Hales, S. D. (2005) - Thinking Tools You Can Prove A Negative. Think, 4 (10), 109-112. Doi10.1017s1477175600001287 - Hales2005
Hales, S. D. (2005) - Thinking Tools You Can Prove A Negative. Think, 4 (10), 109-112. Doi10.1017s1477175600001287 - Hales2005
http://journals.cambridge.org/THI
Steven D. Hales
http://journals.cambridge.org
Downloaded: 19 Mar 2015 IP address: 144.173.6.37
you can prove that you aren't nonexistent. Congratulations,
you've just proven a negative. The beautiful part is that you
can do this trick with absolutely any proposition whatsoever.
Prove P is true and you can prove that P is not false.
Some people seem to think that you can't prove a specific
sort of negative claim, namely that a thing does not exist. So
it is impossible to prove that Santa Claus, unicorns, the Loch
Ness Monster, God, pink elephants, WMD in Iraq, and Bigfoot
don't exist. Of course, this rather depends on what one has in
mind by 'prove.' Can you construct a valid deductive argument
with all true premises that yields the conclusion that there
are no unicorns? Sure. Here's one, using the valid inference
procedure of modus tollens:
Someone might object that that was a bit too fast—after all,
I didn't prove that the two premises were true. I just asserted
that they were true. Well, that's right. However, it would be a
grievous mistake to insist that someone prove all the premises
of any argument they might give. Here's why. The only way to
prove, say, that there is no evidence of unicorns in the fossil
record, is by giving an argument to that conclusion. Of course
one would then have to prove the premises of that argument
by giving further arguments, and then prove the premises of
those further arguments, ad infinitum. Which premises we
should take on credit and which need payment up front is a
matter of long and involved debate among epistemologists. But
one thing is certain: if proving things requires that an infinite
number of premises get proved first, we're not going to prove
much of anything at all, positive or negative.
Maybe people mean that no inductive argument will con-
clusively, indubitably prove a negative proposition beyond all
shadow of a doubt. For example, suppose someone argues
http://journals.cambridge.org
Downloaded: 19 Mar 2015 IP address: 144.173.6.37
that we've scoured the world for Bigfoot, found no credible
evidence of Bigfoot's existence, and therefore there is no
Bigfoot. A classic inductive argument. A Sasquatch defender
can always rejoin that Bigfoot is reclusive, and might just be
hiding in that next stand of trees. You can't prove he's not!
(until the search of that tree stand comes up empty too).
The problem here isn't that inductive arguments won't give
us certainty about negative claims (like the nonexistence of -H
Bigfoot), but that inductive arguments won't give us certainty =j#
about anything at all, positive or negative. All observed swans *"
are white, therefore all swans are white looked like a pretty c
good inductive argument until black swans were discovered 3
in Australia. J
The very nature of an inductive argument is to make a ->
conclusion probable, but not certain, given the truth of the o
premises. That just what an inductive argument is. We'd better §
not dismiss induction because we're not getting certainty out •
of it, though. Why do you think that the sun will rise tomorrow? ^
Not because of observation (you can't observe the future!), —
but because that's what it has always done in the past. Why
do you think that if you turn on the kitchen tap that water will
come out instead of chocolate? Why do you think you'll find
your house where you last left it? Why do you think lunch
will be nourishing instead of deadly? Again, because that's
the way things have always been in the past. In other words,
we use inferences — induction — from past experiences in
every aspect of our lives. As Bertrand Russell pointed out,
the chicken who expects to be fed when he sees the farmer
approaching, since that is what had always happened in the
past, is in for a big surprise when instead of receiving dinner,
he becomes dinner. But if the chicken had rejected inductive
reasoning altogether, then every appearance of the farmer
would be a surprise.
So why is it that people insist that you can't prove a negative?
I think it is the result of two things. (1) an acknowledgement
that induction is not bulletproof, airtight, and infallible, and (2)
a desperate desire to keep believing whatever one believes,
even if all the evidence is against it. That's why people keep
http://journals.cambridge.org
Downloaded: 19 Mar 2015 IP address: 144.173.6.37
believing in alien abductions, even when flying saucers always
turn out to be weather balloons, stealth jets, comets, or too
much alcohol. You can't prove a negative! You can't prove
that there are no alien abductions! Meaning: your argument
against aliens is inductive, therefore not incontrovertible, and
since I want to believe in aliens, I'm going to dismiss the
argument no matter how overwhelming the evidence against
CN aliens, and no matter how vanishingly small the chance of
[H extraterrestrial abduction.
• If we're going to dismiss inductive arguments because they
-p2 produce conclusions that are probable but not definite, then
0 we are in deep doo-doo. Despite its fallibility, induction is vital
*Z> in every aspect of our lives, from the mundane to the most
.c sophisticated science. Without induction we know basically
"c nothing about the world apart from our own immediate per-
!c ceptions. So we'd better keep induction, warts and all, and
«o use it to form negative beliefs as well as positive ones. You
— can prove a negative — at least as much as you can prove
1 anything at all.
http://journals.cambridge.org
Downloaded: 19 Mar 2015 IP address: 144.173.6.37