights
of the Accused.” Journal of International Criminal Justice 8 (1):
137–64.
CHAPTER 3
Of all the secretaries-general of the UN, Kofi Annan was the most
impassioned advocate for human dignity. He viewed the role of the
UN and that of the secretary-general as central in the promotion of
human dignity around the world. He regarded the promotion and
protection of universal human rights as one of the most important
and effective ways for the secretary-general to advance human
dignity. Annan believed that lasting peace and development could
not be achieved without respect for human dignity, and throughout
his decade-long tenure, he stressed the inextricable link between
human rights, development, and security. In his address to the
inaugural session of the Human Rights Council in Geneva on June
19, 2006, he said: “Lack of respect for human rights and dignity is
the fundamental reason why the peace of the world today is so
precarious, and why prosperity is so unequally shared.” He added:
“[T]he strongest states are those that most resolutely defend the
human rights of all their citizens” (Annan 2006).
The secretary-general has an important role to play in shaping
the values that guide UN action, a role that particular secretaries-
general found implicit in the Charter. Equally important, however,
have been the distinctive leadership styles—determined by personal
characteristics—exhibited by occupants of the post (Killie 2006). This
is a subject on which the Charter is silent. This chapter treats the
secretary-general’s office as an institution, but one that depends to a
much greater degree on both the talents and inclinations of an
individual, as well as on external circumstances. In short, whereas
the office of the secretary-general creates the environment for the
exercise of moral authority, the realization of the normative potential
of the role has depended in large part on the individual
officeholders.
Annan sought to advance human dignity in three ways: First, he
worked through norms, particularly by promoting human rights
standards and the Responsibility to Protect (R2P). Second, he
worked through institutions, primarily by reforming the human rights
machinery within the framework of a broader process of UN reform,
specifically by establishing the Human Rights Council. Third, he
worked through the UN’s operational efforts in the field, especially in
zones of conflict. In promoting human dignity in all three ways,
Annan capitalized on his lengthy institutional experience at the UN
(which spanned more than three decades), the unique geopolitical
moment at the end of the Cold War, the growth of a global interest
in human rights concerns, and increasing institutional capacity of
nongovernmental organizations (NGOs) to address them.
Advancing Norms
Although the provisions of the Charter do not imbue the office of the
UN secretary-general with explicit political power, the role provides
great opportunities for exercising influence (Urquhart and Childers
1990, 22). Upon assuming the leadership of the UN in 1997, Annan
sought to capitalize on the normative trends in the international
community toward taking humanitarian interventions and human
rights more seriously. In the early 1990s, the UN went through a
crisis of expectations when peacekeeping forces were deployed in
zones of conflict (Somalia, Bosnia, and Rwanda) without sufficient
resources or a clear mandate to confront local forces engaged in
genocide or mass atrocities. The resulting “blame game” led to a
crisis between the UN Secretariat and the Clinton administration, and
ultimately to the United States’ vetoing Boutros Boutros-Ghali’s bid
for a second term as secretary-general. Yet Annan, the new
secretary-general, was himself compromised in the eyes of at least a
part of world public opinion by his role as undersecretary-general for
peacekeeping operations for the very failures for which the
Secretariat was blamed.
It was against this backdrop that Annan felt driven, both as a
result of his personal implication in the crises of the 1990s and for
the sake of the long-term credibility of the organization which he
now headed, to consolidate the transformed normative environment
that the conclusion of the Cold War augured. Arguably, it is the
realm of norm entrepreneurship, which provides the greatest
political space available to any secretary-general. Norm
entrepreneurs are invariably well-placed individuals whose
prominence enhances their ability to promote norms and prompt
change in the international system. Their promotion of change is
also generally grounded in strong notions about the standards of
behavior to which actors in the international system ought to
adhere. They “spot gaps in the existing normative architecture of
world order and engage in moral proselytism in order to fill those
gaps” (Thakur 2006, 13).
These highly motivated actors use their platforms or bully pulpits,
in Annan’s case the office of the secretary-general, to “launch their
crusades” and to convince state governments of the import of a
norm (Thakur 2006, 13). As a norm entrepreneur, Annan utilized the
platform he possessed to raise the visibility of human rights
challenges in the international system. Annan’s normative impact can
be seen primarily in two areas: first, advocating the belief that
human rights are universal and indivisible, and second, promoting
the principle of the R2P.
When Annan became secretary-general in 1997, human rights
were not necessarily assumed to be universal. Some UN member
states argued that human rights were geographically delimited—the
product of Eurocentric Enlightenment assumptions—or the concern
only of states that had reached a certain level of development. In his
role as a norm entrepreneur, Annan challenged both these
conceptions of human rights and argued that fundamental human
rights were an innate demand of the human condition and not alien
to any country, culture, race or religion. In his first speech to the
Organization of African Unity in Harare, Zimbabwe in June 1997,
Annan said: “The success of Africa’s third wave [of democratization]
depends equally on respect for fundamental human rights. The
conflicts which have disfigured our continent have, all too often,
been accompanied by massive human rights violations. I am aware
of the fact that some view this concern as a luxury of the rich
countries for which Africa is not ready. I know that others treat it as
an imposition, if not a plot, by the industrialized West. I find these
thoughts truly demeaning, demeaning of the yearning for human
dignity that resides in every African heart” (Annan 1997a).
Six months later in an address at the University of Tehran on
Human Rights Day, Annan declared: “Human rights are the
foundation of human existence and co-existence.… Human rights are
universal, indivisible and interdependent.… Human rights are what
make us human. They are the principles by which we create the
sacred home for human dignity” (Annan 1997b).
By the end of his first year as secretary-general, Annan had
placed himself firmly on the side of universalism over relativism in
human rights, signaled his intent to make human rights the
touchstone of his work, and became an international spokesman for
human dignity. This marked a break with previous occupants of the
position, who tended to assume that their responsibility for peace
and security took precedence over an outspoken position on human
rights (Forsythe 1993). Annan’s novel approach was recognized by
the Norwegian Nobel Committee, which when announcing its
intention to award Annan and the UN the 2001 Nobel Peace Prize
observed that, “[Kofi Annan] has been pre-eminent in bringing new
life to the organization. While clearly underlining the UN’s traditional
responsibility for peace and security, [Kofi Annan] has also
emphasized its obligations with regard to human rights” (Norwegian
Nobel Committee 2001).
In the late 1990s, Annan urged UN member states to resolve the
tension between the principles of state sovereignty and the
international community’s responsibility to respond to massive
human rights violations, such as ethnic cleansing. He believed that
sovereignty implied responsibilities as well as powers.1 And a critical
duty was to protect people from violence and war, which were grave
assaults on human dignity. In his view, national sovereignty was not
to be used as a shield for those who wantonly violated human
dignity. In his Ditchley Foundation Lecture in June 1998, Annan
emphasized that if a regime was abusing its own citizens, the
international community had a responsibility to prevent and end the
abuse. As he put it: “The Charter was issued in the name of ‘the
peoples,’ not the governments, of the UN. Its aim is not only to
preserve international peace—vitally important though that is—but
also ‘to reaffirm faith in fundamental human rights, in the dignity
and worth of the human person.’ The Charter protects the
sovereignty of peoples. It was never meant as a license for
governments to trample on human rights and human dignity.
Sovereignty implies responsibility, not just power” (Annan 1998b).
The remark was emblematic of Annan’s instinctive emphasis on
the dignity of individuals rather than on the prerogatives of states,
and it came to define his approach to the role of the international
community in the face of the commission of atrocities.
A year later Annan chose “humanitarian intervention” as the
theme of his speech at the opening of the General Assembly in
September 1999. The tragic failures of the UN in Srebrenica and
Rwanda and the Kosovo crisis provided the context for the speech.
Indeed, the Security Council had failed to act in the Kosovo crisis
because of profound competing national interests and differences
among its permanent members regarding state sovereignty and
whether a moral imperative exists to take action in response to gross
violations of human dignity. Annan underlined that the Security
Council’s paralysis threatened the credibility of the UN: “If the
collective conscience of humanity—a conscience which abhors
cruelty, renounces injustice and seeks peace for all peoples—cannot
find in the United Nations its greatest tribune, there is a grave
danger that it will look elsewhere for peace and for justice” (Annan
1999b). Indeed, when during and since Annan’s tenure divisions in
the Security Council have appeared irresolvable, the resulting
temptation for member states to take unilateral action has
threatened to erode the very foundation of the UN’s effectiveness.2
Annan’s General Assembly speech sparked a fierce and wide-
ranging debate on how the international community could better
protect the dignity and sanctity of human life. The speech was
delivered in a climate where member states were staking their own
claims on the issue, typified by British Prime Minister Tony Blair’s so-
called Chicago Speech in which he enunciated a “doctrine of the
international community” (Blair 1999). In the wake of such
declarations, Annan challenged member states to find a consensus
on the vital issue of the international community’s responsibility in
the face of massive violations of human dignity. However, Annan
acknowledged in his 2000 Annual Report on the UN: “It is, of course,
relatively easy for the international community to assert that the
tragedies of Rwanda and Srebrenica should never be allowed to
happen again. But if the reaction to my address last year to the
General Assembly is any guide, I fear we may still prove unable to
give a credible answer to the question of what happens next time
we are faced with a comparable crime against humanity” (Annan
2000b).
“The dilemma of intervention” was a main theme of the
Secretary-General’s 2000 Millennium Report. In it, Annan recognized
“both the force and importance” of the arguments of member states
who were concerned about the dangers of the concept of
humanitarian intervention. But he added: “We confront a real
dilemma. Few would disagree that both the defense of humanity and
the defense of sovereignty are principles that must be supported.
Alas, that does not tell us which principle should prevail when they
are in conflict” (Annan 2000a).
The International Commission on Intervention and State
Sovereignty (ICISS), a Canadian-led initiative that Annan facilitated
as part of his norm entrepreneurship, restated the core issue at the
heart of the debate on intervention—shifting from debate about a
“right to intervene” towards the assertion of a “responsibility to
protect.” Its 2001 report, The Responsibility to Protect, was a
comprehensive response to Annan’s speech on intervention in the
General Assembly. It correctly interpreted the secretary-general’s
idea of two notions of sovereignty—one for states, one for
individuals—and underlined that the state exists for the benefit of its
individual citizens, not the other way around (ICISS 2001). The aim
reflected both Annan’s normative ambitions as well as his awareness
that, if it were to retain legitimacy in a new century, the UN could
not open itself to further charges of “complicity with evil” (Report of
the Panel on United Nations Peace Operations 2000, xi).
Of course, the international community already had a long-
standing commitment to prevent and punish the crime of genocide
under the Genocide Convention. The Security Council has also
exercised the right to authorize military action to redress gross
violations of human rights, such as ethnic cleansing, that it deems as
threats to international peace and security. In April 2004, in a speech
in Geneva commemorating the tenth anniversary of the genocide in
Rwanda, Kofi Annan outlined a five-point action plan for preventing
genocide: preventing armed conflict, which usually provides the
context for genocide; protecting civilians in armed conflict by UN
peacekeepers and other means; ending impunity through judicial
action in both national and international courts; gathering
information and early warning of crises; and taking swift and
decisive action, including military action. In the speech, he also
announced the appointment of a special adviser on the prevention of
genocide, which was tasked with three functions: to collect
information on potential or existing situations or threats of genocide;
to act as an early-warning mechanism to the Security Council and
other parts of the UN system; and to make recommendations to the
Security Council on actions to prevent or halt genocide (Annan
2004).
In March 2005, drawing on the findings of a high-level panel—a
collaborative means of working that was characteristic of Annan’s
inclinations as a convener of expertise—Annan issued a report, In
Larger Freedom: Towards Development, Security and Human Rights
for All, which contained a number of policy proposals to be taken up
by heads of state and governments at the UN World Summit in
September of that year. The central theme of the report was that the
world must advance the causes of security, development, and
human rights together; otherwise, none will succeed. Annan urged
world leaders to embrace the principle of the Responsibility to
Protect both the potential or the actual victims of mass atrocities. He
recognized that many states were concerned that this principle
would violate sovereignty. However, he believed that no legal
principle should be allowed to shield genocide, crimes against
humanity, and gross human rights abuses and that the R2P doctrine
would not provide an open door to humanitarian intervention.
Annan’s recommendation that member states endorse the
“emerging norm of the responsibility to protect” was vigorously
debated during the General Assembly consultations on his report in
April. Whereas the European Union, the GUUAM group (Georgia,
Ukraine, Uzbekistan, Azerbaijan, and Moldova), and several African
states endorsed the principle, others, including the Non-Aligned
Movement, rejected it as a reformulation of humanitarian
intervention without any basis in the UN Charter or international law.
However, the Non-Aligned Movement expressed its willingness to
further discuss the issue ahead of the 2005 UN World Summit.
After intense intergovernmental debate, the World Summit, held
in September 2005, produced a historic breakthrough on the R2P. In
the Summit Outcome Document, all governments accepted clearly
and unambiguously their collective responsibility to protect
populations from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes
against humanity. While stressing the continued primacy of the UN
Charter, member states also agreed to take timely and decisive
collective action for this purpose through the Security Council when
peaceful means proved inadequate and national authorities were
manifestly failing to protect their populations.
The Summit’s endorsement of R2P was a major advance in
international norm setting that Annan had been advocating for
several years. In its encapsulation of the universality, indivisibility,
and interrelatedness of all human rights, R2P reflected the “Annan
doctrine”: that state sovereignty cannot be used as an excuse to
shield human rights abuses. Emblematic of his norm
entrepreneurship, Annan had helped to shift the narrative from the
rights of states to the rights of individuals. He used the office of the
secretary-general to put the emphasis where it belonged—on the
people who needed protection because their human dignity was
threatened with massacre or ethnic cleansing rather than on
relations between states.
Conclusion
It is clear that there are limitations on the role of the secretary-
general both politically and in terms of his mandate defined in the
Charter. The most significant is that the secretary-general is not a
head of state or government but the chief administrative officer of
an intergovernmental organization. The secretary-general takes
instructions from the political bodies of the UN, particularly the
General Assembly and the Security Council. The secretary-general
can stake out the moral high ground—and Kofi Annan was adept at
choosing occasions on which to do so—but he cannot get too far
ahead of the member states. Given that the influence of the
secretary-general is in large part dependent on the exercise of moral
authority, when the basis of this influence is damaged—as many
deemed it to be during the oil-for-food scandal and when the UN
appeared impotent during the US-led invasion of Iraq—the pursuit of
UN goals can be severely impeded. This reality reflects the delicate
relationship between the Security Council and the secretary-general,
which requires nimble diplomacy—both overt and behind the scenes.
The secretary-general’s personal qualities are critical in creating a
productive and even harmonious relationship with the Council. As
Marrack Goulding, former undersecretary-general for Political Affairs,
noted, the relationship works best if the Security Council
understands that the secretary-general is more than a chief
administrative officer and the secretary-general understands that the
Security Council has primary responsibility for maintaining
international peace and security (Goulding 2004, 267–280).
Kofi Annan’s contributions underline the fact that the promotion
of human dignity by the secretary-general requires effective
intellectual, moral, and political leadership. The ability of the
secretary-general to provide leadership is the result of various
factors including personal conviction, strategic planning,
perseverance, patience, in-depth knowledge of the UN system,
compelling communication skills, and charisma.
Annan’s role in promoting human dignity is central to the
meaning of his secretary-generalship. Annan stressed that lasting
peace was impossible without a respect for human rights, and that
human rights and good governance were important in the struggle
for development. He placed people (rather than states) and their
needs at the center of the UN’s work. To do so, he used a variety of
tools at his disposal: influential, sometimes provocative, speeches
and other forms of advocacy, rigorous and thoughtful reports, high-
level panels, and summits. He used the media to appeal to broader
constituencies beyond states, including civil society and the business
community. He was not reticent about speaking “above the heads of
state” and appealing directly to the peoples of the world. He was an
entrepreneur who was able to use the bully pulpit to generate and
shape norms, such as R2P.
Annan tried to build networks with nonstate actors, including the
private sector, civil society organizations, philanthropic foundations,
universities and think tanks, as well as celebrities in order to
promote human dignity without relying exclusively on state power
and interstate cooperation. An understanding that his accountability
was ultimately not to states but to the people they served informed
his approach to global challenges. In pursuit of human dignity he
worked, to an extent that no secretary-general had done before, to
protect populations threatened by gross and systematic violations of
human rights even in an era when many people had come to regard
global institutions and universal norms as a threat to their particular
identity or interests.
The agenda of human dignity is clearly important enough to
warrant the further engagement of the current and future
secretaries-general. The UN secretary-general must demonstrate the
courage needed to tackle hard questions and to bring forward new
thinking on the concept of human dignity, which is so central to the
relations within and among states, and on the institutional means
and partnerships to advance it. Annan was a quintessential norm
entrepreneur, and like all successful entrepreneurs he translated an
instinctive vision into an agenda for action that won the support of
effective coalitions. The secretary-general must continue to serve as
a catalyst for a new debate on the promotion of human dignity
around the world because in the words of the Universal Declaration
of Human Rights: “All human beings are born free and equal in
dignity and rights.”
Notes
For a detailed discussion about strategic planning in the Executive
Office of the Secretary-General including, inter alia, issues of human
dignity, see Abiodun Williams, “Strategic Planning in the Executive
Office of the UN Secretary General,” Global Governance 16, no. 4
(2010): 435–49.
1. The notion of “sovereignty as responsibility” did not emerge
with the political crises of the 1990s but has philosophical
antecedents coterminous with the very emergence of Westphalian
sovereignty. Nevertheless, it was Annan who expressed the
argument most forcefully and with the greatest resonance, providing
the political as well as philosophical underpinnings for the
Responsibility to Protect.
2. For a treatment of the Security Council’s efforts to address
atrocities and an emerging Responsibility to Protect norm, see Nancy
Soderberg’s chapter 2 in this book.
3. For a detailed assessment of the record of the Human Rights
Council, see chapter 6 in this book by Mark P. Lagon and Ryan
Kaminski on institutional evolution and efficacy in the area of human
rights.
References
Annan, Kofi. 1997a. Annual Assembly of Heads of State and
Government of the Organization of African Unity (OAU) (speech).
Harare, Zimbabwe, June 2.
http://www.un.org/News/ossg/sg/stories/statments_search_full.a
sp?statID=14.
———. 1997b. 50th Anniversary of the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights (speech). University of Tehran, December 10.
Accessed September 22, 2013.
http://www.un.org/rights/50/dpi1937.htm.
———. 1998a. The Causes of Conflict and the Promotion of Durable
Peace and Sustainable Development in Africa, Report of the
Secretary General, Delivered to the Security Council and the
General Assembly. UN Document S/1998/318-A/52/871, April 13.
———. 1998b. “Secretary-General Reflects on ‘Intervention’ in
Thirty-Fifth Annual Ditchley Foundation Lecture.” UN Press
Release SG/SM/6613, June 26.
———. 1998c “The Quiet Revolution.” Global Governance 4: 123.
———. 1999a. “Secretary-General Proposes Global Compact on
Human Rights, Labour, Environment.” UN Press Release
SG/SM/6881, February 1.
———. 1999b. “Secretary-General Presents His Annual Report to the
General Assembly.” UN Press Release SG/SM/7136, September
20.
———. 2000a. We The Peoples: The Role of the United Nations in
the Twenty-First Century. United Nations Publications.
———. 2000b. Report of the Secretary-General on the Work of the
Organization. UN Document A/55/1, August 30.
———. 2004. “Secretary-General Launches Action Plan to Prevent
Genocide in Speech to the Commission on Human Rights.” UN
Press Release SG/SM/9197, April 7.
———. 2005. In Larger Freedom: Towards Development, Security
and Human Rights for All. UN Document A/59/2005, March 21.
———. 2006. “The Secretary General’s Address to the Human Rights
Council” (speech). Geneva, Switzerland, June 19.
http://www.un.org/sg/statements/?nid=2090.
Annan, Kofi (with Nader Mousavizadeh). 2012. Interventions: A Life
in War and Peace. New York: The Penguin Press.
Blair, Tony. 1999. “Doctrine of the International Community”
(speech). Economic Club of Chicago, April 24.
http://www.pbs.org/newshour/bb/international/jan-
june99/blair_doctrine4-23.html.
Forsythe, David P. 1993. “The UN Secretary-General and Human
Rights.” In The Challenging Role of the UN Secretary-General:
Making “The Most Impossible Job in the World” Possible, edited
by Benjamin Rivilin and Leon Gordenker. Westport, CT:
Greenwood Press.
Goulding, Marrack. 2004. “The UN Secretary-General.” In The UN
Security Council: From the Cold War to the 21st Century, edited
by David M. Malone. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty
(ICISS). 2001. The Responsibility to Protect. Ottawa:
International Development Research Centre.
Johnstone, Ian. 2007. “The Secretary-General as Norm
Entrepreneur.” In Secretary or General: The UN Secretary-General
in World Politics, edited by Simon Chesterman. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Killie, Kent J. 2006. From Manager to Visionary: The Secretary-
General of the United Nations. New York: Palgrave.
Mandela, Nelson. 1993. “Acceptance and Nobel Lecture” (speech).
Oslo, Norway, December 10.
http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/1993/m
andela-lecture_en.html.
Norwegian Nobel Committee. 2001. “The Nobel Peace Prize 2001.”
Accessed September 22, 2013.
http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/peace/laureates/2001/pr
ess.html.
Report of the Panel on United Nations Peace Operations—Brahimi
Report. 2000. UN Document A/55/305-S/2000/809, August 21.
Smith, Courtney B. 2007. “Politics and Values at the United Nations:
Kofi Annan’s Balancing Act.” In The UN Secretary-General and
Moral Authority: Ethics & Religion in International Leadership,
edited by Kent J. Killie. Washington DC: Georgetown University
Press.
Terlingen, Yvonne. 2007. “The Human Rights Council: A New Era in
UN Human Rights Work?” Ethics and International Affairs 21 (2):
167–78.
Thakur, Ramesh. 2006. The United Nations, Peace and Security. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Traub, James. 2006. The Best Intentions: Kofi Annan and the UN in
the Era of American World Power. New York: Farrar, Straus, and
Giroux.
United Nations Peacekeeping Operations: Principles and Guidelines.
2008. New York: United Nations.
Urquhart, Brian, and Erskine Childers. 1990. A World in Need of
Leadership: Tomorrow’s United Nations. Uppsala, Sweden: Dag
Hammarskjöld Foundation.
CHAPTER 4
Conclusion
This chapter has argued that RSOs can serve a range of political
purposes and goals, reflecting the interests and priorities of member
states as well as the histories and cultures of different regions. It
further asserts that RSOs are becoming more important actors in
international politics and security, as legitimizers, gatekeepers, and
operational agents. While serving the interests of member states,
they also reflect the broader universe of laws and norms, which are
ever changing. The chapter makes the case that RSOs have the
potential to be relevant players in advancing the agenda of human
dignity. Although not often primary drivers, they do play an
increasingly salient role in shaping the political and institutional
environment in which issues of dignity are acted upon. Leading
democratic states and intergovernmental bodies have possibilities for
action to expand the scope for advancing human dignity if they set
about it consciously. This chapter has identified a number of avenues
for doing so and for strengthening the RSO contribution to building a
more decent global order.
Notes
1. I am indebted to Georgetown University graduate student
Stein-Ivar Eide for his research assistance in the preparation of this
chapter.
2. I am indebted to Georgetown University graduate student
Caitlin Fogerty for drawing my attention to these issues.
References
Acharya, Amitav. 2012. “Comparative Regionalism: A Field Whose
Time Has Come?” The International Spectator: Italian Journal of
International Affairs 47 (1): 3–15.
Annan, Kofi. 2001. “Foreword.” In Human Security and the New
Diplomacy, edited by Rob McRae and Don Hubert. Ottawa:
Carleton University Press.
Asher, David L., Victor D. Comras, and Patrick M. Cronin. 2011.
Pressure: Coercive Economic Statecraft and U.S. National
Security. Washington, DC: Center for a New American Security.
Bailes, Alyson J. K. 2011. “Europe’s Security: Attitudes,
Achievements, and Unsolved Challenges.” In Rewiring Regional
Security in a Fragmented World, edited by Chester Crocker, Fen
Osler Hampson, and Pamela Aall. Washington, DC: United States
Institute of Peace.
Baranyi, Stephen. 2005. Inter-American Institutions and Conflict
Prevention. Ottawa: Canadian Foundation for the Americas.
Bercovitch, Jacob, and Richard Jackson. 2009. Conflict Resolution in
the Twenty-First Century. Ann Arbor: Michigan University Press.
Brzezinski, Zbigniew. 2009. “An Agenda for NATO: Toward a Global
Security Web.” Foreign Affairs 88 (5): 2–20.
Buzan, Barry, and Ole Waever. 2003. Regions and Powers: The
Structure of International Security. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Cismas, Ioana. 2011. “Introductory Note to the Statute of the OIC
Independent Permanent Human Rights Commission.”
International Legal Materials 5 (6): 1148–60.
Crocker, Chester A., Fen Osler Hampson, and Pamela Aall. 2011.
“Collective Conflict Management: A New Formula for Global Peace
and Security Cooperation?” International Affairs 87 (1): 39–58.
———. 2012. “Jumpstarting Conflict Management: Regional
Organizations, Hybrid Groups and Security.” Paper presented at
the International Studies Association Annual Convention, April 1.
Engel, Ulf, and Joao Gomes Porto. 2010. Africa’s New Security
Architecture: Promoting Norms, Institutionalizing Solutions.
Ashgate, England: Ashgate Publishing Ltd.
Glaser, Daniel L. 2011. Speech at the Washington Institute for Near
East Policy. Accessed September 13, 2013.
http://www.washingtoninstitute.org/policy-
analysis/view/treasurys-response-to-the-arab-spring-financial-
tools-for-international-sec.
Hampson, Fen Osler, Jean Daudelin, John B. Hay, Holly Reid, and
Todd Marting. 2002. Madness in the Multitude: Human Security
and World Disorder. Toronto: Oxford University Press.
Krasner, Stephen D. 2011. “International Support for State-Building:
Flawed Consensus.” Prism 2 (3): 65–74.
Martin, Mary, and Mary Kaldor, eds. 2012. The European Union and
Human Security: External Interventions and Missions. London:
Routledge.
Mazrui, Ali A. 1967. Towards a Pax Africana: A Study of Ideology and
Ambition. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
O’Regan, Davin. 2012. “Narco States: Africa’s Next Menace.” New
York Times, March 12.
http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/13/opinion/narco-states-
africas-next-menace.html?_r=0.
Organization of Islamic Cooperation (OIC). 2012. “OIC Is Vigorously
Engaged in Bringing Political Stability in the Region, Said the
Secretary-General at the US-Islamic World Forum.” OIC. Accessed
May 30, 2013. http://www.oic-oci.org/topic_detail.asp?
t_id=6890.
Oudraat, Chantal de Jonge. 2011. “Play It Again, Uncle Sam:
Transatlantic Relations, NATO, and the European Union.” In
Rewiring Regional Security in a Fragmented World, edited by
Chester Crocker, Fen Osler Hampson, and Pamela Aall.
Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace.
Patrick, Stewart. 2012. “The US and Global Conflict Management:
UN, Regional and Ad Hoc Approaches.” Paper presented at the
International Studies Association Annual Convention, April 1.
Quinney, Nigel. 2011. “Culture Counts: A Diplomatic Perspective on
Culture and Regional Conflict Management.” In Rewiring Regional
Security in a Fragmented World, edited by Chester Crocker, Fen
Osler Hampson, and Pamela Aall. Washington, DC: United States
Institute of Peace.
Rostow, Nicholas. 2012. “Grand Strategy and International Law.”
Strategic Forum 277. Washington, DC: National Defense
University.
Suhrke, Astri. 1999. “Human Security and the Interests of States.”
Security Dialogue 30 (3): 265–76.
Wahyuningrum, Yuhun, and Muhammed Hafiz. 2012. “OIC, Human
Rights and Indonesia’s Role.” Jakarta Post, February 24.
http://www.thejakartapost.com/news/2012/02/24/oic-human-
rights-and-indonesia-s-role.html.
Williams, Paul D., and Jurgen Haacke. 2011. “Regional Approaches
to Conflict Management.” In Rewiring Regional Security in a
Fragmented World, edited by Chester Crocker, Fen Osler
Hampson, and Pamela Aall. Washington, DC: United States
Institute of Peace.
CHAPTER 5
Conclusion
The underground economy constitutes a significant portion of the
overall economy in a number of countries. A central finding of this
essay is that when businesses are faced with onerous regulation and
weak and inconsistent enforcement and corruption, they have an
incentive to hide their activities in the underground economy. That
context undercuts accountability and transparency upon which
greater economic growth, shared prosperity, and the realization of
human dignity rest. Another finding focuses on the importance of the
rule of law in curbing shadow economic activity. The policy
implication is that large reductions in tax rates or increasing the
number of regulations will not shrink the shadow economy. Instead,
governments should place emphasis on strengthening the rule of law,
simplifying access to the formal economy, including improving access
to financial services, and strictly enforcing a minimum necessary set
of regulations, rather than increasing the plethora of regulatory
requirements.
The IMF has been involved in strengthening domestic economic
institutions in the context of both provision of surveillance advice and
technical advice to member countries. Since the global financial crisis
of 2008, the IMF has played a key role in the reform of the global
financial regulatory and supervisory framework. Also, in order to
directly combat the problem of the underground economy, the IMF
has been supporting its members by providing technical assistance on
combating money laundering and terrorist finance and on larger
governance and institutional issues when large illicit sectors are
thought to be seriously hindering favorable macroeconomic
outcomes.
To sum up, the empirical examination in this chapter indicates that
the absence of rule of law and widespread corruption inevitably allow
underground economic activities to flourish, particularly in developing
countries. Conversely, in order for the population to more fully
flourish, domestic institutions must be strengthened, thereby
protecting private property rights, regularizing financial flows, and
ensuring full access to economic opportunities. Despite the recent
emergence of new types of international groupings (from the G—20
to philanthropic foundations to public-private partnerships), the
Bretton Woods institutions and the IMF in particular continue to play
an important function to help countries strengthen domestic
institutions. And as those domestic institutions become increasingly
responsible and responsive to the needs of all members of society,
citizens will have more consistent access to legal rights and a greater
assurance that their capabilities, choices, and efforts will translate
into a better life in practice. In short, intergovernmental institutions
can and must help domestic institutions emerge; this will catalyze
inclusive growth and the realization of the fruits of a life of dignity.
Notes
The views expressed herein are those of the author and should
not be attributed to the International Monetary Fund, its Executive
Board, or its management. The author would like to thank Sonali
Jain-Chandra, Carine Chartouni, Jody Meyers, Adil Mohammad,
Melissa Tullis, Victory Thuronyi, and Rhoda Weeks-Brown for their
input and comments.
1. Also variously known as the informal, shadow, or parallel
economy.
2. Institutions are defined as the formal and informal constraints
on political, economic, and social interactions (North 1990).
3. The goal is to use a set of instruments that are correlated with
the endogenous regressors, but not with the error term. This paper
uses a standard set of instruments from the literature, including legal
origins, language, ethno-linguistic diversity, and some geographical
factors (for more details please see IMF 2003).
4. This essay also considers alternative measures of institutional
quality, namely the Heritage Foundation’s (2011) Index of Economic
Freedom.
5. These aggregate indicators are based on hundreds of individual
variables that measure various dimensions of governance and
institutional quality derived from views of household and firm survey
respondents. The paper then uses an Unobserved Components Model
(UCM) to combine these individual indicators into the six composite
measures of governance. The composite measures of governance
generated by the UCM are in units of a standard normal distribution,
with mean 0, standard deviation of 1, and running from
approximately -2.5 to 2.5, with higher values corresponding to better
institutional outcomes.
6. Based on Kodres and Narain (2010).
7. The work done by the IMF LEG’s Financial Integrity Group as
described in this chapter took place until mid-2006 and was
completed jointly by staff in LEG and in the then Monetary and
Financial Systems Department, who together now comprise the
Financial Integrity Group.
8. This list includes all of the countries identified in figure 5.1 with
shadow economies greater than 50 percent of GDP. Fund TA on
AML/CFT targets economies and subject areas where TA can make
the greatest impact.
References
Acemoglu, Daron, and James Robinson. 2012. Why Nations Fail: The
Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty. New York: Crown
Business.
De Soto, Hernando. 1989. The Other Path: The Invisible Revolution in
the Third World. New York: Harper Collins.
Friedman, E., S. Johnson, D. Kaufmann, and P. Zoido-Lobaton. 2000.
“Dodging the Grabbing Hand: The Determinants of Unofficial
Activity in 69 Countries.” Journal of Public Economics 76: 459–93.
Gwartney, James, Robert Lawson, and Joshua Hall. 2011. 2011
Economic Freedom Dataset, published in Economic Freedom of
the World: 2011 Annual Report. Fraser Institute.
http://www.freetheworld.com/datasets_efw.html.
Heritage Foundation. 2011. Index of Economic Freedom. Washington,
DC: Heritage Foundation.
International Labor Organization (ILO). 2011. Key Indicators of the
Labour Market. Geneva: ILO.
International Monetary Fund (IMF). 2003. “Growth and Institutions.”
World Economic Outlook, 95–128. Washington, DC: IMF.
———. 2009a. AML/CFT Methodology with FATF 40 + 9:
Recommendations, Interpretive Notes, and Best Practices.
Washington, DC: IMF.
———. 2009b. Anti-Money Laundering and Combating the Financing
of Terrorism (AML/CFT), Report of the Review of the Effectiveness
of the Program. Washington, DC: IMF.
Johnson, S., D. Kaufmann, and P. Zoido-Lobaton. 1998. “Regulatory
Discretion and the Unofficial Economy.” American Economic
Review 88 (2): 387–92.
Kaufmann, D., A. Kraay, and M. Mastruzzi. 2009. “Governance Matters
VIII: Aggregate and Individual Governance Indicators, 1996–
2008.” World Bank Policy Research Working Paper 4978.
Washington, DC: World Bank.
Kaufmann, D., A. Kraay, and P. Zoido-Lobaton. 1999. “Aggregating
Governance Indicators.” Policy Research Working Paper Series
2195. Washington, DC: World Bank.
Kodres, Laura, and Aditya Narain. 2010. Redesigning the Contours of
the Future Financial System. International Monetary Fund Staff
Position Note SPN/10/10.
North, D. 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic
Performance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Schneider, F. 2004. “The Size of the Shadow Economies of 145
Countries All over the World: First Results over the Period 1999 to
2003.” IZA Discussion Paper No. 1431. Bonn, DE: IZA.
http://ssrn.com/abstract=636661.
Schneider, F., A. Buehn, and C. Montenegro. 2010. “New Estimates
for the Shadow Economies All over the World.” International
Economic Journal 24 (4): 443–61.
Smith, P. 1994. “Assessing the Size of the Underground Economy:
The Statistics Canada Perspectives.” Canadian Economic Observer
7 (5).
World Bank. 2004. Doing Business in 2005: Removing the Obstacles
to Growth. Washington, DC: World Bank.
———. 2012. World Development Indicators Database. Washington,
DC: World Bank.
CHAPTER 6
References
Bellamy, Alex J. 2009. A Responsibility to Protect. Malden: Polity.
Canton, Santiago. 2009. “The Inter-American Commission on Human
Rights: 50 Years of Advances and the New Challenges.” Americas.
Summer.
Duffy, Helen. 2009. “Slavery Unveiled by ECOWAS Court.” Human
Rights Law Review 9: 151–70.
ECOSOC (Economic and Social Council). 2013. “Basic Facts about
NGO Status.” ECOSOC. Accessed August 17, 2013.
http://csonet.org/index.php?menu=100.
Evans, Gareth, 2012. “The International Crisis Group: The Role of a
Global NGO in Preventing and Resolving Deadly Conflict.” Gareth
Evans Professional Webpage, May 17.
http://www.gevans.org/speeches/speech471.html.
Farer, Tom J., and Felice Gaer. 1993. “The UN and Human Rights: At
the End of the Beginning.” In United Nations, Divided World: The
UN’s Roles in International Relations. 2nd ed. Edited by Adam
Roberts and Benedict Kingsbury. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Gershman, Carl, and Michael Allen. 2006. “The Assault on
Democracy Assistance.” Journal of Democracy 17 (2).
Hafner-Burton, Emilie M. 2013. Making Human Rights a Reality.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Haugen, Gary and Victor Boutros. 2010. “And Justice For All:
Enforcing Human Rights for the World’s Poor.” Foreign Affairs.
May/June.
ICG (International Crisis Group). 2013. “Trial by Error: Justice in
Post-Qadhafi Libya.” Brussels: International Crisis Group
Headquarters.
ICISS (International Commission on Intervention and State
Sovereignty). 2002. “The Responsibility to Protect: The Report of
the International Commission on Intervention and State
Sovereignty.” Ottawa: IDRC Books.
ILO (International Labor Organization). 2012. “New ILO Global
Estimate of Forced Labour: 20.9 Million Victims.” ILO. June.
http://www.ilo.org/global/about-the-
ilo/newsroom/news/WCMS_182109/lang--en/index.htm.
Kavanagh, Camino, and Bruce Jones. 2011. “Shaky Foundations: An
Assessment of the UN’s Rule of Law Support Agenda.” New York:
New York University Center on International Cooperation.
Keller, Helen, and Geir Ulfstein. 2012. UN Human Rights Treaty
Bodies: Law and Legitimacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Kethineni, Sesha, and Gail Diane Humiston. 2010. “Dalits, the
‘Oppressed People’ of India: How Are Their Social, Economic, and
Human Rights Addressed?” War Crimes, Genocide, and Crimes
against Humanity 4.
Khan, Irene. 2009. The Unheard Truth: Poverty and Human Rights.
New York: W. W. Norton and Company.
Kim, Jim Yong. 2014. “Discrimination By Law Carries a High Price.”
Washington Post. February 27.
Kravets, David. 2011. “Feds Say China’s Net Censorship Imposes
‘Barriers’ to Free Trade.” Wired. Accessed April 14, 2014.
http://www.wired.com/2011/10/china-censorship-trade-barrier/.
Kurlantzick, Joshua. 2011. “The Great Democracy Meltdown.” The
New Republic. June 9.
http://www.newrepublic.com/article/world/magazine/88632/failin
g-democracy-venezuela-arab-spring.
Lagon, Mark P. 2012. “A Global Trust for Rule of Law.” Council on
Foreign Relations Policy Innovation Memorandum (26). Accessed
September 1, 2013. http://www.cfr.org/rule-of-law/global-trust-
rule-law/p29170.
Lagon, Mark P., and Ryan Kaminski. 2013. “Clash of Elites: What Lies
Behind the Defamation Debates.” Georgetown Journal of
International Affairs 14 (1).
Lagon, Mark P., and William F. Schulz. 2012. “Conservatives, Liberals,
and Human Rights.” Policy Review (171): 23–32.
Lagon, Mark P., and David Shorr. 2007. “How to Keep from
Overselling or Underestimating the United Nations.” In Bridging
the Foreign Policy Divide, edited by Derek Chollet, Tod Lindberg,
and David Shorr. New York: Routledge.
Malloch-Brown, Mark. 2011. The Unfinished Global Revolution: The
Pursuit of a New International Politics. New York: Penguin Press.
McMahon, Edward R. 2012. “The Universal Periodic Review: A Work
in Progress: An Evaluation of the First Cycle of the New UPR
Mechanism of the United Nations Human Rights Council.” Berlin:
Friedrich-Ebert-Stiftung Dialogue on Globalization.
Newman, Edward, and Roland Rich. 2004. “Building Democracy with
UN Assistance: From Namibia to Iraq: Has the United Nations
Found the Right Formula for Promoting Democracy?” UN
Chronicle 41 (4).
OHCHR (Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights). 2014.
“Committee Against Torture.” Accessed April 14, 2014.
http://www.ohchr.org/EN/HRBodies/CAT/Pages/CATIntro.aspx.
———. 1984. “Convention Against Torture, and Other Cruel,
Inhuman or Degrading Treatment of Punishment.” Accessed April
14, 2014.
http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CAT.aspx.
———. 2011. “Discriminatory Laws and Practices and Acts of
Violence against Individuals Based on Their Sexual Orientation
and Gender Identity.” New York: Office of the High Commissioner
for Human Rights.
OSCE (Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe). 2007.
“Human Rights Defenders in the OSCE Region: Our Collective
Conscience.” Warsaw: OSCE Office for Democratic Institutions
and Human Rights.
Perez Solla, María Fernanda. 2009. “Slavery and Human Trafficking:
International Law and the World Bank.” World Bank. Social
Protection and Labor Discussion Paper.
Piccone, Ted. 2012. Catalysts for Change: How the U.N.’s
Independent Experts Promote Human Rights. Washington:
Brookings Institution.
Rice, Susan. 2012. “Testimony of Ambassador Susan E. Rice, U.S.
Permanent Representative to the United Nations, House
Subcommittee on Appropriations for State, Foreign Operations,
and Related Programs.” United States Mission to the United
Nations. March 20.
http://usun.state.gov/briefing/statements/186080.htm.
Rubenstein, Leonard. 2004. “How International Human Rights
Organizations Can Advance Economic, Social and Cultural Rights:
A Response to Kenneth Roth.” Human Rights Quarterly. 845–65.
Ruggie, John. 2013. Just Business: Multinational Corporations and
Human Rights. New York: W. W. Norton and Company.
Smith-Cannoy, Heather. 2012. Insincere Commitments: Human
Rights Treaties, Abusive States, and Citizen Activism.
Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
Tamayo, Juan. 2013. “Watchdog Group: Cuba Cheated on Its UN
Human Rights Review.” Miami Herald. May 3. Accessed April 14,
2014.
http://www.miamiherald.com/2013/05/02/3377370/watchdog-
group-cuba-cheated-on.html.
Tavares, Rodrigo. 2009. Regional Security: The Capacity of Regional
Organizations. New York: Routledge.
Trujillo, César Gaviria. 2012. “The Inter-American Democratic Charter
at Ten: A Commitment by the Americas to the Defense and
Promotion of Democracy.” Latin American Policy 3 (1).
UNDP (UN Development Program). 2006. “The Arab Human
Development Report 2005: Toward the Rise of Women in the
Arab World.” United Nations Development Program, Regional
Bureau for Arab States. Amman: National Press.
———. 2010. “15 Years after Landmark Gathering, Women Still Lack
Equal Rights.” March 1. New York: United Nations.
UNHRC (United Nations Human Rights Council). 2011. “UN Human
Rights Council Resolution 17/14: Human Rights and Transnational
Corporations and Other Business Enterprises.” Geneva: United
Nations.
UNODC (United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime). 2012. “Human
Trafficking, Organized Crime and the Multibillion Sale of People.”
Vienna: United Nations. Accessed September 3, 2013.
http://www.unodc.org/unodc/en/frontpage/2012/July/human-
trafficking_-organized-crime-and-the-multibillion-dollar-sale-of-
people.html.
UNSC (UN Security Council). 2011. “UN Security Council Resolution
1973.” New York: United Nations.
UN Women. 2013. “Facts and Figures: Leadership and Political
Participation.” UN Women. Accessed August 17, 2013.
http://www.unwomen.org/en/what-we-do/leadership-and-
political-participation/facts-and-figures.
Warrick, Joby, and Karen DeYoung. 2009. “Obama Reverses Bush
Policies on Detention and Interrogation.” Washington Post.
January 23. Accessed April 14, 2014.
http://articles.washingtonpost.com/2009-01-
23/news/36920354_1_executive-orders-detention-and-
interrogation-task-force.
CHAPTER 7
What Is Terrorism?
Over the years, the international community has repeatedly sought
to develop a definition of terrorism. But after many lengthy debates
at international conferences and in other fora, states,
intergovernmental organizations (IGOs), and other major actors
have still not been able to reach a consensus on a legal definition.
For purposes of this work, however, I would offer the following
definition: Terrorism is the threat or use of force undertaken for
political purposes by a nonstate actor that intentionally targets
civilians and other noncombatants in violation of existing law relating
to the conduct of hostilities (Arend 2002).
This definition, in my view, captures the essence of what we
commonly call terrorism. First, terrorism involves force—either
threatened or realized. This requirement is inherent in the violent
nature of terrorism. Second, this threat or use of force is undertaken
for political purposes. This is an important criterion that
differentiates terrorism from criminal activity, which is undertaken for
private gain. Third, terrorism is something undertaken by a nonstate
actor. It is true that there can be state-sponsored terrorism, but
there must be some nonstate group involved. Fourth, terrorism
means the targeting of civilians or other noncombatants in violation
of law. One of the hallmarks of terrorism is that it attacks legally
protected persons and places—civilians, commercial airliners,
subways, commuter trains, shopping malls.
It should be noted that this definition of terrorism does not
include forcible actions by nonstate actors when they are directed
against legitimate military targets. There is a long philosophical
tradition of a right of revolution—allowing persons to use force
against their government.2 Indeed, the American Declaration of
Independence specifically acknowledges this right. If such forcible
actions are taken against military targets, such actions do not
constitute terrorism.
Conclusion
Sadly, violence by nonstate actors in pursuit of political aims seems
to be a permanent feature of the twenty-first century. Far too often,
however, discussions of terrorism get lost in ideological or even legal
debates and a fundamental point is missed: Terrorism by definition is
an affront to human dignity. When viewed through the lens of
human dignity, the negative effects of terrorism on the agency and
affirmation of persons is clear. At the same time, a human dignity
lens allows us to affirm that the terrorists themselves—as well as
those who live with and care for them—are still persons, worthy of
having their dignity preserved.
In order to combat terrorism in the short and long term, it is
necessary that both traditional and nontraditional institutions act in
partnership. Actions by states alone are not sufficient—nor are
actions by more traditional IGOs such as the UN. Those actors
frequently have limited recourses, circumscribed geographic reach,
and in some cases insufficient legitimacy. Instead, states, IGOs,
NGOs, and hybrid institutions need to work in partnership to both
combat contemporary acts of terrorism and to address the global
conditions that set the stage for future terrorists to emerge. Human
dignity demands it.
Notes
1. I am indebted to Dr. Elizabeth Grimm Arsenault for her lectures
on the origins of terrorism.
2. We tend to think of John Locke as one of the great
philosophers supporting a right to revolution, but several medieval
political thinkers, such as John of Salisbury, argued that violence
could be permissibly undertaken against a tyrant.
3. One applicable section of US federal law can be found at 18
USC § 2339A: providing material support to terrorists. It holds:
References
Arend, Anthony Clark. 2002. “International Law and Rogue States:
The Failure of the United Nations Charter Framework.” New
England Law Review 36 (4): 740.
Arend, Anthony Clark, and Robert J. Beck. 1993. International Law
and the Use of Force: Beyond the United Nations Charter
Paradigm. London: Routledge.
Dinstein, Yoram. 2004. The Conduct of Hostilities under the Law of
International Armed Conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Greenberg, Karen J., and Joshua L. Dratel, eds. 2005. The Torture
Papers: The Road to Abu Ghraib. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kernig, Claus-Dieter. 1978. “Theorie und Praktisch der Terroristischen
und Anarchistischen Bewegungen [Theory and Practice of
Terrorist and Anarchist Movements]” (lecture). Universität Trier.
Fall.
Lagon, Mark P. 2012. “A Global Trust for the Rule of Law.” Policy
Innovation Memorandum No. 26. Council on Foreign Relations.
Accessed November 4, 2013. http://www.cfr.org/rule-of-
law/global-trust-rule-law/p29170.
Lagon, Mark P., and William F. Schulz. 2012. “Conservatives, Liberals,
and Human Rights.” Policy Review, 171.
PART II
EMERGING INSTITUTIONS
Part II treats what this volume terms “emerging institutions.” These
include various private sector, philanthropic, civil society, and hybrid
institutions. While some of these institutions have been in existence
for some time, such as the Roman Catholic Church or multinational
corporations, in today’s neomedieval world they are properly
considered emerging because they have become engaged in new,
innovative ways in promoting human dignity.
On one hand, the next seven chapters show the impact of actors
separate from international government organizations, such as
chapter 12 by Thomas Banchoff, who focuses on the Catholic Church
and other major faith traditions; chapter 13 by Nicole Bibbins
Sedaca, who addresses faith-based, programmatic,
nongovernmental organizations; and chapter 14 by Michael Samway,
who discusses multinational corporations. On the other hand, two
chapters show emerging institutions collaborating with traditional
ones—such as chapter 8 by Rosalía Rodriguez-García, who considers
UNAIDS and the Global Fund to Fight AIDS, Tuberculosis and
Malaria; and chapter 11 by Mark P. Lagon, who treats institutional
partnerships to combat human trafficking.
Human dignity inspires the work of these emerging institutions.
For instance, chapter 9 by Raj Desai and Homi Kharas explores how
lenders to developing world entrepreneurs are moved and
themselves empowered by new private sector institutions employing
crowdsourcing. So too, Banchoff’s and Bibbins Sedaca’s chapters
reveal the mobilizing power of dignity in faith-based institutions’
work.
Finally, the chapters in part II reveal important yet different types
of impacts on human dignity. Some emerging institutions help
marginalized people seize agency and social recognition, such as the
nimble private sector development entities that Desai and Kharas
examine. Others can stop threats to dignity or reduce complicity in
such threats, such as the institutional reforms to help stateless
persons—a category of human beings denied access to justice—as
proposed in chapter 10 by Benjamin Boudreaux. Samway
enumerates internet companies’ due diligence measures to avoid
helping states infringe on civil liberties. Still other institutions can
reverse the stigma or blame placed on those victimized. Here, Lagon
shows how multistakeholder partnerships can stop human trafficking
victims from being reflexively treated as criminals or from being
deported, and Rodriguez-García shows how UNAIDS and the Global
Fund overcome the social stigma on populations most vulnerable to
HIV/AIDS. Emerging institutions show promise to avert a shameful
double denial of individuals’ dignity.
CHAPTER 8
Much has been said already about the social and economic
impact of the HIV/AIDS epidemic and the threat that it
represents for security and stability in the world. The
projections are truly frightening: HIV/AIDS will kill more
people this decade than all the wars and disasters in the past
50 years. There is no doubt that the pandemic is a global
disaster of catastrophic proportions. But this simply must not
become a cold debate around numbers and figures. Instead
we must make this an ethical debate and move away from
the ethics of mere survival to the ethics of dignity.… The fact
that the discourse has turned into discussion on how much
money is needed or what types of interventions we should or
should not do is indecent and an affront to the dignity of
every person who is living with or has been affected by
HIV/AIDS. (International Federation of Red Cross and Red
Crescent Societies 2003)
Conclusion
Looking back at the early writings on AIDS and human dignity one is
struck by the challenge of appraising progress. There has been
progress in human rights and human dignity, but it has been slow
and patchy.
On the one hand, there is a deeper understanding of what Mann
named the societal nature of the pandemic and the societal
preconditions for HIV vulnerability (Mann 1999, 223). One could
argue that by being responsive to the needs of people they are
meant to serve—enabling them to improve their agency—UNAIDS
and the Global Fund are positioned to work with stakeholders and
country governments to achieve positive change in countries.
On the other hand, significant local impacts are still elusive.
Stating that discrimination must end is not enough. To the extent
that UN resolutions are not legally binding, it falls on national
policymakers to introduce concrete changes in their sociolegal
system. A few have succeeded, but in many countries the legal
environment related to HIV/AIDS has changed relatively little in the
past twenty years. Purposeful action on a broad scale is needed to
repeal discriminatory laws and replace them with antidiscriminatory
ones. If the international community is serious about zero
discrimination, the work on AIDS and human dignity must be
implemented with evidence, realizable goals, sound strategies, and
significant resources—in other words, on a scale more typical of
biomedical interventions (Stemple 2008).
Among the many challenges that scaling up faces, two are
critical. One, as mentioned above, is adequate funding. If actions to
improve the legal environment and to undertake concrete programs
are not adequately funded, it will be difficult to see impact on human
dignity. The other critical challenge is political will. It is usually easier
to commit to broad principles globally than to take action on those
principles locally, and those policymakers who take action face
serious obstacles when they try to uproot long-held national laws
and societal practices that penalize certain behaviors. This is
compounded by the fact that activists in civil society, a key instigator
of change at the local level, often have their own hands tied by
belonging to groups who themselves might be penalized by local
laws. This chapter argues that human rights need to be taken as
seriously in HIV/AIDS programming and funding as biomedical and
prevention programs in order to see tangible results for human
dignity.
This look at HIV/AIDS and human dignity shows that for global
institutions there will always be tension between the need to bring
stakeholders together globally around fundamental principles and
the imperative to translate these principles into concrete actions to
achieve local impacts. Some national governments have
demonstrated the wisdom to devise and implement changes to
safeguard or restore human dignity. Global institutions can make a
difference by recognizing and supporting these efforts with adequate
resources, normative guidance, and good practices. Equally
important, they can empower civil society to engage in those
countries that are more recalcitrant regarding legal and societal
changes and provide adequate support.
Despite slow progress, active multilateral partnerships,
unprecedented engagement of civil society, UNAIDS’s explicit goal of
zero discrimination, and the Global Fund’s support of human agency
taken together appear to be paving a path toward improvements in
human dignity. Global institutions are going beyond protecting
people who are vulnerable to HIV to empowering them.
Notes
The author thanks Mark P. Lagon and Matthew Carnes for their
valuable inputs and comments.
1. This book is recommended reading for anyone interested in
the evolution of HIV/AIDS and human rights.
2. Jonathan Mann was particularly interested in the effect of
health policies on human rights, the health impact of human rights
violations, and the inextricable connection between promoting and
protecting health and rights.
3. In January 2003, under President George W. Bush the United
States committed US$15 billion over five years to address the
international AIDS epidemic. Full implementation of PEPFAR began in
June 2004 and by 2012 the United States was a leading financier
having invested over US$37 billion in bilateral funding and over US$7
billion in the Global Fund. Fact Sheet, November 29, 2012.
Washington, DC,
http://www.state.gov/r/pa/prs/ps/2012/11/201195.htm.
4. In this chapter “tension” does not imply “opposite.” It refers to
the forces that influence possibly equally important demands.
Different actors balance these tensions differently, which in turn
affects the evolution of HIV/AIDS, human rights, and human dignity.
5. See Lagon and Kaminski’s chapter 6 in this book.
6. A “theory of change” is a specific and measurable description
of a social change. It depicts a causal outcomes-based model that
articulates underlying assumptions and hypotheses about why
something will cause something else. Theories of change capture
complex initiatives. They often start with a goal and then link
outcomes and activities to explain how and why the desired change
is expected to come about. Consult: http://www.theoryofchange.org.
7. UNAIDS brings together the resources of its Secretariat (based
in Geneva) and eleven UN system organizations: ILO, UNDP,
UNESCO, UNHCR, UNICEF, UNFPA, UNODC, UN Women, the World
Bank, WFP, and WHO,
http://www.unaids.org/en/aboutunaids/unaidscosponsors/.
8. Gabriel Jaramillo was an able general manager of the Global
Fund during 2012. Since January 2013, the executive director of the
Global Fund is Mark Dybul, who in 2006–2009 served as the US
global AIDS coordinator, which includes PEPFAR.
9. Publications that bring human rights thinking together with
sound public health policy in a clear and consistent way are: The
International Guidelines on HIV/AIDS and Human Rights 1998
(HR/PUB/98/1) and 2006 (consolidated version)
(http://www.unaids.org) and The AIDS Pandemic: Complacency,
Injustice and Unfulfilled Expectations, by Lawrence O. Gostin
(University of North Carolina Press, 2004).
10. See the web pages of these agencies under jobs or
employment.
11. Social transformation refers to individual and societal
processes. Within the social system, transformation refers to large-
scale social change leading to cultural reforms. At the individual level
it refers to a reciprocal relationship whereby people are correctly
identified with the cultural expectations of their particular class
membership. It requires that individuals have their social position be
validated by others.
12. The People Living with HIV Stigma Index is a research tool
used to capture data on HIV-positive people’s experiences and
perceptions regarding stigma and discrimination,
http://www.stigmaindex.org.
References
Africa Science News Service. 2006. “International Civil Society
Denounce UN Meeting on AIDS as a Failure.” Accessed
September 26, 2013.
http://africanscience.blogspot.com/2006/06/international-civil-
society-denounce.html.
All Africa. 2013. “Africa: Most Reforms Already Implemented,
Jaramillo Says in Farewell Letter.” All Africa. February 18.
http://allafrica.com/stories/201302180614.html.
Black, Robert. 2013. “The Future of the US Response to Global
HIV/AIDS.” Lancet 382 (9894): 751–53.
Derrick, Deborah. 2013. “Better Than Ever, Together.” The Huffington
Post. April 1. http://www.huffingtonpost.com/deborah-
derrick/better-than-ever-together_b_2992982.html.
Dietrich, John W. 2007. “The Politics of PEPFAR: The President’s
Emergency Plan for AIDS Relief.” Ethics & International Affairs 21
(3): 277–92.
Economist. 2012. “The Global Fund Heal Thyself: Grappling with a
Controversial Malaria Programme.” Economist, November 24.
http://www.economist.com/news/science-and-
technology/21567054-grappling-controversial-malaria-
programme-heal-thyself.
Global Development Alliance. 2001. “USAID: Strategies for Conflict
Prevention.” Discussion paper.
Global Fund. 2008. Strategy for Ensuring Gender Equality in the
Response to HIV/AIDS, Tuberculosis and Malaria. Geneva: The
Global Fund to Fight AIDS, Tuberculosis and Malaria.
———. 2009. Strategy in Relation to Sexual Orientation and Gender
Identities (SOGI). Geneva: The Global Fund to Fight AIDS,
Tuberculosis and Malaria.
———. 2011a. Information Note: HIV and Human Rights. Geneva:
The Global Fund to Fight AIDS, Tuberculosis and Malaria.
———. 2011b. Response to the Evaluation of the Global Fund’s
Gender Equality and Sexual Orientation and Gender Identities
(SOGI) Strategies. Geneva: The Global Fund to Fight AIDS,
Tuberculosis and Malaria.
———. 2012. Strategic Investments for Impact: Global Fund Results
Report. Geneva: The Global Fund to Fight AIDS, Tuberculosis and
Malaria.
Gostin, Lawrence O. 1998. “A Tribute to Jonathan Mann: Health and
Human Rights in the AIDS Pandemic.” Journal of Law and Medical
Ethics 26 (3): 256-58.
———. 2003. “The Global Reach of HIV/AIDS: Science, Politics,
Economics, and Research.” Emory International Law Review 17:
1-54.
Gruskin, Sofia. 2002. “The UN General Assembly Special Session on
HIV/AIDS: Were Some Lessons of the Last 20 Years Ignored?”
American Journal of Public Health 92 (3): 337-38.
Gruskin, Sofia, Aart Hendriks, and Katarina Tomasevski. 1996.
“Human Rights and Responses to HIV/AIDS.” In AIDS in the
World Two, edited by Jonathan M. Mann and Daniel Tarantola.
New York: Oxford University Press.
IGLHRC. 2007. Off the Map: How HIV/AIDS Programming Is Failing
Same-Sex Practicing People. New York: International Gay and
Lesbian Human Rights Commission.
Institute of Medicine (IOM). 2013. “PEPFAR Evaluation Brief.” IOM.
Accessed September 26, 2013.
http://www.iom.edu/Reports/2013/Evaluation-of-PEPFAR.aspx.
International Federation of Red Cross and Red Crescent Societies.
2003. “HIV/AIDS, Human Dignity, Global Fund—How to Respond
to the Challenge of HIV/AIDS.” Accessed September 26, 2013.
http://www.ifrc.org/en/news-and-media/opinions-and-
positions/speeches/2003/hivaids-human-dignity-global-fund---
how-to-respond-to-the-challenge-of-hivaids/.
Kay, Julie F, and Ashley Jackson. 2008. Sex, Lies and Stereotypes:
How Abstinence-Only Programs Harm Women and Girls. New
York: Legal Momentum.
Lebech, Mette. 2004. “What is Human Dignity?” Maynooth
Philosophical Papers. 59–69.
Mann, Jonathan M. 1999. “Human Rights and AIDS: The Future of
the Pandemic.” In Health and Human Rights: A Reader, edited by
Jonathan M. Mann, Michael A. Grodin, Sofia Gruskin, and George
J. Annas. New York: Routledge.
Meernik, James, Rosa Aloisi, Marsha Sowell, and Angela Nichols.
2012. “The Impact of Human Rights Organizations on Naming
and Shaming Campaigns.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 56 (2):
233–56.
Nussbaum, Martha. 2010. From Disgust to Humanity: Sexual
Orientation and Constitutional Law (Inalienable Rights). United
Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
Obama, Barack. 2011. “Remarks by the President on World AIDS
Day.” Washington, DC: White House. Accessed September 26,
2013. http://www.whitehouse.gov/photos-and-
video/video/2011/12/01/president-obama-world-aids-
day#transcript.
Patterson, David, and Leslie London. 2002. “International Law,
Human Rights and HIV/AIDS.” Bulletin of the World Health
Organization 80 (12): 964–69.
Rodriguez-García, Rosalía. 2002. “Can Diplomacy Serve as a Bridge
for Peace?” International Affairs Review 11 (1): 111–12.
Rodriguez-García, Rosalía, René Bonnel, David Wilson, and N’Della
N’Jie. 2013. Investing in Communities Achieves Results: Findings
from an Evaluation of Community Responses to HIV and AIDS.
Washington, DC: The World Bank.
Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Alfred A.
Knopf Inc.
Stemple, Lara. 2008. “Health and Human Rights in Today’s Fight
against HIV/AIDS.” AIDS 22 (2): S113-S121.
Summers, Todd. 2013. “The IOM’s PEPFAR Evaluation: Implications
for the Global Fund.” Global Health Policy Center at Center for
Strategic and International Studies. Accessed September 26,
2013. http://www.smartglobalhealth.org/blog/entry/the-ioms-
pepfar-evaluation-implications-for-the-global-fund/.
UNAIDS. 2006. International Guidelines on HIV/AIDS and Human
Rights. Consolidated version. Geneva: United Nations
Cosponsored Programme for HIV/AIDS and the UN Office of the
High Commissioner for Human Rights.
———. 2010. UNAIDS Global Report. Geneva: United Nations
Cosponsored Programme for HIV/AIDS.
———. 2011. AIDS at 30: Nations at the Crossroads. Geneva: United
Nations Cosponsored Programme for HIV/AIDS.
———. 2012. Together We Will End AIDS. Geneva: United Nations
Cosponsored Programme for HIV/AIDS.
———. 2013. “Feature Story: Four-Year Evaluation of PEPFAR
Concludes.” UNAIDS. Accessed September 26, 2013.
http://www.unaids.org/en/resources/presscentre/featurestories/2
013/february/20130225iompepfar/.
UNAIDS/WHO. 2010. Technical Guidance Note for Global Fund HIV
Proposals: Reduction of HIV Stigma and Discrimination. Geneva:
United Nations Cosponsored Programme for HIV/AIDS and World
Health Organization.
United Nations. 2000. UN Millennium Declaration. Accessed
September 26, 2013.
http://www.un.org/en/development/devagenda/millennium.shtml
; http://www.un.org/millenniumgoals/.
———. 2001. “Declaration of Commitment on HIV/AIDS.” United
Nations General Assembly Special Session on HIV/AIDS, June 25–
27. Accessed September 26, 2013.
http://www.unaids.org/en/media/unaids/contentassets/dataimpo
rt/publications/irc-pub03/aidsdeclaration_en.pdf.
———. 2006. “Political Declaration on HIV/AIDS.” United Nations
General Assembly A/Res/60/262, June 15.
———. 2011. Report of the UN Secretary-General—Uniting for
Universal Access: Towards Zero New HIV Infections, Zero
Discrimination and Zero AIDS-related Deaths. New York: United
Nations, March 28.
UN Plus. 2013. “Missions and Objectives.” UN Plus. Accessed
September 10, 2013. http://www.unplus.org/wp/about-
unplus/what-we-do.
World Bank. 2000. Intensifying Action against HIV/AIDS in Africa:
Responding to a Development Crisis. Washington, DC: The World
Bank.
———. 2007a. The Africa Multi-Country AIDS Program 2000–2006.
Washington, DC: The World Bank.
———. 2007b. Legal Aspects of HIV/AIDS: A Guide for Policy and
Law Reform. Washington, DC: The World Bank.
———. 2011. The Global HIV Epidemics among Men Who Have Sex
with Men. Washington, DC: The World Bank.
CHAPTER 9
Following the end of the Second World War until very recently,
international development assistance aid was mainly provided by
two types of institutions: donor agencies of richer countries and
multilateral development banks whose capital was contributed
largely by governments of richer countries. But between 2000 and
2011, international private giving by US-based corporate and
independent foundations and individuals more than doubled. Along
with foundations, nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), religious
groups, and charities in the United States contributed $39 billion to
development causes in 2011. By comparison, the World Bank lent
about $43 billion and the United States disbursed about $31 billion in
economic assistance (World Bank 2011; Hudson Institute 2013). Our
chief aim here is to examine the implications of this dramatically
changed aid landscape for global poverty alleviation as well as for
human dignity in international affairs. We argue that although there
remains some uncertainty about the effects of private aid on
development and on the motivations of private aid givers, there is
reason to believe that private aid advances the centrality of personal
agency as the focus of donor-recipient aid transactions both for
individual taxpayers and for beneficiaries. For taxpayers, private aid
most obviously offers opportunities for greater control over funding
and allocation that is not possible through the normal route that
official aid takes in being transferred from rich-country taxpayers to
poor-country beneficiaries. For recipients, private aid fundamentally
involves dignity-enhancing, person-to-person relationships that often
trump sovereign considerations of strategic and commercial interest
in allocating of funds.
Coordination
The public economics literature suggests that collective action
problems may block private giving for worthy causes because each
individual, behaving rationally, tries to free ride on others’ generosity.
Governments can overcome the collective action problem by taxing
everyone and providing grants to the causes to which individuals
would want to give. One common empirical approach is to test
whether individual donations are smaller in areas where government
grants are larger. Such crowding out is evidence of collective action
problems at work.
A review of the literature by Bekkers and Wiepking (2007) finds
evidence that crowding out in domestic charities is significant. Their
summary looks mostly at cross-section studies. Garrett and Rhine
(2007) analyze time series for 1965–2003 and reach the same
conclusion. In the long run, cointegration tests show that increased
government spending crowds out charitable giving, especially in the
education sector. In the short run, however, the effects are weaker
and not significant. The authors suggest that it may take time for
individuals to get full information on what the government is doing.
Andreoni and Payne (2008) also confirm the crowding-out effect
in a large sample of charities. They demonstrate that crowding out
occurs through two channels: classic crowding out (where donors
feel less willing to give) and fundraising crowding out (where grant-
receiving organizations reduce their activity to collect donations).
Their evidence suggests that fundraising crowding out accounts for
68 percent of the observed crowding-out effect.
This evidence, however, relates to giving through NGOs
compared to government tax-and-spend programs. It does not
directly look at new forms of private giving. For these newer types of
private assistance, the premise is that the act of individual giving
gives pleasure directly to the donor—that is, assuming that giving is
altruistic. If so, it would suggest that the collective-action constraint
to international aid is minimal.
Crowdfunding Aid
As we have seen, official aid, although funded by taxpayers, gives
citizens little say over aid allocations. Compared to official aid,
private aid is by definition more sensitive to the preferences of
philanthropic-minded individuals who determine allocations across
countries and, within countries, across sectors, projects, and
individuals; in short, the aid giver is empowered. In recent years,
private development aid has been facilitated by the availability of
peer-to-peer, internet-based platforms, which bundle large amounts
of small, individual contributions for investments, grants, or loans.
The bundling of funds is generally done through internet-based
social networks. From the United States, internet-based companies
such as Global Giving, Kiva, Wokai, and Zidisha, have channeled
millions of dollars to individuals and partner organizations in
developing countries.
Crowd funded private aid also offers the promise of a much
shorter route from giver to recipient. Internet-based platforms offer
a direct matching between the two. Although there are some
differences in approach across platforms (e.g., Kiva focuses on
individuals or entrepreneurs whereas Global Giving highlights the
worthiness of the projects they are proposing for funding), all
enhance social recognition of the beneficiaries’ worth and catalyze
their agency. Donors contribute directly to those activities rather
than to individuals. In both cases, the flow of funds route is short.
The money goes from an individual to the internet-based bundler,
where it is pooled and transferred to a financial or project
intermediary in the recipient country that then disburses it to the
final beneficiaries. The long route of passing through government
bureaucracies is avoided.
Conclusion
In this chapter we have argued that, in the new aid landscape,
newer forms of private aid enhance the personal agency of both
donors and recipients in aid transactions. Donors, who are better
able to select countries, sectors, projects, and in many cases
individuals to whom funds (and loans) can be given, are afforded
greater control over allocative decisions. Beneficiaries who can
provide input and information directly to donors are better able to
influence funding decisions and have greater flexibility in the timing
and disbursement of funds, that is, accorded agency. Through these
institutions, they are accorded social recognition too, helping them
realize dignity. For both groups, these person-to-person relationships
constitute a shorter route than official aid normally takes. The result
can economize on coordination, transaction, and agency costs of
official aid.
Private aid can make a difference, but it is by no means a
panacea for all that ails the world’s poor. For all the amounts that
have been granted, there has been little evaluation of the cost-
effectiveness of private aid, and there are few examples of privately-
funded programs being expanded in ways needed to make a dignity-
building dent in global poverty. The history of global charity has also
had its share of scandals involving misappropriations of funds and
theft. And the universe of foundations, charities, educational
organizations, and private and voluntary organizations may be too
crowded and too fragmented to make a real difference on a large
scale.
There are four possible implications of the spread of private aid
for the alleviation of global poverty. First, private aid functions best
as a complement to, rather than a substitute for, official aid. Indeed,
there are many things that private aid cannot support in recipient
countries; development strategies, debt reduction, and so on are
generally beyond the scope of private aid modalities. Private aid also
raises separate (but related) issues of accountability compared to
official aid.
Second, private aid is supported by new types of global
institutions that rely principally on multilayer connectedness between
individuals—linked through social networks that, supported by
internet technology and social media, now span the globe—rather
than on bilateral or multilateral intergovernmental relations.
Although many of the longer-term implications of the expansion in
influence of these global private institutions are uncertain, the
private sector has grown from a small player in development
assistance to a major, dynamic force. Yet the world has little noticed.
Annually, approximately 800 press credentials were issued for the
World Bank-IMF annual or spring meetings. Meanwhile, at the Global
Philanthropy Forum (GPF), few if any members of the press were on
hand. This lopsidedness is unfortunate. The fact is that the
attendees who meet at the GPF will soon give more aid to the
world’s poor than the Bretton-Woods institutions.
Third, although at present private aid is not connected to policy
reforms in the way official aid is, it is plausible that the proliferation
of private aid will encourage governments in recipient countries to
reform in order to permit individual or group beneficiaries to take
advantage of these new forms of aid. Pressures to permit greater
cross-border capital flows, for example, can be driven by citizens
who do not wish to be deprived of the benefits of peer-to-peer
financial flows—whether they are remittances, microloans, or private
grants.
Fourth, it is also possible that private aid will make foreign aid
more competitive. For decades, poor developing nations have faced
a take-it-or-leave-it attitude from international financial institutions
and official donors and were forced to deal exclusively with a
particular official bureaucracy on development projects. Private aid
now can offer alternative channels for development assistance. But
to make this competition work, recipient countries must be free to
choose whether aid is channeled through an official government
project or through a more efficient NGO provider. Recipients of aid
must also be able to rely on benchmarks that compare the
effectiveness of private and official aid programs.
But a competitive aid system also requires a better understanding
of what works and what doesn’t. Neither the demand side—the
priority needs of the underserved—nor the supply side—who is doing
what and for which communities—has been mapped out at the
country level. Without that, it is inevitable that both public and
private aid providers will fail to provide systemic change and will fail
to help poor nations develop their own capabilities, both of which
are needed for sustained poverty reduction and greater realization of
dignity in practice. These are the efforts to which the global
development community should dedicate itself—not to the
maintenance of the current inflexible foreign aid system but to its
transformation into a system of global institutions that are both
flexible and dignity enhancing for both donors and recipients.
Notes
The authors thank Mark P. Lagon and Michael Morfit for valuable
comments on earlier drafts.
1. The remaining 41 percent of funds have still not been
classified by use.
2. Formerly known as Christian Children’s Fund.
3. See the treatment of Omidyar-funded Humanity United
underwriting NGO partnerships to combat human trafficking in
chapter 11 in this book by Mark P. Lagon.
4. On these problems, see Wenar (2006).
References
Alm, James. 1985. “The Welfare Cost of the Underground Economy.”
Economic Inquiry 23 (2): 243-63.
Andreoni, James, and A. Abigail Payne. 2008. “Crowding out Both
Sides of the Philanthropy Market.” Mimeo. Accessed September
22, 2013.
http://econ.ucsd.edu/~jandreon/WorkingPapers/andreoni_payne
2.pdf.
Bekkers, Rene, and Pamala Wiepking. 2007. “Generosity and
Philanthropy: A Literature Review.” Mimeo. Accessed September
22, 2013. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?
abstract_id=1015507.
Bonbright, David, Natalia Kiryttopoulou, and Lindsay Iversen. 2008.
Online Philanthropy Markets: From ‘Feel-Good’ Giving to Effective
Social Investing? London: Keystone.
Büthe, Tim, Solomon Major, and Andre de Mello e Souza. 2012. “The
Politics of Private Foreign Aid: Humanitarian Principles, Economic
Development Objectives, and Organizational Interests in the
Allocation of Private Aid by NGOs.” International Organization 66
(44): 571-607.
Chong, Alberto, and Mark Gradstein. 2008. “What Determines
Foreign Aid? The Donors’ Perspective.” Journal of Development
Economics 87 (1): 1–13.
Dreher, Axel, Peter Nunnenkamp, Hannes Oehler, and Johannes
Weisser. 2009. “Acting Autonomously or Mimicking the State and
Peers: A Panel Tobit Analysis of Financial Dependence and Aid
Allocation by Swiss NGOs.” Working Paper No. 2617. Munich:
CESifo.
Easterly, William. 2005. “How to Assess the Needs for Aid?” Paper
for the 3rd AFD/EUDN Conference. Paris, December 14.
Facchini, Giovanni, and Anna M. Mayda. 2008. “From Individual
Attitudes towards Migrants to Migration Policy Outcomes: Theory
and Evidence.” Economic Policy 23 (56): 651–713.
Fleck, Robert, and Christopher Kilby. 2001. “Foreign Aid and
Domestic Politics.” Southern Economic Association 67 (3): 598–
617.
Garrett, Thomas, and Russell Rhine. 2007. “Does Government
Spending Really Crowd Out Charitable Contributions? New Time
Series Evidence.” Working Paper No. 2007–012. Federal Reserve
Bank of St. Louis.
Giving USA. 2012. Annual Report on Philanthropy. Chicago: Giving
USA Foundation.
Government Accountability Office (GOA). 2007. “Analysis of
Millennium Challenge Corporation Compact Disbursements
through March 2007.” Letter to congressional committees, May
14.
Hartley, Thomas, and Bruce Russett. 1992. “Public Opinion and the
Common Defense: Who Governs Military Spending in the United
States?” American Political Science Review 86 (4).
Hill, Kim Quaile. 1998. “The Policy Agenda of the President and the
Mass Public: A Research Validation and Extension.” American
Journal of Political Science 42: 1328–34.
Hudson Institute. 2013. The Index of Global Philanthropy and
Remittances. Washington, DC: Center for Global Prosperity.
Keohane, Robert, and Joseph Nye, Jr. 2000. “Introduction.” In
Governance in a Globalizing World, edited by Joseph Nye, Jr. and
John Donahue. Washington, DC: Brookings Press.
Koch, Dirk-Jan, Axel Dreher, Peter Nunnenkamp, and Rainer Thiele.
2008. “Keeping a Low Profile: What Defines the Allocation of Aid
by NGOs.” Working Paper No. 191. Zurich: KOF Swiss Economic
Institute.
Kono, Daniel. 2008. “Does Public Opinion Affect Trade Policy?”
Business and Politics 10 (2): 1224–26.
Lawrence, Steven, Aglernon Austin, and Reina Mukai. 2007.
Foundation Growth and Giving Estimates. New York: The
Foundation Center.
Lindelow, Magnus, Inna Kushnarova, and Kai Kaiser. 2006.
“Measuring Corruption in the Health Sector.” In Global Corruption
Report 2006. Cambridge: Transparency International/Cambridge
UP.
Lumsdaine, David H. 1993. Moral Vision in International Politics: The
Foreign Aid Regime, 1949–1989. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Mansfield, Edward, and Diana Mutz. 2009. “Support for Free Trade:
Self-lnterest, Sociotropic Politics, and Out-Group Anxiety.”
International Organization 63 (3): 425–57.
Milner, Helen, Daniel Nielson, and Michael Findley. 2013. “Which
Devil in Development? A Randomized Study of Citizen Actions
Supporting Foreign Aid in Uganda.” Mimeo. Accessed October 4,
2013. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?
abstract_id=2134409.
Milner, Helen, and Dustin Tingley. 2010. “The Political Economy of
US Foreign Aid: American Legislators and the Domestic Politics of
Aid.” Economics and Politics 20 (2): 200–32.
Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD).
2011. “Aid Effectiveness 2005–10: Progress in Implementing the
Paris Declaration.” Paris: OECD.
Ramsay, Clay, Steven Weber, Steven Kull, and Evan Lewis. 2009.
“American Public Opinion and Global Health.” College Park, MD:
Program on International Policy Attitudes.
Renz, Loren, and Jose Atienza. 2006. “International Grantmaking
Update.” New York: Foundation Center.
Roodman, David. 2006. “Tax Policies to Promote Private Charitable
Giving in DAC Countries.” Working Paper No. 82. Washington:
Center for Global Development.
Sobel, Richard. 2001. The Impact of Public Opinion on US Foreign
Policy since Vietnam: Constraining the Colossus. Ithaca, NY:
Oxford University Press.
Tingley, Dustin. 2007. Preferences over Foreign Aid Funding: Survey
Evidence from Norway. Working paper. Princeton University.
———. 2009. “Donors and Domestic Politics: Political and Economic
Influences on Foreign Aid.” The Quarterly Review of Economics
and Finance 50 (1): 40–49.
Wenar, Leif. 2006. “Accountability in International Development Aid.”
Ethics and International Affairs 20 (1): 1–23.
Wlezien, Christopher. 1995. “The Public as Thermostat: Dynamics of
Preferences for Spending.” American Journal of Political Science
39 (4): 981–1000.
World Bank. 2011. Annual Report 2011. Washington, DC: The World
Bank Group.
CHAPTER 10
What Is Statelessness?
My brief discussion of Arendt and international law has already
indicated to what extent statelessness is a significant affront to one’s
dignity and quality of life. It is worth exploring, however, the array of
vulnerabilities the stateless face in order to emphasize the stakes in
failing to protect them. First, there is the fundamental connection
highlighted above between the state and the protection of a person’s
rights. The stateless generally lack all political rights and thus submit
to a government for which they have had no voice or influence. In
addition, they often lack the economic rights associated with
property and employment as well as the mobility rights to travel or
to reenter their country of habitual residence once they leave. They
are frequently the victims of discrimination in such crucial aspects of
life as housing, education, police protection, or even when opening a
bank account. Further, there is an important connection between a
state and a person’s identity: Persons often identify with their state
as a valuable cultural community and, moreover, by registering one’s
birth and issuing an identity card, the state is most often literally the
source of one’s official identity. According to classical theorists like
Plato and Aristotle, social contract theorists of modernity, such as
Hobbes and Locke, and contemporary political thinkers like Sen, the
state is a necessary precursor to enjoying important capabilities and
living well (Sen 1999).
Depending on one’s definition, the numbers of stateless range
greatly, and different definitions imply different gaps in protection.
The crucial consideration when defining the stateless is whether one
considers only the de jure or legally stateless or whether one also
includes the de facto stateless, those who possess some legal
nationality, but do not have an effective nationality.
De Jure Statelessness
The most widespread and established definition in international law
stems from the 1954 Convention Relating to the Status of Stateless
Persons, the first major international treaty that focused exclusively
on the stateless. Article 1 offers this definition: “‘[S]tateless person’
means a person who is not considered as a national by any State
under the operation of its law.” This definition is a de jure definition
as it is based exclusively on the legal status of a person as
determined by sovereign states. The 1954 Convention, framed on
the heels of the 1951 Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees,
was motivated by the stateless population that emerged after World
War II. Those who designed the Convention believed that this
definition would fully close all gaps in protection without overlapping
this category of persons with refugees protected by the 1951
Refugee Convention. Besides minimizing overlap, this de jure
definition enjoys the advantage of simplicity: A person’s status
comes down to how states identify the person, a presumably
ascertainable legal fact. And it focuses the problem of statelessness
on a relatively small and manageable group of persons who lack a
basic legal right resolvable through legal means. Given these
advantages and its place in the international stateless regime, this
definition guides most international action.
According to the de jure definition, the UNHCR counts
approximately twelve million persons as stateless (UNHCR 2010a).7
These persons become stateless in a variety of complex ways,
including through explicit state discrimination and through accident.
The sovereign state system is one in which states determine
nationality according to their own standards: some by jus soli or
citizenship by birth in the territory, whereas others only by jus
sanguinis or blood ancestry. But cracks between these laws create
situations in which one has no nationality whatsoever: One might be
born in a state that does not have jus soli citizenship or one might
lack the ability to claim citizenship through descent.8
Other laws that cause statelessness include gender-discriminatory
laws that pass citizenship exclusively through patrilineal descent, like
those in Jordan, the Gulf Arab States, and over twenty states across
Africa. If one is born in these states to a female citizen but a male
noncitizen, then one lacks a de jure nationality. Indonesia’s
citizenship laws are also gender-discriminatory, holding that if one is
born out of wedlock to a citizen mother but a noncitizen father, one
is denied Indonesian citizenship.
Statelessness also results from laws that specifically exclude
groups on ethnonational grounds. The Bihari Urdu speakers in
Bangladesh are denied Bangladeshi citizenship because of doubts
about their national loyalties. Similarly, almost a million mostly
Muslim Rohyngya are denied nationality by the ruling junta in
predominantly Buddhist Myanmar. Further, more than 3 million
persons in Cote d’Ivoire, ethnic Nepalese in Bhutan, Nubians in
Kenya, and people of Slavic origin in Latvia are all denied citizenship
because of ethnic exclusion (Blitz 2009). Each group is a victim of
discriminatory laws that seem to violate the UDHR’s guarantee that
“no one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his nationality.”
Others become de jure stateless simply through the difficulties of
registering births. The UN estimates that 36 percent of total annual
births go unregistered for practical or cultural reasons, mostly in
South Asia and sub–Saharan Africa, and many of those persons
legally lack nationality of any state. State succession can also lead to
statelessness. During the break-up of the Ottoman Empire and the
USSR, for instance, millions were left without a state.
The overall number of de jure stateless is particularly difficult to
determine. The UNHCR’s twelve million estimate relies heavily on the
numbers provided by state governments. The Department of
Homeland Security, for instance, has estimated that the de jure
stateless in the United States is a mere 4,000 persons. But the
stateless are a particularly difficult group for states to identify given
the fact that, by definition, they live without state recognition.
Determining the number of stateless is made even more difficult by
the fact that most states do not have specific procedures by which to
identify or process the stateless. Stateless determinations are
typically done through the refugee process, and persons are thus
identified as stateless on an ad hoc basis when and if they apply for
asylum (Batchelor 1998). What’s worse, some states have an
incentive to undercount the number of domestic stateless,
minimizing the problem to deflect negative international attention.
There is therefore good reason to believe that the UNHCR estimate
is not an accurate count; indeed, the UNHCR itself calls the number
a “guesstimate.”9
Despite possessing the advantage of simplicity, the de jure
definition has been attacked for posing an excessively high hurdle.
To be considered de jure stateless, a person must prove a negative
—that none of the over 190 states in the international system claim
him or her as a citizen. This burden of proof falls on the applicant,
but many candidates are unable to prove they have no legal state
because the transactional costs can often be prohibitively high, other
states might not cooperate with the investigation, or the state in
which they have had strong links no longer exists (e.g., Yugoslavia).
Consider also the difficult situation of thousands of persons of
Haitian descent living in the Dominican Republic. The Dominican
Republic does not grant them citizenship, claiming that they have
Haitian citizenship even though the Haitian government also does
not grant them nationality. Although they have no citizenship, these
persons are not considered stateless by the Dominican Republic
because it treats them as being Haitian citizens.
An additional drawback of the de jure definition is that it excludes
many persons who, although they might be claimed as a citizen by
some states, in practice reside and have strong attachments to a
state that does not recognize them. Consider the case of persons
who have a nationality but because of severe conflict are forced to
flee to other states where they develop social attachments. These
persons are not identified as stateless by the customary de jure
definition nor are they refugees according to the 1951 Refugee
Convention. Nonetheless, such persons might still face the same
affronts to their dignity as the de jure stateless, vulnerable to
exploitation and without any of the protections accorded by either
their state of residence or state of nationality. This consideration
suggests that although international legal instruments have largely
focused on the de jure stateless, the specific affronts to dignity seem
to apply equally to both the de jure and other persons who,
although they may have some nationality, lack an effective
nationality. From the person’s perspective, the vulnerabilities of de
jure and de facto statelessness are equivalent. The customary de
jure definition enshrined in international law is blind to this reality as
the definition was developed from the perspective of the states that
contain the stateless, rather than the perspective of the stateless
themselves. The assumption of the de jure definition seems to be
that a de facto stateless person can be repatriated or otherwise
could seek the protection of their state of nationality, whereas a de
jure stateless person cannot and thus the latter should be granted
special protection. This, however, simply raises a further question.
How should states identify the persons mentioned above who claim
some nationality but cannot be repatriated? Their right to a
nationality is ineffective, as the mere fact of nationality de jure
includes with it no protections.10 Moreover, because they already
have a nationality, the solution to their plight is not simply to give
them a legal nationality; hence, there is no obvious legal remedy.
The UNHCR, the organization vested with the most expansive
international mandate to grapple with the problem of statelessness,
seems to agree with these considerations. In the Information and
Accession Package to the Stateless Conventions, they state:
De Facto Statelessness
A de facto definition of the stateless includes a broader category of
persons who might have some legal nationality but nonetheless lack
an effective nationality. There is no consensus on how best to
understand this category of persons; indeed, some have even
suggested that there is no such thing. Nehemiah Robinson, for
instance, argues that “nationality is a legal concept; therefore de
facto statelessness is a somewhat illogical term” (Robinson 1955;
Hudson 1952). Robinson’s point is that the de facto stateless do not
face a problem solvable through juridical means as they already
have a legal nationality. If they have a nationality, how are they
stateless? Others, however, have been struck by the vulnerabilities of
and significant gaps in protection for these persons. Even the
UNHCR, as noted above, argues that the de facto stateless should
be treated as far as possible as stateless. I consider below several
alternative definitions, pointing to the potential advantages and
disadvantages of each; rather than argue for a particular view, my
goal is to demonstrate the need for a consistent and operational
definition.
One definition of de facto statelessness takes seriously the
perspective of persons living without a state rather than the
perspective of the states administering nationality laws. According to
this definition, persons are stateless if they are not accorded the
protections of citizenship from their state. Weissbrodt and Collins
offer one version: “De facto statelessness can occur when
governments withhold the usual benefits of citizenship, such as
protection, and assistance … persons who are de facto stateless
might have legal claim to the benefits of nationality but are not, for
a variety of reasons, able to enjoy these benefits. They are,
effectively, without a nationality” (2006, 251–52).
The UNHCR offers a similar definition in its Handbook for
Parliamentarians, stating: “[D]e facto stateless persons …
technically, still hold a nationality but do not receive any of the
benefits generally associated with nationality, notably national
protection” (UNHCR 2005, 25).11 For Weissbrodt and Collins and in
this UNHCR publication, then, de facto statelessness occurs when
persons fail to possess certain legal protections of their state.
This definition has come under significant fire. First, the definition
requires a clear explanation of what it means for a person to lack the
usual protections of citizenship, and which protections, if denied,
cause statelessness. Consider the myriad examples of persons in
conflict with their state—Tibetans in China, for instance, the Syrian
opposition, or internally displaced persons worldwide. Others are
denied legal protections generally thought of as basic human rights,
such as women in Taliban-era Afghanistan or present-day Saudi
Arabia. These persons are in some sense denied state protections,
but is this sufficient to render them stateless? Weissbrodt and Collins
claim that “most persons considered de facto stateless are the
victims of state repression,” which suggests that persons in conflict
or otherwise repressed by their state should count as de facto
stateless (Weissbrodt and Collins 2006, 263). After all, they lack the
benefits usually associated with nationality.
But, to recall Arendt’s argument, these persons are oppressed in
the sense that their rights are not respected, though this does not
entail that they are genuinely stateless. The genuinely stateless,
according to Arendt, do not merely face oppression, but they do not
possess the very preconditions of receiving protection. Compare
UNHCR Senior Legal Adviser Hugh Massey’s treatment, who argues
that the “right to a nationality is distinct from the rights attached to
nationality … and the violation of one does not necessarily entail a
violation of the other” (Massey 2010, 38). So even if the Assad
regime violates rights usually associated with the nationality of the
Syrian opposition, this does not entail that they have no nationality—
they are, after all, still Syrian. Massey goes even further in rejecting
this definition: “[T]o argue that persons who are deprived of their
nationality are de facto stateless, and that all de facto stateless
persons should be treated as de jure stateless, would be doing a
grave disservice to persons who should be treated as the nationals
that they are, rather than as stateless persons” (Massey 2010, 39).
One is not stateless so long as one has a nationality, even if this
nationality does not offer the protections that might ideally be
associated with it; the definition severely overstretches the term
“stateless.”
One problem with Arendt and Massey’s distinction is that the
right to a nationality means little unless it is attached to rights
accorded to being a national. The right to a nationality is a means to
live well, not an end on its own. Thus, the cost of keeping their
distinction intact is potentially to neglect all those who, even if they
have some nominal nationality, do not enjoy even the most basic
protections and thereby seem to live a life of de facto statelessness.
That said, it is important to keep in mind Arendt’s and Massey’s
distinction between not having a state (and therefore being
stateless) and not enjoying protections provided by the state and to
not make the problem of statelessness completely unmanageable.
The definition of de facto stateless that is under consideration
significantly enlarges the numbers: Depending on the withheld rights
that are deemed the crucial benefits of nationality, the number of de
facto could be hundreds of millions or more, constituting perhaps all
persons living in irresponsible states (Goldston 2006). This massive
scale alone precludes an effective international response. Moreover,
by what methods can the international community respond to
persons denied these benefits of nationality? If the UNHCR takes
seriously the stated definition of de facto stateless, and they seek to
treat the de facto similarly to the de jure, this might involve major
intervention within sovereign states, potentially enlarging UNHCR’s
purview to protect all those oppressed globally.
Consider, then, a second potential definition that has also been
promulgated by the UNHCR: A person is de facto stateless if they do
not have a nationality from the state in which they have a “genuine
and effective” link. In their words: “Governments must acknowledge,
formally and in practice, that they do not have the right to withdraw
or withhold the benefits of citizenship from individuals who can
demonstrate a genuine and effective link with the country” (UNHCR
2005, 3). If governments do withdraw or withhold benefits, then
those persons are de facto stateless. Being de facto stateless is not a
matter of failing to be protected; rather, it is that one lacks
nationality from the state in which one lives. The Nottebohm case
and other international instruments have also invoked this account
of nationality through attachment—sometimes referred to as jus
connectionis, or the law of connectedness.12
However, this definition likewise raises a variety of questions that
are problematic for its applicability. First, what more precisely is the
genuine and effective link, and how might it be determined?
Standard international practice and law, such as the Nottebohm
case, leaves this to state discretion, and states typically deny that
persons without a proper jus soli or jus sanguinis connection have a
“genuine and effective” link. Even relatively welcoming states, such
as the United States, have been unwilling to give citizenship to
persons on the basis of social attachment. Taking the UNHCR’s
suggestion seriously might require that states radically alter their
citizenship laws, thereby greatly affecting their right to make their
own determinations of nationality. Although ideally jus connectionis
might best promote human dignity worldwide, this principle surely is
not what drives UNHCR action nor will it likely guide state action in
responding to the particular issue of statelessness.
A third definition responds to one problem with the de jure
definition, holding that persons are de facto stateless when they
have a nationality but cannot prove it. As indicated above,
administrative, technical or other reasons might make this proof
difficult if not impossible to obtain, and as a result many persons live
without the preconditions for basic protection. This definition is
significantly more narrow than previous definitions, excluding many
irregular migrants or those systematically oppressed by their state. It
thereby tries to balance the perspective of the state and the
perspective of the vulnerable person while acknowledging the extent
to which many who have de jure nationality should be treated as
stateless.
Although this definition seeks to balance the perspective of states
and of persons, it might be challenged from either side. Many
vulnerable persons might be able to prove their nationality yet still
lack all of their state’s protections and thus might live identical lives
as those who are de jure stateless. This definition might not
therefore be sufficiently strong to give teeth to the notion that all
persons have a right to a nationality.
But a state might also challenge this designation because it
enables persons to qualify as de facto stateless if they still reside in
their state of nationality. States might object that the concept of
statelessness must only apply to persons who are outside of their
own state. Although this might not matter for the persons
themselves, some might believe that this is crucial to limiting the
definition to a manageable group to which the UNHCR and states
might provide response.
Consider now a fourth alternative definition of de facto
statelessness: “Persons who are outside the State of their nationality
and lacking in that State’s protection, the protection in question
being diplomatic and consular protection and assistance (as opposed
to protection on the territory of the State of nationality itself)”
(Massey 2010, ii). This definition, stemming from the 1946
Memorandum on Statelessness by the Intergovernmental Committee
on Refugees and recently promoted by UNHCR Senior Legal Adviser
Massey, is sufficiently narrow and does not include those who are
systematically oppressed by their own state. Its criteria require that
one be outside one’s state of nationality and that one’s state of
nationality fails to provide protection in specific diplomatic or
consular functions. According to Massey, this failure to provide
protection must be the result of one’s state refusing to provide it
rather than being unable to provide protection, or if there is simply
an absence of diplomatic recognition (Massey 2010).
But this definition likewise seems too limited to characterize
persons who live functionally equivalent lives as those who are de
jure stateless. One’s de jure state might provide diplomatic or
consular services, though one might live with strong attachments in
a different state that provides none of the protections essential to
living well. From the perspective of the person, this definition thus
fails to capture something crucial about the right to nationality. And
surely what matters for a definition of statelessness, if it is to be
made operational to fill a protection gap, is to capture the lived
experience of the unprotected person. To further bolster this point, it
might be asked, why would it matter from a person’s perspective
whether one’s de jure state fails to provide protection simply
because it does not have diplomatic relations with one’s de facto
state? This is a trivial distinction, perhaps meaning something to the
respective states but not the vulnerable person left out of all
protections in their de facto residence simply because they have
some de jure connection to a state that does not protect them. On
this definition, the right to a state is thus divorced from the rights
associated with having a state; the former might be granted without
any provision of the latter.
As should be clear by now, the major potential definitions of de
facto statelessness are subject to scrutiny. Without fully arbitrating
this dispute, this discussion does hopefully suggest the difficulties of
defining statelessness in a way that reasonably balances the
concerns of states and the vulnerabilities of persons who fall into a
protection gap and points again to a solution that requires breaking
through the basic tension in international law that animates this
dispute. I offer my own approach to broker this tension in the
recommendation section below. But, before making
recommendations and with these conceptual complications in mind,
I turn now to efforts taken by states to address the problem.
Conclusion
How would Arendt assess our progress on the problem of
statelessness? Given the ongoing challenges and the enduring gaps
in protection, she would likely not be satisfied. She herself
understood how difficult the problem would be and the sort of
massive transformation of the state system required to fully address
it. In her view, half steps and subtle reforms, like international
conventions, were bound to fail: They remained too close to a state-
based system. She writes, “[F]or, contrary to the best intentioned
humanitarian attempts to obtain new declarations of human rights
from international organizations, it should be understood that this
idea transcends the present sphere of international law which still
operates in terms of reciprocal agreements and treaties between
sovereign states; and for the time being, a sphere that is above the
nations does not exist” (Arendt 1973, 298).
Although I have not followed her lead by proposing a sphere
above nations to resolve the problem—that is, I have not proposed a
suprastate that gives all nationality—I have sought to eliminate a
debilitating tension in international law by reconceptualizing state
sovereignty and nationality in a way that better suits the array of
actors in the neomedieval world and better protects stateless
persons. Arendt would perhaps find these suggestions too optimistic
in their tendency to make states responsible for persons. But they
remain the best step forward in creating a world without the
stateless.
Notes
1. The 1930 Convention on Certain Questions Relating to the
Conflict of Nationality Laws Article 1 states: “It is for each State to
determine under its own law who are its nationals. This law shall be
recognised by other States in so far as it is consistent with
international conventions, international custom, and the principles of
law generally recognised with regard to nationality.” The Nottebohm
case (Liechtenstein v. Guatemala) holds that nationality “is a legal
bond having as its basis a social fact of attachment, a genuine
connection of existence, interest and sentiments, together with the
existence of reciprocal rights and duties.” Note that although the
latter part to the claim seems to limit the right, the genuine effective
link is up to states to determine and includes birth or descent.
2. I use the concepts of “citizenship” and “nationality”
interchangeably. For one canonical definition of nationality, see (Weis
1956): Nationality guarantees “the allocation of individuals, termed
nationals, to a specific State—the State of nationality—as members
of that State, a relationship which confers upon that State under
customary international law rights and duties in relation to other
States.”
3. The International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Article
24.3: “Every child has the right to acquire a nationality.” The
Convention on the Rights of the Child, Article 7.1: All children “shall
be registered immediately after birth and shall have the right from
birth to a name, the right to acquire a nationality.”
4. The Preamble to the UDHR makes this explicit: “Whereas
recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable
rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of
freedom, justice, and peace in the world.”
5. Consider for instance how Eleanor Roosevelt, in working to
develop the UDHR, argued that the rights of the individual are above
the rights of the state. See the account in (Glendon 2002).
6. This tension supports Lagon and Arend’s attempt in the
introductory chapter of this book to move beyond stalemated
debates within the discourse of “rights” to establish a new normative
foundation for assessing institutions.
7. The UNHCR also notes that they do not have “comprehensive
statistics on stateless populations worldwide” (UNHCR 2010b).
8. Some analysts point to jus sanguinis as the central contributor
to the problem. For instance, Blitz argues that, “the principle of
membership on the basis of blood origin has historically locked many
minority groups out of the right to citizenship in their habitual state
of residence” (Blitz 2009).
9. “This number is a ‘guesstimate’. It has been very difficult for
organizations to collect comprehensive data on the number of
stateless persons because the concept of statelessness is disputed
among countries, because governments are often reluctant to
disclose information about statelessness, and because the issue of
statelessness is not high on the international community’s agenda”
(UNHCR 2005, 3).
10. Compare the special rapporteur to the International Law
Commission Roberto Codova, who wrote in 1954: “It seems to the
Special Rapporteur that the most important aspect of this problem of
statelessness is not the technical question of nationality only, but the
real situation.… Needless to say that the Commission is not only
obliged to deal with juridical statelessness, but is also under the
solemn obligation to provide juridical solutions for the situation of
thousands of human beings who are in a much worse position than
those only are de jure stateless” (Codova 1954, 30).
11. They also report that, “the individual is thus unable to
demonstrate that he/she is de jure stateless, yet he/she has no
effective nationality and does not enjoy national protection. He/She
is considered to be de facto stateless” (UNHCR 2005, 11).
12. The Nottebohm decision states: “Nationality is a legal bond
having as its basis a social fact of attachment, a genuine connection
of existence, interest and sentiments, together with the existence of
reciprocal rights and duties.” But this raises the question: Is one
stateless if one has strong social attachments but no rights?
13. Article 32 states: “The Contracting States shall as far as
possible facilitate the assimilation and naturalization of stateless
persons. They shall in particular make every effort to expedite
naturalization proceedings and to reduce as far as possible the
charges and costs of such proceedings.”
14. As mentioned earlier, Resolution No. 1 of the Final Act states,
“The Conference recommends that persons who are stateless de
facto should as far as possible be treated as stateless de jure to
enable them to acquire an effective nationality.” This resolution,
however, is a recommendation rather than an obligation.
15. There are thirty-one cities of this sort in the United States,
including New York, Los Angeles, and Chicago.
16. The World Summit text reads: “Each individual State has the
responsibility to protect its populations from genocide, war crimes,
ethnic cleansing and crimes against humanity. This responsibility
entails the prevention of such crimes, including their incitement,
through appropriate and necessary means. We accept that
responsibility and will act in accordance with it. The international
community should, as appropriate, encourage and help States to
exercise this responsibility and support the UN in establishing an
early warning capability.”
References
Arendt, Hannah. 1973. The Origins of Totalitarianism. 5th ed. San
Diego, CA: Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich.
Batchelor, Carol. 1998. “Statelessness and the Problem of Resolving
Nationality Status.” International Journal of Refugee Law 10: 156.
Blitz, Brad. 2009. Statelessness, Protection, and Equality. Oxford,
UK: Refugees Studies Centre, University of Oxford. Assessed on
April 17, 2014. http://www.refworld.org/docid/4e5f3d572.html.
Codova, Roberto. 1954. “Nationality, Including Statelessness—Third
Report on the Elimination or Reduction of Stateless.” Extract from
the Yearbook of the International Law Commission 1954 vol. 2.
A/CN/4/81. Accessed September 13, 2013.
http://untreaty.un.org/ilc/documentation/english/a_cn4_81_corrl.
pdf.
Cohen, Roberta. 2003. “Sovereignty as Responsibility: The Guiding
Principles on Internal Displacement.” Public Lecture at the
Calcutta Research Group and the Refugees Studies Centre.
December 5. Calcutta, India.
Convention on the Nationality of Married Women. 1958.
Convention on the Rights of the Child “Convention” Article 7.1. 1990.
Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees. 1951.
Convention Relating to the Status of Stateless Persons. 1954.
Glendon, Mary. 2002. A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the
Universal Declaration of Human Rights. New York: Random
House.
Goldston, J. A. 2006. “Holes in the Rights Framework: Racial
Discrimination, Citizenship, and the Rights of Noncitizens.” Ethics
& International Affairs 20 (3): 321–47.
Green, Nicole, and Todd Pierce. 2009. “Combatting Statelessness: A
Government Perspective.” Forced Migration Review Journal 11
(32).
Hobbes, Thomas. 1994. Leviathan: With Selected Variants from the
Latin Edition of 1668. 3rd ed. Edited by Edwin Curley. Cambridge,
MA: Hackett Publishing.
Hudson, Manley O. 1952. “Report on Nationality, Including Stateless”
Extract from the Yearbook of the International Law Commission
vol. 2. A/CN.450. Accessed September 13, 2013.
http://untreaty.un.org/ilc/documentation/english/a_cn4_50.pdf.
Loescher, Gil. 1996. Beyond Charity: International Cooperation and
the Global Refugee Crisis. New York: Oxford University Press.
Massey, Hugh. 2010. “UNHCR and De Facto Statelessness.” Legal
and Protection Policy Research Series. Geneva, Switzerland:
UNHCR.
Nottebohm Case. 1955. (Liechtenstein v. Guatemala [second
phase]). Judgment of April 6.
Robinson, Nehemiah. 1955. Convention Relating to the Status of
Stateless Persons: Its History and Interpretation. New York:
World Jewish Congress. Reprinted by the Division of International
Protection of the UN High Commissioner for Refugees, 1997.
Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Alfred A.
Knopf.
UNHCR (UN High Commissioner for Refugees). 1999. “Information
and Accession Package: The 1954 Convention Relating to the
Status of Stateless Persons and the 1961 Convention on the
Reduction of Statelessness.” Geneva, Switzerland: UNHCR.
———. 2005. Nationality and Statelessness: A Handbook for
Parliamentarians. Inter-Parliamentary Union.
———. 2010a. Statistical Report 2009: Trends in Displacement,
Protection, and Solutions. UNHCR. Accessed September 13,
2013. http://www.unhcr.org/4ce532ff9.html.
———. 2010b. UNHCR Action to Address Statelessness: A Strategy
Note. UNHCR. Accessed September 13, 2013.
http://www.unhcr.org/4b960ae99.html.
UNHCR Executive Committee. 2006. “Conclusion on Identification,
Prevention and Reduction of Stateless and Protection of Stateless
Persons.” UNHCR. Accessed September 13, 2013.
http://www.unhcr.org/453497302.html.
Weis, Paul. 1956. Nationality and Statelessness in International Law.
New York: Frederick A. Praegar.
Weissbrodt, David S., and Clay Collins. 2006. “The Human Rights of
Stateless Persons.” Human Rights Quarterly 28 (1): 245-76.
CHAPTER 11
Notes
Many thanks go to Mathew Caldwell, Nicole Michels, and Andrew
Reddie for superb research assistance and input into this chapter.
1. In full disclosure and regarding objectivity, I edited and
supervised the production of this report for two years.
2. As the former CEO of Polaris and later a LexisNexis adviser, I
may not be the source to offer a wholly unbiased assessment of the
impact of the hotline.
3. As State Department antitrafficking director from 2007 to
2009, I raised concerns but the partnerships with MTV Exit
continued.
References
Alvarez, Anita. 2011. “State’s Attorney Announces Charges in Joint
Undercover Human Trafficking Investigation: Operation ‘Little Girl
Lost’ Targets Chicago Street Gang Members.” Office of Cook
County State’s Attorney, August 24.
http://www.statesattorney.org/index2/press_littlegirllost01.html.
Bales, Kevin. (1999) 2004. Disposable People: New Slavery in the
Global Economy. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Brusca, Carol S. 2011. “Palermo Protocol: The First Ten Years after
Adoption.” Global Security Studies 2 (3): 8–20.
Clinton, Hillary Rodham. 2009. “Partnering Against Trafficking.”
Washington Post. July 17.
http://articles.washingtonpost.com/2009-06-
17/opinions/36784296_1_sexual-exploitation-prostitution-human-
rights.
Coalition Against Trafficking in Women (CATW). 2011. “Join Us to
Protest Backpage.com’s Facilitation of Sex Trafficking in Front of
Its New York City Headquarters.” Coalition Against Trafficking in
Women (CATW). Accessed September 1, 2013.
http://www.catwinternational.org/Home/Article/472-leading-
human-rights-groups-catw-pre-to-protest-village-voice-media-in-
nyc-on-62012.
———. 2012. “Leading Human Rights Groups CATW & PRE to Protest
Village Voice Media in NYC on 6/20/2012.” Coalition Against
Trafficking in Women (CATW). Accessed September 1, 2013.
http://action.web.ca/home/catw/readingroom.shtml?x=133517.
Doyle, Kevin. 2006. “Cambodia’s Child Sex Crackdown.” Time
Magazine, October 5.
http://content.time.com/time/world/article/0,8599,1543174,00.ht
ml.
Ford Motor Company. 2010/2011. “Case Study: Forced Labor in the
Pig Iron Supply Chain in Brazil.” Ford Motor Company. Accessed
September 1, 2013.
http://corporate.ford.com/microsites/sustainability-report-2010-
11/issues-supply-materials-brazil.
Free The Slaves. 2014. “Our Work: Frontline Partners—India.”
Accessed April 9, 2014. https://www.freetheslaves.net/india/.
Haugen, Gary, and Victor Boutros. 2010. “And Justice for All:
Enforcing Human Rights for the World’s Poor.” Foreign Affairs 89
(3): 51–62.
———. 2014. The Locust Effect: Why the End of Poverty Requires
the End of Violence. New York: Oxford University Press, 242–57.
Huang, Shirlena, Noor Abdul Rahman, and Brenda S. A. Yoeh, eds.
2005. Asian Women as Transnational Domestic Workers.
Singapore: Marshall Cavendish Academic.
International Justice Mission (IJM). 2010. “Project Lantern: Game-
Changing Results in the Fight against Trafficking.” International
Justice Mission. Accessed September 1, 2013.
http://www.ijm.org/projectlantern.
International Labour Organisation (ILO). 2008. Combating Forced
Labour: A Handbook for Employers and Business. Geneva:
International Labour Organization.
———. 2012. “New ILO Global Estimate of Forced Labour: 20.9
million victims.” International Labour Organization. June 01.
http://www.ilo.org/global/about-the-
ilo/newsroom/news/WCMS_182109/lang--en/index.htm.
Kelley, Judith, and Beth Simmons. 2014. “Politics by Number:
Indicators as Social Pressure in International Relations.” American
Journal of Political Science. Forthcoming.
Khan, Irene. 2009. The Unheard Truth: Poverty and Human Rights.
New York: W. W. Norton and Company.
LexisNexis. 2009. “Polaris Project and LexisNexis Form Public-Private
Partnership to Fight Human Trafficking.” LexisNexis. May 27.
http://www.lexisnexis.com/risk/newsevents/press-release.aspx?
Id=1256036772792737.
ManpowerGroup. 2012. “Ethical Framework for International Labor
Recruitment.” ManpowerGroup. Accessed September 1, 2013.
http://www.manpowergroup.com/wps/wcm/connect/manpowerg
roup-en/home/social-responsibility/social-impact/human-
trafficking/ethical-framework-for-international-
labor#.UhUMv5KkobE.
Mehran, Farhad, and Michaëlle de Cock. 2012. “ILO Global Estimate
of Forced Labour: Results and Methodology.” Geneva:
International Labour Office–Special Action Programme to Combat
Forced Labour (SAP-FL).
Naly, Sok. 2004. “Abuse a Child in this Country—Go to Jail in Yours.”
World Vision Cambodia. July 8.
http://www.worldvision.org.kh/newsdet_25.html.
O’Connor, Clare. 2012. “Inside eBay Billionaire Pierre Omidyar’s
Battle to End Human Trafficking,” Forbes. November 08.
http://www.forbes.com/sites/clareoconnor/2012/11/08/inside-
ebay-billionaire-pierre-omidyars-battle-to-end-human-
trafficking/3/.
Office of Missouri Attorney General Chris Koster. 2012. “State
Attorneys General Reject Backpage Demand.” Office of Missouri
Attorney General Chris Koster. May 23.
http://ago.mo.gov/newsreleases/2012/State_attorney_generals_r
eject_demand/.
Office of Senator Mark Kirk. 2012. “Senators Call for Backpage to
End Ads Promoting Child Prostitution.” Office of Senator Mark
Kirk. May 2. http://www.kirk.senate.gov/?
p=press_release&id=479.
Office of Senator Richard Blumenthal. 2012. “Senators Call on
Backpage to End Human Trafficking through Adult Services
Advertising.” Office of Senator Richard Blumenthal. Accessed
September 1, 2013.
http://www.blumenthal.senate.gov/newsroom/press/release/sena
tors-call-on-backpage-to-end-human-trafficking-through-adult-
services-advertising.
Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe (OSCE). 2014.
Accessed May 8, 2014. http://www.osce.org/secretariat/107221.
Polaris Project. 2011. Increasing Awareness and Engagement:
Strengthening the National Response to Human Trafficking in the
US Polaris Project. Accessed September 1, 2013.
http://www.polarisproject.org/resources/hotline-statistics.
Pompeo, Joe. 2012. “Meet Liz McDougall, the Unlikely-Seeming
Lawyer Defending Village Voice Media in Backpage Controversy.”
Capital New York. April 26.
http://www.capitalnewyork.com/article/media/2012/04/5773538/
meet-liz-mcdougall-unlikely-seeming-lawyer-defending-village-
voice-med.
Powers, Kirsten. 2012. “Boycott Village Voice Media? Senators and
Clergy Push for Action on Backpage.com.” The Daily Beast, April
19. http://www.thedailybeast.com/articles/2012/04/19/boycott-
village-voice-senators-push-for-action-on-backpage-com.html.
Report on the Vienna Forum to Fight Human Trafficking
(presentation). 2008. UN Global Initiative to Fight Human
Trafficking (UN.GIFT). Vienna, Austria, UN Document
E/CN.15/2008/CRP.2. Submitted to the UN Commission on Crime
Prevention and Criminal Justice, seventeenth session. Vienna,
April 14–18.
http://www.unodc.org/documents/treaties/COP2008/CTOC-COP-
2008-CRP-1-E.pdf.
Salvation Army. [2013. “STOP-IT Initiative Against Human
Trafficking.” Accessed September 1, 2013. http://sa-stopit.org/.
Singh, Sunit, and Rama Charan Tripathi. 2010. “Why Do the Bonded
Fear Freedom? Some Lessons from the Field.” Psychology and
Developing Societies 22 (2): 249–97.
Skibola, Nicole. 2012. “Technology, Business, and Anti-Human
Trafficking Innovation.” Forbes—Corporate Responsibility Blog.
January 4.
http://www.forbes.com/sites/csr/2012/01/04/technology-
business-and-anti-human-trafficking-innovation/.
Solis, Hilda L. 2012. “Statement by Secretary of Labor Hilda L. Solis
on Statistics Updated by International Labour Organization
Regarding Forced Labor.” International Labour Affairs Bureau.
June 1.
http://www.dol.gov/opa/media/press/ilab/ILAB20121144.htm.
Sweeney, Annie. 2012. “New Task Force Targets Traffickers Who
Force Children into the Sex Trade,” Chicago Tribune. May 14,
2012. http://articles.chicagotribune.com/2012-05-14/news/ct-
met-human-trafficking-20120514_1_chicago-police-traffickers-
law-enforcement.
Tavares, Rodrigo. 2009. Regional Security: The Capacity of
International Organizations. New York: Routledge.
TIP Report. 2009. Trafficking in Persons Report. US Department of
State.
———. 2010. Trafficking in Persons Report. US Department of State.
———. 2011. Trafficking in Persons Report. US Department of State.
———. 2012. Trafficking in Persons Report. US Department of State.
———. 2013. Trafficking in Persons Report. US Department of State.
Tyldum, Guri, and Anette Brunovskis. 2005. “Describing the
Unobserved: Methodological Challenges in Empirical Studies on
Human Trafficking.” International Migration, 43 (1-2): 17-34.
UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights (UNOHCHR).
2012. “United Arab Emirates: UN Expert Urges Further Action to
Protect Victims of Trafficking.” United Nations Office of the High
Commissioner for Human Rights (UNOHCHR). April 17.
http://www.ohchr.org/en/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?
NewsID=12068&LangID=E.
Verité. 2010. “Forced Labor & Trafficking, Help Wanted: Hiring,
Human Trafficking, and Slavery.” Accessed September 1, 2013.
http://www.verite.org/forced-labor.
———. 2013. “A Framework for Action: What Can Suppliers Do?”
Accessed September 1, 2013.
http://www.verite.org/helpwanted/toolkit/suppliers.
Vidyamali, Samarasinghe, and Barbara Burton. 2007. “Strategizing
Prevention: A Critical Review of Local Initiatives to Prevent
Female Sex Trafficking.” Development in Practice 17 (1): 51–64.
CHAPTER 12
The idea of human dignity can serve to cultivate shared moral and
political ground in a world divided along religious, social, economic,
and ideological lines. At the same time, the ambiguity of the concept
is a challenge. Unlike human rights, human dignity has not been
codified. Human rights, although contested, have been the object of
a structured conversation for more than half a century. Specific
rights are set down in treaties, conventions, and other legal
instruments. Professionals the world over—including lawyers, judges,
activists, civil servants, and scholars—apply them in their work.
The concept of human dignity does not have these robust
institutional foundations, but it does have a political force that
human rights lacks. The language of rights is legal, whereas the idea
of dignity has deep emotional resonance. Rights are adjudicated and
balanced against one another, whereas human dignity is, by
definition, inviolable. To claim that something violates human dignity
is to assert that it contradicts basic moral precepts and must be
remedied. Over the past two centuries, struggles against slavery,
colonialism, racism, sexism, and the oppression of minorities have
deployed the idea of human dignity—and revulsion at its violations—
in building coalitions and bringing about change. Since the turn of
the twenty-first century, the idea of human dignity and its
implications for economic, social, and political life in a global era has
informed an ambitious human development agenda around poverty,
health care, and education.
The emotional pull and political force of the idea of human dignity
has shaped, and been shaped by, the public role of religion in world
affairs (Casanova 1994). The idea that human life is sacred—widely
shared across the world’s major traditions—adds a powerful
expressive layer to the politics of human dignity. Violations of human
dignity are viewed (and felt) as affronts to both a moral and a
cosmic order. The call of religious leaders to advance human dignity
and human rights is construed and experienced as a response to
God or some ultimate concern. From Mahatma Gandhi to Martin
Luther King Jr. and the Dalai Lama, faith leaders have mobilized
members of their own and other communities around a wide range
of human rights agendas. In a world of state competition for
material power and advantage, religious communities do not
dominate the politics of human dignity and human rights. But they
have contributed to human rights coalitions by infusing the
emotional power of the idea of human dignity with a spiritual
dimension (Banchoff and Wuthnow 2011; Witte and van der Vyver
1996).
This chapter explores the religious politics of human dignity in the
case of the Roman Catholic Church, the most influential formally
organized religious community in the world. After an overview of the
evolution of the idea of human dignity in world politics, it tracks the
Church’s shift towards a human dignity and human rights agenda at
the Second Vatican Council (1962-1965) and its wider impact since.
A concluding section sketches the idea of human dignity in two other
leading traditions, Islam and Confucianism, as one way to explore
the potential of interfaith and intercultural dialogue and collaboration
to strengthen the international human rights regime.
Conclusion
Over the past half century, the prominence of the idea of human
dignity and the emergence of a robust international human rights
regime have gone hand in hand. Appeals to human dignity and of
the inviolable worth of each and every human person have helped to
mobilize national and international coalitions in support of diverse
human rights agendas. Moral outrage in the face of violations of
human dignity—the unjust suffering and deprivation of fellow human
beings—has advanced the cause of equal human rights of women
and children, racial, religious, and ethnic minorities, and other
groups over time. Each of these contexts has seen fierce
contestation over the precise meaning and implications of human
dignity. Most recently, for example, discrimination on the basis of
sexual orientation has emerged as a controversial issue within and
across countries. Here, as previously, claims about the violation of
fundamental human dignity have found emotional resonance and
structured human rights debates.
In the context of globalization, religious communities have
emerged as key actors in the politics of human dignity and human
rights. The idea of human dignity can, of course, be conceptualized
and articulated in a secular idiom. But it finds perhaps its most
powerful expression in a religious context in which unjust suffering
and the violation of human dignity are viewed not only as an ethical
affront but as a transgression of divine law or an attack on the
cosmic order. Religious communities do not, of course, speak with
one voice on the issue of human dignity. For decades, struggles for
equal rights and respect regardless of race and gender have divided
faith communities internally, and they continue to do so today
around questions of sexual orientation and other issues. Religious
passions can be mobilized for or against social and political change.
Since World War II, however, the mobilization of religious
communities against violations of human dignity and in favor of a
general widening and deepening of the international human rights
regime has been a striking development, unforeseen by the prophets
of secularization.
The path of the Roman Catholic Church is the clearest illustration
of this trend. With the Second Vatican Council of the 1960s, the
Church made the turn from an entrenched opponent of liberal
democratic ideas to one of the greatest proponents of human rights
on a global scale. The idea of human dignity provided a pivot of
continuity. In response to what Pope John XXIII called the “signs of
the times,” an established theological prism of dignity bestowed by
God took on a full social and political dimension in Catholic thought
and teaching. In the decades since, successive popes have taken up
the idea of human dignity and, through their global diplomacy,
emerged as influential proponents of basic economic, social, and
political rights. In his first months in office in 2013, Pope Francis
made the plight of the world’s poor his top priority and expressed his
strong support for the UN’s global human development agenda.
In the years and decades to come, progress in human rights and
human development will depend in no small part on the support of
the Catholic Church and other religious communities across multiple
traditions. We still live in a world of nation-states in which politics,
both domestic and international, center on the clash of material
interests. Many have grown inured to violations of human dignity—
what Pope Francis calls the “globalization of indifference.” In this
context, the world’s great secular and religious traditions help to
keep alive the idea of a common humanity bound by mutual
obligation. What religions can add, and interfaith dialogue and
collaboration can support, is a spiritual as well as emotional ground
for indignation and action—a transcendent, ultimate basis for human
fellow feeling and solidarity in practice. Religious communities are
not the only players in the politics of human dignity and human
rights. But their contributions to date have been critical, as is their
potential moving forward.
Notes
1. On the importance of human dignity as a driver of a politics of
human rights, see Jeffrey C. Isaac, “A New Guarantee on Earth:
Hannah Arendt on Human Dignity and the Politics of Human Rights,”
The American Political Science Review 90, no. 1 (March 1996): 61–
73.
2. One exception was Maritain’s purported influence on the
human dignity language in the 1948 Universal Declaration. See Mary
Ann Glendon, A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the
Universal Declaration of Human Rights (New York: Random House,
2001).
3. Into the 1970s, many national Church leaders continued to
support Catholic dictators in Spain, Portugal, the Philippines, and
parts of Latin America. It was only with the wave of democratization
in the 1970s and 1980s across those regions and countries, much of
it led by progressive clerics and laypersons, that the Church came to
be more clearly identified with the human rights and human dignity
agenda.
4. All passages from the Qur’an come from Muhammad Asad’s
translation. See Muhammad Asad, The Message of the Qur’an, trans.
Muhammad Asad (Gibraltar: Dar al-Andalus, 1980), accessed
November 29, 2013.
http://www.usc.edu/schools/college/crcc/private/cmje/religious_text/
The_Message_of_The__Quranby_Muhammad_Asad.pdf.
References
Amato, Joseph. 1975. Mounier andMaritain: A French Catholic
Understanding of the Modern World. Reprint, Washington, DC:
Catholic University of America Press, 2010.
An-Na’im, Abdullahi. 2010. Islam and Human Rights: Selected
Essays of Abdullahi An-Na’im, edited by Mashood A. Baderin.
Farnham, UK: Ashgate.
Banchoff, Thomas. 2012. “Interreligious Dialogue and International
Relations.” In Rethinking Religion and World Affairs, edited by
Timothy Samuel Shah, Alfred Stepan, and Monica Duffy Toft,
204–14. New York: Oxford University Press.
Banchoff, Thomas, and Robert Wuthnow, eds. 2011. Religion and
the Global Politics of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Bell, Daniel. 2008. China’s New Confucianism: Politics and Everyday
Life in a Changing Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Bell, Daniel, and Hahm Chaibong, eds. 2003. Confucianism for the
Modern World. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Benedict XVI. 2009. Caritas in veritate (Encyclical on Integral Human
Development in Charity and Truth). June 29.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/encyclicals/docu
ments/hf_ben-xvi_enc_20090629_caritas-in-veritate_en.html.
Bloom, Irene, J. Paul Martin, and Wayne L. Proudfoot, eds. 1996.
Religious Diversity and Human Rights. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Bolívar, Simón. 1826. “Message to the Congress of Bolivia.” In Símon
Bolívar: His Basic Thoughts, edited by Manuel Pérez Vila, 133-52.
Caracas: Academia Nacional de la Historia, Comité Venezolano de
Ciencias Históricas, 1980.
Casanova, José. 1994. Public Religions in the Modern World.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
———. 1999. “The Sacralization of the Humanum: A Theology for a
Global Age.” International Journal of Politics, Culture, and Society
13 (1): 21–40.
Francis. 2013a. “Address of His Holiness Pope Francis to Participants
in the 38th Conference of the Food and Agriculture Organization
of the United Nations (FAO)” (speech). Vatican City, June 20.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/francesco/speeches/2013/june
/documents/papa-francesco_20130620_38-sessione-fao_en.html.
———. 2013b. “Homily of Holy Father Francis at ‘Arena’ Sports
Camp, Salina Quarter of Lampedusa” (homily). Lampedusa, Italy,
July 8.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/francesco/homilies/2013/docu
ments/papa-francesco_20130708_omelia-lampedusa_en.html.
Huntington, Samuel P. 1991. The Third Wave: Democratization in the
Late Twentieth Century. The Julian J. Rothbaum Distinguished
Lecture Series. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press.
İhsanoğlu, Ekmeleddin. 2012. “Statement H. E. Ekmeleddin
İhsanoğlu, Secretary-General of the Organisation of Islamic
Cooperation (OIC) at the Symposium on Tolerance Vienna,”
(speech). Vienna, Austria, November 29.
http://www.oicoci.org/topic_detail.asp?t_id=7497.
InterAction Council. 1997. Universal Declaration of Human
Responsibilities. September 1.
http://www.interactioncouncil.org/universal-declaration-human-
responsibilities.
Joas, Hans. 2013. The Sacredness of the Person: A New Genealogy
of Human Rights. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.
John Paul II. 1987. Sollicitudo rei socialis (Encyclical for the
Twentieth Anniversary of Populorum Progressio). December 30.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/docu
ments/hf_jp-ii_enc_30121987_sollicitudo-rei-socialis_en.html.
———. 1991. Centesimus annus (Encyclical on the Hundredth
Anniversary of Rerum Novarum). May 1.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/docu
ments/hf_jp-ii_enc_01051991_centesimus-annus_en.html.
———. 2001. Novo millennio ineunte (Apostolic Letter at the Close of
the Great Jubilee of the Year 2000). January 6.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/apost_letters/doc
uments/hf_jp-ii_apl_20010106_novo-millennio-ineunte_en.html.
Kant, Immanuel. 1797. The Metaphysics of Morals, edited and
translated by Mary Gregor. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press, 1996.
Kateb, George. 2011. Human Dignity. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press
of Harvard University Press.
Lauren, Paul Gordon. 2011. The Evolution of International Human
Rights: Visions Seen, Pennsylvania Studies in Human Rights. 3rd
ed. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Leo XIII. 1891. Rerum novarum (Encyclical on Capital and Labor).
May 15.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/leo_xiii/encyclicals/documents
/hf_l-xiii_enc_15051891_rerum-novarum_en.html.
Maritain, Jacques. 1947. The Person and the Common Good,
translated by John J. Fitzgerald. New York: Charles Scribner’s
Sons. Accessed November 29, 2013.
http://www3.nd.edu/Departments/Maritain/etext/CG.HTM.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. 1848. The Communist Manifesto,
edited by Gareth Stedman Jones. London: Penguin Classics,
2002.
National Constituent Assembly of Tunisia. 2013. Draft Constitution of
the Tunisian Republic, translated by the International Institute for
Democracy and Electoral Assistance. April 22. Accessed
November 29, 2013.
http://www.constitutionnet.org/files/2013_04_23_-
_third_draft_english_idea_3.pdf.
O’Malley, John W. 2010. What Happened at Vatican II. Cambridge,
MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD).
1996. Shaping the 21st Century: The Contribution of
Development Co-operation. Paris: Organisation for Economic Co-
operation and Development.
Organisation of the Islamic Conference (OIC). 1990. Cairo
Declaration on Human Rights in Islam. August 5. http://www.oic-
oci.org/english/article/human.htm.
Paine, Thomas. 1791. The Rights of Man, Part 1. In Paine: Political
Writings, edited by Bruce Kuklick, 57–154. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Parliament of the World’s Religions. 1993. Declaration toward a
Global Ethic. September 4.
http://www.parliamentofreligions.org/_includes/FCKcontent/File/
TowardsAGlobalEthic.pdf.
Paul VI. 1965a. Dignitatis humanae (Declaration on Religious
Freedom; On the Right of the Person and of Communities to
Social and Civil Freedom in Matters Religious). December 7.
http://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/do
cuments/vat-ii_decl_19651207_dignitatis-humanae_en.html.
———. 1965b. Gaudium et spes (Pastoral Constitution on the Church
in the Modern World). December 7.
http://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/do
cuments/vat-ii_cons_19651207_gaudium-et-spes_en.html.
———. 1965c. Nostra aetate (Declaration on the Relation of the
Church to Non-Christian Religions). October 28.
http://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/do
cuments/vat-ii_decl_19651028_nostra-aetate_en.html.
———. 1965d. “Address by Pope Paul VI to the General Assembly.”
In Yearbook of the United Nations: 1965, 237–42. New York: UN
Department of Public Information.
http://www.unmultimedia.org/searchers/yearbook/page.jsp?
bookpage=237&volume=1965.
———. 1967. Populorum progressio (Encyclical on the Development
of Peoples). March 26.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/paul_vi/encyclicals/documents
/hf_p-vi_enc_26031967_populorum_en.html.
Pius XI. 1931. Quadragesimo anno (Encyclical on Reconstruction of
the Social Order). May 15.
http://www.vatican.va/holy_father/pius_xi/encyclicals/documents
/hf_p-xi_enc_19310515_quadragesimo-anno_en.html.
Pius XII. 1942. “The Internal Order of States and People” (speech).
Vatican City, December 24. Accessed November 29, 2013.
http://www.ewtn.com/library/papaldoc/p12ch42.htm.
Rosen, Michael. 2012. Dignity: Its History and Meaning. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1754. Discourse on the Origin of
Inequality, translated by Franklin Philip; edited by Patrick
Coleman. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1994.
Sachedina, Abdulaziz. 2009. Islam and the Challenge of Human
Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.
Simpson, Alfred William Brian. 2004. Human Rights and the End of
Empire: Britain and the Genesis of the European Convention.
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Smith, Adam. 1759. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. New York:
Gutenberg Publishers, 2011.
Tu, Weiming. 2001. “The Global Significance of Local Knowledge: A
New Perspective on Confucian Humanism.” Sungkyun Journal of
East Asian Studies 1 (1): 22–27. Accessed November 29, 2013.
http://sjeas.skku.edu/upload/200605/Tu%20Weiming.pdf.
UN Development Programme. 1990. Human Development Report
1990. New York: Oxford University Press. Accessed November 29,
2013. http://hdr.undp.org/en/reports/global/hdr1990/chapters/.
———. 2000. Human Development Report 2000. New York: Oxford
University Press. Accessed November 29, 2013.
http://hdr.undp.org/en/media/HDR_2000_EN.pdf.
UN Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO).
1945. Constitution of the United Nations Educational, Scientific
and Cultural Organization. UNESCO. November 16. 4 UNTS 275.
http://portal.unesco.org/en/ev.php-
URL_ID=15244&URL_DO=DO_TOPIC&URL_SECTION=201.html.
UN General Assembly. 1948. “Universal Declaration of Human
Rights.” UN Document A/81, December 10.
———. 2000. “Resolution 55/2: United Nations Millennium
Declaration.” UN Document A/RES/55/2, September 18.
Waldron, Jeremy. 2012. Dignity, Rank, and Rights, edited by Meir
Dan-Cohen. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wesley, John. 1757. The Dignity of Human Nature, Library of
Methodist Classics. Nashville, TN: United Methodist Publishing
House.
Witte Jr., John, and Johan D. van der Vyver, eds. 1996. Religious
Human Rights in Global Perspective: Religious Perspectives. The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.
Xinhua News Agency. 2005. “Building Harmonious Society Crucial for
Progress: Hu.” Xinhua News Agency, June 26. Accessed on
November 29, 2013. http://news.xinhuanet.com/english/2005-
06/26/content_3139097.htm.
CHAPTER 13
Growing Religiosity
In his April 2008 speech in Westminster, former British prime
minister Tony Blair highlighted key global shifts and the centrality of
faith in dealing with them: “Under the momentum of globalisation
the world is opening up, and at an astonishing speed. Old
boundaries of culture, identity, and even nationhood are falling. The
twenty-first century world is becoming ever more interdependent.…
Faiths can transform and humanize the interpersonal forces of
globalization, and shape the values of the changing set of economic
and power relationships of the early twenty-first century” (Blair
2008, 1).
Rising global religiosity is a megatrend that defied what many
scholars and practitioners have held as sacred since the Second
World War: the belief that religion would become obsolete as
modernity swept in and the people were exposed to ideas from
different parts of the world (Thomas 2005, 29). For decades,
scholars and practitioners had upheld the theory of secularization,
which posits that with modernization, societies will progress, and
religion will lose its voice in the public realms. Now there is a
growing recognition among scholars that not only is faith not
receding, it is indeed playing a more prominent role in many
societies as a driving force in the foreign and domestic policies of
many countries and in people’s personal experiences, making it a
pivotal and influential motivating factor in the lives of the majority of
people around the world (Thomas 2005, 26; Abrams 2001, viii;
Johnston 1995, 9).
As faith has maintained its centrality in individual lives and
communities, globalization has further bolstered the growth of faith
globally. Through swift technological developments, significant
movements of people, and tremendous connectivity, globalization
has created unprecedented opportunity for connection between
societies and individuals, which has allowed people to learn about
other faiths and for people of faith to become and stay connected
with fellow believers around the world in an unprecedented way.
Whereas scholars believed that increased exposure to a wider
spectrum of information and a plurality of views would weaken
faith’s impact, today’s increased connectivity has allowed people to
be part of active global faith communities rather than experiencing
their faith only in their local context.
Globalization has also brought significant dislocation, societal
upheaval, and the disintegration of conventional community
structures and traditions. Again, scholars believed that faith would
diminish as such traditional community structures are weakened; the
opposite has proven true. People have turned to faith to deal with
personal dislocation and to faith-based groups to address the
negative factors and affronts to human dignity—poverty, injustice,
and suffering—that have come with globalization. Global institutions
and response mechanisms, which have relied heavily on states and
state-based solutions, have often not adequately addressed these
problems or overlooked the importance of faith to aid recipients.
Local faith communities as well as international FBOs—alongside
secular NGOs—have filled the gap in addressing these issues. For
example, a 2007 World Health Organization (WHO) study reported
that between 30 percent and 70 percent of the African health
infrastructure is currently owned by FBOs (WHO 2007, 1). Globally,
one-third of all HIV/AIDS patients are cared for under the auspices
of the Catholic Church (Ferris 2005, 316–17).
Global demographic trends further reinforce this rising religiosity,
indicating that faith will continue to be relevant for the foreseeable
future. Pew Research Center’s Forum on Religion and Public Life
estimates that in 2010 some 5.8 billion of the world’s 6.9 billion
people are religiously affiliated adults and children, representing 84
percent of the world population (Pew 2005, 1). Faith is growing in all
parts of the world, particularly in the global South where the
population size is also increasing. Where faith is receding, as it is in
Europe, the population is shrinking as well. In 1900, 32 percent of
the world’s population was in the North, whereas this number
dropped to 18 percent in 2000 and is projected to be as low as 10
percent in 2050 (Thomas 2010, 93). The global percentage of world
population that is Christian has remained the same from 1910 to
2010, approximately 32 to 35 percent, but the percentage of those
Christians living in Europe or the United States dropped from 93
percent of the global population in 2010 to 63 percent in 2010.
Global faith communities are also growing significantly; for example,
the world’s Muslim population is expected to increase by
approximately 35 percent over the next two decades, rising from
2010’s level of 1.6 billion to 2.2 billion by 2030 (Pew 2005, 1).
Former administrator of the United States Agency for International
Development Andrew Natsios’s observation that “While most
American and European foreign policy elites may hold a secular
worldview, much of the rest of the world lives in one of the great
religious traditions” highlights the differing lenses of understanding
between the West and the remainder of the world (Thomas 2004,
23).
Micah 6:8
Heal the sick who are there and tell them, “The
kingdom of God is near you.”
The Challenges
Although these external and internal factors have combined to pave
the way for FBOs to play a greater role on the international stage,
the picture of FBOs’ engagement is naturally not a perfectly rosy
one. The expanding role of FBOs comes with significant challenges
and complications.
The receptivity that FBOs enjoy with local populations is not
uniform. Although it is impossible to measure the degree and
frequency with which faith, in and of itself, is the singular factor that
spurs rejection, FBOs do experience opposition from local
communities due in part to their faith identity, and at times the
skepticism and mistrust FBOs have met because of their faith or
national origin directly impact their ability to operate. In the
developing world, long histories of colonialism and interventionism
have left some populations skeptical of Western Christian FBOs,
seeing them as part of a broader effort to expand Western influence
or convert locals to Christianity even when Christian FBOs have
humanitarian objectives that are similar to secular organizations.
Related to this, many countries—particularly those for whom the
concept of separating faith and state is unfamiliar—find the notion
that foreign governments hire FBOs solely for humanitarian purposes
suspect at best. Some populations have viewed Western
governments’ use of FBOs as a covert means to infiltrate societies to
spread Christianity as opposed to provide humanitarian or other
services. Likewise, in countries in which Muslim FBOs are active,
Western governments and donors have raised concerns about
whether these groups have links to Islamic terrorist or other radical
organizations (Barnett and Stein 2011, 7). Both of these perceptions
have impacted FBOs’ ability to operate on the ground.
There are ongoing debates about whether secular governments,
international organizations, and financial institutions should fund
FBOs or whether this violates the separation between faith and
public institutions. One particularly contentious element of this
debate has been what the correct balance is between FBOs’
exercising their freedom of religion and expression versus broader
concerns about nondiscrimination in hiring.2 Likewise, many in
Western donor countries and international organizations have
debated the extent to which FBOs should have influence on the
policy process. Some have argued that the growing influence of
FBOs on the decision-making process of governments is another
instance where faith groups overstep boundaries, violating the
separation of faith and state (Haynes 2010, 389). Others argue that
FBOs, just like any other subset of society, should be able to
influence the public policy process. Additionally, some recipient
communities are skeptical that FBOs are capable of or committed to
providing services without proselytizing, given the strong faith
adherence of staff, even when performing nonproselytizing activities.
Similarly, some donor organizations and governments remain
concerned that FBOs will proselytize with public funds meant for
other work (Abrams 2001, 184). Each of these issues adds a
challenging layer to FBOs’ engagement on policy and programmatic
issues.
There continue to be differing views between religious and
secular communities around key family issues, such as sexual
orientation, women’s rights, reproductive rights, and family planning.
How the agency and social recognition dimensions of human dignity
apply to these specific issues has been at the core of significant
substantive clashes between these communities.
These are just a few of the challenges that have emerged with
the changing role of FBOs, making clear that this growing role is not
without serious, substantive controversy or complications. These
important debates, however, also illustrate and reinforce the thesis
of this chapter: Faith and FBOs have moved into the public sphere
and have become global institutions impacting human dignity. If
faith were irrelevant or FBOs largely ineffective, faith and FBOs
would be sidelined or absent from the global stage, and these
debates would dissipate. Because faith has become more central to
the debate on international issues and faith-based actors more vocal
on matters of human dignity, FBOs’ perspectives on human dignity
are germane, whether in congruence or conflict with other voices.
Likewise, if the concept of human dignity did not resonate with such
a significant portion of the global population, it too would not be
gaining traction within the international community.
Notes
1. In this chapter the term “liberal” refers to the political
philosophy based on the ideals of equality and liberty, as well as
pluralism and tolerance. It should be distinguished from the use of
the word “liberal” within the context of current US political debates
between liberal and conservative political groups.
2. Most FBOs require staff to adhere to specific faith doctrines
and have policies that follow their faith tradition, such as the
recognition of marriage as a union between one man and one
woman or opposition to birth control. Public policy debates have
emerged when FBOs that have internal policies that differ from legal
rights granted in the wider national context have sought public
funding.
References
Abrams, Elliott. 2001. The Influence of Faith: Religious Groups and
U.S. Foreign Policy. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield.
Aga Khan Development Network. 2013. “Frequently Asked
Questions”. Accessed August 8, 2013.
http://www.akdn.org/faq.asp.
American Jewish World Service (AJWS). 2011. “2011 Annual Report.”
Accessed August 1, 2013. ajws.org.
Barnett, Michael, and Janice Gross Stein. 2011. Sacred Aid: Faith and
Humanitarianism. New York: Oxford University Press.
Blair, Tony. 2008. “Faith and Globalisation” (speech). The Cardinal’s
Lectures 2008. Westminster Cathedral. London, April 3.
Catholic Relief Services. 2013. “HIV Healing Now in Local Church
Hands.” Accessed August 8, 2013. http://crs.org/south-africa/hiv-
care-transition/.
Duffy Toft, Monica, Daniel Philpott, and Timothy Shah. 2011. God’s
Century: Resurgent Religion and Global Politics. New York: W. W.
Norton & Company.
Economist. 2009. “A Slow Maturing of Democracy: The
Latinobarómetro Poll.” Economist, December 12.
http://www.economist.com/node/15080535.
Ferris, Elizabeth. 2005. “Faith-based and Secular Humanitarian
Organizations.” International Review of the Red Cross. Accessed
June 2005.
https://www.icrc.org/eng/resources/documents/article/review/rev
iew-858-p311.htm.
Global Fund. 2010. “Update on the Report on the Involvement of
Faith-Based Organizations in the Global Fund.” Accessed August
8, 2013.
http://www.theglobalfund.org/documents/civil_society/CivilSociet
y_InvolvemenOfFaithBasedOrganizationsInTheGlobalFund_Report
_en/.
Haynes, Jeffrey. 2010. Routledge Handbook of Religion and Politics.
Oxford: Routledge.
Johnston, Douglas. 1995. The Missing Dimension of Statecraft. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Juergensmeyer, Mark. 2003. Terror in the Mind of God: The Global
Rise of Religious Violence. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Kaldor, Mary, Henrietta L. Moorem, and Sabine Selchow. 2012.
Global Civil Society 2012: Ten Years of Critical Reflection. UK:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Narayan, Deepa, Robert Chambers, Meera Kaul Shah, and Patti
Petesch. 2000. Voices of the Poor: Crying Out for Change. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Narayan, Deepa, Raj Patel, Kai Schafft, Anne Rademacher, and Sarah
Koch-Schulte. 2000. Voices of the Poor: Can Anyone Hear Us?
New York: Oxford University Press.
Oomman, Nandini, Michael Bernstein, and Steven Rosenzweig. 2008.
“PEPFAR Funding for Fiscal Years 2004 to 2006: The Numbers
Behind the Stories.” Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.cgdev.org/files/15799_file_theNumbersBehindTheSto
ries.PDF.
Pew Forum on Religion and Public Life. 2005. “Event: Building a
‘Harmonious Society’ in China.” Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.pewforum.org/2005/09/26/building-a-harmonious-
society-in-china/.
———. 2006. “Interview: Katherine Marshall.” Accessed August 1,
2013. http://www.pewforum.org/Government/Religion-and-
International-Development.aspx.
Thomas, Scott M. 2004. “Faith and Foreign Aid: How the World Bank
Got Religion, and Why It Matters.” The Brandywine Review of
Faith & International Affairs 2 (2): 21–29.
———. 2005. The Global Resurgence of Religion and the
Transformation of International Relations: The Struggle for the
Soul of the Twenty-First Century. UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
———. 2010. “A Globalized God: Religion’s Growing Influence in
International Politics.” Foreign Affairs 89: 93.
United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR). 2007.
“NGO Partnerships in Refugee Protection.” Accessed August 1,
2013. http://www.refworld.org/docid/47a7078f0.html.
World Health Organization (WHO). 2007. “Faith-Based Organizations
Play a Major Role in HIV/AIDS Care and Treatment in Sub-
Saharan Africa.” Accessed August 1, 2013.
http://www.who.int/mediacentre/news/notes/2007/np05/en/.
World Vision International. 2011. “Annual Report 2011.” Accessed
August 1, 2013. http://www.wvi.org/publication/world-vision-
international-annual-review-2011.
CHAPTER 14
Corporate Challenges
The principal challenge in this context for companies in the ICT
sector arises where the law, or the day-to-day practice by
government entities and officials, in a foreign country in which a
company is doing business comes into conflict with internationally
recognized human rights enshrined in the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights (UDHR) and other international accords, such as the
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights or the
International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights.
Companies, once they establish local operations in a certain
jurisdiction, are bound as a matter of corporate legal obligation, to
follow the law in those places, including the laws involving the
regulation of online speech and government access to online records
and activities. Failure by a locally incorporated entity to follow the
laws of that state might jeopardize the freedom, or even the safety,
of the company’s employees, potentially substituting one human
rights challenge for another. Criminal penalties, including
imprisonment, are real risks for locally-based employees who
disobey local laws. The decision to open a locally incorporated
business, with all it entails from a local legal perspective, is a
threshold decision companies should only make after thorough due
diligence on the implications for both users and local employees.
In thinking about these challenges while working at Yahoo!, we
posed questions on the company’s public-facing corporate blog to
give others a sense of some of the freedom of expression and
privacy challenges confronting the business as it expanded into new,
more politically restrictive international markets. These questions
included:
Background
The UDHR was adopted with near unanimity by the UN General
Assembly on December 10, 1948, in the aftermath of World War II
and the state-directed genocide of the Holocaust. Although UN
member states subsequently adopted covenants including the
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, the focus for
purposes of this chapter is on certain provisions of the UDHR itself.
For the discussion on freedom of expression and privacy in the ICT
sector, UDHR Articles 19 and 12 apply. Article 19 states: “Everyone
has the right to freedom of opinion and expression; this right
includes freedom to hold opinions without interference and to seek,
receive, and impart information and ideas through any media and
regardless of frontiers.” Article 12 states: “No one shall be subjected
to arbitrary interference with his privacy, family, home, or
correspondence, nor to attacks upon his honour and reputation.
Everyone has the right to the protection of the law against such
interference or attacks” (UN General Assembly 1948).
Why have human rights become an issue for companies? Nobel
economics laureate Milton Friedman’s theory of corporate
responsibility is that a corporation’s principal task is to follow the law
and maximize value for shareholders. Although he noted that a
company may realize long-term benefits from other activities,
potentially including social responsibility work, his overall point is
clear on the primary responsibilities that should drive corporate
decision making (Friedman 1970). This view is often echoed in the
corporate community, and the argument most often advanced is that
human rights are the responsibilities of governments.
This industry position sidesteps the point that even though
governments have assumed primary responsibility in the
international system to protect human rights, nonstate actors also
have human rights obligations. Whereas the UDHR does not
explicitly mention corporations, its preamble refers to individuals
“and every organ of society,” a term suggesting the obligations
enshrined in the document may indeed apply under international law
to organs such as corporations in addition to states themselves. The
idea that corporations may have responsibilities pursuant to
international legal norms or by some accounts even under domestic
law (with a number of cases filed in the United States under the
Alien Tort Claims Act for example), beyond the treatment of their
own employees, with respect to human rights in the communities in
which they operate, is a newly evolving field.
Until the 1980s, there was only limited public focus on companies
as defenders of human rights. The environmental movement, as
applied to business, was brought further into the international
community’s focus by the chemical plant disaster in Bhopal, India in
1984 with the devastating loss of human life resulting from industrial
gas leaks at a corporate pesticide-producing facility. In the 1990s,
supply chain and labor rights abuses in the apparel industry became
global issues, as newspaper headlines announced stories of
sweatshops and child labor. At the same time, the oil, gas, and
mining industries came under the spotlight for environmental
degradation, labor abuses, and community safety and security
concerns. With the growing focus on the sometimes direct role of
companies infringing on human rights, company codes of conduct
became common by the end of the 1990s.
Recommendations
The practical approach set out in this chapter is based principally on
a business and human rights program created at Yahoo! and
formally launched in 2008.2 This section recommends steps essential
to building and sustaining a human rights program in the ICT
industry. Although each company should tailor its human rights
program to meet the needs of its multiple internal and external
stakeholders, these steps should form a common thread in any
program.
Executive Commitment
A corporate human rights program must have executive level
commitment within the company. The board of directors, corporate
executive officer, and senior executives must actively support the
company’s commitment to human rights and understand their own
roles and responsibilities in ensuring the company fulfills its
commitments in this area. The message, importance, and urgency of
human rights in a corporation emanates from the top of the
personnel hierarchy, much in the same way business priorities are
established for a company and then implemented throughout the
corporate ranks. The executive commitment should be
communicated directly to employees to have maximum impact. The
corporation should also make a public commitment to human rights.
In the ICT sector, this is becoming increasingly important since
global intersection points with freedom of expression and privacy
have become commonplace.
Many socially responsible investment firms (SRIs) and other
individual and institutional investors have suggested, often through
corporate shareholder resolutions, that company boards of directors
form human rights committees responsible for overseeing corporate
human rights practices. Corporate legal teams usually respond to
these proposals with the argument that given the role of directors
versus management teams, the direct responsibility for human rights
oversight is more appropriately aligned with executive and
operational management than board direction. This mostly
persuasive response emphasizes that day-to-day decision making on
human rights at the board level confuses the role of a board and its
executive management team.
Informing board members in detail of the potential human rights
issues associated with the industry and giving in-depth background
on a company’s responsibilities must be a part of board of director
training, whether for new or existing board members. Bringing
strategic issues to the board’s attention in a timely manner is
essential; however, relying on regular board decisions is less
effective than positioning that responsibility in the hands of a
dedicated team that has executive officer input and support and the
ability to act with sufficient speed, understanding, and resources.
Whatever corporate approach taken with respect to senior-level
commitment and oversight, a company must have inward and
outward facing executive and senior-level commitment to human
rights, including from its board of directors. This is particularly true
in a global ICT business where the nature of the business itself
directly implicates two internationally recognized human rights.
Accountability Framework
Companies working to protect human rights should design and
implement an effective accountability framework beginning with an
internal human rights system and results assessment. This
framework should also include incentives for employee compliance
as well as consequences for failure to follow company guidelines. An
internal review, which may follow many of the same principles used
by existing internal financial or other audit and compliance teams,
can combine systems review, data analysis, and in-person
assessments to measure and evaluate a company’s compliance with
its own operational guidelines. The accountability framework should
be closely connected to the human rights touch-point inventory,
following the nexus between business operations and human rights
issues.
An internal assessment is also essential to pave the way for
external review and assessment. Public credibility for companies’
respect for human rights will also come from submitting to an
independent external assessment. Initiatives like GNI should model
the way for assessments. GNI’s assessment system is designed
around third-party review of a member company’s process for
anticipating and dealing with human rights issues, and the
assessment progresses into results analysis—all with a view to
assisting companies to strengthen their processes and operational
steps to protect freedom of expression and privacy. It is designed to
be compatible with a highly competitive industry and as a result
does not reveal sensitive corporate data between companies or to
the public. Numerous safeguards are in place to ensure
confidentiality in key areas. The direct goal of the GNI assessment is
to assist the companies in strengthening their internal systems
designed to protect human rights.
Another aspect of an accountability framework is for companies,
similar to those in multistakeholder initiatives, to create dispute
resolution channels for users with legitimate complaints regarding
corporate actions impacting human rights. With the global reach of
the products and services in the ICT sector, an effective corporate
dispute resolution process, or grievance mechanism, must be
manageable and scalable—a substantial challenge given the universe
of company consumers online.
Notes
1. I raised these questions in a previously written blog for Yahoo!
Inc. The 2007 post can be accessed on the Yahoo! Business and
Human Rights Program website: http://yahoobhrp.tumblr.com/press-
archive.
2. More on this can be found in my 2008 blog on the Yahoo!
Business and Human Rights Program.
3. The Global Network Initiative, a multistakeholder group of
companies, civil society organizations (including human rights and
press freedom groups), investors, and academics, was created in
2008 to foster a collaborative approach to protect and advance
freedom of expression and privacy in the ICT sector globally. For
more information, see http://www.globalnetworkinitiative.org.
References
Bader, Christine. 2008. “Beyond CSR: How Companies Can Respect
Human Rights.” Stanford Social Innovation Review 6 (4).
Clinton, Hillary. 2010. “Remarks on Internet Freedom.” The
Newseum. Washington, DC, January 21.
Friedman, Milton. 1970. “The Social Responsibility of Business Is to
Increase Its Profits.” The New York Times Magazine, September
13.
MacKinnon, Rebecca. 2012. Consent of the Networked: The
Worldwide Struggle for Internet Freedom. New York: Basic
Books.
Morozov, Evgeny. 2012. The Net Delusion: The Dark Side of Internet
Freedom. New York: Public Affairs.
Posner, Michael. 2012. “Assistant Secretary Posner’s Speech on
Internet Freedom” (speech). State of the Net Conference.
Washington, DC, January 17.
Ruggie, John. 2011. “Guiding Principles on Business and Human
Rights, Implementing the United Nations ‘Protest, Respect and
Remedy’ Framework.” UN Document A/HRC/17/31, March 21.
UN General Assembly. 1948. Universal Declaration of Human Rights
(UDHR). December 10.
PART III
In the introductory chapter of this book we set forth the two goals
of our project: First, we sought to explore the extent to which
human dignity is already embedded in the practices of international
institutions. Second, we sought to develop ways in which human
dignity can play more of a role in the work of these institutions. As
this book reaches an end, it is clear that there is still much work to
be done. On one hand, the book points to areas of future research
by others. On the other hand, the conclusions of the authors of this
project invite a more thorough discussion in this chapter about how
a dialogue on dignity can be constructed. What can be said about
these two areas?
References
Albright, Madeleine. 1998. Interview by Matt Lauer on the Today
show. February 19. Accessed April 23, 2014.
http://www.fas.org/news/iraq/1998/02/19/98021907_tpo.html.
Alexandroff, Alan S. 2010. “Challenges in Global Governance:
Opportunities for G-x Leadership.” The Stanley Foundation.
Accessed October 10, 2013.
www.stanleyfoundation.org/publications/pab/AlexandroffPAB310.
pdf.
Aristotle. 1999. Nicomachean Ethics, translated by Terence Irwin.
2nd ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.
Bacevich, Andrew. 2008. The Limits of Power: The End of American
Exceptionalism. New York: Macmillan.
Bloom, Allan David, trans. 1991. The Republic of Plato. New York:
Basic Books.
Central Intelligence Agency (CIA). 2013. “World Factbook.” Accessed
September 9, 2013. https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-
world-factbook/geos/xx.html.
Dolan, Michael, and Chris Hunt. 1998. “Negotiating in the Ottawa
Process: The New Multilateralism.” Canadian Foreign Policy
Journal 5 (3): 25–50.
Doyle, Michael W. 1983. “Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs.”
Philosophy and Public Affairs I and II: 205–35, 323–53.
———. 1986. “Liberalism and World Politics.” American Political
Science Review 80 (4): 1151-69.
Dybul, Mark, Peter Piot, and Julio Frenk. 2012. “Reshaping Global
Health.” Policy Review 173: 3-18.
Ford Motor Company. 2010/2011. “Case Study: Forced Labor in the
Pig Iron Supply Chain in Brazil.” Ford Motor Company. Accessed
September 1, 2013.
http://corporate.ford.com/microsites/sustainability-report-2010-
11/issues-supply-materials-brazil.
Fukuyama, Francis. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. New
York: Free Press.
Ghonim, Wael. 2012. Revolution 2.0: The Power of the People Is
Greater than the People in Power: A Memoir. New York:
Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.
Ignatieff, Michael. 2012. “Reimagining a Global Ethic.” Ethics &
International Affairs 26(1): 7-19.
Ikenberry, G. John. 2011. “The Future of the Liberal World Order:
Internationalism after America.” Foreign Affairs 90 (3): 56-68.
Johnson, Chalmers. 2007. Nemesis: The Last Days of the American
Republic. New York: Metropolitan Books.
Jorgensen, Rikke Frank. 2013. Framing the Net: The Internet and
Human Rights. Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar Publishing.
Kung, Hans. 1990. Global Responsibility: In Search of a New World
Ethic, translated by John Bowden. London: SCM Press Ltd.
Kung, Hans, and Helmut Schmidt, eds. 1993. A Global Ethics and
Global Responsibilities: Two Declarations, translated by John
Bowden. London: SCM Press Ltd.
Kupchan, Charles A. 2012. No One’s World: The West, the Rising
Rest, and the Coming Global Turn. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Newman, Edward, and Roland Rich, eds. 2004. The United Nations
Role in Promoting Democracy: Between Ideals and Reality. New
York: United Nations University Press.
Nussbaum, Martha C. 1997. “Capabilities and Human Rights.”
Fordham Law Review 66 (2): 273-300.
———. 2001. Women and Human Development. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Knopf
Publishing Group.
Shorr, David. 2012. “Making the G—20 a Reservoir of Global
Leadership—A Maximalist Argument.” The Stanley Foundation.
Accessed October 10, 2013.
www.stanleyfoundation.org/publications/pab/ShorrPAB411.pdf.
Slaughter, Anne-Marie. 2009. “America’s Edge: Power in a Networked
Century.” Foreign Affairs 88 (1): 94–113.
Sunstein, Cass R. 1996. “Social Norms and Social Roles.” Columbia
Law Review 96 (4): 903–68.
Vance, Cyrus. 1977. “Human Rights and Foreign Policy” (address).
University of Georgia Law Day Ceremonies on April 30, 1977.
Accessed September 18, 2013.
http://digitalcommons.law.uga.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?
article=1015&context=lectures_pre_arch_lectures_lawday.
Weber, Katja. 2011. “Lessons from the ASEAN Regional Forum:
Transcending the Image of Paper Tiger?” In The Security
Governance of Regional Organizations, edited by Emil J. Kirchner
and Roberto Dominguez. New York: Routledge.
CONTRIBUTORS
Anthony Clark Arend
Professor of Government and Foreign Service and director of the
Master of Science in Foreign Service at the Walsh School of Foreign
Service at Georgetown University. He is author of Pursuing a Just
and Durable Peace: John Foster Dulles and International
Organization; Legal Rules and International Society; co-author of
International Law and the Use of Force: Beyond the UN Charter
Paradigm; editor and contributor of The United States and the
Compulsory Jurisdiction of the International Court of Justice; co-
editor and contributor of The Falklands War: Lessons for Strategy,
Diplomacy, and International Law; International Rules: Approaches
from International Law and International Relations.
Thomas Banchoff
At Georgetown University, he serves as vice president for global
engagement; director of the Berkley Center for Religion, Peace, and
World Affairs; and professor in the Government Department and the
School of Foreign Service. His research centers on religious and
ethical issues in world politics. He is the author of Embryo Politics:
Ethics and Policy in Atlantic Democracies; The German Problem
Transformed: Institutions, Politics, and Foreign Policy, 1945–1995;
co-author of Legitimacy and the European Union: The Contested
Polity; editor of Religious Pluralism, Globalization, and World Politics;
Democracy and the New Religious Pluralism; and co-editor of
Religion and the Global Politics of Human Rights.
Benjamin Boudreaux
Foreign affairs officer at the Office of the Coordinator for Cyber
Issues at the US Department of State, where he is responsible for
the Middle East and South Asia portfolio. He holds a Ph.D. in
philosophy from the University of California, Berkeley with an area of
specialty in political philosophy, and a master of science in Foreign
Service from Georgetown University. He formerly worked at the US
Institute of Peace.
Chester A. Crocker
James R. Schlesinger Professor of Strategic Studies at the Walsh
School of Foreign Service at Georgetown University. He served as
assistant secretary for African Affairs at the US Department of State,
chairman of the board at the US Institute of Peace and is founding
member of the Global Leadership Foundation. He is the author of
High Noon in Southern Africa: Making Peace in a Rough
Neighborhood; co-author of Rewiring Regional Security in a
Fragmented World; America’s Role in the World: Foreign Policy
Choices for the Next Administration; Taming Intractable Conflicts:
Mediation in the Hardest Cases; Turbulent Peace: The Challenges of
Managing International Conflict; Herding Cats: Multiparty Mediation
in a Complex World; Managing Global Chaos: Origins of and
Responses to International Conflict; African Conflict Resolution: The
US Role; co-editor of Leashing the Dogs of War: Conflict
Management in a Divided World; Grasping the Nettle: Analyzing
Cases of Intractable Conflict.
John J. DeGioia
President of Georgetown University and member of the faculty of the
Department of Philosophy at Georgetown University.
Raj M. Desai
Associate professor of International Development at the Walsh
School of Foreign Service and in the Department of Government at
Georgetown University. He is a nonresident senior fellow at the
Brookings Institution. He formerly served as a private sector
development specialist at the World Bank. He is an author of World
Development Report 2005: A Better Investment Climate for
Everyone.
Ryan Kaminski
Leo Nevas human rights fellow with the United Nations Association
of the USA. He is a former research associate in the International
Institutions and Global Governance Program at the Council on
Foreign Relations.
Homi Kharas
Senior fellow and deputy director in the Global Economy and
Development program of the Brookings Institution in Washington,
DC. He is formerly lead author and executive secretary of the
secretariat supporting the High Level Panel advising the UN
secretary-general on the post—2015 development agenda.
Previously, he spent twenty-six years at the World Bank, serving for
seven years as chief economist for the World Bank’s East Asia and
Pacific region and as director for Poverty Reduction and Economic
Management. He is co-author of After the Spring: Economic
Transitions in the Arab World and Catalyzing Development: A New
Vision for Aid.
Mark P. Lagon
Chair for global politics and security and professor in the practice of
international affairs within the Master of Science in Foreign Service
Program at Georgetown University. He served as ambassador-rank
director of the Office to Monitor and Combat Trafficking in Persons;
deputy assistant secretary of state for International Organization
Affairs; and as executive director and CEO of Polaris Project. He is
author of The Reagan Doctrine: Sources of American Conduct in the
Cold War’s Last Chapter.
Tod Lindberg
Research fellow at the Hoover Institution and adjunct faculty at
Georgetown University. He was previously editor of the journal Policy
Review. Formerly senior staff member, Genocide Prevention Task
Force, US Holocaust Memorial Museum. He is author of The Political
Teaching of Jesus; co-author of Means to an End: U.S. Interest in
the International Criminal Court; editor of Beyond Paradise and
Power: Europe, the United States and the Future of a Troubled
Partnership; co-editor of Bridging the Foreign Policy Divide.
Rosalía Rodriguez-García
Currently, adviser to the International Labor Organization, UNAIDS,
and the World Bank. Formerly the World Bank’s team leader of a
major research portfolio on community-level effects of HIV/AIDS
investments and co-Chair of the UN Cosponsoring Agencies Group of
UNAIDS (2012). Previously, senior adviser in the Global Fund to
Fight AIDS, Tuberculosis, and Malaria; and professor and chair of
International Health at George Washington University, from which
she holds a PhD. She is co-author of Investing in Communities
Achieves Results: Findings from an Evaluation of Community
Responses to HIV and AIDS; Self-Assessment in Managing for
Results: Conducting Self-Assessment for Development Practitioners;
Microenterprise Development for Better Health Outcomes.
Michael A. Samway
Former vice president and deputy general counsel of Yahoo! Inc. He
is founder of Yahoo!’s Business and Human Rights Program and a
co-founding board member of the Global Network Initiative.
Anoop Singh
Managing director and head of regulatory strategy and policy, Asia
Pacific, with JP Morgan in Hong Kong. He wrote his chapter herein
as director of the Asia-Pacific Department of the International
Monetary Fund. He previously served as director of the Western
Hemisphere Department, and director of Special Operations, at the
IMF. He has been adjunct faculty at the Master of Science in Foreign
Service Program at Georgetown University. He is co-editor of
Australia Benefiting from Economic Reform; Stabilization and Reform
in Latin America; and Macroeconomic Issues Facing ASEAN
Countries.
Nancy E. Soderberg
Senior fellow at the Enough Project. She is former president of
Connect US Fund. She served as ambassador-rank alternate
representative to the UN and as deputy assistant to the president for
national security affairs on the National Security Council. She is
author of The Superpower Myth: The Use and Misuse of American
Might; co-author of The Prosperity Agenda: What the World Wants
from America—and What We Need in Return.
Abiodun Williams
President of The Hague Institute for Global Justice. From 2008 to
2012, he served at the United States Institute of Peace, first as vice
president of the Center for Conflict Analysis and Prevention and later
as senior vice president of the Center for Conflict Management. From
2001 to 2007, Dr. Williams was director of Strategic Planning for UN
Secretaries-General Ban Ki-Moon and Kofi Annan. He served as
associate dean of the Africa Center for Strategic Studies at the
National Defense University in Washington, DC, and held faculty
appointments at Georgetown, Rochester, and Tufts universities. He is
author of The Brilliant Art of Peace: Lectures from the Kofi Annan
Series; Preventing War: The United Nations and Macedonia; and the
editor of Many Voices: Multilateral Negotiations in the World Arena.
INDEX
Abu Ghraib prison scandal, 153
accountability measures: atrocity response, 132–34
corporate responsibility in human rights and, 312–13
global human rights regime and, 124
Acemoglu, Daron, 105
advanced democracies, human dignity in, 260–62
Afghanistan, de facto statelessness in, 216
Africa: anticolonialism in, 259
atrocity prevention organizations in, 39–40
human dignity discourse in, 260–62
International Criminal Court and, 44–45
Multi-country AIDS Program (MAP) in, 173
patrilineal descent and citizenship in, 213
sexual rights in, 142
statelessness in, 222–23
African Union (AU), 85
Constitutive Act of, 93
empowerment and action from, 142
human rights monitoring and, 131
regionalism in, 90, 127
security architecture in, 91–93, 96
U.S. ambassadors to, 89
Aga Khan Development Network, 284
agency: costs of, 196–202
HIV/AIDS management and, 182–83
human dignity and, 15–16, 322
microlending programs and, 199–200
poverty alleviation and role of, 190–91
private aid and personal agency, 196–202
aggregate indicators, 121n5
AIDS Relief consortium, 286
Albright, Madeleine (Secretary of State), 331
Alien Tort Claims Act (U.S.), 302
Alliance against Trafficking in Persons, 237
Alliance Export Coordination Team (ACET), human trafficking
initiatives and, 236–37
Alm, James, 193
al-Qaeda: September 11, 2001 attacks by, 154
Syrian crisis and, 35, 154
American Jewish World Service, 284
American Revolution, human dignity and, 259
American Service-Members’ Protection Act of 2002, 44–45
Amnesty International, human rights discourse and, 7
The Anarchical Society (Bull), 2–3, 5
ancient philosophy: Fukuyama and, 14
human dignity in, 9, 15
Andreoni, James, 192
Annan, Kofi (UN Secretary-General), 18, 23, 36
atrocity prevention and, 133–34
career highlights of, 69
economic rights and, 136–37
Global Compact and, 302–3
HIV/AIDS initiatives and, 175
human dignity and case study of, 67–83
human security concept and, 87–88
institutional reform for promotion of human dignity, 76–78
Kosovo crisis and, 31
legacy of, 81–82
norm-creation and norm-implementation by, 70–75
program operations and evaluations under, 78–81
Responsibility to Protect doctrine and, 28
“Annan doctrine,” Responsibility to Protect and, 75
anti-demand efforts, human trafficking prevention and, 247–49
anti-money laundering and countering the Financing of terrorism
(AML/CFT) policy, 118–20
Anti-Personnel Mine Ban Convention, 127
antiretroviral therapy (ART), regulatory approval of, 169
anti-stateless regime, proposal for development of, 220–23
Aquinas, Thomas, 263
Arab League: dignitarian dialogue and, 327–28
Libyan crisis and, 34, 127
regional security and, 92–93
Syrian crisis and, 35–37. See also League of Arab States
Arab Spring, 39–40, 99, 135, 268, 297
social media tools and, 330–32
women and children’s rights and, 137–38
Arab states, atrocity prevention organizations in, 39–40
Arbour, Louise, 78
Arend, Anthony Clark, 18, 23, 151–63, 195, 199, 209, 228n6, 251,
277, 319–34
Arendt, Hannah, 207–10, 212, 217, 221, 227
Aristotle: on human dignity, 9, 322
on role of state, 212
ASEAN Way, 246–47, 328
Asia: anticolonialism in, 259
Confucianism in, 269–70
human dignity discourse in, 260–62
human trafficking in, 236
regional human rights organizations in, 127
regional security in, 94
statelessness in, 222–23
Assad, Bashar al-, 35–37
Assembly of States Parties, 45, 59–60
Association of Southeast Asian Nations (ASEAN), 89, 96, 127, 142,
246–47, 328
Association of Volunteers in International Service and Interplast
Holland, 57–48
asylum seekers, de jure stateless persons and, 214
ATEST alliance (Alliance To End Slavery and Trafficking), 250
Atrocities Prevention Board (U.S.), 45
atrocity prevention: global human rights regime and, 123–28
human rights/human dignity language and, 61–63
institutionalized response to, 132–34
International Criminal Court and, 50, 58–60
regional organizations for, 39–40
selective action concerning, 132–34
UN Security Council and, 30
attachment, de facto statelessness and, 218–20
Aum Shinrikyo, 158
Aung San Suu Kyi, 1, 20n1
Australian Aid, 246
authoritarian regimes, information and communications technology
in, 298–99
Axworthy, Lloyd, 325–26
racial sovereignty, 90
racism, group rights and, 140–41
Reagan, Ronald, faith-based organizations and, 280–81
Reagan Doctrine, 3
recipients’ perspectives on economic aid, 197–202
faith-based organizations and issues of, 287–88
recognition, human dignity and, 15–16, 322
Red Army, 158
Red Brigade, 158
Redress institution, 58
Refugee Convention (1951), 212–15, 214–15, 220–21
refugee regime, right to nationality and, 210–11
Refugees International, 223–24
regime change, human rights interventions and, 34–35
regime security, regional security organizations and, 94
regional consensus, human rights interventions and, 34–35
regional courts, atrocity response, institutionalization and selective
action concerning, 132–34
regional development banks, 146
regional human rights organizations: atrocity prevention and, 39–40
conflict management and human dignity in, 18
dignitarian dialogue and, 327–32
empowerment of, 141–42
norm and treaty creation and, 128–29
uneven efforts of, 125–28
regional integration, Europe as example of, 3
regionalism, emergence of, 88–91
regional security organizations (RSOs): growing importance of, 88–
91
human dignity and, 85–99
promotion of human dignity agenda and, 91–93
strategies for strengthening of, 93–99
regulatory burden, underground economies and, 109–11
relativist approach to human rights, 72
religiosity, global growth of, 278–80
religious blasphemy laws, 135
religious organizations: freedom of expression for, 135
global politics of human dignity and, 257–72
growing influence of, 5
human dignity and, 19
illiberal actors in, 288–89
joint counterterrorism actions and, 162–63
pluralism in religion and, 320–21
trends in, 280–81. See also faith-based institutions
Renaissance humanism, human dignity in, 258–62
reparations, International Criminal Court and, 56–58
Report of the Panel on UN peace operations (Brahimi Report), 42,
79–80
Reports on the Observance of Standards and Codes (ROSCs), 117–
18
reproductive rights, faith-based organizations and, 287–88
The Republic (Plato), 9, 14
Rerum novarum, 263
Rescue Foundation (India), 240–41
reservations, understandings, and declarations (RUDs), human rights
evasions, 128–29
Reserve Bank of India, 201–2
Responsibility to Protect (R2P) doctrine, 18
Annan’s work for, 68
atrocity prevention and, 133–34
corporate responsibility for human rights and, 303
development of, 28
dignitarian dialogue and, 325–26
formation of, 73–75
International Criminal Court and, 49–64
limits of, 38
regional security organizations and, 87
statelessness and, 225–27
The Retreat of the State: The Diffusion of Power in the World
Economy (Strange), 5
Revolutionary Armed Forces of Colombia FARC, goods and services
provision by, 3–4
Rewards for Justice, 45
Rhine, Russell, 192
Rice, Susan, 25
right to have rights, international law and, 207–27. See also human
rights
Robinson, James, 105
Robinson, Nehemiah, 216
Rockefeller Foundation, 190
Rodriguez-García, Rosalía, 16, 19, 322, 329
Rohyngya minority, Myanmar denial of nationality for, 213
Rome Statute (creating the International Criminal Court), 44–45, 50,
52–53
Article 68, 53
Article 75, 56
Article 79, 56
critical review of, 59–60
norm and treaty creation and, 128–29
violence against women and, 138–39
Roosevelt, Eleanor, Universal Declaration of Human Rights and, xiii,
11–12, 228n5
Roosevelt, Franklin Delano, 334n5
Rosen, Michael, 15
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 259
Roy, Olivier, 283
Ruggie, John, 136, 302–3
Rule of Law: a Global Trust for, 143–44
prosecution of human trafficking and, 244
Rules of Procedure and Evidence (RPE) (ICC): critical review of, 59–
60
victims’
rights and, 52–58
Russia: International Criminal Court and, 44
Kosovo crisis and, 31
Libyan crisis and, 34–35
NATO security programs and, 97
Serbia and, 34
Sierra Leone war crimes tribunal and, 25
sovereignty ideology in, 225
Syrian crisis and, 35–37
UN Security Council membership, 27
Rwanda: genocide in, 26, 74
HIV/AIDS advocacy and, 177, 183
international criminal tribunal in, 43–44
public foreign aid in, 193–94
UN peacekeeping missions in, 43
Waever, Ole, 89
war crimes, terrorism vs., 153
War Crimes Issues, ambassador for (U.S.), 45
war crimes tribunals, in Sierra Leone, 25–26
weapons of mass destruction (WMD), proliferation of, 99
Weis, Paul, 208, 211
Weissbrodt, David S., 216–20
Welch, Jack, 1, 20n1
Wesley, John, 259
Why Nations Fail (Acemoglu and Robinson), 105
Wiepking, Pamala, 191–92
Williams, Abiodun, 23–24, 66–82, 325
Williams, Archbishop Rowan, 1, 20n1
Wokai, 196
women’s rights: faith-based organizations and issues of, 287–88
HIV/AIDS policies and, 173–74
human dignity discourse and, 260–62
human trafficking and, 237–40, 248–49
institutional progress and implementation barriers, 137–40
International Criminal Court initiatives for, 59–60
in Islam, 268
regional rulings against spousal abuse and, 127
right to nationality and, 211
A World Made New (Glendon), 11–12
World Bank: capacity building and, 130–31
dignitarian dialogue and, 327–32
Doing Business database, 110
faith-based organizations and, 280–81
gender inequality and, 139
Governance database of, 112
HIV/AIDS funding by, 19, 169–70, 173–76, 182–83
human rights and, 145–46, xiv
poverty alleviation and economic development and, 189
underground economies and, 110–11
World Conference for Religions of Peace, 278
World Drug Report, 236
World Economic Forum, 80–81
World Food Program, 133–34
World Health Organization (WHO): big data used by, 161
children’s rights and, 139–40
faith-based organizations and, 279–80
global health initiatives and, 329
HIV/AIDS antidiscrimination resolution, 168
human rights and, xiv
rule of law and, 143
World Trade Organization (WTO), 176
capacity building and, 131–32
Chinese censorship and, 134
World Vision Cambodia (WVC), 244–45
World Vision International, 139, 284