Empathy and Political Reasoning
Empathy and Political Reasoning
Political
Belgium, Chile, Ireland, and the UK to test the theoretical
expectations.
Lala Muradova
University of Southampton
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 8EA, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009643603
DOI: 10.1017/9781009643573
© Lala Muradova 2025
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions
of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take
place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.
When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781009643573
First published 2025
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
ISBN 978-1-009-64360-3 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-009-64361-0 Paperback
ISSN 2633-3554 (online)
ISSN 2633-3546 (print)
Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence
or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this
publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will
remain, accurate or appropriate.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning
DOI: 10.1017/9781009643573
First published online: February 2025
Lala Muradova
University of Southampton
Author for correspondence: Lala Muradova, [email protected]
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Contents
1 Introduction 1
References 54
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 1
1 Introduction
How do individuals make up their minds about politics? This question has
sparked a vigorous debate in the study of mass political behavior for the last few
decades. Some scholars contend that citizens can and should engage in political
reflection, while others highlight the biases in human political reasoning that
make reflection impossible. This Element is about the conditions under which
citizens can be motivated to transcend their egocentric biases and engage in
reflection.
Normative democratic theorists expect citizens to engage in reflective polit-
ical thinking, whereby they consider and assimilate diverse and opposing
viewpoints into their thinking, weigh up the pros and cons of an issue or
a candidate, and reexamine their prior beliefs when forming their political
beliefs and attitudes. Aristotle posited that individuals’ political judgments
should be the product of “determined effort, a pausing-and-reflecting, and
a self-distance,” as opposed to “spontaneous, immediate intuition” (Beiner
1983, 105). In Reflective Democracy, Robert Goodin argues that people should
think “long and hard what they want and why [ . . . ], what others want and why,
and how those others’ goals might articulate with their own” (2003, 1). For
Arendt, critical political thinking “is possible only where the standpoints of all
others are open to inspection” (Arendt 1989, 43). Reflection, according to John
Dewey, is the hallmark of democratic citizenship (Dewey 1933).
However, there is a widespread pessimism about the capability and willing-
ness of voters to reflect. This skepticism stems from empirical evidence in
political science and psychology. Research finds that most people rarely think
about opposing perspectives, and when faced with opposing information, they
react defensively by clinging to their existing attitudes and beliefs (Taber and
Lodge 2006). People’s emotional attachment to their favored political party
makes them support their party and endorse party positions, irrespective of
whether these positions reflect citizens’ policy preferences or not (Bartels
2002). This strand of literature concludes that prior political beliefs and social
identities predetermine and shape people’s political beliefs and policy choices.
Those findings prompted some critics to argue that there is a disjuncture
between the normative conceptions about how citizens should reason, and
empirical research on how citizens do think (Achen and Bartels 2016;
Campbell et al. 1960; Converse 1964). Pointing to empirical findings that
citizens have biased, “thin, disorganized and ideologically incoherent” belief
systems (12), Achen and Bartels (2016) argue that the normative democratic
theory, in particular, its deliberative conception, is “unrealistic,” “populist,”
“romanticized,” and “folk”; and “amount[s] to fairy tales” (7). But such an
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
2 Political Psychology
1
Research shows there are also individual-level characteristics that make people either more or less
willing to process political information in a reflective manner (e.g., Arceneaux and Vander Wielen
2017; Bakker et al. 2020; Valli and Nai 2023; see Muradova and Arceneaux 2022a for a review of
the literature). Engaging with this literature, however, falls outside of the scope of this Element.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 3
account of how and under what conditions deliberative institutions have the
potential of providing a fertile environment that facilitates the kind of affective
engagement that enables citizens to connect with each other and experience
empathy for the other side. This elicited empathy motivates individuals to
reflect about their political judgments. In developing my argument, I focus on
structured deliberative forums, because these approximate the ideals of demo-
cratic theorists through their design. Lastly, I explore the upscaling potential of
interpersonal deliberation.
I test my theoretical expectations through the examination of diverse policy
issues, such as abortion, assisting aging populations, climate change, legalizing
assisted dying, and universal basic income, using a mix of experimental, quasi-
experimental, and qualitative data collected from Belgium, Chile, Ireland, and
the UK.
This Element speaks to different strands of literature within political psych-
ology and deliberative democracy. First, the findings have implications for the
contemporary political psychology and communication literatures on political
reasoning, emotions, and attitude formation. It adds to the motivational theories
of political reasoning by showing that empathy for the other side can create
a motivation for individuals to engage in more reflective political reasoning.
The findings are consistent with the argument advanced by George Marcus and
others about the motivating role of some emotions for the deliberativeness of
political reasoning (Marcus et al. 2000; Webster and Albertson 2022). Prior
literature examined the role of different discrete emotions, such as anxiety,
anger, and enthusiasm in individuals’ political reasoning, showing the ways via
which anxiety can lead to more enlightened political judgments. For the first
time in the literature, I argue about and study the motivational effect of another
emotion, empathy, for reflectiveness of people’s political reasoning. I show
that when a political environment triggers empathy for the other side in individ-
uals, this elicited empathy engenders more reflective political reasoning in
individuals.
The findings of this project also hold important implications for the recent
political science literature investigating the role of empathy in politics (Clifford
et al. 2019; McDonald 2023; Simas et al. 2020; Sirin et al. 2016, 2021). This
work has broadly fallen into two distinct camps: (a) the studies that investigate
empathy as a disposition (a stable, trait-level characteristic), and (b) the studies
that examine the effect of perspective-taking interventions, that is, those that
focus on cognitive dimension of empathy. My contribution to this field is (at
least) two-fold. First, contrary to studies suggesting that individual-level dis-
positional empathy is biased against outgroups (Brophy and Mullinix 2024;
Simas et al. 2020), I demonstrate that situational empathy toward the opposing
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
4 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 5
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
6 Political Psychology
Reflection is also distinct from critical reasoning. Both reflection and critical
reasoning require a skeptical mindset when evaluating political information at
hand. Yet reflective reasoning extends past mere skepticism, involving an active
consideration and incorporation of different and opposing perspectives on the
issue or the candidate.
The concept of reflective thinking shares similarities with the concept of
accuracy-motivated reasoning. According to the influential motivated reason-
ing framework, individuals are driven by different goals when processing
political information. Two main motivations guide people’s political reasoning.
The default goal is directional. Political reasoning is directional when individ-
uals are motivated by a goal of protecting their prior beliefs and partisan
identities. When motivated directionally, people process and evaluate new
information through the lens of their existing beliefs and/or partisan attach-
ments. This motivation leads individuals to seek out arguments that align with
their existing beliefs, while deliberately ignoring those that challenge them
(Taber and Lodge 2006). In my conceptualization, directionally motivated
reasoning stands in opposition to what constitutes “reflective reasoning.”
When engaging in directionally motivated thinking, individuals do not consider
or integrate the perspectives of those they disagree with. Neither are they
willing to reconsider their previously held views on a political issue. Their
affective attachments to their prior beliefs and political partisanship drive their
political attitude formation. Conversely, when individuals are motivated by
accuracy goals, they strive to develop a belief or attitude that can be considered
the most correct or optimal (Kunda 1990; Taber and Lodge 2006, 756).
Accuracy-motivated political reasoning, thus, is similar to reflective thinking.
Yet the former fails to fully encapsulate the essence of the latter. Reflection goes
beyond achieving accuracy in political judgments. Reaching accurate judg-
ments may not always be attainable or relevant. It could be conceptually and
empirically much easier to apply “accuracy” to the matters of fact, but less so to
the matters of morality, where different, more other-regarding considerations
should come into play. Moral issues involve complex and nuanced consider-
ations of values, norms and ethics, and the goal of attaining accurate judgments
on such issues may be elusive (if possible, at all). To illustrate this, consider this
(simplified) example about attitude formation on legalizing assisted dying.
Person A holds a belief that it is individuals’ right to decide to die on their
own terms, particularly if they suffer from a terminal illness and, therefore,
supports the legalization of assisted dying. Person B is against legalizing
assisted dying and is convinced that its legalization would put vulnerable
parts of the population, such as the elderly and those with physical and mental
needs, at risk of coercion and pressure. When motivated to think reflectively
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 7
about legalizing assisted dying, Person A should actively consider and integrate
Person B’s opposing perspective. The goal here, however, is not accuracy,
which is impossible, but more reflective judgments.
Another distinct feature of reflection is its nonlinear relationship with attitude
change. I believe this is what makes reflection normatively more desirable than
mere persuasion. Reflective political reasoning offers an opportunity for a shift
in beliefs and/or attitudes, though the change is not always the ultimate outcome
of reflection (Muradova and Arceneaux 2022b, 741). At times, upon hearing the
opposing argument/viewpoint and reflecting upon it, an individual may decide
to update their prior beliefs in the direction of a new piece of information. In
other instances, reflection may ultimately reaffirm one’s initial beliefs or even
strengthen them. Reflection may also encourage behavioral change without
transforming people’s beliefs.2 Furthermore, while observable transformation
of attitudes may capture attitude change post-exposure to an intervention,
reflection may yield changes in beliefs and attitudes in the longer run.
Reflection can also increase future openness and tolerance to opposing views
without immediately altering one’s existing beliefs. Finally, the outcome of
reflection may not warrant any change in people’s political attitudes, either
short- or long-term. I believe all these outcomes are democratically valid, as far
as they are the result of reflective political reasoning.
2
I illustrate this point empirically with an example in Study 2.
3
The expression of “definitional morass” comes from Gerring (2004).
4
Due to space restrictions, I’m unable to discuss the vibrant contemporary debate about the
definition of empathy. For comprehensive and interdisciplinary reviews on empathy, see
Decety (2012) and Stüber (2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
8 Political Psychology
each other, and work in synch (Cikara et al. 2011). Empathy is thus defined as
“actively imagining, feeling and understanding the world from the other per-
son’s vantage point” (Muradova and Arceneaux 2022b, 743). Even though
empathy has a motivational cognitive component (“actively putting yourself
into someone else’s shoes”), it also includes affective reactions of sympathy and
compassion to the target (whose perspective one is taking) and to their emo-
tional experiences (Sirin et al. 2016). I argue that these affective reactions,
together with the parallel processes of understanding where the target is coming
from, influence and motivate our reasoning.
In building my argument, I depart from previous research and focus on
situational empathy, defined as a “situational [empathic] response in specific
situations” (Stüber 2019), rather than a dispositional one. I build on the premise
that social contexts can either activate or depress people’s empathic reactions,
with some contexts exerting a strong influence on individuals’ inclination to
empathize with others (Cheng et al. 2017). Lastly, my focus here is on empathy
targeted toward political opponents, people whom one disagrees with on polit-
ical matters, which I call empathy for the other side. Empathy for the other side
thus entails imagining the feelings and perspectives of someone who does not
share one’s political views on a given issue.
However, actively imagining the world from the vantage point of someone
who doesn’t share our political views may be challenging and come with
inherent biases and barriers. For instance, we may be more predisposed to be
empathetic toward people who share common characteristics or backgrounds
with us. I argue that, for empathy for the other side to happen, at least three
conditions need to be met.
The first necessary condition is for the individual to be actively willing to
engage in empathy – “to put themselves in the shoes of the other,” figuratively
speaking. Empathy is not automatic. It requires a personal commitment to
engage in such a process. Different situational and institutional factors can
create a motivation in individuals to engage in empathy for the other side. In
experimental settings, specific empathy instructions could play this motiv-
ational role.
Second, for an individual to imagine the world of the other, they need to have
enough and accurate information about that world (Muradova 2020). The lack
of information may lead the individual to make erroneous inferences about the
lives and experiences of the target of their empathy, reinforcing their biases. In
the absence of information about the other side, an individual may automatic-
ally rely on their stored knowledge, which may consist of “stereotypes or other
idiosyncratic information known about the target” (Epley and Caruso 2009,
300–305; Muradova 2020).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 9
5
My conceptualization of empathy for the other side has some similarities with the concept of
perspective-getting, proposed by Kalla and Broockman (2023). The authors make a distinction
between perspective-taking (where one self-generates a narrative about the life of an outgroup
member) and perspective-getting (when an individual hears a narrative about a life of an outgroup
member either from them directly or from a third party). Both concepts (empathy for the other
side and perspective-getting) incorporate the narrative format and information about the experi-
ences of the different other. Perspective-getting is only one aspect of empathy, with other
dimensions involving affective engagement with the feelings, perspectives, and life experiences
of others, which are important for its reflection-inducing motivation. Hence, while Kalla and
Broockman (2023) focus on perspective-getting, my argument includes both the cognitive and
affective dimensions of empathy, examining it in its entirety. Moreover, according to my
conceptualization, all forms of empathy require information about the other side; without it,
our potentially flawed perceptions can impede our ability to empathize effectively.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
10 Political Psychology
and anger, on the other hand, are argued to prompt more intuitive and biased
political reasoning. There is an increasing body of work that shows that anxiety is
linked to people’s tendency to seek more information, rely less on party identifi-
cation or ideology as a heuristic and consider the characteristics of policy
proposals and candidates when making political decisions (Brader et al. 2008;
Gadarian and Albertson 2014; Huddy et al. 2015; Marcus et al. 2000). I argue that
empathy, more specifically empathy for the other side, can start similar reflective
processes in individuals. When the cues in the environment elicit empathy in
individuals toward people with opposing views, the resulting empathy signals
them to stop relying exclusively on their default system of reasoning and engage
in more even-handed thinking. In the language of AIT, empathy acts as a trigger
for individuals’ surveillance systems, prompting them to go beyond their egocen-
tric reasoning. Empathy, therefore, disrupts our habitual patterns of political
thinking and encourages us to consider opposing perspectives and arguments.
I argue that the arousal of empathy for the other side can activate and engender
more reflective political thinking.
This argument is in line with the findings of social and political psychological
research that shows empathy has the potential to reduce explicit and implicit
intergroup biases at the individual and group level (Simonovits et al. 2018; Sirin
et al. 2021), foster more inclusive and altruistic behavior (Batson 2010; Todd and
Galinsky 2014), lead to transformation of political views (Tuller et al. 2015) and
influence political ambition (Clifford et al. 2019).6 I extend this body of work by
studying how situational empathy is related to people’s tendency to engage in
a more demanding and normatively desirable kind of political reasoning, reflection.
Several causal mechanisms could be responsible for the relationship between
empathy for the other side and reflection. First, the argument on self-other
merging in empathetic imaginings suggests that empathy can create a sense of
psychological connectedness between individuals (Todd et al. 2012, 739) and
help them recognize shared similarities and fates with the person whose per-
spective they are adopting (Erle and Topolinski 2017). Consequently, one may
perceive oneself as being more like the other and/or vice versa. Second,
empathic imaginings could activate more positive evaluations of others, and
more liking (Galinsky and Moskowitz 2000). This may lead to openness about
the arguments and perspectives of different others. Therefore, when political
environments are fertile for eliciting empathy in individuals toward those with
divergent political views, people would be more likely to engage in reflective
reasoning.
6
The source of empathy-related interest in psychology dates to the moral philosophy of the
eighteenth century and is inspired by the works of David Hume and Adam Smith. For
a discussion of the history of scholarly interest in empathy, see Stüber (2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 11
This argument leads us to expect that empathy for the other side would
motivate more reflective political reasoning in individuals (H1). Figure 1
lays out this and other proposed relationships.
2.3 Political Institutions that Induce Empathy for the Other Side
How to make people more empathetic toward different others, outside the
controlled experimental settings? How can political institutions help individuals
to feel empathetic toward their policy opponents and consequently, engage in
more reflective political reasoning?
The second main argument of this Element is that one type of institutions –
deliberative minipublics – have the potential to elicit empathy for the other in
individuals. Minipublics are nonconventional, non-electoral and participatory
institutions that approximate the ideals of deliberative democracy through their
design (Fung 2003). They are considered to be the microcosm of the larger
population that they represent. Minipublics bring together randomly chosen
citizens with diverse views to hear from the experts and witnesses, engage in
consideration, discussion, and deliberation about the chosen issue, and arrive at
a set of recommendations under the conditions of respect and equality (Curato
and Farrell 2021). The assumption underlying these institutions is that
a minipublic models “what the electorate would think if, hypothetically, it
could be immersed in intensive deliberative processes” (Fishkin 1991, 81).
There are different types of minipublics (e.g., citizens’ juries, consensus
conferences, citizens’ assemblies, and deliberative polling) and their political
influence differ from case to case.7 The organization and use of a specific type of
minipublic – citizens’ assemblies – by governments and nongovernmental
7
See Ryan (2021) for the discussion and policy impact of another type of democratic innovations,
participatory budgeting.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
12 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 13
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
14 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 15
9
See the supplementary materials of Muradova and Arceneaux (2022b) for more detailed
information.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
16 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
Part of the
Study Country theory Method Outcome variable(s)
Study 1: UBI (2019) UK (H1) Survey experiment Cognitive complexity of
reasoning
Study 2: ICA (2017−2018), issues: Ireland (H2) and (H3) Participant observation Empathy for the other side
abortion, climate change, and aging Interviews Deliberation within
population
Study 3: Assisted dying (2018−2019) Belgium (H2) and (H3) Pretest-posttest quasi Empathy for the other side
experiment Cognitive complexity of
reasoning
Study 4: Assisted dying (2018) UK (H3) Laboratory experiment Deliberation within
Study 5: UBI (2019, 2020) UK and Chile Scaling up H3 Survey experiment Cognitive complexity of
reasoning
18 Political Psychology
10
This section is based on a study reported at Muradova and Arceneaux (2022b).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 19
was induced by a text vignette. Individuals were exposed to a short text about
a fictitious character – Sarah – who is either in favor or against the UBI,
providing a justification for her position. The experiment was designed so that
Sarah’s position on UBI was always opposite to that of the respondent. The
text includes Sarah’s photo to enhance realism and engagement. This was
held constant across placebo and empathy conditions. Thus, respondents in
both conditions were exposed to political disagreement through a text
about Sarah and her position on UBI. Empathy for the other was induced via
a writing assignment (Todd and Galinsky 2014). Individuals randomly assigned
to the empathy condition were instructed to actively imagine the feelings and
thoughts of their policy opponent, Sarah, and to write about what they had
imagined.
The design also included a control condition in which individuals neither read
about Sarah nor received empathy instructions. They only completed a pre- and
post-survey. The objective was to account for the effects of time. I summarize
the structure of the experiment in Figure 2.
4.3 Sample
We preregistered and conducted a survey experiment in March 2019 with
a sample of 2,014 British residents, recruited through the survey company
Dynata. The subject pool was non-probability based but nationally representa-
tive across census age, gender, and region (see the supplementary materials of
Muradova and Arceneaux 2022b for more information).
4.4 Measures
Reflection was measured through the cognitive complexity (CC) of political
reasoning, captured using an open-ended display item. After measuring
respondents’ posttreatment policy attitudes on UBI, individuals were asked to
provide written justifications for their position in four to five sentences.
Individuals’ policy attitudes on UBI were measured using a question from the
European Social Survey, which provided a brief overview of a hypothetical UBI
scheme. They were then asked to indicate their support or opposition to
implementing this scheme in the UK, using a scale from 1 (“strongly oppose”)
to 6 (“strongly favor”). Using automated text analysis with validated dictionar-
ies, we calculated the cognitive complexity score from the qualitative short
essays written by individuals. As stated in the previous section, cognitive
complexity taps into the multidimensional reasoning, that is the hallmark of
reflection. It captures how individuals define and integrate different dimensions
of the issue in their reasoning.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
4.5 Results
The preexperimental survey shows that the majority of individuals in our
sample favor UBI (Figure 3). Approximately 65.3 percent of respondents are
either “slightly,” “somewhat” or “strongly” in favor of introducing a UBI
scheme in the UK. On average, baseline support for UBI differs across gender,
age, political ideology, and partisanship. Younger and more liberal individuals
are more supportive of UBI, while supporters of the Conservative Party, UKIP,
and non-partisans are significantly less so.
First, I begin by exploring the extent to which the empathy treatment induced
the feelings of affective empathy in respondents toward their issue opponents,
by comparing the mean affective empathy (a sum index of sympathy, empathy,
concern, being moved, compassion, warmth, and soft-heartedness; rescaled to
0–1) across placebo and empathy conditions.
Figure 4 shows that individuals in the empathy condition experienced greater
affective empathy toward their issue opponent (M = 0.38; SD = 0.24) than those in
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
22 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 23
4.6 Discussion
This study finds that when individuals are motivated to empathize with their
policy opponents, they become more open to considering diverse and opposing
perspectives. Even amid political disagreement, empathy for those with oppos-
ing views to ours can foster more reflective political thinking. The effect size of
empathy on reflection is consistent with the effect sizes observed in real-world
interventions designed to change people’s attitudes (e.g., Kalla and Broockman
2023).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
24 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 25
11
The 8th amendment to the Irish constitution, approved in 1983, guaranteed the right to life of the
unborn, making abortion constitutionally illegal except in cases where there was a life-
threatening risk to the mother. The ICA and subsequent referendum aimed to determine whether
the 8th Amendment should be repealed.
12
Stratified random sampling was used to recruit the subjects. A market research company, RED C,
was responsible for cold calling door-to-door to recruit ninety-nine subjects and an additional
ninety-nine substitute members (see Farrell et al. 2023).
13
Submissions played a key role in the ICA process. The general public had the opportunity to
share their views on the issue by submitting their perspectives and suggestions, which enriched
the debate. All submissions were published on the ICA website (https://citizensassembly.ie/
submissions/).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
26 Political Psychology
by the independent chair, along with the participation of two other assembly
members. The results of the vote were submitted to the Irish Parliament for
further deliberation and policy action.
14
The convention on the constitution was convened by the Irish government and considered a set of
issues, including same-sex marriage and blasphemy. The convention consisted of 66 randomly
chosen lay citizens, and 29 members of the parliament. This made it different from the subse-
quent citizens’ assemblies whose members were lay people only.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 27
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
28 Political Psychology
As illustrated by the following two quotes, the social aspects of the ICA
meetings were crucial for getting to know different others and understand
where they were coming from. Social bonding facilitated the formation of
shared hopes and goals.
[W]hen the meetings are over, you are going to your dinner, and discuss
something else, sport or whatever . . . . Discuss families [ . . . ] It is like
bonding. People feel like they are a part of something. (male, in his late 40s)
[I]f you are going to talk about such difficult things [ . . . ], such intense kind
of discussions, it is important to be able to have a bit of laugh, a bit of
comradery with people. [ . . . ] Especially, when we are seeing each other all
the time. [ . . . ] It is nice to have a bit of laugh with people. [ . . . ] It enlightens
the mood. (female, in her 20s)
15
See Muradova (2020) for more information.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 29
anybody that has been outright disrespectful of other people’s opinions. You
can sit back, listen, and then make your point, knowing that you do not agree
or whatever. But there has never been any kind of backlash, if you will, for
having an opinion that was not the popular opinion at the table [ . . . ].
Everybody feels like it is a safe space for their opinion, even if they know
that it is not going to be popular with the people at the table. (female, in her
20s)
[T]he set-up of the whole thing [ . . . ]. The secretariat set it up in a way that it
makes it easy to talk. There is no fear. You feel confident talking and
expressing opinions and knowing that [no-one] will take an offense or will
get upset about. I think that the fact that we get information from both sides,
and as I see, non-confrontational manner, so the information given is to use to
listen, to digest and reflect upon, and then vote upon it at various stages.
(male, in his late 40s)
I felt very free to express my view without fear of being denigrated or of being
made feel small; it does not matter what point of view you have to make . . . to
feel free to make it [is what counts]. (female, in her early 50s)
Through its design, ICA created three conditions that promoted empathy for the
opposing side. First, it actively motivated empathic engagement. The organizers
consistently encouraged members to stay open to each other’s arguments,
perspectives, and life experiences. The ICA was governed with six key prin-
ciples: openness (including openness to hear from all other members of the
wider society via submissions), fairness (diverse perspectives on every issue to
be heard during deliberations along with the provision of high-quality briefing
materials), equality of voice (everyone has the right to express their views),
efficiency (good time management), and respect and collegiality. These prin-
ciples were consistently reinforced in each session, actively encouraged, and
nurtured throughout the meetings.
Second, the presence of diverse opinions and perspectives at the ICA enabled
participants to imagine what the others’ lives looked like, and why they held the
perspectives that they held. Diversity was ensured at different stages during the
ICA processes. First, the topics discussed impacted various segments of Irish
society. Abortion clearly affected the women. Climate change pertained mostly
to the future generations, while the aging population concerned the elderly.
Second, the ICA tried to resemble a microcosm of the Irish society, at least with
regards to age, education, gender, and region, as well as the baseline perspec-
tives they held at the start of the process. Third, one of the characteristics of the
ICA meetings was that the members of each small group would be rotated at
every meeting. The aim was to ensure participants didn’t sit with the same
people, but instead were exposed to a diverse range of individuals and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
30 Political Psychology
[A] lot of the kind of personal stuff were self-generated, within the people
who had already experienced that, you know, dealing with elderly relatives.
[ . . . ] Let us not to forget, because of the population spread within the group,
there was, you know, the number of elderly, yeah, so they [ . . . ] had an
opinion, because a lot directly affects them. [ . . . ] For people who are little bit
younger to have one to one conversation, that, or round table conversation,
was important. (male, in his late 30s)
Third, the ICA, via its design, created and continuously nurtured an environ-
ment where all kinds of arguments were welcomed – both fact-based, rational
information and more emotional expressions, such as personal stories, narra-
tives, testimonies, and humor. In addition to the statistical and factual evidence
presented by experts, the ICA invited witnesses to share their lived experiences.
For example, on the issue of abortion, members heard from women directly
impacted by Ireland’s abortion ban, including rape survivors who had to travel
abroad for the procedure. They also heard from doctors who performed abor-
tions and organizations supporting vulnerable women from disadvantaged
backgrounds. On the issue of climate change, nonexpert speakers shared their
personal experiences in proactively dealing with its challenges. One speaker
had founded a nonprofit that connected supermarkets with impoverished citi-
zens, aiming to contribute to tackling both food waste and hunger.
Stories and narratives helped members navigate complex issues. Everyday
language on climate change, especially from nonexpert witnesses, encouraged
individuals to see it as an issue impacting daily life, fostering a deeper, more
personal connection (Muradova et al. 2020). Personal stories and narratives
were especially powerful on moral issues like abortion and elderly care.
Consider the following thoughts from one interviewee:
For another member, the interplay between factual evidence and personal
stories was crucial to the deliberative process of abortion:
[T]he first few meetings were specifically about facts, and statistics. [ . . . ]
They [referring to the organizers] wanted to make sure that we understood the
facts surrounding the 8th amendment, around the constitution, around what
currently is happening. [ . . . ] Further along the process, because some of it
was kind of abstract, then became more personal, when we heard personal
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 31
Personal stories . . . it is the part that gets you in the guts. It is the part you
actually feel something . . . hearing that it is somebody’s story. We heard one
story of an older lady who had been put in a care home, against her will
basically, and you know that was just incredibly sad, no amount of statistics
could give you what actually happens on the ground, what actually happens in
people’s lives. Because you cannot boil down the people to numbers, gener-
ally speaking. (female, in her 20s)
Stories and testimonies brought out compassion and understanding among the
members. Consider the following quotes regarding the deliberations on legaliz-
ing abortion.
[T]hey had people speak via tape recorder about their experience on the
termination [of pregnancy] [ . . . ], and there were six people. [ . . . ] and it
was very powerful. You can never [ . . . ] ignore the lived experience.”
(female, in her late 50s)
“[I]f you take something like the 8th amendment, listening to conversation of
women who already experienced. Their experiences, good or bad, kind of
gives you greater insight of what it is like to walk in that person’s shoes. [ . . . ]
that has emotional impact on how you would vote on the issue. (male, in his
early 40s)
I’d be a lot of more patient in the face of the opinions that do not necessarily
align themselves with my own. I think, I would be a little bit, [ . . . ] more
respectful and patient with, you know, diverging opinions, than previously.
That is probably been my, personally my biggest takeaway. [ . . . ]I would now
have more than of an ability to do that. In the first meeting, if somebody
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
32 Political Psychology
disagreed with me, I would be little bit more like, ‘how can you think that,
you know, how can you think that?’ Now, I would be like . . . ‘Ok, I do not
agree with you, but ok’ . . . I would have more difficult discussions [now].
(female, in her 20s)
Before I would have . . . been probably under the basis of if somebody had
a conflicting view to me, I would go, yea, idiot . . . Now I’m more open-
minded. I have seen people, people that were presenting to us and also fellow
citizens who have conflicting views. Everybody is entitled to those views. My
views might, to somebody else, look idiotic or strange. I realize it now. When
I see people, hear people, I kind of go, well, these are your views, you [may]
not know all the facts, fair enough. (male, in his early 30s)
In sum, the institutional characteristics of the ICA motivated and facilitated the
processes of empathy for the other side. Affective engagement of the members
of the ICA was a necessary condition for empathy to be evoked in interpersonal
deliberative settings. Despite its central focus on learning and deliberating,
human emotions and social bonding took a central stage in these processes.
Sharing a friendly and respectful space over an extended period allowed distant
individuals to get to know each other, connect with one another’s lives, and
bond, resulting in greater emotional responsiveness to each other’s perspectives
despite political differences on contentious issues. Emotionally engaged indi-
viduals were more inclined to empathize with the other side. Furthermore, two
institutional characteristics of the assembly were crucial in facilitating the
processes of empathy for the other side: the presence of diversity of perspec-
tives, and the interplay of fact-based rational argumentation and storytelling and
narratives during deliberations.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 33
the issues, resulting in stronger positions after discussions and reflection. The
following quotes are good illustrations of this reasoning:
I’d say that I stayed pro-choice, but I did swing. I was pro-choice. I was not
a fanatical pro-choice, just pro-choice. It was, then, given all the
information . . . Then, I heard the arguments from the pro-life side, and then
I was . . . ‘they have a point, they have a point, but I still see the reason of
having the choice’. So, I would have been less pro-choice than I was, but I am
still pro-choice. (male, in his early 60s)
I would have had a view, but having heard the information that we were
given, my view has softened. I would not say that my view changed radically,
but it became less conservative. [ . . . ] I am not in a position to stand in
a position of judging anybody else in terms of changing the legislation,
changing the constitution. (female, in her early 50s)
Perhaps the most surprising finding of this study was that empathy led some
individuals to vote against their deeply entrenched beliefs on the morally
divisive issue of abortion. This perfectly illustrates how reflection can change
political behavior without first altering beliefs and attitudes. Two quotes at the
outset of this section illustrate this idea. Repeating one such quote:
In the booth, the ballot booth, when I was voting, after all the information we
had heard . . . from the witnesses especially [ . . . ], when I stood in that voting
booth and a woman stood in front of me, and I said, ‘I cannot make a decision
for you’. I would have had views that said, ‘Yes, but under these circum-
stances, and yes, under those’ . . . then I found myself . . . I would still find
myself in the conservative end [of the issue] [ . . . ] But I said, I am not going
to be the one to say [ . . . ]: ‘You cannot have it’ . . . (female, in her early 50s)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
34 Political Psychology
beyond the deliberative process. For example, one might ponder the role of
conventional partisan politics in these processes, questioning whether the ICA
created a nonpartisan environment, and how dynamics within the ICA might
unfold differently in more partisan contexts.
Deliberations of the ICA did not happen in a vacuum and were not divorced from
conventional partisan politics. First, the ICA’s predecessor, the Constitutional
Convention, was established by the coalition government formed after the 2011
election, comprising Fine Gael (a liberal-conservative and Christian-democratic
party) and Labor (a center-left social-democratic party). The ICA was established
in accordance with the program led by a Fine Gael – independent minority govern-
ment. The most recent assemblies were convened under a coalition government of
Fianna Fáil (a conservative, Christian-democratic party), Fine Gael and the Green
Party. Hence, it would be inaccurate to characterize the ICA as an experiment
conducted solely by left-wing politicians. Second, well before the assembly mem-
bers were recruited and the sessions began, the ICA attracted significant media
attention, primarily due to the contentious and partisan nature of its initial agenda:
the legalization of abortion. The organization’s formation was sometimes seen as
a sign that Irish politicians were either unable or unwilling to address this sensitive
issue on their own, prompting them to delegate decision-making responsibility to
ordinary citizens (Marlborough 2016). The initiative also faced intense scrutiny
from both pro-choice and pro-life advocates, each with distinct perspectives. Pro-
choice activists called for an immediate referendum on the issue, while pro-life
proponents claimed the ICA was inherently biased, and that its outcome was
predetermined. Even during the deliberations, pro-life activists voiced their dissent
both online and outside the hotel where the discussions were held. Thus, the ICA
emerged within a highly charged partisan context.
Deliberations on abortion happened against the backdrop of a polarized polit-
ical context. However, what the ICA achieved was to help transcend the partisan
divide on the issue of legalizing abortion. My qualitative data shows that the ICA
created and nurtured a safe and neutral space, where individuals were encouraged
to set aside their ideology, partisanship, and their preconceived ideas about the
issue. The institutional characteristics of the ICA that elicited empathy in individ-
uals helped individuals to transcend their partisan attachments and prior beliefs
and engage in more reflective political thinking and vote accordingly.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 35
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
36 Political Psychology
16
The question was measured with a scale that ranges from 0 (never justified) to 10 (always
justified). These percentages were calculated by grouping the responses from 6 to 10. Those who
reported “10” constituted 32 percent of the surveyed Belgian and 21 percent of the surveyed UK
citizens.
17
As of today, assisted dying is also legal in all six states of Australia (since 2022), New Zealand
(since 2021), Portugal (since 2023) and Spain (since 2021).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 37
18
In total, there were thirty-seven nationalities in our sample.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
38 Political Psychology
participants took part (Mage = 26.6; SDage = 6.4; range: 18–47; 63 percent self-
identified as female19).
Measures: The main outcome variable of interest, reflection, was captured with
cognitive complexity of political reasoning. The variable was a within-subject
change in cognitive complexity (CC) score. The CC was captured with an open-
ended question. At Wave 1, individuals were first questioned about their position on
legalizing assisted dying. They were asked to indicate, on a scale from 0 to 10,
whether they disapproved or approved of legalizing assisted dying in their country
of origin (M = 6.9; SD = 3.1, range: 0–10), preceded by a short explanation of what
assisted dying entails. Furthermore, participants were given the opportunity to
justify their position in four to five sentences through an open-ended question.
This question was repeated after the small-group deliberation, allowing for
a comparison of responses pre- and posttreatment. The qualitative responses
(short essays) were analyzed quantitatively to assess the complexity of their polit-
ical reasoning. The complexity score was standardized for easier interpretation.
I also measured the level of situational empathy experienced by individuals as
a result of small-group deliberation. Both affective and cognitive dimensions of
empathy were captured. As a part of the post-deliberation questionnaire, individuals
were instructed to indicate, on a 7-point scale, the extent to which they experienced
empathic feelings, captured with seven empathy adjectives, including, “compas-
sionate,” “warm,” “empathic,” among others (McCullough et al. 1997). Moreover,
situational perspective-taking was measured with four statements from an adapted
version of Davis (1983): (a) I tried to imagine how I would feel if I were in the place
of people who thought differently than me, (b) I believe there are at least two sides to
the issue of legalizing assisted dying and I tried to look at them both during the
discussion, (c) I found it difficult to see things from the other person’s point of view,
during the discussion (inverse), and (d) One should try to place oneself in the
position of the person who thinks differently on the issue of legalization of assisted
dying. Two indices were created and were further rescaled (0–1).
Results: To test whether interpersonal deliberation induces more reflective
political reasoning in individuals, I examine within-subject change in cognitive
complexity by running paired t-tests comparing (standardized) pre- and post-
cognitive complexity scores (Table 3). The results show that respondents’ mean
cognitive complexity score increased post-discussions (Mpre = 0.04; SDpre = 0.96;
Mpost = 0.47, SDpost = 0.53, two-tailed p < 0.00). The effect is large and substantive,
equaling to nearly half a standard deviation (0.43 SD). Engaging in small-group
19
The drop-out rate was primarily due to individuals leaving Belgium at the end of their exchange
programs or because the proposed dates and times for the group discussions did not fit their
schedules. Post-hoc analyses indicate that dropout was not systematic with respect to socio-
demographic factors or attitudes toward legalizing assisted dying.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 39
Mean SD Range
Pretreatment CC score 0.04 0.95 –4.23 to 2.49
Posttreatment CC score 0.47 0.53 –0.71 to 2.18
20
Although it is not the primary focus of my studies, I also examined potential attitude changes
regarding the legalization of assisted dying following the discussions. The results of a paired t-test
comparing pre- and post-discussion attitudes among participants in both Wave 1 and Wave 2
revealed no statistically significant within-subject attitude transformation (Mpre = 7, SDpre = 3.05;
Mpost = 7.07, SDpost = 3.26; range: 0–10; two-tailed p < 0.78).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Figure 7 Situational empathy experienced by deliberators
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 41
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
42 Political Psychology
Post-hoc analyses indicated that the attrition was not systematic with respect to
socio-demographic variables or baseline attitudes toward assisted dying. The
dropouts were primarily due to heavy snowfall on the day of the discussions
and the potentially demanding nature of the deliberations. The smaller sample
size for the control condition was intentional, reflecting the relatively low interest
in that group.
Measure: To capture reflection, in this study, I use Weinmann’s (2018)
psychometric self-reported measure for the concept of “deliberation within.”
The battery is designed to assess the cognitive information processing steps
involved in reflective political reasoning, as predicted by the normative ideals of
deliberative democracy. Respondents are asked to self-report on a 7-point scale,
where “1” means “strongly disagree” and “7” means “strongly agree,” how each
of five items, (a) reassessing the biases favoring or opposing different argu-
ments, (b) taking responsibility for making up one’s own mind about the topic,
after having heard the arguments of others; (c) simulating several opinions
about the topic, (d) thinking about the arguments for and against ones’ own as
well as others’ opinion, and (e) evaluating the arguments that speak for and
against own as well as others’ opinions, describe the development of thought
processes during and after either having deliberated in a group (deliberation
condition), read the text (information condition), or forming their opinion
(control condition). The results of the factor analyses indicated that the first
two items did not load effectively onto a single deliberation within variable.
Consequently, a summary index was created from the remaining three items
(alpha = 0.75; M = 16; SD = 3; range: 6–21) and was subsequently standardized
using the control group’s mean and standard deviation.21
Results: Table 4 reports the means and standard deviations of reflective
political thinking across three experimental conditions.
Mean SD N
Control 0.00 1.00 31
Information 0.50 0.69 58
Deliberation 0.59 0.95 37
21
This experiment was also reported in Muradova (2020). Yet the analytical strategy in Muradova
(2020) differed from the current strategy along two dimensions. First, in Muradova (2020),
despite a low Cronbach’s alpha, an index of all five items was created. Second, in the original
study, the outcome variable was standardized by sample mean and standard deviation. For
experimental studies, the common practice is to standardize it by control mean and SD, which
I adopt here.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 43
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
44 Political Psychology
Mean SD N
UK
Placebo 0.00 1.00 106
Treatment (cross-cutting) −0.09 1.22 109
Chile
Placebo 0.00 1.00 104
Treatment (cross-cutting) 0.05 1.12 104
22
Their chosen response was generated by a piped text function of the Qualtrics.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 45
6.5 Discussion
Study 3 (Belgium) shows that discussing legalizing assisted dying in small
groups has a within-subject positive effect on the reflectiveness of individuals’
political thinking. In a similar vein, Study 4 (UK) demonstrates that small-group
deliberation can enhance reflective political thinking. However, exposure to
information about the issue, along with a balanced presentation of arguments,
can also have similarly positive effects. Although the effect of deliberation is
greater than that of the information effect, the difference between these two
effects is not statistically significant. This may be due to the smaller size of the
sample. In Study 5 (UK and Chile), I isolate one element of small-group
deliberation – exposure to cross-cutting view – and study its direct effect on
the reflectiveness of people’s political judgments and find that it exerts a null
effect. To sum up, the first two studies show the potential of deliberation and
balanced information provision to enhance the reflectiveness of people’s polit-
ical judgments. The last study demonstrates that mere exposure to an opposing
perspective on the issue of universal basic income fails to influence political
thinking.
It is challenging to approximate the small-group deliberation designed at lab
settings or online to that of the real-world deliberative institutions. While the
presence of diverse perspectives is crucial for fostering high-quality interper-
sonal deliberation, individuals in laboratory settings often lack sufficient time to
form meaningful connections, engage in empathetic reflections, and build
rapport. This absence of a nurturing environment may inhibit their ability to
transcend biased political thinking, making it difficult for them to incorporate
and integrate opposing viewpoints into their reasoning. Without the opportunity
for these essential social interactions, the potential for deeper understanding
and more comprehensive deliberation may be significantly diminished.
Experiments with interpersonal deliberation of longer duration have been
demonstrated to yield more robust positive democratic outcomes (e.g.,
Fishkin et al. 2021; Grönlund et al. 2015). Future research should take this
into account in designing laboratory experiments approximating participation in
a deliberative institution.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
46 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 47
Second, I show that situational empathy for the other side can engender more
reflective thinking. While the potential of empathy for other political outcomes,
such as intergroup prejudice, altruism, affective polarization, intergroup sup-
port, and political ambition, has been studied, this Element theorizes and tests
the role of situational empathy in encouraging individuals to go beyond their
biased political reasoning and engage in reflection. My findings show that
empathy for the other side is a powerful emotion that can promote political
reflection. These findings have important implications for the literature on AIT
(Marcus 2010; Marcus et al. 2000). This Element challenges the previously held
belief that only negative emotions engender reflective political judgments.
I demonstrate that, in the context of political disagreement, empathy can help
individuals move beyond simply dismissing opposing views and engage in
thoughtful reflection. Elsewhere, in the context of correcting misperceptions
about climate change, I find the magnitude of the positive effect of empathy on
people’s accurate political judgments to be comparable to that of anxiety
(Muradova, Michalaki, and Tsakiris 2024). Both emotions enhance people’s
willingness to correct their misperceptions. This highlights the critical role of
empathy as an important emotion in understanding reflective political thinking.
This Element departs from previous studies that focus on the dark side of
empathy (Bloom 2017; Simas et al. 2020). In contrast to these studies, this
Element focuses on situational empathy instead of dispositional empathy. I build
on the premise that social contexts can either activate or depress people’s empathic
reactions, with certain environments exerting a strong influence on individuals’
inclination to empathize with others (Cheng et al. 2017). Research shows that the
activation of individuals’ empathy depends on various factors, including the nature
of interpersonal relationships and the motivations of the empathizer (Stüber 2019).
Moreover, in the existing political science literature, dispositional empathy is
typically measured through self-reported responses to a series of items. However,
prior research indicates that individuals often lack accurate meta-knowledge about
their own empathic abilities, making dispositional measures likely to be poor
predictors of actual empathic accuracy (Ickes 1993, 603; Ickes 2003). Third,
studies asserting that empathy negatively impacts important democratic outcomes,
such as political polarization, primarily concentrate on one dimension of empathy
(i.e., empathic concern). In fact, Simas et al. (2020) finds that the cognitive
dimension of dispositional empathy (i.e., perspective-taking) does not contribute
to increased political polarization. I demonstrate that empathy for the other side,
encompassing both affective and cognitive dimensions, fosters greater (not lesser)
reflective political thinking in individuals.
Third, I argue that when designed properly, deliberative institutions, such as
citizens’ assemblies, can cultivate an environment conducive to eliciting empathy
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
48 Political Psychology
for the other side. I marshal a set of original qualitative, and experimental data to
test the plausibility of this theoretical idea. First, I rely on a real-world and
influential institution, the Irish Citizens’ Assembly (2016–2018). My qualitative
data shows that citizens’ assemblies have the potential to nurture political envir-
onments where people spend time with different others, leading to the develop-
ment of affective bonds and mutual trust among participants. In these processes,
the presence of diversity of viewpoints and arguments is important.
Affective engagement encourages individuals to be more receptive to new
information and diverse, opposing perspectives, whether conveyed through
factual arguments or personal stories and testimonies, ultimately enhancing
their empathy toward others. It is the empathy for other side that motivates
individuals to engage in more demanding processes of reflection. My focus on
deliberative institutions here is distinct from prior work investigating reflection-
enhancing potential of interpersonal deliberation. An overwhelming majority of
prior studies have mostly focused on the cognitive causal mechanisms – such as
knowledge acquisition and persuasion through the Habermasian force of the
better argument – underpinning small-group discussion and their potentially
beneficial outcomes.23 Deliberative democrats have usually emphasized the
reason-giving and learning aspects of interpersonal deliberation in these pro-
cesses. This Element focuses on an affective mechanism. Learning, and delib-
erating are intertwined with deliberative institution’s capacity to create
emotional bonding and empathetic engagement both during and beyond small-
group discussions. My hope is that the theoretical argument presented in this
Element can serve as an inspiration for deliberation scholars to develop their
own testable and generalizable theories about the role of affect in deliberation.
Furthermore, I substantiate my argument about the relationship between
interpersonal deliberation and reflective political reasoning with laboratory,
and quasi-experiments. The findings relate to several different strands of
research investigating the effects of political disagreement and small-group
deliberation on individuals’ political opinion formation and intergroup rela-
tions. First, the results with regards to the reflection-enhancing potential of
interpersonal deliberation are consistent with recent experiments on deliber-
ation. For example, Fishkin and colleagues (2021) employ a field experiment –
America in One Room – to investigate the effect of participating in
a deliberative forum on political polarization among Republicans and
Democrats. Their findings reveal that interpersonal deliberation not only trans-
forms individuals’ policy attitudes but also reduces affective polarization.
23
But see Lindell et al. (2017) and Saam (2018) for different perspectives.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 49
Second, in the context of the Irish Citizens’ Assembly, I find that one of the
necessary design features of a deliberative institution for its empathy-inducing
potential is the presence of diversity of perspectives. This finding relates to the
argument in political science and communication that cross-cutting political
conversations can enhance the quality of people’s political judgments
(Huckfeldt et al. 2004; Mutz 2002; but see Wojcieszak and Price 2010). In the
context of discussions about energy and health care policies in the US, Samara
Klar (2014) finds that heterogenous small-group discussions can exert a positive
effect on individuals’ political opinion formation by alleviating partisan-
motivated reasoning, while homogenous group discussions tend to have
a polarizing effect.
The findings of this Element give suggestive evidence that an affective causal
mechanism (feeling empathy for the other side) may be responsible for positive
relationship between cross-cutting political conversations and reflection. This
Element also broadens the empirical scope of this strand of literature by moving
beyond the predominantly studied country contexts, such as the US, to include
data from four different countries – Belgium, Chile, Ireland, and the UK.
The findings of this Element can also help practitioners of deliberative
minipublics design forums that enhance participants’ reflective potential.
Ensuring that empathy-sparking institutional features of deliberative minipub-
lics (e.g., affective engagement, presence of diversity of perspectives, instruc-
tions that encourage active imagination) are present when organizing such
institution can enhance the process of reflective political attitude formation
among participants in democratic innovation institutions.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
50 Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 51
24
The Convention was established following the “yellow vest movement” sweeping France in
2018 and lasted between October 2019 to June 2020.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
52 Political Psychology
Ireland, they report feeling more empathy for the opposing side (Suiter et al.
2020). To the extent that this way of providing information about the issue can
work well across different country and issue contexts, it could be a cost-effective
strategy for eliciting empathy for the other side in individuals.
[ . . . ] be really driven by empathy. [ . . . ] When you think about all the big
challenges that we face in the world. . . . We need our leaders to be able to
empathize with the circumstances of others . . . to empathize with the next gener-
ation that we’re making decisions on behalf of.
Jacinda Ardern, for Guardian, May 30, 2020
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Empathy and Political Reasoning 53
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
References
Achen, C., & Bartels, L. (2016). Democracy for realists: Why elections do not
produce responsive government. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Allport, G. W. (1954). The nature of prejudice. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Arceneaux, K., & Vander Wielen, R. J. (2017). Taming intuition: How reflection
minimizes partisan reasoning and promotes democratic accountability.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Arendt, H. (1989). Lectures on Kant’s political philosophy. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
Bakker, B. N., Lelkes, Y., & Malka, A. (2020). Understanding partisan cue
receptivity: Tests of predictions from the bounded rationality and expressive
utility perspectives. The Journal of Politics, 82(3), 1061–1077.
Bartels, L. M. (2002). Beyond the running tally: Partisan bias in political
perceptions. Political Behavior, 24, 117–150.
Batson, C. D. (2010). Altruism in humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Beiner, R. (1983). Political judgment. London: Methuen.
Bidadanure, J. U. (2019). The political theory of universal basic income. Annual
Review of Political Science, 22, 481–501.
Black, L. W. (2008). Deliberation, storytelling, and dialogic moments.
Communication Theory, 18, 93–116.
Bloom, P. (2017). Against empathy: The case for rational compassion.
New York City, NY: Random House.
Bottoni, G. (2023). CROss-National Online Survey 2 (CRONOS-2) panel data
and documentation user guide. London: ESS ERIC.
Brader, T., & Marcus, G. E. (2013). Emotion and political psychology. In
L. Huddy, D. O. Sears, & J. S. Levy (eds.), The Oxford handbook of political
psychology, Second Ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press (165–204).
Brader, T., & Tucker, J. A. (2018). Unreflective partisans? Policy information
and evaluation in the development of partisanship. Political Psychology, 39,
137–157.
Brader, T., Valentino, N. A., & Suhay, E. (2008). What triggers public oppos-
ition to immigration? Anxiety, group cues, and immigration threat. American
Journal of Political Science, 52(4), 959–978.
Broockman, D., & Kalla, J. (2016). Durably reducing transphobia: A field
experiment on door-to-door canvassing. Science, 352(6282), 220–224.
Brophy, N., & Mullinix, K. J. (2024). Partisan motivated empathy and policy
attitudes. Political Behavior, 46(3), 1701–1723.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
References 55
Brundidge, J., Reid, S. A., Choi, S., & Muddiman, A. (2014). The “deliberative
digital divide”: Opinion leadership and integrative complexity in the US
political blogosphere. Political Psychology, 35(6), 741–755.
Bullock, J. G., Gerber, A. S., Hill, S. J., & Huber, G. A. (2015). Partisan bias in
factual beliefs about politics. Quarterly Journal of Political Science, 10(4),
519–578.
Cameron, C. D., Hutcherson, C. A., Ferguson, A. M., et al. (2019). Empathy is
hard work: People choose to avoid empathy because of its cognitive costs.
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 148(6), 962.
Campbell, A., Converse, P. E., Miller, W. E., & Stokes, D. E. (1960). The
American voter. New York: Wiley.
Carswell, S. (2017). Citizens’ assembly: Reaction from both sides of abortion
debate, 23 April, www.irishtimes.com/news/ireland/irish-news/citizens-
assembly-reaction-from-both-sides-of-abortion-debate-1.3058645.
Cheng, Y., Chen, C., & Decety, J. (2017). How situational context impacts
empathic responses and brain activation patterns. Frontiers in Behavioral
Neuroscience, 11, 165.
Chwalisz, C. (2021). Eight ways to institutionalise deliberative democracy,
OECD Public Governance Policy Papers, No.12, December 14, www.oecd
.org/gov/open-government/eight-ways-to-institutionalise-deliberative-dem
ocracy.htm.
Cikara, M., Bruneau, E. G., & Saxe, R. R. (2011). Us and them: Intergroup
failures of empathy. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 20(3),
149–153.
Clifford, S., Kirkland, J. H., & Simas, E. N. (2019). How dispositional empathy
influences political ambition. The Journal of Politics, 81(3), 1043–1056.
Colombo, C. (2018). Hearing the other side? Debiasing political opinions in the
case of the Scottish independence referendum. Political Studies, 66(1),
23–42.
Connors, E. C., Pietryka, M. T., & Ryan, J. B. (2022). Examining motivations in
interpersonal communication experiments. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Converse, P. E. (1964). The nature of belief systems in mass publics. In
D. E. Apter (ed.), Ideology and discontent. New York: Free Press (206–261).
Courant, D. (2021). The promises and disappointments of the French citizens’
convention for climate. Deliberative Democracy Digest, June 9. www.pub
licdeliberation.net/the-promises-and-disappointments-of-the-french-citi
zens-convention-for-climate/.
Crawford, N. C. (2014). Institutionalizing passion in world politics: Fear and
empathy. International Theory, 6(3), 535–557.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
56 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
References 57
Ferguson, E. (2016). Empathy: “The good, the bad and the ugly”. In
A. M. Wood & J. Johnson (eds.), The Wiley handbook of positive clinical
psychology. Wiley-Blackwell (103–123).
Fishkin, J., Siu, A., Diamond, L., & Bradburn, N. (2021). Is deliberation an
antidote to extreme partisan polarization? Reflections on “America in one
room.” American Political Science Review, 115(4), 1464–1481.
Fishkin, J. S. (1991). Democracy and deliberation: New directions for demo-
cratic reform. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.
Fournier, P., Turgeon, M., Blais, A., et al. (2011). Deliberation from within:
Changing one’s mind during an interview. Political Psychology, 32(5),
885–919.
Fung, A. (2003). Recipes for public spheres: Eight institutional design choices
and their consequences. Journal of Political Philosophy, 11, 338, 345.
Gadarian, S. K., & Albertson, B. (2014). Anxiety, immigration, and the search
for information. Political Psychology, 35(2), 133–164.
Galinsky, A. D., & Moskowitz, G. B. (2000). Perspective-taking: Decreasing
stereotype expression, stereotype accessibility, and in-group favoritism.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78(4), 708.
Gastil, J. (2008). Political communication and deliberation. Los Angeles, CA:
Sage.
Gastil, J. (2018). The lessons and limitations of experiments in democratic
deliberation. Annual Review of Law and Social Science, 14, 271–291.
Gastil, J., & Wright, E. O. (eds.) (2019). Legislature by lot: Transformative
designs for deliberative governance. London: Verso Books.
Germann, M., Marien, S., & Muradova, L. (2024). Scaling up? Unpacking the
effect of deliberative mini-publics on legitimacy perceptions. Political
Studies, 72(2), 677–700.
Gerring, J. (2004). What is a case study and what is it good for? American
Political Science Review, 98(2), 341–354.
Goodin, R. E. (2003). Reflective democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Groenendyk, E., & Krupnikov, Y. (2021). What motivates reasoning? A theory
of goal-dependent political evaluation. American Journal of Political
Science, 65(1), 180–196.
Grönlund, K., Herne, K., & Setälä, M. (2015). Does enclave deliberation
polarize opinions? Political Behavior, 37, 995–1020.
Grönlund, K., Herne, K., & Setälä, M. (2017). Empathy in a citizen deliberation
experiment. Scandinavian Political Studies, 40(4), 457–480.
Guess, A., & Coppock, A. (2020). Does counter-attitudinal information cause
backlash? Results from three large survey experiments. British Journal of
Political Science, 50(4), 1497–1515.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
58 References
Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Huckfeldt, R., Mendez, J. M., & Osborn, T. (2004). Disagreement, ambiva-
lence, and engagement: The political consequences of heterogeneous
networks. Political Psychology, 25(1), 65–95.
Huddy, L., Mason, L., & Aarøe, L. (2015). Expressive partisanship: Campaign
involvement, political emotion, and partisan identity. American Political
Science Review, 109(1), 1–17.
Ickes, W. (1993). Empathic accuracy. Journal of Personality, 61(4), 587–610.
Ickes, W. (2003). Everyday mind reading: Understanding what other people
think and feel. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.
Jacquet, V. (2017). Explaining non-participation in deliberative mini-publics.
European Journal of Political Research, 56(3), 640–659.
Jennings, G., Cullen, J., Bryant, J., et al. (2019). The empathetic museum:
A new institutional identity. Curator: The Museum Journal, 62(4), 505–526.
Johnson, G. F., Morrell, M. E., & Black, L. W. (2019). Emotions and deliber-
ation in the citizens’ initiative review. Social Science Quarterly, 100(6),
2168–2187.
Kalla, J. L., & Broockman, D. E. (2023). Which narrative strategies durably
reduce prejudice? Evidence from field and survey experiments supporting the
efficacy of perspective-getting. American Journal of Political Science, 67(1),
185–204.
Kam, C. D. (2006). Political campaigns and open-minded thinking. The Journal
of Politics, 68(4), 931–945.
Kawulich, B. B. (2005). Participant observation as a data collection method.
Forum Qualitative Sozialforschung/Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 6
(2), Article 43.
Klar, S. (2014). Partisanship in a social setting. American Journal of Political
Science, 58(3), 687–704.
Krause, S. R. (2008). Civil passions: Moral sentiment and democratic deliber-
ation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin,
108(3), 480.
Lacelle-Webster, A. (2024). “What should we hope for? Democratic hope and
the collective, uncertain, and future-oriented dimensions of democratic pol-
itics.” A conference paper presented at Yale ISPS conference “Deliberative
Democracy with a passion: Identities, emotions, and the formation of polit-
ical judgement,” May 16, 2024.
Landemore, H. (2020). Open democracy: Reinventing popular rule for the
twenty-first century. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
References 59
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
60 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
References 61
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
62 References
Tetlock, P. E., Bernzweig, J., & Gallant, J. L. (1985). Supreme Court decision
making: Cognitive style as a predictor of ideological consistency of voting.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48(5), 1227.
Todd, A. R., & Galinsky, A. D. (2014). Perspective-taking as a strategy for
improving intergroup relations: Evidence, mechanisms, and qualifications.
Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 8(7), 374–387.
Todd, A. R., Bodenhausen, G. V., & Galinsky, A. D. (2012). Perspective taking
combats the denial of intergroup discrimination. Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology, 48(3), 738–745.
Trian, N. (2021). Macron’s “direct democracy” to be tested as citizens’ panel on
climate wraps up, March 01, www.france24.com/en/france/20210301-mac
ron-s-direct-democracy-to-be-tested-as-citizens-panel-on-climate-wraps-up.
Tuller, H. M., Bryan, C. J., Heyman, G. D., & Christenfeld, N. J. S. (2015).
Seeing the other side: Perspective taking and the moderation of extremity.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 59, 18–23.
Turkenburg, E., & Goovaerts, I. (2024). Food for thought: A longitudinal
investigation of reflection-promoting speech in televised election debates
(1985–2019). Political Studies, 72(1), 67–89.
Ugarriza, J. E., & Nussio, E. (2017). The effect of perspective-giving on postconflict
reconciliation. An experimental approach. Political Psychology, 38(1), 3–19.
Valli, C., & Nai, A. (2023). Dispositioned to resist? The Big Five and resistance
to dissonant political views. Personality and Individual Differences, 207,
112152.
Van Reybrouck, D. (2016). Against elections: The case for democracy. London:
The Bodley Head.
Webster, S. W., & Albertson, B. (2022). Emotion and politics: Noncognitive
psychological biases in public opinion. Annual Review of Political Science,
25, 401–418.
Weinmann, C. (2018). Measuring political thinking: Development and valid-
ation of a scale for “deliberation within.” Political Psychology, 39(2),
365–380.
Wojcieszak, M., & Price, V. (2010). Bridging the divide or intensifying the
conflict? How disagreement affects strong predilections about sexual
minorities. Political Psychology, 31(3), 315–339.
Wyss, D., Beste, S., & Bächtiger, A. (2015). A decline in the quality of debate?
The evolution of cognitive complexity in Swiss parliamentary debates on
immigration (1968–2014). Swiss Political Science Review, 21(4), 636–653.
Zaki, J. (2018). Empathy is a moral force. In K. Gray, & J. Graham (eds.), Atlas
of moral psychology. New York City, NY: The Guilford Press (49–58).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Acknowledgments
This Element was only possible thanks to the support of many mentors,
colleagues, and friends. Incredibly thankful to the former series editor Yanna
Krupnikov for trusting me with this Element, and for her insightful feedback.
The current series editor Liz Suhay and two anonymous reviewers were instru-
mental in helping me refine my ideas. This project benefited from invaluable
feedback I received over the years from my mentors and friends Vin Arceneaux
and Bert Bakker. I’m grateful to Michael Neblo for his kind email about my first
publication as a PhD student and his advice on my book proposal, despite not
knowing me personally. I’m immensely grateful to Nicole Curato, Sofie Marien,
André Bächtiger, David Farrell, Michael Morrell, Robert Goodin, Andrea
Felicetti, Diana Mutz, Shana Gadarian, Jane Suiter, Maija Setälä, Kaisa
Herne, Manos Tsakiris, Jean Decety, Christopher Karpowitz, Matt Ryan,
Edana Beauvais, Hélène Landemore, my PhD committee members, University
of Leuven friends and colleagues and many other academics for their feedback on
my ideas. The Element was revised during the first few months of my new faculty
job at Southampton University and I’m grateful to my new wonderful colleagues
for making me feel welcomed. Thanks also go to my girlfriends Laura, Hayley,
Carmen, Tània, Amélie, Amy, Nieves, Ine, Catherine, and Lila for their love,
support, and dance parties, and to my sister and parents for their excitement about
this Element.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Political Psychology
Elizabeth Suhay
American University, Washington, D.C.
Elizabeth Suhay is Associate Professor of Government in the School of Public Affairs at
American University, Washington, D.C. Her research focuses on political psychology and
political communication, with particular interests in the politics of inequality and the
politicization of knowledge. Her research has been published in political science,
psychology, and interdisciplinary journals, and she has co-edited three edited volumes.
Suhay will be Co-Editor-in-Chief of the journal Political Psychology beginning in 2025.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573
Political Psychology
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 151.250.210.201, on 13 Mar 2025 at 09:01:51, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009643573