Buckland English
Buckland English
Michael K. Buckland
School of Library and Information Studies, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720
Three meanings of "information" are distinguished: (1) Information-as-process: When someone is in-
'Information-as-process"; "information-as-knowledge"; formed, what they know is changed. In this sense
and "information-as-thing," the attributive use of "in- "information" is "The act of informing.. .; com-
formation" to denote things regarded as informative. munication of the knowledge or 'news' of some
The nature and characteristics of "information-as- fact or occurrence; the action of telling or fact of
thing" are discussed, using an indirect approach ("What
things are informative?"). Varieties of "information-
being told of something" (Oxford English Dic-
as-thing" include data, text, documents, objects, and tionary, 1989, vol. 7 , p. 944).
events. On this view "information" includes but extends ( 2 ) Information-as-knowledge: "Information" is also
beyond communication. Whatever information storage used to denote that which is perceived in "infor-
and retrieval systems store and retrieve is necessarily mation-as-process:" the "knowledge communi-
'information-as-thing." cated concerning some particular fact, subject, or
These three meanings of "information," along with event; that of which one is apprised or told; intelli-
"information processing," offer a basis for classifying gence, news" (Oxford English Dictionary, 1989,
disparate information-related activities (e.g., rhetoric, vol. 7 , p. 944). The notion of information as that
bibliographic retrieval, statistical analysis) and, thereby, which reduces uncertainty could be viewed as
suggest a topography for "information science."
a special case of "information-as-knowledge."
Sometimes information increases uncertainty.
Introduction: The Ambiguity of "Information" (3) Information-as-thing: The term "information" is
also used attributively for objects, such as data and
An exploration of "information" runs into immedi- documents, that are referred to as "information"
ate difficulties. Since information has to do with be- because they are regarded as being informative, as
coming informed, with the reduction of ignorance and "having the quality of imparting knowledge or
of uncertainty, it is ironic that the term "information" is communicating information; instructive." (Oxford
itself ambiguous and used in different ways. (For a con- English Dictionary, 1989, vol. 7 , p. 946).
cise and convenient introduction to varieties of mean-
7
ings of "information" and some related terms see A key characteristic of "information-as-knowledge '
Machlup (1983). See also Braman (1989), NATO (1974, is that it is intangible: one cannot touch it or measure it
1975, 1983); Schrader (1983), Wellisch (1972), Wersig in any direct way. Knowledge, belief, and opinion are
and Neveling (1975)). Faced with the variety of mean- personal, subjective, and conceptual. Therefore, to
ings of "information," we can, at least, take a pragmatic communicate them, they have to be expressed, de-
approach. We can survey the landscape and seeking scribed, or represented in some physical way, as a sig-
to identify groupings of uses of the term "information." nal, text, or communication. Any such expression,
The definitions may not be fully satisfactory, the description, or representation would be "information-
boundaries between these uses may be indistinct, and as-thing." We shall discuss implications of this below.
such an approach could not satisfy anyone determined Some theorists have objected to the attributive use
to establish the one correct meaning of "information." of the term "information" to denote a thing in the third
But if the principal uses can be identified, sorted, and sense above. Wiener asserted that "Information is infor-
characterized, then some progress might be made. mation, not material nor energy." Machlup (1983,
Using this approach we identify three principal uses of p. 642), who restricted information to the context of
the word "information:" communication, was dismissive of this third sense of
information: "The noun 'information' has essentially
two traditional meanings.. .Any meanings other than
Received November 14, 1989; revised March 16, 1990; accepted
March 29, 1990. (1) the telling of something or (2) that which is being told
are either analogies and metaphors or concoctions re-
©1991 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc sulting from the condoned appropriation of a word that
JOURNAL OF THE AMERICAN SOCIETY FOR INFORMATION SCIENCE. 42(5):351-360, 1991 CCC 0002-8231/91/050351-10$04.00
had not been meant by earlier users." Fairthorne (1954) event can be filmed. However, the representation is no
objected scornfully to information as "stuff": "informa- more knowledge than the film is the event. Any such
tion is an attribute of the receiver's knowledge and in- representation is necessarily in tangible form (sign, sig-
terpretation of the signal, not of the sender's, nor some nal, data, text, film, etc.) and so representations of
omniscient observer's nor of the signal itself." knowledge (and of events) are necessarily "information-
But language is as it is used and we can hardly dis- as-thing."
miss "information-as-thing" so long as it is a commonly Information-as-thing is of special interest in the
used meaning of the term "information." Indeed, lan- study of information systems. It is with information in
guages evolve and with the expansion of information this sense that information systems deal directly. Li-
technology, the practice of referring to communica- braries deal with books; computer-based information
tions, databases, books, and the like, as "information" systems handle data in the form of physical bits and
appears to be becoming commoner and, perhaps, a sig- bytes; museums deal directly with objects. The inten-
nificant source of confusion as symbols and symbol- tion may be that users will become informed (informa-
bearing objects are easily confused with whatever the tion-as-process) and that there will be an imparting of
symbols denote. Further, "information-as-thing," by knowledge (information-as-knowledge). But the means
whatever name, is of especial interest in relation to provided, what is handled and operated upon, what is
information systems because ultimately information stored and retrieved, is physical information (informa-
systems, including "expert systems" and information re- tion-as-thing). On these definitions, there can be no
trieval systems, can deal directly with information only such thing as a "knowledged-based" expert system or a
in this sense. The development of rules for drawing in- "knowledge access" system, only systems based on
ferences from stored information is an area of theoreti- physical representations of knowledge.
cal and practical interest. But these rules operate upon This introductory discussion can be rounded out by
and only upon information-as-thing. reference to a fourth element: information processing,
The purpose of this examination of the notion of the handling, manipulating, and deriving of new forms
"information-as-thing" is to or versions of information-as-thing. (One could regard
the process of becoming informed as a sort of informa-
(1) Clarify its meaning in relation to other uses of the
term "information;" tion processing, but, to reduce confusion, we prefer to
(2) Affirm the fundamental role of "information-as- separate and exclude mental information-as-process
thing" in information systems; and from the scope of "information processing.")
(3) Speculate on possible use of the notion of "infor- Our discussion thus far can be summarized in terms
mation-as-thing" in bringing theoretical order to of two distinctions (1) between entities and processes;
the heterogeneous, ill-ordered fields associated and (2) between intangibles and tangibles. Taken in
with "information science." conjunction, these two distinctions yield four quite dif-
The distinction between intangibles (knowledge and ferent aspects of information and information systems.
information-as-knowledge) and tangibles (information- See Fig. 1.1.
as-thing) is central to what follows. If you can touch it
or measure it directly, it is not knowledge, but must be
A Reverse Approach: What is Informative?
some physical thing, possibly information-as-thing.
(This distinction may be overstated. Knowledge may Instead of the tedious task of reviewing candidate
well be represented in the brain in some tangible, physi- objects and inquiring whether or not they should be
cal way. However, for present purposes and for the considered to be examples of information-as-thing, we
time being, treating knowledge in the mind as impor- can reverse the process and ask people to identify the
tantly different from artificial stores of information things by or on account of which they came to be in-
seems reasonable and useful. Academic examinations formed. People will say that they are informed by a very
test individuals' ability to answer questions or to solve wide variety of things, such as messages, data, docu-
problems, which is presumed to provide indirect mea- ments, objects, events, the view through the window, by
sures of what they know. But that is not the same.) any kind of evidence. This point was recognized by
Knowledge, however, can be represented, just as an Brookes (1979, p. 14): "In the sciences it has long been
INTANGIBLE TANGIBLE
ENTITY 2. Information-as-knowledge 3. Information-as-thing
Knowledge Data, document
JOURNAL OF THE AMERICAN SOCIETY FOR INFORMATION SCIENCE- June 1991 357
in relation to other documents makes them unique by and texts to data. Exceptions to this, such as from
association and, thereby, different. object to object or from document back to object
In electronic data bases the situation is a little less (physical replicas and models) can also be found
clear. One can have copies of two sorts: There can be (Schlebecker, 1977).
temporary, virtual copies displayed on a screen; or one (4) Additional details related to the object but not evi-
dent from it might be added to the representation,
can make copies of a longer lasting form on paper or
either to inform or to misinform.
other storage medium. These copies might not, from
(5) Representation can continue indefinitely. There
some engineering error, be quite the same as the origi- can be representations of representations of repre-
nal. However, it is ordinarily assumed that either the sentations.
copy is authentic or that errors will be so marked as to (6) For practical reasons representations are com-
be self-evident. There may be difficulty in knowing monly (but not necessarily) briefer or smaller than
whether the copy is a copy of the latest, official version whatever is being represented, concentrating on
of the database, but that is a different issue. With hand- the features expected to be most significant. A
written, manuscript texts, one should expect each ex- summary, almost by definition, is an incomplete
ample to be at least slightly different, even if it purports description.
to be a copy. The person making a copy is likely to Progress in information technology continually per-
omit, add, and change parts of the text. A significant mits improvements in our ability to make physical
feature of medieval studies is the necessity of examin- descriptions, examples of information-as-thing. Photo-
ing closely all copies of related manuscripts not only to graphs improve on drawings; digital images improve on
identify the differences, but also to infer which might photographs. The voice of the nineteenth century
be the more correct versions where they do differ. singer, Jenny Lind, was described by Queen Victoria as
In general, then, the existence of identical, equally "a most exquisite, powerful and really quite peculiar
informative, equally authoritative copies is unusual. voice, so round, so soft and flexible.. ." (Sadie, 1980,
Printed materials in libraries are a notable exception. v. 10, p. 865). Although this description is better than
More general is the case where copies are not altogether none, we could learn much more from a phonograph
identical, though they may be equally acceptable for recording.
most purposes. Reproductions of works of art and of museum arti-
facts may suffice for some purposes and have the ad-
Interpretations and Summaries of Evidence vantages that they can provide much increased physical
access without wear and tear on the originals. Yet they
Progress in information technology increases the will always be deficient in some ways as representations
scope for creating and using information-as-thing. of the original, even though, as in the case of works of
Much of the information in information systems has art and museum objects, even experts cannot always
been processed by being coded, interpreted, summa- identify which is an original and which is a copy (Mills
rized, or otherwise transformed. Books are a good ex- & Mansfield, 1979).
ample. Virtually all of the books in the collections are
based, at least in part, on earlier evidence, both texts
and other forms of information. Scholarship is perme- Information, Information Systems, Information
ated with descriptions and summaries, or, as we prefer Science
to call them, representations. We started with two academically respectable usages
Representations have important characteristics: of the term "information" ("information-as-knowledge"
(1) Every representation can be expected to be more and "information-as-process")and we noted that infor-
or less incomplete in some regard. A photograph mation systems can deal directly only with "information-
does not indicate movement and may not depict as-thing." Stating this paradox differently, information
the color. Even a color photograph will generally systems handle information only in a sense of informa-
show colors imperfectly-and fade with time. A tion dismissed by leading theorists of information. We
written narrative will reflect the viewpoint of the also concluded that anything might be information-as-
writer and the limitations of the language. Films thing. Small wonder that progress in the development
and photographs usually show only one perspec- of paradigms for describing and explaining phenomena
tive. Something of the original is always lost. in the shapeless, ill-defined reaches of "information
There is always some distortion, even if only science" has been slow. But, perhaps, "information-as-
through incompleteness.
thing" could be used to provide some order or arrange-
(2) Representations are made for convenience, which
in this context tends to mean easier to store, to ment with respect t o information-related activities,
understand, and/or to search. along with the two more respectable definitions.
(3) Because of the quest for convenience, representa- First, although all information systems deal directly
tions are normally a shift from event or object to with "information-as-thing," we might create some
text, from one text to another text, or from objects order within this area if we could identify a subset of
360 JOURNAL OF THE AMERICAN SOCIETY FOR INFORMATION SCIENCE- June 1991