Python Programming An Introduction to Computer Science 3rd Edition John M. Zelle pdf download
Python Programming An Introduction to Computer Science 3rd Edition John M. Zelle pdf download
https://textbookfull.com/product/python-programming-an-
introduction-to-computer-science-3rd-edition-john-m-zelle/
https://textbookfull.com/product/python-programming-an-
introduction-to-computer-science-john-m-zelle/
https://textbookfull.com/product/practical-programming-an-
introduction-to-computer-science-using-python-3-6-3rd-edition-
paul-gries/
https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-computation-and-
programming-using-python-3rd-edition-john-v-guttag/
https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-computation-and-
programming-using-python-3rd-edition-john-v-guttag-2/
Bite Size Python An Introduction to Python Programming
1st Edition April Speight
https://textbookfull.com/product/bite-size-python-an-
introduction-to-python-programming-1st-edition-april-speight/
https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-computation-and-
programming-using-python-with-application-to-understanding-data-
second-edition-john-v-guttag/
https://textbookfull.com/product/introduction-to-scientific-
programming-with-python-joakim-sundnes/
https://textbookfull.com/product/discovering-computer-science-
interdisciplinary-problems-principles-and-python-programming-1st-
edition-jessen-havill/
https://textbookfull.com/product/discovering-computer-science-
interdisciplinary-problems-principles-and-python-programming-
first-edition-jessen-havill/
Other documents randomly have
different content
or there, or to enrich itself or impoverish itself in such and such a
fashion? Since it is impossible to avoid taking sides on this initial
problem, and since the solution given is destined to affect the whole
science, it must be attacked at the outset: that is what we propose
to do.
Besides this, outside of these indirect reactions, the study of
primitive religions has of itself an immediate interest which is of
primary importance.
If it is useful to know what a certain particular religion consists in,
it is still more important to know what religion in general is. This is
the problem which has aroused the interest of philosophers in all
times; and not without reason, for it is of interest to all humanity.
Unfortunately, the method which they generally employ is purely
dialectic: they confine themselves to analysing the idea which they
make for themselves of religion, except as they illustrate the results
of this mental analysis by examples borrowed from the religions
which best realize their ideal. But even if this method ought to be
abandoned, the problem remains intact, and the great service of
philosophy is to have prevented its being suppressed by the disdain
of scholars. Now it is possible to attack it in a different way. Since all
religions can be compared to each other, and since all are species of
the same class, there are necessarily many elements which are
common to all. We do not mean to speak simply of the outward and
visible characteristics which they all have equally, and which make it
possible to give them a provisional definition from the very outset of
our researches; the discovery of these apparent signs is relatively
easy, for the observation which it demands does not go beneath the
surface of things. But these external resemblances suppose others
which are profound. At the foundation of all systems of beliefs and
of all cults there ought necessarily to be a certain number of
fundamental representations or conceptions and of ritual attitudes
which, in spite of the diversity of forms which they have taken, have
the same objective significance and fulfil the same functions
everywhere. These are the permanent elements which constitute
that which is permanent and human in religion; they form all the
objective contents of the idea which is expressed when one speaks
of religion in general. How is it possible to pick them out?
Surely it is not by observing the complex religions which appear in
the course of history. Every one of these is made up of such a
variety of elements that it is very difficult to distinguish what is
secondary from what is principal, the essential from the accessory.
Suppose that the religion considered is like that of Egypt, India or
the classical antiquity. It is a confused mass of many cults, varying
according to the locality, the temples, the generations, the dynasties,
the invasions, etc. Popular superstitions are there confused with the
purest dogmas. Neither the thought nor the activity of the religion is
evenly distributed among the believers; according to the men, the
environment and the circumstances, the beliefs as well as the rites
are thought of in different ways. Here they are priests, there they
are monks, elsewhere they are laymen; there are mystics and
rationalists, theologians and prophets, etc. In these conditions it is
difficult to see what is common to all. In one or another of these
systems it is quite possible to find the means of making a profitable
study of some particular fact which is specially developed there,
such as sacrifice or prophecy, monasticism or the mysteries; but how
is it possible to find the common foundation of the religious life
underneath the luxuriant vegetation which covers it? How is it
possible to find, underneath the disputes of theology, the variations
of ritual, the multiplicity of groups and the diversity of individuals,
the fundamental states characteristic of religious mentality in
general?
Things are quite different in the lower societies. The slighter
development of individuality, the small extension of the group, the
homogeneity of external circumstances, all contribute to reducing
the differences and variations to a minimum. The group has an
intellectual and moral conformity of which we find but rare examples
in the more advanced societies. Everything is common to all.
Movements are stereotyped; everybody performs the same ones in
the same circumstances, and this conformity of conduct only
translates the conformity of thought. Every mind being drawn into
the same eddy, the individual type nearly confounds itself with that
of the race. And while all is uniform, all is simple as well. Nothing is
deformed like these myths, all composed of one and the same
theme which is endlessly repeated, or like these rites made up of a
small number of gestures repeated again and again. Neither the
popular imagination nor that of the priests has had either the time or
the means of refining and transforming the original substance of the
religious ideas and practices; these are shown in all their nudity, and
offer themselves to an examination, it requiring only the slightest
effort to lay them open. That which is accessory or secondary, the
development of luxury, has not yet come to hide the principal
elements.[2] All is reduced to that which is indispensable, to that
without which there could be no religion. But that which is
indispensable is also that which is essential, that is to say, that which
we must know before all else.
Primitive civilizations offer privileged cases, then, because they are
simple cases. That is why, in all fields of human activity, the
observations of ethnologists have frequently been veritable
revelations, which have renewed the study of human institutions. For
example, before the middle of the nineteenth century, everybody
was convinced that the father was the essential element of the
family; no one had dreamed that there could be a family
organization of which the paternal authority was not the keystone.
But the discovery of Bachofen came and upset this old conception.
Up to very recent times it was regarded as evident that the moral
and legal relations of kindred were only another aspect of the
psychological relations which result from a common descent;
Bachofen and his successors, MacLennan, Morgan and many others
still laboured under this misunderstanding. But since we have
become acquainted with the nature of the primitive clan, we know
that, on the contrary, relationships cannot be explained by
consanguinity. To return to religions, the study of only the most
familiar ones had led men to believe for a long time that the idea of
god was characteristic of everything that is religious. Now the
religion which we are going to study presently is, in a large part,
foreign to all idea of divinity; the forces to which the rites are there
addressed are very different from those which occupy the leading
place in our modern religions, yet they aid us in understanding these
latter forces. So nothing is more unjust than the disdain with which
too many historians still regard the work of ethnographers. Indeed,
it is certain that ethnology has frequently brought about the most
fruitful revolutions in the different branches of sociology. It is for this
same reason that the discovery of unicellular beings, of which we
just spoke, has transformed the current idea of life. Since in these
very simple beings, life is reduced to its essential traits, these are
less easily misunderstood.
But primitive religions do not merely aid us in disengaging the
constituent elements of religion; they also have the great advantage
that they facilitate the explanation of it. Since the facts there are
simpler, the relations between them are more apparent. The reasons
with which men account for their acts have not yet been elaborated
and denatured by studied reflection; they are nearer and more
closely related to the motives which have really determined these
acts. In order to understand an hallucination perfectly, and give it its
most appropriate treatment, a physician must know its original point
of departure. Now this event is proportionately easier to find if he
can observe it near its beginnings. The longer the disease is allowed
to develop, the more it evades observation; that is because all sorts
of interpretations have intervened as it advanced, which tend to
force the original state into the background, and across which it is
frequently difficult to find the initial one. Between a systematized
hallucination and the first impressions which gave it birth, the
distance is often considerable. It is the same thing with religious
thought. In proportion as it progresses in history, the causes which
called it into existence, though remaining active, are no longer
perceived, except across a vast scheme of interpretations which
quite transform them. Popular mythologies and subtile theologies
have done their work: they have superimposed upon the primitive
sentiments others which are quite different, and which, though
holding to the first, of which they are an elaborated form, only allow
their true nature to appear very imperfectly. The psychological gap
between the cause and the effect, between the apparent cause and
the effective cause, has become more considerable and more
difficult for the mind to leap. The remainder of this book will be an
illustration and a verification of this remark on method. It will be
seen how, in the primitive religions, the religious fact still visibly
carries the mark of its origins: it would have been well-nigh
impossible to infer them merely from the study of the more
developed religions.
The study which we are undertaking is therefore a way of taking
up again, but under new conditions, the old problem of the origin of
religion. To be sure, if by origin we are to understand the very first
beginning, the question has nothing scientific about it, and should
be resolutely discarded. There was no given moment when religion
began to exist, and there is consequently no need of finding a
means of transporting ourselves thither in thought. Like every
human institution, religion did not commence anywhere. Therefore,
all speculations of this sort are justly discredited; they can only
consist in subjective and arbitrary constructions which are subject to
no sort of control. But the problem which we raise is quite another
one. What we want to do is to find a means of discerning the ever-
present causes upon which the most essential forms of religious
thought and practice depend. Now for the reasons which were just
set forth, these causes are proportionately more easily observable as
the societies where they are observed are less complicated. That is
why we try to get as near as possible to the origins.[3] It is not that
we ascribe particular virtues to the lower religions. On the contrary,
they are rudimentary and gross; we cannot make of them a sort of
model which later religions only have to reproduce. But even their
grossness makes them instructive, for they thus become convenient
for experiments, as in them, the facts and their relations are easily
seen. In order to discover the laws of the phenomena which he
studies, the physicist tries to simplify these latter and rid them of
their secondary characteristics. For that which concerns institutions,
nature spontaneously makes the same sort of simplifications at the
beginning of history. We merely wish to put these to profit.
Undoubtedly we can only touch very elementary facts by this
method. When we shall have accounted for them as far as possible,
the novelties of every sort which have been produced in the course
of evolution will not yet be explained. But while we do not dream of
denying the importance of the problems thus raised, we think that
they will profit by being treated in their turn, and that it is important
to take them up only after those of which we are going to undertake
the study at present.
II
But our study is not of interest merely for the science of religion.
In fact, every religion has one side by which it overlaps the circle of
properly religious ideas, and there, the study of religious phenomena
gives a means of renewing the problems which, up to the present,
have only been discussed among philosophers.
For a long time it has been known that the first systems of
representations with which men have pictured to themselves the
world and themselves were of religious origin. There is no religion
that is not a cosmology at the same time that it is a speculation
upon divine things. If philosophy and the sciences were born of
religion, it is because religion began by taking the place of the
sciences and philosophy. But it has been less frequently noticed that
religion has not confined itself to enriching the human intellect,
formed beforehand, with a certain number of ideas; it has
contributed to forming the intellect itself. Men owe to it not only a
good part of the substance of their knowledge, but also the form in
which this knowledge has been elaborated.
At the roots of all our judgments there are a certain number of
essential ideas which dominate all our intellectual life; they are what
philosophers since Aristotle have called the categories of the
understanding: ideas of time, space,[4] class, number, cause,
substance, personality, etc. They correspond to the most universal
properties of things. They are like the solid frame which encloses all
thought; this does not seem to be able to liberate itself from them
without destroying itself, for it seems that we cannot think of objects
that are not in time and space, which have no number, etc. Other
ideas are contingent and unsteady; we can conceive of their being
unknown to a man, a society or an epoch; but these others appear
to be nearly inseparable from the normal working of the intellect.
They are like the framework of the intelligence. Now when primitive
religious beliefs are systematically analysed, the principal categories
are naturally found. They are born in religion and of religion; they
are a product of religious thought. This is a statement that we are
going to have occasion to make many times in the course of this
work.
This remark has some interest of itself already; but here is what
gives it its real importance.
The general conclusion of the book which the reader has before
him is that religion is something eminently social. Religious
representations are collective representations which express
collective realities; the rites are a manner of acting which take rise in
the midst of the assembled groups and which are destined to excite,
maintain or recreate certain mental states in these groups. So if the
categories are of religious origin, they ought to participate in this
nature common to all religious facts; they too should be social affairs
and the product of collective thought. At least—for in the actual
condition of our knowledge of these matters, one should be careful
to avoid all radical and exclusive statements—it is allowable to
suppose that they are rich in social elements.
Even at present, these can be imperfectly seen in some of them.
For example, try to represent what the notion of time would be
without the processes by which we divide it, measure it or express it
with objective signs, a time which is not a succession of years,
months, weeks, days and hours! This is something nearly
unthinkable. We cannot conceive of time, except on condition of
distinguishing its different moments. Now what is the origin of this
differentiation? Undoubtedly, the states of consciousness which we
have already experienced can be reproduced in us in the same order
in which they passed in the first place; thus portions of our past
become present again, though being clearly distinguished from the
present. But howsoever important this distinction may be for our
private experience, it is far from being enough to constitute the
notion or category of time. This does not consist merely in a
commemoration, either partial or integral, of our past life. It is an
abstract and impersonal frame which surrounds, not only our
individual existence, but that of all humanity. It is like an endless
chart, where all duration is spread out before the mind, and upon
which all possible events can be located in relation to fixed and
determined guide lines. It is not my time that is thus arranged; it is
time in general, such as it is objectively thought of by everybody in a
single civilization. That alone is enough to give us a hint that such an
arrangement ought to be collective. And in reality, observation
proves that these indispensable guide lines, in relation to which all
things are temporally located, are taken from social life. The
divisions into days, weeks, months, years, etc., correspond to the
periodical recurrence of rites, feasts, and public ceremonies.[5] A
calendar expresses the rhythm of the collective activities, while at
the same time its function is to assure their regularity.[6]
It is the same thing with space. As Hamelin has shown,[7] space is
not the vague and indetermined medium which Kant imagined; if
purely and absolutely homogeneous, it would be of no use, and
could not be grasped by the mind. Spatial representation consists
essentially in a primary co-ordination of the data of sensuous
experience. But this co-ordination would be impossible if the parts of
space were qualitatively equivalent and if they were really
interchangeable. To dispose things spatially there must be a
possibility of placing them differently, of putting some at the right,
others at the left, these above, those below, at the north of or at the
south of, east or west of, etc., etc., just as to dispose states of
consciousness temporally there must be a possibility of localizing
them at determined dates. That is to say that space could not be
what it is if it were not, like time, divided and differentiated. But
whence come these divisions which are so essential? By themselves,
there are neither right nor left, up nor down, north nor south, etc.
All these distinctions evidently come from the fact that different
sympathetic values have been attributed to various regions. Since all
the men of a single civilization represent space in the same way, it is
clearly necessary that these sympathetic values, and the distinctions
which depend upon them, should be equally universal, and that
almost necessarily implies that they be of social origin.[8]
Besides that, there are cases where this social character is made
manifest. There are societies in Australia and North America where
space is conceived in the form of an immense circle, because the
camp has a circular form;[9] and this spatial circle is divided up
exactly like the tribal circle, and is in its image. There are as many
regions distinguished as there are clans in the tribe, and it is the
place occupied by the clans inside the encampment which has
determined the orientation of these regions. Each region is defined
by the totem of the clan to which it is assigned. Among the Zuñi, for
example, the pueblo contains seven quarters; each of these is a
group of clans which has had a unity: in all probability it was
originally a single clan which was later subdivided. Now their space
also contains seven quarters, and each of these seven quarters of
the world is in intimate connection with a quarter of the pueblo, that
is to say with a group of clans.[10] "Thus," says Cushing, "one
division is thought to be in relation with the north, another
represents the west, another the south," etc.[11] Each quarter of the
pueblo has its characteristic colour, which symbolizes it; each region
has its colour, which is exactly the same as that of the corresponding
quarter. In the course of history the number of fundamental clans
has varied; the number of the fundamental regions of space has
varied with them. Thus the social organization has been the model
for the spatial organization and a reproduction of it. It is thus even
up to the distinction between right and left which, far from being
inherent in the nature of man in general, is very probably the
product of representations which are religious and therefore
collective.[12]
Analogous proofs will be found presently in regard to the ideas of
class, force, personality and efficacy. It is even possible to ask if the
idea of contradiction does not also depend upon social conditions.
What makes one tend to believe this is that the empire which the
idea has exercised over human thought has varied with times and
societies. To-day the principle of identity dominates scientific
thought; but there are vast systems of representations which have
played a considerable rôle in the history of ideas where it has
frequently been set aside: these are the mythologies, from the
grossest up to the most reasonable.[13] There, we are continually
coming upon beings which have the most contradictory attributes
simultaneously, who are at the same time one and many, material
and spiritual, who can divide themselves up indefinitely without
losing anything of their constitution; in mythology it is an axiom that
the part is worth the whole. These variations through which the
rules which seem to govern our present logic have passed prove
that, far from being engraven through all eternity upon the mental
constitution of men, they depend, at least in part, upon factors that
are historical and consequently social. We do not know exactly what
they are, but we may presume that they exist.[14]
PRELIMINARY QUESTIONS
CHAPTER I
DEFINITION OF RELIGIOUS
PHENOMENA AND OF RELIGION[25]
If we are going to look for the most primitive and simple religion
which we can observe, it is necessary to begin by defining what is
meant by a religion; for without this, we would run the risk of giving
the name to a system of ideas and practices which has nothing at all
religious about it, or else of leaving to one side many religious facts,
without perceiving their true nature. That this is not an imaginary
danger, and that nothing is thus sacrificed to a vain formalism of
method, is well shown by the fact that owing to his not having taken
this precaution, a certain scholar to whom the science of
comparative religions owes a great deal, Professor Frazer, has not
been able to recognize the profoundly religious character of the
beliefs and rites which will be studied below, where, according to our
view, the initial germ of the religious life of humanity is to be found.
So this is a prejudicial question, which must be treated before all
others. It is not that we dream of arriving at once at the profound
characteristics which really explain religion: these can be determined
only at the end of our study. But that which is necessary and
possible, is to indicate a certain number of external and easily
recognizable signs, which will enable us to recognize religious
phenomena wherever they are met with, and which will deter us
from confounding them with others. We shall proceed to this
preliminary operation at once.
But to attain the desired results, it is necessary to begin by freeing
the mind of every preconceived idea. Men have been obliged to
make for themselves a notion of what religion is, long before the
science of religions started its methodical comparisons. The
necessities of existence force all of us, believers and non-believers,
to represent in some way these things in the midst of which we live,
upon which we must pass judgment constantly, and which we must
take into account in all our conduct. However, since these
preconceived ideas are formed without any method, according to the
circumstances and chances of life, they have no right to any credit
whatsoever, and must be rigorously set aside in the examination
which is to follow. It is not from our prejudices, passions or habits
that we should demand the elements of the definition which we
must have; it is from the reality itself which we are going to define.
Let us set ourselves before this reality. Leaving aside all
conceptions of religion in general, let us consider the various
religions in their concrete reality, and attempt to disengage that
which they have in common; for religion cannot be defined except
by the characteristics which are found wherever religion itself is
found. In this comparison, then, we shall make use of all the
religious systems which we can know, those of the present and
those of the past, the most primitive and simple as well as the most
recent and refined; for we have neither the right nor the logical
means of excluding some and retaining others. For those who regard
religion as only a natural manifestation of human activity, all
religions, without any exception whatsoever, are instructive; for all,
after their manner, express man, and thus can aid us in better
understanding this aspect of our nature. Also, we have seen how far
it is from being the best way of studying religion to consider by
preference the forms which it presents among the most civilized
peoples.[26]
But to aid the mind in freeing itself from these usual conceptions
which, owing to their prestige, might prevent it from seeing things
as they really are, it is fitting to examine some of the most current of
the definitions in which these prejudices are commonly expressed,
before taking up the question on our own account.
II
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
textbookfull.com