Iconoclasm in European Cinema The Ethics and Aesthetics of Image Destruction Chiara Quaranta PDF Download
Iconoclasm in European Cinema The Ethics and Aesthetics of Image Destruction Chiara Quaranta PDF Download
https://ebookbell.com/product/iconoclasm-in-european-cinema-the-
ethics-and-aesthetics-of-image-destruction-chiara-
quaranta-50776896
https://ebookbell.com/product/iconoclasm-in-european-cinema-the-
ethics-and-aesthetics-of-image-destruction-chiara-quaranta-52103746
https://ebookbell.com/product/calvinist-preaching-and-iconoclasm-in-
the-netherlands-15441569-phyllis-mack-crew-49033938
https://ebookbell.com/product/buddhism-and-iconoclasm-in-east-asia-a-
history-fabio-rambelli-eric-reinders-50670408
https://ebookbell.com/product/buddhism-and-iconoclasm-in-east-asia-a-
history-fabio-rambelli-eric-reinders-22683112
Under The Hammer Iconoclasm In The Angloamerican Tradition Clarendon
Lectures In English Literature James Simpson
https://ebookbell.com/product/under-the-hammer-iconoclasm-in-the-
angloamerican-tradition-clarendon-lectures-in-english-literature-
james-simpson-2514320
https://ebookbell.com/product/shattered-images-the-rise-of-militant-
iconoclasm-in-syria-fred-a-reed-6873320
https://ebookbell.com/product/sabotage-art-politics-and-iconoclasm-in-
contemporary-latin-america-ezcurra-11782318
https://ebookbell.com/product/negating-the-image-case-studies-in-
iconoclasm-anne-mcclanan-11235876
https://ebookbell.com/product/literary-circles-in-byzantine-
iconoclasm-patrons-politics-and-saints-scar-prieto-domnguez-23948194
ICONOCLASM
I N E U RO P E A N
CINEMA
THE ETHICS AND AESTHETICS
O F I M AG E D E S T R U C T I O N
C H I A R A Q U A R A N TA
Iconoclasm in European Cinema
Iconoclasm in European Cinema
The Ethics and Aesthetics of Image
Destruction
Chiara Quaranta
Edinburgh University Press is one of the leading university presses in the UK. We publish
a cademic books and journals in our selected subject areas across the humanities and social
sciences, combining cutting-edge scholarship with high editorial and production values to
produce academic works of lasting importance. For more information visit our
website: e dinburghuniversitypress.com
We are committed to making research available to a wide audience and are pleased to be
publishing an Open Access ebook edition of this title.
A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library
The right of Chiara Quaranta to be identified as author of this work has been asserted in
accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 and the Copyright and Related
Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498).
Contents
Introduction1
Prologue: The Eikōn-Eidōlon Dichotomy from Plato to Film 23
Notes195
Glossary201
Bibliography205
Filmography223
Index226
Figures
This book has developed from my PhD thesis on the topic of cinema and icono-
clasm, which would not have been possible without the constant guidance of my
doctoral supervisor, David Sorfa, whom I would like to thank in particular also
for strongly encouraging me to turn the thesis into a book and for his help and
support throughout. My sincere thanks also go to my second supervisor, Daniel
Yacavone, for his insightful comments and his hard questions which encour-
aged me to broaden the research; my PhD examiners, Libby Saxton and Marion
Schmid, who provided helpful insights into various ways in which I could
develop my thesis into a book; and my master’s supervisor, Ivelise Perniola, who
was my first interlocutor on the topic of iconoclasm and cinema.
Once I set my mind to undertake the task of writing this book, I struggled
with envisioning my thesis as a publishable work, and I am extremely grateful to
Gillian Leslie at Edinburgh University Press for believing in my idea, even when
it was not ready yet, for meeting with me and for explaining the ways in which
I could have developed it for publication. Sincere thanks also go to Sam Johnson
and the editorial team at EUP.
I would like to express my gratitude to Krister Collin at Svenska Filminstitutet
for his help with the cover image and to Carl-Gustaf Nykvist for giving permis-
sion. Thanks to you, the cover image I had in my head is now on the cover of
this book. I would also like to thank wholeheartedly Dan Harrison, Jack Walker
and Nicholas Canny for their prompt help, and Davide Messina for his valuable
advice on various aspects of the book.
This book has significantly benefitted from suggestions and conversations
with friends and colleagues over the past few years; these include Silvia Angeli,
William Brown, David Fleming, François Giraud, Pasquale Iannone and
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS | ix
Tyler Parks. Thank you for pushing me to question my ideas by providing feed-
back at conferences, or by sharing your thoughts in front of a friendly pint. I
would like to thank especially Francesco Sticchi for reading drafts of some chap-
ters and discussing ideas with me. I am also grateful to the anonymous reader
whose thorough feedback has helped me deepen the argument.
Finally, I wish to express my sincere gratitude to all those persons whose
support, encouragement and love have left a mark on this work. I could not have
endured the stress and self-doubts of writing this book without the comfort of
my dear friends, who listened to my worries and brought a smile to my face. A
special thought goes to my friend Francesco Roscino, for this work is at times
haunted by his memory. I am profoundly grateful to my parents, Maria Adele
and Nicola, and my sister, Lavinia, without whose support and love I would not
have completed this book. Last but not least, warmest thanks to my wee neph-
ews Giulio and Davide, who have unknowingly restored my faith in this world.
It was no ‘empty square’ which I had exhibited but rather the experience of
non-objectivity.
– Kazimir Malevich, The Manifesto of Suprematism
I am Echo, dwelling in the recesses of your ears; and if thou wouldst paint my
likeness, paint sound.
– Ausonius, In Echo Pictam
Introduction
WE LIVE IN an age and society profoundly affected by visual images. From the
screens of our phones to work computers, from advertising images scattered
across towns to films and television programmes, the emphasis on sight and
recorded images (both still and moving) is stronger than ever in our quotid-
ian life. And yet, this abundance of images has not brought about a greater
awareness regarding their nature. The contemporary ‘iconocracy’, as Marie-José
Mondzain (2019, 17)1 aptly defines it, allows anyone to become a producer of
images but, at the same time, it has not made it any easier for individuals to
understand the power and risk of our uses of images. What is more, and seem-
ingly paradoxically, this extremely visible society is characterised by an unprec-
edented and unnoticed destruction of images on a daily basis. Hardly anybody
is immune to this dichotomic situation – for instance, we easily take pictures
and make videos with digital technologies, but just as easily we delete them for a
variety of reasons, such as the lack of hard drive space or because a beloved face
has become intolerable. Hence, the destruction of images – that is, iconoclasm
(etymologically ‘the breaking of images’)2 – constitutes a pervasive element of
contemporary Western society and can, thus, be used as a way to investigate
how we interact with and understand still and moving images.
Western Europe represents an exemplary context for exploring iconoclastic
attitudes since, historically and philosophically, it has been the ground for com-
peting interpretations regarding visual representations: bequeathed by Imperial
Roman and Catholic iconophilia, it is simultaneously heir to Platonic, Biblical
and Christian iconoclasm. Contradictory influences have contributed to the
shaping of current European imaginary, within which a continuous production
of images is accompanied by a sharp criticism and a mistrust thereof. There is
2 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
for the duration of the West’s history, this motif [of the deceitful image] will
have resulted from the alliance (and it is doubtless this that has so decisively
marked the West as such) forged between the principle of monotheism and the
Greek problematic of the copy or the simulation, of artifice and the absence of
the original. Of course, this alliance is also the source of the mistrust toward
images that continues unabated into our own time (and this in a culture that
produces images in abundance), a mistrust that has, in its turn, produced a
deep suspicion regarding ‘appearances’ or ‘the spectacle’, as well as a certain
self-satisfied critique of the ‘civilization of images’. (31–32)
The history of Western thought about images is thus the contradictory result of
two extremes: always on the verge of refusing sensible representations, echoing
Platonic philosophy and Christian iconoclasm, it has nonetheless welcomed
the image following the Christian legitimation of sacred icons. In a culture
which constantly communicates through images and in which the individual
is surrounded by elements addressing sight, iconoclasm and its opposite –
iconophilia – find a place in the spectrum of possible attitudes towards images.
The study of iconoclastic approaches to images can therefore contribute to
our understanding of current visual culture, further exploring the ambiguous
nature of representations. Destructive gestures in the visual arts constitute both
INTRODUCTION | 3
a way to criticise the image’s illusory nature and a means for acknowledging
the image’s ability to provide an alternative engagement with the world when it
ceases to be a mere mimetic appearance.
This book develops from the potential value of iconoclasm in the ambit of
cinema. While the topic of iconoclasm has been at the centre of many scholarly
works in philosophy, theology and history, it has been quite overlooked by the
arts and film studies. The core of the book coils around cinematic iconoclasm
and what can be termed broken images – both recalling the etymological mean-
ing of iconoclasm and because their relationship with the referent is broken.
The audio-visual images analysed throughout are literally or metaphorically
broken: no longer functioning as self-evident, mimetic images of reality, these
images are either broken in their physicality (the film strip is literally dam-
aged), or broken in their ability to figuratively represent something (hence,
monochromatic screens, fades to colour, disruptive sounds and altered motion).
Accordingly, I have selected films characterised by an anti-mimetic aesthetics
which responds to an iconoclastic understanding of the image-referent relation-
ship; namely, Isidore Isou’s Traité de bave et d’éternité (Treatise on Venom and
Eternity, 1951), Guy Debord’s Hurlements en faveur de Sade (Howls for Sade,
1952), The Society of the Spectacle (La Société du spectacle, 1973) and In girum
imus nocte et consumimur igni (We Wander in the Night and Are Consumed by
Fire, 1978), Carmelo Bene’s Our Lady of the Turks (Nostra signora dei turchi,
1968), Jean-Luc Godard’s Histoire(s) du cinéma (1988–98), Marguerite Duras’s
Le Navire Night (1979), Derek Jarman’s Blue (1993), Ingmar Bergman’s Cries
and Whispers (Viskningar och rop, 1972) and Krzysztof Kieślowski’s Three
Colours: Blue (Trois Couleurs: Bleu, 1993).
The selected films effectively exemplify cinematic iconoclasm, which refers
to the deliberate, literal or metaphorical, destruction of film images and which
hinges on an interpretation of the relationship between the image and its ref-
erent in terms of alterity. That is, the image as copy is understood as inade-
quate for the representation of a specific model. My main contention is that the
destruction of images in the cinema can be a breeding ground for an aesthetic
and ethical investigation of the ways in which we understand and use moving
images. Contrary to historical iconoclasm, which consists of a negation of the
other’s point of view through the destruction of the other’s artefacts (an atti-
tude evident in iconoclastic gestures such as the smashing of sacred icons in
Byzantium in the eighth and ninth centuries and the destruction of Catholic
abbeys in Scotland during the Reformation; or, more recently, in the blowing
up of the Buddhas of Bamiyan and the ancient city of Palmira [Besançon 2000;
Bettetini 2006, 92–104, 142; Latour and Weibel 2002; Mondzain 2019, 314]),
4 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
the opposition between the eikōn and the eidōlon can be thought of in cinema,
depending on whether the attention is primarily on the eidōlon or on the eikōn.
Accordingly, cinematic iconoclasm can concentrate on critiquing the image
as illusory and deceptive copy (eidōlon), thereby bearing many similarities to
the arguments made by the iconoclasts in the eighth and ninth centuries. Both
theoretically and practically, cinematic iconoclasm as critique frequently occurs
within the context of a Marxist criticism of commodities, mass media and cap-
italism’s fundamental values. In the films selected for Part I, a certain type of
image, that of Hollywood-like cinema, is decried insofar as it produces an illu-
sory ‘impression of reality’ (Rodowick 1994, xvi), thereby concealing capitalist
ideology under non-contradictory images. Particularly the exponents of leftist
film theory in their arguments echoed the iconoclastic criticism of the image as
a deceitful copy, which is matched practically in the audio-visually destructive
works by the likes of Isidore Isou, Guy Debord, Carmelo Bene and Jean-Luc
Godard.
Another way of approaching cinematic iconoclasm and its ethical poten-
tial is through what I address as iconoclastic eikōn. By this term I define an
image which retains the character of the eikōn of referencing the prototype,
while being reflective of an iconoclastic understanding of the image-prototype
relationship. That is to say, an iconoclastic eikōn maintains at once the quality
of being a mediator between two elements otherwise separated and an icon-
oclastic aspect given by the negation of mimesis; hence, the visual image is
in some way insufficient to figuratively represent its model. The theme of the
image’s insufficiency to represent recalls the ongoing issue of mimesis, which
has troubled aesthetics since its inception. How can an image, conceived as
copy, represent a referent? And what if the referent lacks a phenomenal equiv-
alent (such that it can only be thought or experienced emotionally)? Assuming
that the act of looking is never neutral and that there exists specific subject
matter which more forcefully entails a taking of responsibility from producers
and viewers of images, iconoclastic approaches to cinema often involve the
ethical significance of moving beyond mimesis. The film image as iconoclastic
eikōn constitutes a way of showing something without making it completely
visible and aurally accessible, thereby encouraging an ethics based on the fragile
equilibrium between visibility and invisibility. Poignant examples are found in
the work of, among others, Marguerite Duras, Derek Jarman, Ingmar Bergman
and Krzysztof Kieślowski, where a need to represent audio-visually is met with a
striving for an ethical film form at the limits of intelligibility.
The questions tying the book together therefore concern the ways in which
iconoclastic film images establish a web of relationships with their models and
6 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
the spectator. Can everything have a copy of itself? That is, can we make images
of everything? This question, which is more of a quandary, also leads to interro-
gating the limits of our right to see and show something on a screen. Ultimately,
when this right is challenged by iconoclastic gestures, we are left wondering
what it is that we see when we see images of imagelessness.
Because of the very nature of iconoclasm and the way in which I explore it
in relation to philosophy and cinema, this book is characterised by a lively
interdisciplinarity, bringing together works in continental philosophy, medieval
theology, history, history of art and film studies. Iconoclasm, in fact, encom-
passes different ambits and cannot be ascribed to one field without referring
to other disciplines. It is impossible, for instance, to discuss the iconoclastic
value of a monochromatic image in a film without referencing the philosophical
and historical interpretations of the copy-prototype relationship. Moreover, the
multidisciplinary approach is also a consequence of the scarcity of scholarly
work on iconoclasm and cinema.
In a film context, only two main sources are available, and neither of them is
in English. Marion Poirson-Dechonne’s Entre spiritualité et laïcité, la tentation
iconoclaste du cinéma [Between Spirituality and Secularism, the Iconoclastic
Temptation of Cinema] (2016) represents the only monograph on the topic to
date. The book establishes conceptual links between certain aspects of Christian
Catholic theology and the film medium, identifying some secularised iconoclastic
tendencies in the cinema, and constitutes an important source for approaching
the issue of iconoclasm in film. The author discusses iconoclasm in the cinema
in a broad sense, taking into account a variety of films, many of which are not
iconoclastic stricto sensu. While also touching on two potentially iconoclastic
devices (the black screen and cacophony), Poirson-Dechonne focuses more on
the films’ content, investigating cinematic representations of Christian themes,
such as the father-son resemblance and the incarnation, in both religious and
secularised terms. Her book does however contain an overview of films which
directly put into crisis the relation between images and their referents, differen-
tiating among aesthetic, political and ethical iconoclasm. It is in particular her
addressing questions on our right to show and see everything on a screen that
is significant to my discussion of cinematic iconoclasm. Nevertheless, my treat-
ment of the topic considerably differs from Poirson-Dechonne’s since I develop
my argument from a more philosophically focused notion of iconoclasm, con-
centrating on the film form by means of the two opposing notions of eidōlon and
INTRODUCTION | 7
This does not mean that films made before World War II cannot be iconoclastic
(for instance, there is an argument to be made about the iconoclasm of the
historical avant-gardes of the 1910s and 1920s). However, I believe that the war,
the Shoah and the Liberation have brought some of the already present issues of
images to the limit and have accentuated the feeling of disorientation regarding
reality, which find a new expression in the cinema. Moreover, the Shoah has
marked an unprecedented crisis in Western representation, famously expressed
in Theodor W. Adorno’s (1967, 34) then retracted claim on the barbarism of
writing poetry after Auschwitz. Rather than placing the Shoah under such an
extreme and dangerous ban, it should be considered as one of those historical
‘objects’ that lack a direct image and yet demand to be made visible (see, Nancy
2005, 27–50; Saxton 2007; 2008; Wajcman 1998).
Following this thread of thought, it would seem that films on the Shoah
constitute the most appropriate works for discussing iconoclasm in the cinema,
and in a way they are. Nonetheless, I have chosen not to consider such films
for several reasons. Firstly, the Shoah is a broad and extremely complex theme
which would have taken most of the book if it were to be appropriately con-
sidered. My aim, however, is to delineate a wider notion of cinematic icon-
oclasm and its possible applications. Secondly, the issue of representing the
Shoah in films, the absence of images of the event per se and its status beyond
mimetic reproduction have already been thoroughly discussed by film scholars
such as Joshua Hirsch (2004), Oleksandr Kobrynskyy and Gerd Bayer (2015)
and Libby Saxton (2007; 2008). Lastly, the issue of iconoclasm in relation to
the cinematic representation of the Shoah has been considered, albeit not
systematically, in Ivelise Perniola’s L’immagine spezzata: Il cinema di Claude
Lanzmann [The Broken Image: Claude Lanzmann’s Cinema] (2007) and Gérard
Wajcman’s L’Objet du siècle [The Object of the Century] (1998). Therefore,
while my framework can be used to further discuss the problem of representa-
tion in relation to the Shoah, I have selected films which deal with a variety of
topics, from self-reflexivity to others’ suffering. Moreover, the initial selective
criteria regarded the film form. Rather than being concerned with depictions of
iconoclasm at the level of content, my exploration of the topic focuses on icon-
oclastic aesthetic forms in the cinema. Accordingly, the film images analysed
throughout are characterised by the breaking of a mimetic audio-visual form:
I look at monochromatic screens, freeze-framed shots, slow-motion sequences
and scenes where sound is disruptive or disjointed from the visual element.
Such stylistic devices result from an iconoclastic understanding of the copy-
prototype relationship, opening up sudden audio-visual hiatuses that require
spectators to fill them with meaning.
10 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
history through multiple images; Duras explores sexual desire via the severing
of any tie between aural and visual elements; Jarman operates a subversion of
the negative representation of the person with AIDS by employing a monochro-
matic screen as the constitutive image track of the film, thus denouncing the
status of homosexuality in 1980s UK; finally, Bergman and Kieślowski destroy
female faces through fades out, recalling a long iconographic tradition con-
cerning the face of Holy Mary and women’s suffering. The films thus share not
only an iconoclastic understanding of cinema and an anti-mimetic approach to
film style, but also a lively interest in social, cultural and political issues, which
actively contributes to making these works excellent examples of the ethical
relevance of iconoclastic gestures.
the reality of counter-cinema. Galt (2011) effectively claims that ‘in this model
of the image [i.e., the eidōlon], Plato lays the foundations for an iconoclasm that
grounds much modern image theory’ (181).
In their critical analysis of the iconoclasm of Marxist-influenced film theory,
Kibbey, Rushton and Galt reject an iconoclastic perspective for its supposed
reduction of cinema to an opposition between illusionistic images and self-
critical images, exhibiting analogies between the Platonic and Christian suspi-
cion of visual images and some of the arguments of leftist film theory. While I
agree with their reading of leftist film theory as iconoclastic, I endorse an icon-
oclastic perspective in the arts, grounding my argument on a representational
understanding of the cinema within which images do not stand on their own but
relate to a world they re-present and re-produce. In this scenario, the eidōlon
escapes a reduction to a simple false image. In his poetical delineating of the
ancient meaning of eidōlon, Régis Debray (1992, 28–30) emphasises its phan-
tasmatic status as a shadow and therefore as a double, connecting the birth of
the image to death (via mortuary rites as well as the image’s potential to mortify
reality). Indeed, the main issue with the image as eidōlon is its being a double, a
copy that replicates the visible features of its model, to the point of being always
on the verge of replacing it, and that retains a power of influencing thought
and making someone believe in a falsity. As in Plato and Christian iconoclasm,
where the eidōlon distracts from the contemplation of intelligible ideas and God,
respectively, relating itself only to the sensible realm, so in the cinema the eidōlon
is an image which overshadows the original and aims at substituting it. In the
work of Isou, Debord, Bene and Godard, the eidōlon is the kind of film image that
hides its character of artificial copy through the naturalism of mise-en-scène and
continuity editing, and this carries ethico-political consequences. The limit of
this critique, however, is its trouble in overcoming the logic of self-reflexivity and
bringing the discourse beyond the criticism of the image as illusory copy. As both
Kibbey and Rushton observe, caught in the urge of dismantling the impression
of reality of Hollywood-like cinema, some of the exponents of iconoclasm as
critique risk remaining trapped in their own criticism.
Vacche (2003) and Barbara Grespi (2013) explicitly address the issue of the
face in the close-up as a field of debate between iconoclastic and iconophilic
interpretations in the cinema. They dwell particularly on the iconophilic stance,
identifying a sacred conception of the cinematic medium as a tool for revealing a
human essence that finds its most suitable expression in the magnification of the
close-up – a position exemplified by early film theorists Louis Delluc’s ([1920]
1985, 34–36, 50–61) and Jean Epstein’s ([1921] 1977; [1926] 2012) notion of
photogénie, and Béla Balázs’s ([1945] 1970, 52–88; [1924] 2010, 27–51) concept
of physiognomy. Accordingly, Dalle Vacche’s and Grespi’s notion of iconoclasm
suggests a disbelief in the revelatory capacity of the cinematic medium and in
the close-up’s viability as a mediator between a visible, exterior surface and
a purported invisible, inner depth. It is ‘the face in close-up and the close-up
as the face of objects’ (Dalle Vacche 2003, 15) that elicits a division between
iconophilic and iconoclastic stances in the cinema. The opposition originates
from the interpretation of the face, whether as a door to the soul or as a surface
of inhumanity.
Grespi is the only scholar theorising a proper opposition between iconoclasts
and iconophiles in cinema with specific reference to the face in the close-up,
in her article ‘L’immagine sfregiata: Il cinema e i volti del sacro’ [The Scarred
Image: Cinema and Sacred Faces] (2013). On the one hand, she discusses the
trust in film images in the work of Epstein and Balázs, and their understanding
of the facial close-up as a site for the surfacing of the soul and a manifestation of
inner life; on the other hand, she considers Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari’s
concept of cinematic close-up as a dehumanising device, consequently under-
standing the defacement of such a close-up as an iconoclastic gesture – a con-
troversial and imprecise perspective that does not take into account Deleuze’s
rejection of Platonism and duality.
In Grespi’s view, the notions of photogénie and physiognomy bespeak an
iconophilic attitude, since they hinge on the strong bond between the cinematic
close-up and its phenomenal referent. Magnified by the close-up, the face inten-
sifies its expressive power by filling up the whole screen and by connecting inte-
riority and exteriority. In Epstein and Balázs, mystics ‘of the 1920s close-up, the
filmic face simply constitutes the place of interception of the sacred concealed in
man’4 (Grespi 2013, 42). The face in the close-up is therefore eikōn insofar as it is
capable of establishing a truthful link with the phenomenal referent in a mimetic
manner. This stance is corroborated by other accounts of the privileged role
accorded to the face in cinema. For instance, Mary Ann Doane (2003) addresses
photogénie as a form of cinephilia, and Jacques Aumont defines Epstein’s and
Balázs’s perspectives as idealistic since they presuppose the very possibility of a
INTRODUCTION | 15
nexus between reality and its filmic representation. Aumont (2003) remarks that
photogénie and physiognomy ‘outline an aesthetic of the face in film. Idealistic
aesthetic that is, it is based on the hope of a revelation that it believes is possible
because it believes fundamentally in the face as organic unit, infrangible, total.
The form of this revelation is [. . .] the close-up’ (139).
Grespi sets Epstein’s and Balázs’s iconophilic position against Deleuze and
Guattari’s account of the facial close-up, erroneously defining the French philos-
ophers as iconoclasts. While sharing some of Epstein’s and Balázs’s arguments,
Deleuze and Guattari conceive of the face as a surface, hence pure exteriority.
That is, the connection between the face and interiority is severed, and the
face becomes the result of a process of abstraction called ‘faciality’ [visagéité]
(Deleuze and Guattari 1987, 168). This process of ‘making a face’ alludes to the
frontal part of the head where the eyes and mouth are, but more importantly
comes to signify a reference to any surface that functions as the cultural and
political construct of face. The process of facialisation designates the imposi-
tion of a face onto a subject and is codified by the binary system white wall/
black holes which produces the face as a politics. The facialised face is a politics
because it consists in the acquisition of a standardised face, that of the ‘white
man’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987, 176). Deleuze and Guattari claim that ‘the
face is [. . .] White Man himself, with his broad white cheeks and the black
holes of his eyes. The face is Christ. The face is the typical European’ (176). As a
socio-political construct, the face is closely linked to Christianity; however, the
Christological reference acquires a political connotation rather than a religious
one, in the sense of Christianity as the socio-political machine of meaning in
Western Europe. Accordingly, the face in itself contains the seeds for racism
since it suppresses the other’s differences and aims at conforming all faces to its
own. As Deleuze and Guattari explain, the face of the other than the white man
‘must be Christianized, in other words, facialized’ (178). Instead of establishing
a relation with the other, the face produces a distance with the specific purpose
of ascribing every face to the dominant face, the standardised ‘white man’; the
facial close-up accordingly becomes the vehicle for the revelation of inhumanity:
The face, what a horror. It is naturally a lunar landscape, with its pores, planes,
matts, bright colors, whiteness, and holes: there is no need for a close-up to
make it inhuman; it is naturally a close-up, and naturally inhuman. (Deleuze
and Guattari 1987, 190)
In the face’s status as entity disconnected from reality in its hic et nunc lies
the core of Deleuze and Guattari’s interpretation of the cinematic close-up.
16 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
Complete in itself, the face does not contain the traces of its relationship with
the world. Thus, the face in the close-up, far from being the site of human revela-
tion, like in Balázs and Epstein, turns into a means for revealing ‘the inhuman in
human beings’ (Deleuze and Guattari 1987, 171). The facial close-up is stripped
of any connecting capacity and presents, instead, the very void at the core of
humanity, the fact that there is nothing to be shown and revealed.
As a result, Deleuze and Guattari advocate for the dismantling of the
face, making it a pockmarked face that ceases to respond to the facialisation
machine – the white wall/black holes system. Indeed, if the facial close-up
responds to a logic of eliminating differences in the uniqueness of the Christ-
face, the defacement of this close-up would allow for a deviation from the stand-
ard and, consequently, for the expression of a face other than that of the ‘white
man’. However, defacing the close-up does not correspond to a return to the
human head, but constitutes a politics itself. In both cases – the Christ-face and
the dismantled face – Deleuze and Guattari’s facial close-up ceases to configure
itself as the Epsteinian and Balázsian mediator between the individual and the
social life in the rising metropolis of the early twentieth century. In the view of
Deleuze and Guattari, who write in the context of a globalised, post-war world,
the face comes to signify the very impossibility of the encounter with the other.
It is possible to trace here a specific change in the vision of the world, taking
World War II as the separating event. Both the iconophilic interpretation and
that of Deleuze and Guattari assign to the facial close-up a revelatory power.
However, in the iconophilic perspective there is always something interior (a
soul) to reveal, an invisible life of humans and things that the film medium is
able to record and reproduce on the screen. Quite differently, in Deleuze and
Guattari’s interpretation, the cinema lays bare the absence of revelation in real-
ity, the fact that there is nothing to be unconcealed.
Grespi (2013, 45–49) proposes an iconoclastic interpretation of the inhu-
man and defacement in Deleuze and Guattari, understanding the facial close-up
as a de-humanising device and its defacement as an iconoclastic gesture. For
Grespi, erasing the facialised face becomes the iconoclastic re-appropriation of
the face, which would allow for the overcoming of the faciality process: from
a facial twitch to a deformed or scarred face, the attack towards the unity of
the facialised face would enable a breaking with the politics of the faciality
process. That is, by interpreting Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of inhumanity
as something that ought to be escaped, she identifies in the defacement of the
close-up an iconoclastic intent to break with a false image of a true model.
However, Deleuze and Guattari never mention the possibility of a humanity in
humans. Rather, it is inhumanity itself which is constituent of human beings.
INTRODUCTION | 17
and Whispers and Three Colours: Blue, where iconoclastic gestures occur on
the magnified faces of the female characters. The figurative destruction of the
women’s faces in these films represents a clear passing from a mere rejection
of the cinematic eidōlon (namely, a mimetic image incapable of represent-
ing interiority) to the creation of iconoclastic eikones (that is, anti-mimetic
images which maintain a relationship with the invisible model). The human
face, which is the most emotionally charged part of the body, becomes the locus
for an interrogation of visibility and its limits, also developing a criticism of the
mimetic representability of the female face and women’s suffering – from the
iconography of the Holy Mary, the quietly suffering mother, to the iconoclastic
rendering of Liv Ullmann’s, Ingrid Thulin’s and Juliette Binoche’s raw pain.
Paradoxically, the destruction of the women’s figurative faces becomes a way
to account for a much more realistic, disorderly pain that rejects a spectacular-
isation of suffering.
Iconoclasm of Anti-Mimesis
Iconoclasm has been bounded to anti-mimesis since its inception – the biblical
ban on any graven image and the Platonic condemnation of images of art, for
instance, were fuelled by a rejection of the eidōlon’s excessive visual similar-
ity with the referent. Artistic anti-mimesis does not always correspond to an
iconoclastic intent, whereas the opposite is true; namely, that iconoclastic ges-
tures within the arts are directed against mimesis. From Russian abstract art’s
attempts at representing the Absolute via monochromatic paintings to Lucio
Fontana’s cut canvases aimed at reaching the unrepresentable reality beyond
the painting’s surface, from avant-garde cinema’s and video art’s disrupting of
habitual engagements with images and sounds to contemporary audio-visual
media’s uses of blank screens and off-screen sounds, anti-mimetic aesthetics
hinge on the distance between copy and prototype, thereby implying that the
image cannot truthfully reproduce the model. While intelligible models may
appear to place mimetic representation more decidedly in a moral maze (how
to figuratively render the invisibility at their core?), also sensible phenomena
challenge a seemingly uncomplicated reproduction of reality, especially follow-
ing an understanding of the visual field as ethically laden. Libby Saxton (2010c)
convincingly ties the issue of mimesis to that of ethics, observing that it is from
cinema’s ‘privileged bond with reality’ (26) – namely, from its possibility to
mimetically reproduce people, animals, objects (their appearance, sounds and
movement) – that ethical questions arise. Similarly, Asbjørn Grønstad (2016)
stresses the ethical weight deriving from the close nexus between cinematic
INTRODUCTION | 19
The book is comprised of a prologue and two parts, which are further divided
into four chapters each. The prologue provides a brief philosophical and his-
torical background to the discussion on cinema and iconoclasm, delineating
the main turning points in the iconoclastic debate, from Plato’s and Plotinus’s
ambiguous understanding of artistic mimesis to early Christian theology of the
image and the Byzantine controversy. Engaging with the eikōn-eidōlon dichot-
omy, the prologue also outlines how cinema reworks such an opposition, argu-
ing for the aesthetic and ethical potential of artistic destruction.
Part I dwells on cinematic iconoclasm as critique of the eidōlon via the work
of directors Isidore Isou, Guy Debord, Carmelo Bene and Jean-Luc Godard.
The films analysed in this part metaphorically and literally proceed to destroy
mimetic audio-visual images to counter their illusory power, thereby reiterating
the criticism of the image found in philosophical iconoclasm. The first chapter
looks at Isou’s explicitly iconoclastic project and his avant-garde film Traité de
bave et d’éternité, which heralds the destruction of cinema and presents sev-
eral iconoclastic devices. The second chapter considers the iconoclastic use of
monochromatic screens, sound-image disjunctions and freeze-frames in some
of Guy Debord’s films. Specifically, I take into account Hurlements en faveur de
Sade, The Society of the Spectacle and In girum imus nocte et consumimur igni,
which exacerbate Isou’s iconoclastic perspective. The third chapter examines
Carmelo Bene’s project to destroy cinema as a medium able to communicate
meaning by way of linguistic and sonic disruptions. Through an analysis of his
film Our Lady of the Turks, I explore how the negation of intelligible images via
destructive editing chimes with the elimination of intelligible speech in favour
of the voice as logos-less sound. To conclude this part, the fourth chapter goes
over some of Jean-Luc Godard’s narrative films, specifically Une Femme mariée
(A Married Woman, 1964), Alphaville, une étrange aventure de Lemmy Caution
(Alphaville: A Strange Adventure of Lemmy Caution, 1965) and Slow Motion
(Sauve qui peut (la Vie), 1980), as well as the destructive works made with the
Dziga Vertov Group, before engaging with Histoire(s) du cinéma, which consti-
tutes the work ideally bridging Part I and Part II. In Godard’s magnum opus, in
fact, are found both the critique of the film image as eidōlon and the production
of iconoclastic eikones, those images capable of establishing a relationship with
the model by going beyond mimesis.
Part II focuses on iconoclastic eikones in the cinema, exploring their e thical
quality, and conceptualises cinematic iconoclasm as an ethics of (in)visibility.
Addressing questions concerning our right to show and see something on a
22 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
In Plato’s philosophy, both the image as eidōlon and the image as eikōn coexist,
paving the way for the future opposition between the Christian idol and icon.
However, Plato alone is insufficient to account for the influence of Hellenic
thought on the Christian theology of the image. Another essential source
includes Plotinus’s philosophy, which constitutes a significant link between the
Platonic interpretation of the eikōn and the Christian understanding of the icon.
Plotinus’s more positive notion of image derives from his hierarchical cos-
mology, within which the image becomes an intermediary between the con-
creteness of sensible matter and the abstraction of the intelligible sphere. For
Plotinus, both the sensible and the intelligible worlds derive by emanation
26 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
from the first principle of all, the One, which in a downward movement creates
everything that exists (Ennead V.1[6]). There is therefore continuity between
the intelligible realm and the sensible sphere which breaks with the immeasur-
able Platonic distance between the two worlds. This conception, where every-
thing exists in a single world, shapes the overall Plotinian understanding of
the image. While what is intelligible continues to form the highest level of
being and sensible matter is the last thing created by the One, images none-
theless belong to, and thus are in a connection with, the same world of what is
super-sensible, only at a lower ontological degree (Ennead V.8[1]). On the one
hand, sensible matter – the lowest level of the hierarchy – corresponds to the
eidōlon insofar as it is a formless reflection of the One; on the other hand, the
image, when it is elevated to the role of intermediary between the sensible and
the intelligible spheres, becomes eikōn; namely, the first means for carrying
out the inner journey towards the One. Such partial rehabilitation of the image
hinges on the continuum between the sensible and the intelligible worlds: no
longer condemned to the sensible sphere only, the image as eikōn positions
itself between the two.
However, Plotinus, too, maintains an ambiguous attitude towards mimetic
art, now praising it as a means for passing from the sensible to the intelligi-
ble world, now diminishing it to a ‘plaything’ that ‘produce[s] a simulacrum
[eidōlon] of nature’ (Halliwell 2002, 318). Art and the image as eikōn acquire
value as the starting point for the soul’s journey towards the One, mediating
between sensible and intelligible realms; and yet, the representation of the point
of arrival – the One – is interdicted. Christian Catholic thought about images
will, however, ignore Plotinus’s iconoclastic aspect, instead conceiving of the
icon as a way to diminish the distance between humans and God.
The Christian theology of the image intertwines Platonic, Plotinian and
Neoplatonic perspectives with the Biblical prohibition of any graven image
and the Christian notion of the incarnation of God (Besançon 2000, 81–146;
Halliwell 2002, 314, 334; Ladner 1953; Mondzain 2005, 73; Wunenburger 1999,
154). While early Christian theologians (second to fifth century) did not neces-
sarily provide an aesthetics regarding sacred representations, they nonetheless
offered two opposite ways of interpreting the sensible world which were to
play a fundamental role in the development of iconophilic and iconoclastic
arguments. There were conflicting views on the legitimacy of sacred images
deriving from different interpretations of, especially, the incarnation, whether as
a positive event or, at the opposite end, as an act ontologically inferior to God.1
In favour of icons were those theologians who interpreted the incarnation
in a positive manner, for God himself had taken a visible, perishable form, and
PROLOGUE | 27
More importantly, the icon is ‘not the object of a passive fascination’ (Mondzain
2005, 90) but aims at taking the viewer’s look beyond the visibility of the rep-
resentation; that is, at transcending the materiality of the icon to reach the
intellectual contemplation of God. In iconophilic thought, what differentiates
the icon from the idol resides in the relationship they have with the sensible and
the intelligible spheres: while the icon exists as an intermediary between the two
realms, the idol purely addresses the world of corporeal things.
Conversely, in iconoclastic thought, the icon is far from diminishing the
distance separating humans and God and assumes, instead, the connotations
of the idol, a false god that consequently has to be destroyed. The iconoclasts
rebutted the iconophilic theses, decrying them as heretic because (1) the icon
cannot be consubstantial to the model since what is sensible cannot share the
same nature as what is intelligible;2 (2) the icon circumscribes both human
and divine essence of Christ because the two are inseparable – God is the
invisible, unlimited and un-circumscribable par excellence. In the iconoclasts’
view, the gap between the divine model and its material image is therefore
unbridgeable.
The same image was thus at once icon and idol, depending on the interpre-
tation of the image-model relationship. Icon and idol, coming from eikōn and
eidōlon, respectively, reiterate the same opposition found in Plato and Plotinus.
Accordingly, the idol inherits the negative connotations of the Greek eidōlon as
something that reproduces exclusively a sensible appearance, thereby address-
ing only sight, and as an image that implies the possibility of producing a visually
identical double of the prototype. The image of God as idol/eidōlon is idolatrous
because it offers itself as the direct object of adoration, without being a means
for passing from the visible contemplation of the image to the intellectual con-
templation of God.
While both iconophilic and iconoclastic stances rejected the idol, their con-
ception of the icon differed. The iconophiles attributed to the icon the meaning
of the eikōn as that which mediates between the here below and the there above,
whereas for the iconoclasts the icon as conceived by the iconophiles was nothing
other than an idol. The same image, therefore, was caught between two diamet-
rically opposed interpretations.
The iconoclastic crisis of the eighth century eventually led to the second
Council of Nicaea in 787 and the victory of the iconophilic thesis. The icon
of Christ was legitimated and recognised as an image having a privileged link
with the divine model. The sacred icon thus became the intermediary between
humans and God, albeit not reproducing divine nature. To look on the visible
sacredness ideally leads to the imageless contemplation of God. This l egitimation
PROLOGUE | 29
was to play a key role in the future of Western thought about images: once the
praise of images was detached from the religious context, any type of image
began to enjoy an ever-increasing power in the social imaginary that still per-
sists today. Therefore, it is possible to trace a pathway that goes from ancient
Greek philosophy to the Byzantine controversy up to contemporary Western
imaginary and cinema. As Maria T. Bettetini (2006) insightfully observes,
there is no doubt that the second Council of Nicaea played a role in Western
medieval, modern and postmodern civilization. The legitimation of sacred
images drawn up in 787 by the council Fathers is universally recognised as the
theoretical and political origin of our civilization of images: from Byzantium
to Hollywood. (103)
My argument develops from the assumption that the binary between the eikōn
and the eidōlon can be found in the cinema as well, generating conflicting
stances. More specifically, different interpretations derive from a dichotomy
between reality and illusion, which opposes cinema’s claim to a mimetic restitu-
tion of reality and cinema’s deceptive nature. Such antagonism goes back to the
beginning of film theory and involves clashing views about the film image (Allen
1993; Andrew 1976; 1984, 37–56; Perniola 2013; Pezzella 2011; Rushton 2011;
Thomson-Jones 2008). There are various stances in the spectrum of the reality-
illusion dichotomy in the cinema, which range from a quasi-religious faith in the
revelatory capacity of the film medium, such as in the writings of Louis Delluc
([1920] 1985), Jean Epstein ([1921] 1977; [1926] 2012), Béla Balázs ([1945] 1970;
[1924] 2010) and Siegfried Kracauer (1960), to a fierce disdain for the cinematic
image as a deceitful representation, as in the work of the exponents of political
modernism (Comolli and Narboni 1971; Fargier 1971; Heath 1974; MacCabe
1974; Rodowick 1994; Wollen 1976). This picture is further complicated by the
30 | ICONOCLASM IN EUROPEAN CINEMA
Concluding Remarks
to the sound track. The privileging of the sonorous grounds much of Lettrist
artistic practices, in which the political critique of words and images is part
of a more widespread scepticism about language and representation and their
ability to express reality. Thus, the criticism of artistic mimesis encompasses
the aural, visual and linguistic dimensions, in an overall rejection of the sounds
and images that had accompanied fascist propaganda before and during World
War II. Lettrist cinema becomes one of the diverse ways through which this
avant-garde expresses its attempts at overcoming the limitations imposed by
figurative representation and logocentric speech.
The chapter first locates Lettrism within the broader context of
twentieth-century Europe, with particular attention to the crisis of language and
representation in philosophy, literature and the arts. It then delineates Isou’s
cinematic project, known as ‘discrepant cinema’ (cinéma discrépant), which
aims at dismantling cinema as spectacle by way of breaking with mimesis and
granting a privileged role to sound. Such an undermining of the visual image
is also discussed through a detailed analysis of Isou’s only film, Traité de bave
et d’éternité (Treatise on Venom and Eternity, 1951).1 The film’s iconoclastic
quality emerges from an account of the disruptive devices of discrepant edit-
ing (montage discrépant), which destroys synchronous sound, and the chiseled
image (image ciselante),2 which results from the literal scraping of and aggres-
sions against the filmstrip.
The reader will see, by the printer’s sign at the bottom, that it is a
season advertisement, and, therefore, would meet the eye of the
child week after week. The paper from which we have cut this
contains among its extracts passages from Dickens’ Household
Words, from Professor Felton’s article in the Christian Examiner on
the relation of the sexes, and a most beautiful and chivalrous appeal
from the eloquent senator Soulé on the legal rights of women. Let
us now ask, since this paper is devoted to education, what sort of an
educational influence such advertisements have. And, of course,
such an establishment is not kept up without patronage. Where
there are negro-hunters advertising in a paper, there are also negro-
hunts, and there are dogs being trained to hunt; and all this process
goes on before the eyes of children; and what sort of education is it?
The writer has received an account of the way in which dogs are
trained for this business. The information has been communicated to
the gentleman who writes it by a negro man, who, having been
always accustomed to see it done, described it with as little sense of
there being anything out of the way in it as if the dogs had been
trained to catch raccoons. It came to the writer in a recent letter
from the South.
The way to train ‘em (says the man) is to take these yer pups,—any kind o’ pups
will do,—fox-hounds, bull-dogs, most any;—but take the pups, and keep ‘em shut
up and don’t let ‘em never see a nigger till they get big enough to be larned.
When the pups gits old enough to be set on to things, then make ‘em run after a
nigger; and when they cotches him, give ‘em meat. Tell the nigger to run as hard
as he can, and git up in a tree, so as to larn the dogs to tree ‘em; then take the
shoe of a nigger, and larn ‘em to find the nigger it belongs to; then a rag of his
clothes; and so on. Allers be carful to tree the nigger, and teach the dog to wait
and bark under the tree till you come up and give him his meat.
See also the following advertisement from the Ouachita Register, a
newspaper dated “Monroe, La., Tuesday evening, June 1, 1852.”
NEGRO DOGS.
The undersigned would respectfully inform the citizens of Ouachita and adjacent
parishes, that he has located about 2½ miles east of John White’s, on the road
leading from Monroe to Bastrop, and that he has a fine pack of Dogs for catching
negroes. Persons wishing negroes caught will do well to give him a call. He can
always be found at his stand when not engaged in hunting, and even then
information of his whereabouts can always be had of some one on the premises.
Terms.—Five dollars per day and found, when there is no track pointed out. When
the track is shown, twenty-five dollars will be charged for catching the negro.
M. C. Goff.
Now, do not all the scenes likely to be enacted under this head form
a fine education for the children of a Christian nation? and can we
wonder if children so formed see no cruelty in slavery? Can children
realize that creatures who are thus hunted are the children of one
heavenly Father with themselves?
But suppose the boy grows up to be a man, and attends the courts
of justice, and hears intelligent, learned men declaring from the
bench that “the mere beating of a slave, unaccompanied by any
circumstances of cruelty, or an attempt to kill, is no breach of the
peace of the state.” Suppose he hears it decided in the same place
that no insult or outrage upon any slave is considered worthy of
legal redress, unless it impairs his property value. Suppose he hears,
as he would in Virginia, that it is the policy of the law to protect the
master even in inflicting cruel, malicious and excessive punishment
upon the slave. Suppose a slave is murdered, and he hears the
lawyers arguing that it cannot be considered a murder, because the
slave, in law, is not considered a human being; and then suppose
the case is appealed to a superior court, and he hears the judge
expending his forces on a long and eloquent dissertation to prove
that the slave is a human being; at least, that he is as much so as a
lunatic, an idiot, or an unborn child, and that, therefore, he can be
murdered. (See Judge Clark’s speech, on p. 75.) Suppose he sees
that all the administration of law with regard to the slave proceeds
on the idea that he is absolutely nothing more than a bale of
merchandise. Suppose he hears such language as this, which occurs
in the reasonings of the Brazealle case, and which is a fair sample of
the manner in which such subjects are ordinarily discussed. “The
slave has no more political capacity, no more right to purchase, hold
or transfer property, than the mule in his plough; he is in himself but
a mere chattel,—the subject of absolute ownership.” Suppose he
sees on the statute-book such sentences as these, from the civil
code of Louisiana:
Art. 2500. The latent defects of slaves and animals are divided into two classes,—
vices of body and vices of character.
Art. 2501. The vices of body are distinguished into absolute and relative.
Art. 2502. The absolute vices of slaves are leprosy, madness and epilepsy.
Art. 2503. The absolute vices of horses and mules are short wind, glanders, and
founder.
The influence of this language is made all the stronger on the young
mind from the fact that it is not the language of contempt, or of
passion, but of calm, matter-of-fact, legal statement.
What effect must be produced on the mind of the young man when
he comes to see that, however atrocious and however well-proved
be the murder of a slave, the murderer uniformly escapes; and that,
though the cases where the slave has fallen a victim to passions of
the white are so multiplied, yet the fact of an execution for such a
crime is yet almost unknown in the country? Does not all this tend to
produce exactly that estimate of the value of negro life and
happiness which Frederic Douglass says was expressed by a
common proverb among the white boys where he was brought up:
“It’s worth sixpence to kill a nigger, and sixpence more to bury him”?
We see the public sentiment which has been formed by this kind of
education exhibited by the following paragraph from the Cambridge
Democrat, Md., Oct. 27, 1852. That paper quotes the following from
the Woodville Republican, of Mississippi. It seems a Mr. Joshua Johns
had killed a slave, and had been sentenced therefor to the
penitentiary for two years. The Republican thus laments his hard lot:
This cause resulted in the conviction of Johns, and his sentence to the penitentiary
for two years. Although every member of the jury, together with the bar, and the
public generally, signed a petition to the governor for young Johns’ pardon, yet
there was no fault to find with the verdict of the jury. The extreme youth of Johns,
and the circumstances in which the killing occurred, enlisted universal sympathy in
his favor. There is no doubt that the negro had provoked him to the deed by the
use of insolent language; but how often must it be told that words are no
justification for blows? There are many persons—and we regret to say it—who
think they have the same right to shoot a negro, if he insults them, or even runs
from them, that they have to shoot down a dog; but there are laws for the
protection of the slave as well as the master, and the sooner the error above
alluded to is removed, the better will it be for both parties.
The unfortunate youth who has now entailed upon himself the penalty of the law,
we doubt not, had no idea that there existed such penalty; and even if he was
aware of the fact, the repeated insults and taunts of the negro go far to mitigate
the crime. Johns was defended by I. D. Gildart, Esq., who probably did all that
could have been effected in his defence.
The Democrat adds:
We learn from Mr. Curry, deputy sheriff, of Wilkinson County, that Johns has been
pardoned by the governor. We are gratified to hear it.
This error above alluded to, of thinking it is as innocent to shoot
down a negro as a dog, is one, we fairly admit, for which young
Johns ought not to be very severely blamed. He has been educated
in a system of things of which this opinion is the inevitable result;
and he, individually, is far less guilty for it, than are those men who
support the system of laws, and keep up the educational influences,
which lead young Southern men directly to this conclusion. Johns
may be, for aught we know, as generous-hearted and as just
naturally as any young man living; but the horrible system under
which he has been educated has rendered him incapable of
distinguishing what either generosity or justice is, as applied to the
negro.
The public sentiment of the slave states is the sentiment of men who
have been thus educated, and in all that concerns the negro it is
utterly blunted and paralyzed. What would seem to them injustice
and horrible wrong in the case of white persons, is the coolest
matter of course in relation to slaves.
As this educational influence descends from generation to
generation, the moral sense becomes more and more blunted, and
the power of discriminating right from wrong, in what relates to the
subject race, more and more enfeebled.
Thus, if we read the writings of distinguished men who were slave-
holders about the time of our American Revolution, what clear views
do we find expressed of the injustice of slavery, what strong
language of reprobation do we find applied to it! Nothing more
forcible could possibly be said in relation to its evils than by quoting
the language of such men as Washington, Jefferson, and Patrick
Henry. In those days there were no men of that high class of mind
who thought of such a thing as defending slavery on principle: now
there are an abundance of the most distinguished men, North and
South, statesmen, civilians, men of letters, even clergymen, who in
various degrees palliate it, apologize for or openly defend it. And
what is the cause of this, except that educational influences have
corrupted public sentiment, and deprived them of the power of just
judgment? The public opinion even of free America, with regard to
slavery, is behind that of all other civilized nations.
When the holders of slaves assert that they are, as a general thing,
humanely treated, what do they mean? Not that they would consider
such treatment humane if given to themselves and their children,—
no, indeed!—but it is humane for slaves.
They do, in effect, place the negro below the range of humanity, and
on a level with brutes, and then graduate all their ideas of humanity
accordingly.
They would not needlessly kick or abuse a dog or a negro. They may
pet a dog, and they often do a negro. Men have been found who
fancied having their horses elegantly lodged in marble stables, and
to eat out of sculptured mangers, but they thought them horses still;
and, with all the indulgences with which good-natured masters
sometimes surround the slave, he is to them but a negro still, and
not a man.
In what has been said in this chapter, and in what appears
incidentally in all the facts cited throughout this volume, there is
abundant proof that, notwithstanding there be frequent and most
noble instances of generosity towards the negro, and although the
sentiment of honorable men and the voice of Christian charity does
everywhere protest against what it feels to be inhumanity, yet the
popular sentiment engendered by the system must necessarily fall
deplorably short of giving anything like sufficient protection to the
rights of the slave. It will appear in the succeeding chapters, as it
must already have appeared to reflecting minds, that the whole
course of educational influence upon the mind of the slave-master is
such as to deaden his mind to those appeals which come from the
negro as a fellow-man and a brother.
CHAPTER III.
SEPARATION OF FAMILIES.
“What must the difference be,” said Dr. Worthington, with startling energy,
“between Isabel and her servants! To her it is loss of position, fortune, the fair
hopes of life, perhaps even health; for she must inevitably break down under the
unaccustomed labor and privations she will have to undergo. But to them it is
merely a change of masters”!
“Yes, for the neighbors won’t allow any of the families to be separated.”
“Of course not. We read of such things in novels sometimes. But I have yet to see
it in real life, except in rare cases, or where the slave has been guilty of some
misdemeanor, or crime, for which, in the North, he would have been imprisoned,
perhaps for life.”—Cabin and Parlor, by J. Thornton Randolph, p. 39.
“But they’re going to sell us all to Georgia, I say. How are we to escape that?”
“Spec dare some mistake in dat,” replied Uncle Peter, stoutly. “I nebber knew of
sich a ting in dese parts, ‘cept where some niggar’d been berry bad.”—Ibid.
By such graphic touches as the above does Mr. Thornton Randolph
represent to us the patriarchal stability and security of the slave
population in the Old Dominion. Such a thing as a slave being sold
out of the state has never been heard of by Dr. Worthington, except
in rare cases for some crime; and old Uncle Peter never heard of
such a thing in his life.
Are these representations true?
The worst abuse of the system of slavery is its outrage upon the
family; and, as the writer views the subject, it is one which is more
notorious and undeniable than any other.
Yet it is upon this point that the most stringent and earnest denial
has been made to the representations of “Uncle Tom’s Cabin,” either
indirectly, as by the romance-writer above, or more directly in the
assertions of newspapers, both at the North and at the South. When
made at the North, they indicate, to say the least, very great
ignorance of the subject; when made at the South, they certainly do
very great injustice to the general character of the Southerner for
truth and honesty. All sections of country have faults peculiar to
themselves. The fault of the South, as a general thing, has not been
cowardly evasion and deception. It was with utter surprise that the
author read the following sentences in an article in Fraser’s
Magazine, professing to come from a South Carolinian.
Mrs. Stowe’s favorite illustration of the master’s power to the injury of the slave is
the separation of families. We are told of infants of ten months old being sold from
the arms of their mothers, and of men whose habit it is to raise children to sell
away from their mother as soon as they are old enough to be separated. Were our
views of this feature of slavery derived from Mrs. Stowe’s book, we should regard
the families of slaves as utterly unsettled and vagrant.
And again:
We feel confident that, if statistics could be had to throw light upon this subject,
we should find that there is less separation of families among the negroes than
occurs with almost any other class of persons.
As the author of the article, however, is evidently a man of honor,
and expresses many most noble and praiseworthy sentiments, it
cannot be supposed that these statements were put forth with any
view to misrepresent or to deceive. They are only to be regarded as
evidences of the facility with which a sanguine mind often overlooks
the most glaring facts that make against a favorite idea or theory, or
which are unfavorable in their bearings on one’s own country or
family. Thus the citizens of some place notoriously unhealthy will
come to believe, and assert, with the utmost sincerity, that there is
actually less sickness in their town than any other of its size in the
known world. Thus parents often think their children perfectly
immaculate in just those particulars in which others see them to be
most faulty. This solution of the phenomena is a natural and amiable
one, and enables us to retain our respect for our Southern brethren.
There is another circumstance, also, to be taken into account, in
reading such assertions as these. It is evident, from the pamphlet in
question, that the writer is one of the few who regard the
possession of absolute irresponsible power as the highest of motives
to moderation and temperance in its use. Such men are commonly
associated in friendship and family connection with others of similar
views, and are very apt to fall into the error of judging others by
themselves, and thinking that a thing may do for all the world
because it operates well in their immediate circle. Also it cannot but
be a fact that the various circumstances which from infancy conspire
to degrade and depress the negro in the eyes of a Southern-born
man,—the constant habit of speaking of them, and hearing them
spoken of, and seeing them advertised, as mere articles of property,
often in connection with horses, mules, fodder, swine, &c., as they
are almost daily in every Southern paper,—must tend, even in the
best-constituted minds, to produce a certain obtuseness with regard
to the interests, sufferings and affections, of such as do not
particularly belong to himself, which will peculiarly unfit him for
estimating their condition. The author has often been singularly
struck with this fact, in the letters of Southern friends; in which,
upon one page, they will make some assertion regarding the
condition of Southern negroes, and then go on, and in other
connections state facts which apparently contradict them all. We can
all be aware how this familiarity would operate with ourselves. Were
we called upon to state how often our neighbors’ cows were
separated from their calves, or how often their household furniture
and other effects are scattered and dispersed by executor’s sales, we
should be inclined to say that it was not a misfortune of very
common occurrence.
But let us open two South Carolina papers, published in the very
state where this gentleman is residing, and read the advertisements
FOR ONE WEEK. The author has slightly abridged them.
Fairfield District.
R. W. Murray and wife and }
others }
v. } In Equity.
William Wright and wife }
and others. }
In pursuance of an Order of the Court of Equity made in the above case at July
Term, 1852, I will sell at public outcry, to the highest bidder, before the Court
House in Winnsboro, on the first Monday in January next,
Commisioner's Office, }
Winnsboro, Nov. 30, }
1852.
Dec. 2 42 x4.
ADMINISTRATOR’S SALE.
Will be sold at public outcry, to the highest bidder, on Tuesday, the 21st day of
December next, at the late residence of Mrs. M. P. Rabb, deceased, all of the
personal estate of said deceased, consisting in part of about
2,000 Bushels of Corn.
25,000 pounds of Fodder.
Wheat—Cotton Seed.
Horses, Mules, Cattle, Hogs, Sheep.
There will, in all probability, be sold at the same time and place several likely
Young Negroes.
The Terms of Sale will be—all sums under Twenty-five Dollars, Cash. All sums of
Twenty-five Dollars and over, twelve months’ credit, with interest from day of Sale,
secured by note and two approved sureties.
William S. Rabb,
Administrator.
Nov. 11. 39 x2
Fairfield District.
James E. Caldwell, }
Admr., with the Will }
annexed, of Jacob Gibson, }
deceased, } In Equity.
v. }
Jason D. Gibson }
and others. }
In pursuance of the order of sale made in the above case, I will sell at public
outcry, to the highest bidder, before the Court House in Winnsboro, on the first
Monday in January next, and the day following, the following real and personal
estate of Jacob Gibson, deceased, late of Fairfield District, to wit:
The Plantation on which the testator lived at the time of his death, containing 661
Acres, more or less, lying on the waters of Wateree Creek, and bounded by lands
of Samuel Johnston, Theodore S. DuBose, Edward P. Mobley, and B. R. Cockrell.
This plantation will be sold in two separate tracts, plats of which will be exhibited
on the day of sale:
Commissioner’s Office, }
Winnsboro, 29th Nov. }
1852.
On the first Monday in January next I will sell, before the Court House in
Columbia, 50 of as Likely Negroes as have ever been exposed to public sale,
belonging to the estate of A. P. Vinson, deceased. The Negroes have been well
cared for, and well managed in every respect. Persons wishing to purchase will
not, it is confidently believed, have a better opportunity to supply themselves.
J. H. Adams,
Executor.
Nov. 18 40 x3
ADMINISTRATOR’S SALE.
Will be sold on the 15th December next, at the late residence of Samuel Moore,
deceased, in York District, all the personal property of said deceased, consisting
of:
35 LIKELY NEGROES,
a quantity of Cotton and Corn, Horses and Mules, Farming Tools, Household and
Kitchen Furniture, with many other articles.
Samuel E. Moore,
Administrator.
Nov. 18 40 x4t.
ADMINISTRATOR’S SALE.
Will be sold at public outcry, to the highest bidder, on Tuesday, the 14th day of
December next, at the late residence of Robert W. Durham, deceased, in Fairfield
District, all of the personal estate of said deceased: consisting in part as follows:
Nov. 23.
SHERIFF’S SALE.
Sheriff’s }
Office,
Nov. 19 1852. }
Nov. 20 37
†xtf
COMMISSIONER’S SALE.
John A. Crumpton, }
and others, } In Equity.
v. }
Zachariah C. Crumpton. }
In pursuance of the Decretal order made in this case, I will sell at public outcry to
the highest bidder, before the Court House door in Winnsboro, on the first Monday
in December next, three separate tracts or parcels of land, belonging to the estate
of Zachariah Crumpton, deceased.
I will also sell, at the same time and place, five or six likely Young Negroes, sold as
the property of the said Zachariah Crumpton, deceased, by virtue of the authority
aforesaid.
The Terms of sale are as follows, &c. &c.
W. R. Robetson,
C. E. F. D.
Commissioner’s }
Office,
Winnsboro, Nov. 8, }
1852.
Nov. 11 30 x3
56 NEGROES,
STOCK, CORN, FODDER, ETC. ETC.
Sep. 2 29 x16
By virtue of sundry writs of fieri facias, to me directed, will be sold before the
Court House in Columbia, within the legal hours, on the first Monday and Tuesday
in January next,
Seventy-four acres of Land, more or less, in Richland District, bounded on the
north and east by Lorick’s, and on the south and west by Thomas Trapp.
Also, Ten Head of Cattle, Twenty-five Head of Hogs, and Two Hundred Bushels of
Corn, levied on as the property of M. A. Wilson, at the suit of Samuel Gardner v.
M. A. Wilson.
Seven Negroes, named Grace, Frances, Edmund, Charlotte, Emuline, Thomas and
Charles, levied on as the property of Bartholomew Turnipseed, at the suit of A. F.
Dubard, J. S. Lever, Bank of the State and others, v. B. Turnipseed.
450 acres of Land, more or less, in Richland District, bounded on the north, &c.
&c.
By permission of Peter Wylie, Esq., Ordinary for Chester District, I will sell, at
public auction, before the Court House, in Chesterville, on the first Monday in
February next,
Will be sold, at our store, on Thursday, the 6th day of January next, all the
Household and Kitchen Furniture, belonging to the Estate of B. L. McLaughlin,
deceased, consisting in part of
Hair Seat Chairs, Sofas and Rockers. Piano, Mahogany Dining, Tea, and Card
Tables; Carpets, Rugs, Andirons, Fenders, Shovel and Tongs, Mantel Ornaments,
Clocks, Side Board, Bureaus, Mahogany Bedsteads, Feather Beds and Mattresses,
Wash Stands, Curtains, fine Cordial Stand, Glassware, Crockery, and a great
variety of articles for family use.
Terms cash.
ALSO,
A Negro Man, named Leonard, belonging to same.
Terms, &c.
ALSO,
It is seldom such an opportunity occurs us now offers. Among them are only four
beyond 45 years old, and none above 50. There are twenty-five prime young men,
between sixteen and thirty; forty of the most likely young women, and as fine a
set of children as can be shown!!
Terms, &c.
Will be sold, on Monday, the 3d January next, at the Court House, at 10 o’clock,
22 LIKELY NEGROES, the larger number of which are young and desirable. Among
them are Field Hands, Hostlers and Carriage Drivers, House Servants, &c., and of
the following ages: Robinson 40, Elsey 34, Yanaky 13, Sylla 11, Anikee 8, Robinson
6, Candy 3, Infant 9, Thomas 35, Die 38, Amey 18, Eldridge 13, Charles 6, Sarah
60, Baket 50, Mary 18, Betty 16, Guy 12, Tilla 9, Lydia 24, Rachel 4, Scipio 2.
The above Negroes are sold for the purpose of making some other investment of
the proceeds; the sale will, therefore, be positive.
Terms.—A credit of one, two, and three years, for notes payable at either of the
Banks, with two or more approved endorsers, with interest from date. Purchasers
to pay for papers.
Dec 8 43
☞ Black River Watchman will copy the above, and forward bill to the auctioneers
for payment.
Poor little Scip!
A LIKELY GIRL, about seventeen years old (raised in the up-country), a good Nurse
and House Servant, can wash and iron, and do plain cooking, and is warranted
sound and healthy. She may be seen at our office, where she will remain until
sold.
Allen & Phillips,
Auctioneers & Com. Agents.
The subscriber, having located in Columbia, offers for sale his Plantation in St.
Matthew’s Parish, six miles from the Railroad, containing 1,500 acres, now in a
high state of cultivation, with Dwelling House and all necessary Out-buildings.
ALSO,
T. J. Goodwyn.
FOR SALE.
A LIKELY NEGRO BOY, about twenty-one years old, a good wagoner and field hand.
Apply at this office.
Dec. 20 52.
NO. I.
75 NEGROES.
I have just received from the East 75 assorted A No. 1 negroes. Call soon, if
you want to get the first choice.
Benj. Little.
NO. II.
CASH FOR NEGROES.
I will pay as high cash prices for a few likely young negroes as any trader in
this city. Also, will receive and sell on commission at Byrd Hill’s, old stand, on
Adams-street, Memphis.
Benj. Little.
NO. III.
We will pay the highest cash price for all good negroes offered. We
invite all those having negroes for sale to call on us at our Mart,
opposite the lower steamboat landing. We will also have a large lot of
Virginia negroes for sale in the Fall. We have as safe a jail as any in the country,
where we can keep negroes safe for those that wish them kept.
Bolton, Dickins & Co.
NEGROES.
The undersigned would respectfully state to the public that he has leased the
stand in the Forks of the Road, near Natchez, for a term of years, and that he
intends to keep a large lot of NEGROES on hand during the year. He will sell
as low or lower than any other trader at this place or in New Orleans.
He has just arrived from Virginia with a very likely lot of Field Men and Women;
also, House Servants, three Cooks, and a Carpenter. Call and see.
A fine Buggy Horse, a Saddle Horse and a Carryall, on hand, and for sale.
Thos. G. James.
NEGROEES WANTD.
The subscriber, having located in Lynchburg, is giving the highest cash prices for
negroes between the ages of 10 and 30 years. Those having negroes for sale may
find it to their interest to call on him at the Washington Hotel, Lynchburg, or
address him by letter.
All communications will receive prompt attention.
J. B. McLendon.
Nov. 5-dly.
NEGROES WANTED.
The subscriber continues in market for Negroes, of both sexes, between the ages
of 10 and 30 years, including Mechanics, such as Blacksmiths, Carpenters, and will
pay the highest market prices in cash. His office is a newly erected brick building
on 1st or Lynch street, immediately in rear of the Farmers’ Bank, where he is
prepared (having erected buildings with that view) to board negroes sent to
Lynchburg for sale or otherwise on as moderate terms, and keep them as secure,
as if they were placed in the jail of the Corporation.
Aug 26.
Seth Woodroof.
WANTED.
ebookbell.com